William James on Sensations, Emotions and Instincts

William James on Sensations, Emotions and Instincts William James on Sensations, Emotions and Instincts

williamjamesstudies.org
from williamjamesstudies.org More from this publisher

ANNA STOKLOSA 73c<strong>on</strong>tinuing relevance of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account. Ellsworth (1994), for example, argues that<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s work anticipates many of the current questi<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> ideas in emoti<strong>on</strong> research,<strong>and</strong> more recently, Palencik (2007) defends the view that several of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s ideas areindispensable to the c<strong>on</strong>temporary study of emoti<strong>on</strong>. 2 Barbalet (1999) defends a narrowerversi<strong>on</strong> of this claim, arguing that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account is of particular importance to thesocial psychology of emoti<strong>on</strong>s. On the empirical side, Laird <strong>and</strong> Bressler (1990) arguethat much c<strong>on</strong>temporary research supports <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s theory.While at least some scholars thus seem to be amenable to the idea ofrec<strong>on</strong>sidering the merit of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account of emoti<strong>on</strong>s, the philosophers of emoti<strong>on</strong>s, forthe most part, c<strong>on</strong>tinue to treat it like the ugly duckling of emoti<strong>on</strong> theories. This isbecause they generally categorise <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account of emoti<strong>on</strong>s as a feeling theory, 3which emphasises ‘the actual feel’ of an emoti<strong>on</strong> – the physiological changes <strong>and</strong>disturbances we feel when we are angry, for example (Calhoun <strong>and</strong> Solom<strong>on</strong>, 1984). Thatis, feeling theories of emoti<strong>on</strong>s assimilate emoti<strong>on</strong>s to bodily sensati<strong>on</strong>s (Deigh, 1994).While a ‘feeling theory’ label sounds prima facie innocuous, this label is the lastnail in the coffin of a theory so labelled, since feeling theories of emoti<strong>on</strong>s are viewed asunable to adequately capture a key property of emoti<strong>on</strong>s – their intenti<strong>on</strong>ality(Hatzimoysis, 2003). Although ‘intenti<strong>on</strong>ality’ is a notoriously slippery c<strong>on</strong>cept, it isusually described as the property of being about, for, of, at or towards some<strong>on</strong>e orsomething (Deigh, 1994; Solom<strong>on</strong>, 1993). Mental states such as beliefs areparadigmatically intenti<strong>on</strong>al; it seems, however, that emoti<strong>on</strong>s, too, are intenti<strong>on</strong>al. One’sanger, for example, is generally directed at some<strong>on</strong>e or something – the unruly child whorelentlessly kicks <strong>on</strong>e’s seat <strong>on</strong> a 14 hour flight, say. Sensati<strong>on</strong>s, <strong>on</strong> the other h<strong>and</strong>, arenot thought to be intenti<strong>on</strong>al in this way. In labelling <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s theory of emoti<strong>on</strong>sa feeling theory, philosophers thus ascribe to him the view that emoti<strong>on</strong>s areintenti<strong>on</strong>ality-less sensati<strong>on</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sequently c<strong>on</strong>sign his account to the dustbin ofintellectual history, al<strong>on</strong>g with the four humours <strong>and</strong> the like. 4I think, however, that ascribing to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> the view that emoti<strong>on</strong>s are sensati<strong>on</strong>s –<strong>and</strong> labelling <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account a feeling theory – rests <strong>on</strong> a misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’sviews. Instead, I will argue, many of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s emoti<strong>on</strong>s are more accurately categorised asinstincts. This classificati<strong>on</strong>, moreover, entails that emoti<strong>on</strong>s do have a functi<strong>on</strong>, c<strong>on</strong>trary


CHASING THE BEAR 74to a criticism frequently levied against <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account. To this end, I will proceed in thefollowing manner. In secti<strong>on</strong> 2, I will offer a brief exegesis of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account ofemoti<strong>on</strong>s. I will then discuss <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account of sensati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> percepti<strong>on</strong>s in secti<strong>on</strong> 3,<strong>and</strong> argue against the view that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s emoti<strong>on</strong>s are sensati<strong>on</strong>s (in secti<strong>on</strong> 4), thusundercutting the tenability of labelling <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account a ‘feeling theory.’ I will thenoutline <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s view <strong>on</strong> instincts in secti<strong>on</strong> 5, <strong>and</strong>, in secti<strong>on</strong> 6, I will argue that many of<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s emoti<strong>on</strong>s are actually instincts. I will close by devoting some space toelaborating what the functi<strong>on</strong> of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s might be in secti<strong>on</strong> 7.II. EMOTIONSThe ignominiously labelled ‘feeling theory’ begins innocuously enough, with adivisi<strong>on</strong> of emoti<strong>on</strong>s into coarse <strong>and</strong> subtle. 5 Subtle emoti<strong>on</strong>s (which will be largely setaside here), are defined as those “feelings of pleasure <strong>and</strong> displeasure, of interest <strong>and</strong>excitement, bound up with mental operati<strong>on</strong>s, but having no obvious bodily expressi<strong>on</strong>sfor their c<strong>on</strong>sequence” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 189; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 449). 6 <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account, however,focuses primarily <strong>on</strong> the coarse emoti<strong>on</strong>s “in which a wave of bodily disturbance of somekind accompanies the percepti<strong>on</strong> of the interesting sights or sounds, or the passage of theexciting train of ideas” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 189; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 449). Coarse emoti<strong>on</strong>s includethe usual suspects – grief, fear, anger, love (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 189; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 449) – aswell as some of the less frequently encountered <strong>on</strong>es, such as surprise, curiosity, rapture,lust <strong>and</strong> greed (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 189).Prior to elaborating his own views <strong>on</strong> emoti<strong>on</strong>s, however, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> first outlines hisbête noire – what he calls our ‘natural way’ of thinking about coarse emoti<strong>on</strong>s. Accordingto him, we naturally think of emoti<strong>on</strong>s as occurring in the following sequence: a mentalpercepti<strong>on</strong> of a fact excites an emoti<strong>on</strong>, which in turn gives rise to a bodily expressi<strong>on</strong>(<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 190; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 449). On this ‘natural way’ of thinking about emoti<strong>on</strong>s,a loss of fortune, for example, excites the emoti<strong>on</strong> of sadness, which in turn gives rise totears, or an encounter with a bear precipitates the emoti<strong>on</strong> of fear, subsequently causing<strong>on</strong>e to run away (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 190; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 449).According to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, however, this ‘natural’ view of emoti<strong>on</strong>s is inverted. <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>thinks that the proper way to think about the emoti<strong>on</strong>-sequence is to view “the bodily


ANNA STOKLOSA 75changes [as following] directly the percepti<strong>on</strong> of the exciting fact; […] our feeling of thesame changes as they occur is the emoti<strong>on</strong>” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 190; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 449). On<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s view, then, we are sad because we shed tears over our lost fortunes, or fearfulbecause we are shaking; it is not the case that we shed tears or shake because we are sador afraid, respectively.<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> remained c<strong>on</strong>sistently committed to this view of emoti<strong>on</strong>s. The claim thatwhen we perceive some exciting fact, our feeling of bodily changes that follow thatpercepti<strong>on</strong> is the emoti<strong>on</strong> is reiterated several times in the <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian corpus. First, itappears in the 1884 article “What is an emoti<strong>on</strong>?” 7 <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> then restated it in 1890, in thePrinciples of Psychology. As Barbalet (1999) notes, the Principles’ Emoti<strong>on</strong>s chapterwas retained (albeit in a somewhat c<strong>on</strong>densed form) for re-publicati<strong>on</strong>, in 1892, aschapter 24 of Psychology: Briefer Course. The final restatement of this view can befound in 1894’s “The Physical Basis of Emoti<strong>on</strong>.” 8<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s unwavering commitment to his view <strong>on</strong> emoti<strong>on</strong>s, moreover, manifestsitself in the absence of disagreement in the literature regarding what <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s positi<strong>on</strong> is.In discussi<strong>on</strong>s of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s theory, what is referred to – invariably – is his view that “thebodily changes [follow] directly the percepti<strong>on</strong> of an exciting fact, <strong>and</strong> that our feeling ofthe same changes as they occur is the emoti<strong>on</strong>” 9 (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 190; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 449).Where the c<strong>on</strong>troversy does arise, therefore, is with respect to the tenability of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’saccount. Four types of criticisms are typically levied against <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s view (Barbalet,1999). First, it is argued that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s lack functi<strong>on</strong>, pace c<strong>on</strong>temporaryneuroscientific findings <strong>on</strong> emoti<strong>on</strong>s. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account is charged with failing torecognise the import of experience in emoti<strong>on</strong>. The third set of criticisms accuses <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>of overstating the importance of the body in emoti<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong>, finally, the fourth charges<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> with proffering a theory that is empirically false. 10It is bey<strong>on</strong>d the remit of this paper to c<strong>on</strong>sider all of these charges in an adequatedetail. I will therefore focus <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong> the charge of functi<strong>on</strong>lessness. Two members of thecavalry leading the charge against <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, here, are Keith Oatley <strong>and</strong> Ant<strong>on</strong>io Damasio.Oatley charges <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s with being “at best a kind of froth <strong>on</strong> top of the realbusiness of behaviour” (Oatley, 1992, 133), <strong>and</strong>, in a similar vein, Damasio (1994)accuses <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> of saying little about the possible functi<strong>on</strong> of emoti<strong>on</strong>s. An account of


1990). 11 Lack of attenti<strong>on</strong> notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> does make some claims about theCHASING THE BEAR 76emoti<strong>on</strong>s that fails to award any type of functi<strong>on</strong> to emoti<strong>on</strong>s is in tensi<strong>on</strong> with thefindings of c<strong>on</strong>temporary neuroscience, which suggests that emoti<strong>on</strong>s do have a functi<strong>on</strong>(Damasio, 1994; Carroll, 2001). Therefore, if, as critics charge, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s arefuncti<strong>on</strong>less entities, then his account is rightly dismissed. I think, however, that adismissal of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account – at least <strong>on</strong> the grounds of emoti<strong>on</strong>s’ functi<strong>on</strong>lessness – ispremature. This is because for <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, many emoti<strong>on</strong>s are actually instincts, which entailsthat <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s do have a functi<strong>on</strong>. To show this, however, let us first c<strong>on</strong>sider<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account of sensati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> evaluate the feasibility of ascribing to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> the viewthat emoti<strong>on</strong>s are sensati<strong>on</strong>s.III. SENSATIONS AND PERCEPTIONSIn c<strong>on</strong>trast to his voluminous writings <strong>on</strong> emoti<strong>on</strong>s, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s writings <strong>on</strong>sensati<strong>on</strong>s are quite scarce, comprising <strong>on</strong>ly two chapters in Principles of Psychology.This dearth of attenti<strong>on</strong> may be due to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s dislike for sensati<strong>on</strong>s as an area of studyin psychology (Boring, 1942). The c<strong>on</strong>sequence of this inattenti<strong>on</strong>, however, is that<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s views <strong>on</strong> sensati<strong>on</strong>s lack the impact of his writings <strong>on</strong> emoti<strong>on</strong>s (Dember,sensati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> percepti<strong>on</strong>s, from which his views can be gleaned. For edificati<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> thesubject matter of natural history <strong>and</strong> classificati<strong>on</strong> of sensati<strong>on</strong>, more generally, heencourages the reader to turn to physiology textbooks (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 3). 12 The focus in thechapters that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> actually devotes to the discussi<strong>on</strong> of sensati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> percepti<strong>on</strong>s israther narrow, c<strong>on</strong>sisting largely in juxtaposing sensati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> percepti<strong>on</strong>s.In order to c<strong>on</strong>vey what a sensati<strong>on</strong> is, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> offers the following example. Inschools for the blind, numerous c<strong>on</strong>ceptual facts about light are imparted <strong>on</strong> the students:the light’s refracti<strong>on</strong>, reflecti<strong>on</strong>, spectrum properties, <strong>and</strong> so forth. N<strong>on</strong>e of these facts,however, c<strong>on</strong>stitute sensible knowledge about light (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 5). A sensati<strong>on</strong> is theextremely simple c<strong>on</strong>tent of our experience of the world (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 2), the ‘what-it’slike-ness’of having our sense organs affected (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 77). According to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>,sensati<strong>on</strong>s include, for example: hot, cold, colour, noise, <strong>and</strong> pain (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1879, 11;<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 1).


CHASING THE BEAR 78sensati<strong>on</strong> of colour <strong>and</strong> numerous percepti<strong>on</strong>s intricately interwoven with it (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890,77).IV. EMOTIONS AS SENSATIONS?Because feeling theories assimilate emoti<strong>on</strong>s to sensati<strong>on</strong>s (Deigh, 1994), inlabelling <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s theory of emoti<strong>on</strong>s a feeling theory, philosophers ascribe tohim the view that emoti<strong>on</strong>s are sensati<strong>on</strong>s. Martha Nussbaum (2001), Robert Solom<strong>on</strong>(1976, 1993), Anth<strong>on</strong>y Kenny (1963) <strong>and</strong> John Deigh (1994), for example, are am<strong>on</strong>gsome of the philosophical champi<strong>on</strong>s of this view. The grounds <strong>on</strong> which this view restsare not entirely clear, since – as previously noted – <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account of sensati<strong>on</strong>s isalmost never discussed in the literature. Some support for the view that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ianemoti<strong>on</strong>s are sensati<strong>on</strong>s is lent by <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s statement that “our feeling of the changes asthey occur is the emoti<strong>on</strong>” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> 1890 449; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> 1884 190). Nevertheless, there areseveral good reas<strong>on</strong>s to resist this interpretati<strong>on</strong>.First, recall that <strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s view, we may have pure sensati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong>ly in childhood.In adulthood, pure sensati<strong>on</strong>s can no l<strong>on</strong>ger be had – as a sensati<strong>on</strong> “never takes place […]without percepti<strong>on</strong> also being there” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 1). In other words, for <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, themultitude of stimulati<strong>on</strong>s from the external world fuses into an undifferentiatedexperience (Dember, 1990). Given that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> holds that it is impossible to tell which partof that experience is a sensati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>and</strong> which part is a percepti<strong>on</strong> (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 77), atmost, <strong>on</strong>e could claim that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s are an amalgam of percepti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong>sensati<strong>on</strong>s. 15 It is, of course, possible, that those who accept the ‘feeling theory’interpretati<strong>on</strong> of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account of emoti<strong>on</strong>s simply rely <strong>on</strong> a c<strong>on</strong>temporary (rather than<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian) underst<strong>and</strong>ing of sensati<strong>on</strong>s. If this is the case, however, the point would needto be made explicitly, <strong>and</strong> would require both a discussi<strong>on</strong> of the particular account ofsensati<strong>on</strong>s that underpins the claim, <strong>and</strong> an argument for the identity between thataccount of sensati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s c<strong>on</strong>ceptualisati<strong>on</strong> of emoti<strong>on</strong>s. Absent that, theascripti<strong>on</strong> to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> of the view that emoti<strong>on</strong>s are sensati<strong>on</strong>s is insufficiently grounded.The sec<strong>on</strong>d reas<strong>on</strong> to refrain from labelling <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s emoti<strong>on</strong>s sensati<strong>on</strong>s, is that<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> himself does not do so. What appears to lend credence to the view that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ianemoti<strong>on</strong>s are sensati<strong>on</strong>s is the claim that “the bodily changes follow directly the


ANNA STOKLOSA 79percepti<strong>on</strong> of the exciting fact, <strong>and</strong> that our feeling of the same changes as they occur isthe emoti<strong>on</strong>” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 449; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 190). Interestingly enough, despite usingthe term ‘percepti<strong>on</strong>’ here, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> does not use the term ‘sensati<strong>on</strong>’ – although <strong>on</strong>e wouldhave expected him to do so, given that he treats the two c<strong>on</strong>cepts together in thePrinciples. Moreover, he repeatedly describes the various bodily changes that occur inemoti<strong>on</strong>s – the shaking (in fear), the tears (in grief) (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 450; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 190)<strong>and</strong> the many other changes that occur (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 462; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1884, 197) – but at nopoint does he use the term ‘sensati<strong>on</strong>s’ to refer to these changes. 16There is yet another – even str<strong>on</strong>ger, I think – reas<strong>on</strong> to resist the view that<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s emoti<strong>on</strong>s are sensati<strong>on</strong>s: namely, that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> explicitly labels many emoti<strong>on</strong>s asstates other than sensati<strong>on</strong>s. To clarify this, however, we must first briefly c<strong>on</strong>sider<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s discussi<strong>on</strong> of instincts.V. INSTINCTSAlthough Harlow (1969) <strong>on</strong>ce asserted that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s insights <strong>on</strong> instinctsc<strong>on</strong>stitute <strong>on</strong>e of his greatest c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s to the study of psychology, little scholarship<strong>on</strong> this topic was produced am<strong>on</strong>g the many publicati<strong>on</strong>s celebrating the centennial of thepublicati<strong>on</strong> of Principles of Psychology, in 1990 (Dewsbury, 1992). Since then, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’swork <strong>on</strong> instincts has received some attenti<strong>on</strong> from many prominent scholars in the fieldof evoluti<strong>on</strong>ary psychology – including Pinker (1994) <strong>and</strong> Tooby <strong>and</strong> Cosmides (1992). 17Outside of that particular niche, however, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s writings <strong>on</strong> instincts generally appearto garner as much attenti<strong>on</strong> as do his writings <strong>on</strong> sensati<strong>on</strong>s: that is to say, very little.There is some indicati<strong>on</strong> that the topic of instincts was important to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> himself.As Dewsbury (1992) points out, the topic recurs throughout the Principles, <strong>and</strong> when thebook was abridged, the chapter devoted to the topic of instinct was shortened less thanother chapters. What, then, are <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s views <strong>on</strong> the subject matter? <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> definesinstincts as those acti<strong>on</strong>s which “produce certain ends, without foresight of the ends, <strong>and</strong>without previous educati<strong>on</strong> in the performance” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1887a, 355; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 383).He further divides instincts into two types. First, he counts am<strong>on</strong>g instincts those acti<strong>on</strong>swhich “go no further than our own bodies” – for example, the facial expressi<strong>on</strong> generatedwhen observing a novel object. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, he also includes am<strong>on</strong>g instincts those acti<strong>on</strong>s


CHASING THE BEAR 80which “take effect up<strong>on</strong> the outer world”, such as a flight from a wild beast, or mimicryof a friend’s acti<strong>on</strong>s (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 403).<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> holds that humans possess the largest number of instincts of any creature,since we possess all of the instincts that lower creatures possess, <strong>and</strong> great many instinctsin additi<strong>on</strong> to those (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1887b, 666; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 390). Some of the human instinctsinclude: sucking, biting, chewing, spitting, grasping objects, pointing, swallowing,alimentati<strong>on</strong>, locomoti<strong>on</strong>, etc (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 403). Am<strong>on</strong>g the lower animals, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>siders egg-laying (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 388), silk-worm’s winding of her coco<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> hawk’suse of tal<strong>on</strong>s against her prey (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 383) to be instinctive.<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> charges his c<strong>on</strong>temporaries with an undue preference for describinginstincts by reference to their functi<strong>on</strong> (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1887a, 355; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 383). <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’sown descripti<strong>on</strong> of instincts emphasises their physiology because he thinks this approachyields more clarity – as many of the relevant creatures lack the abstract c<strong>on</strong>cepts invokedin functi<strong>on</strong>al descripti<strong>on</strong> of instincts. Thus, typical in his discussi<strong>on</strong> is a statement that“instinctive acti<strong>on</strong>s are called forth by determinate sensory stimuli in c<strong>on</strong>tact with theanimal's body, or at a distance in his envir<strong>on</strong>ment” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 384, emphases added)which highlights the physical nature of the instinct, rather than what it does – or does not– accomplish.The emphasis <strong>on</strong> the physiological rather than functi<strong>on</strong>al descripti<strong>on</strong> of instincts,however, ought not to be interpreted as a denial that instincts have functi<strong>on</strong>s. On thec<strong>on</strong>trary, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s very definiti<strong>on</strong> of instincts – as acti<strong>on</strong>s that produce particular ends –suggests that instincts do have a functi<strong>on</strong> for <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>. While <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s preference forphysiological rather than functi<strong>on</strong>al descripti<strong>on</strong>s precludes him from engaging in anextended discussi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> the subject-matter of instincts’ functi<strong>on</strong>s, his views can begleaned from several remarks he does make. It seems that for <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, the functi<strong>on</strong> ofinstincts is related to self-preservati<strong>on</strong> or, in other words, survival. This is suggested, forexample, by his claim that the truth of evoluti<strong>on</strong> requires that since “the destructi<strong>on</strong> ofprey <strong>and</strong> of human rivals must have been am<strong>on</strong>g the most important of man's primitivefuncti<strong>on</strong>s, the fighting <strong>and</strong> the chasing instincts must have become ingrained” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>,1890, 412, emphasis added). 18


CHASING THE BEAR 82the states explicitly identified as emoti<strong>on</strong>s, are also explicitly identified as instincts. Forexample, fear, is said by <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> to be “<strong>on</strong>e of the three most exciting emoti<strong>on</strong>s of whichour nature is susceptible” is also identified – <strong>on</strong>ly two lines later – as “a genuine instinct,<strong>and</strong> <strong>on</strong>e of the earliest shown by the human child” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 415, emphases added).Elsewhere in the chapter, the “utterly blind instinctive character” of fear is said to bedem<strong>on</strong>strated by reas<strong>on</strong>’s inability to c<strong>on</strong>trol it (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 418, emphasis added). 20<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> also identifies sympathy as both an emoti<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> an instinct (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 410).Love (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 411; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1887b, 678) <strong>and</strong> hate (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 411) are, too,labelled as both instincts <strong>and</strong> emoti<strong>on</strong>s (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 474 <strong>and</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 448,respectively). Finally, shame – an “instinctive impulse 21 to hide certain parts of the body”(<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1887b, 676) – is also elsewhere identified by <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> as an emoti<strong>on</strong> (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890,474).In short, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> clearly identifies at least 6 states – anger, fear, sympathy, love,hate <strong>and</strong> shame – as both emoti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> instincts. It is worth noting that in his initialstatement of the definiti<strong>on</strong> of emoti<strong>on</strong> – as the feeling of bodily changes – <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> offersthree examples: grief (up<strong>on</strong> loss of fortune), fear (up<strong>on</strong> encountering the bear) <strong>and</strong> anger(towards a rival who insults us) (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 449). It is therefore quite suggestive that ofhis three paradigmatic emoti<strong>on</strong>s, two – namely, anger <strong>and</strong> fear – are also labelledinstincts.Finally, the third reas<strong>on</strong> in favour of adopting the view that many of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ianemoti<strong>on</strong>s are instincts, is <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s statement identifying the two, at the beginning ofPrinciples’ Chapter 25, “The Emoti<strong>on</strong>s”:Emoti<strong>on</strong>al reacti<strong>on</strong>s are often excited by objects with which we have nopractical dealings. A ludicrous object, for example, or a beautiful objectare not necessarily objects to which we do anything; we simply laugh, orst<strong>and</strong> in admirati<strong>on</strong>, as the case may be. The class of emoti<strong>on</strong>al, is thusrather larger than that of instinctive, impulses, comm<strong>on</strong>ly so called. Itsstimuli are more numerous, <strong>and</strong> its expressi<strong>on</strong>s are more internal <strong>and</strong>delicate, <strong>and</strong> often less practical. The physiological plan <strong>and</strong> essence of


ANNA STOKLOSA 83the two classes of impulse, however, is the same. (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 442;emphases added)<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> makes three important claims here. First, he points out that ‘emoti<strong>on</strong>s’ are alarger class than ‘instincts’. This precludes us from claiming that all emoti<strong>on</strong>s areinstincts for <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, for, as the above quote implies, some emoti<strong>on</strong>s are not instincts. 22Nevertheless, as identified above, many are – including two of the three states heidentifies as emoti<strong>on</strong>s in his discussi<strong>on</strong> of the definiti<strong>on</strong> of emoti<strong>on</strong>s. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> als<strong>on</strong>otes here that the ‘essence’ of emoti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> instincts is the same. What, precisely, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>means by ‘essence’ is not entirely clear – he does not define the term. This suggests thathe may be using the term in its c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>al sense – to mean the very nature of a thing(Johns<strong>on</strong>, 1755-56). Third, he points out that emoti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> instincts share a‘physiological plan.’ Recall, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> emphasises that instincts ought to be discussed interms of physiology (rather than functi<strong>on</strong>) in order to yield the most clarity. Thesignificance of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s claim that emoti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> instincts are identical with regard to whathe c<strong>on</strong>siders to be <strong>on</strong>e of their most salient properties – their physiology – thereforecannot be overemphasised.The c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> between <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> instincts has thus far not meritedmuch attenti<strong>on</strong> in the literature – perhaps obscured by the dominant interpretati<strong>on</strong> of hisaccount of emoti<strong>on</strong>s as sensati<strong>on</strong>s. Occasi<strong>on</strong>ally, however, the link between emoti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong>instincts has been tentatively suggested. Dewsbury (1992), for example, notes that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>viewed emoti<strong>on</strong>s as intimately linked to instincts, but takes the significance of this to bethat instincts are therefore at the centre of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian psychology, much like emoti<strong>on</strong>s are.Golightly (1953), similarly, points out that Darwin’s influence caused <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> to linkemoti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> instincts, <strong>and</strong> to emphasise the biological aspect of the former. Barbalet(1999), finally, points out that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s chapter <strong>on</strong> instincts does discuss several emoti<strong>on</strong>s,but falls short of drawing the c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> about what this suggests. 23Although the claim that some <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s are instincts thus appearsplausible <strong>and</strong> is, moreover, not entirely without precedent, two challenges maynevertheless be raised in resp<strong>on</strong>se to this claim. First, <strong>on</strong>e may object to classifying <strong>on</strong>eset of states as another set of states. However, those who categorise <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s as


CHASING THE BEAR 84sensati<strong>on</strong>s – by labelling his account of emoti<strong>on</strong>s a ‘feeling theory’ – adopt the samemove: categorising <strong>on</strong>e class of states as another. 24 In other words, if there is nothingimproper about categorising emoti<strong>on</strong>s as sensati<strong>on</strong>s, there ought to be nothing improperabout categorising emoti<strong>on</strong>s as instincts. In light of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s claims about emoti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong>instincts, such categorisati<strong>on</strong> is, in fact, obligatory. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, <strong>on</strong>e may challenge that it israther peculiar to categorise emoti<strong>on</strong>s as brute instincts, since many emoti<strong>on</strong>s are quitesophisticated. To this, however, <strong>on</strong>e may resp<strong>on</strong>d by noting that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s underst<strong>and</strong>ingof ‘instinct’ is quite broad. In Chapter 24 (“Instinct”) of the Principles al<strong>on</strong>e, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>counts am<strong>on</strong>g human instincts such varied states as: biting, pointing at objects, smiling,turning the head aside, holding head erect, st<strong>and</strong>ing, pugnacity, hunting, kleptomania,playing, sociability <strong>and</strong> shyness, secretiveness, cleanliness, jealousy, <strong>and</strong> parental love,am<strong>on</strong>g others (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 403-440). While <strong>on</strong>e may, perhaps, be reluctant to categoriseemoti<strong>on</strong>s as instincts <strong>on</strong> a c<strong>on</strong>temporary account of instincts, within <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian tax<strong>on</strong>omy,it is permissible to do so.VII. EMOTIONS’ FUNCTIONSWhat yet remains to be shown is the significance of the categorisati<strong>on</strong> of<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s as instincts. What is most salient here, I think, is the implicati<strong>on</strong> ofthis categorisati<strong>on</strong>. Given that instincts clearly do have a functi<strong>on</strong> for <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, categorisingemoti<strong>on</strong>s as instincts entails that those emoti<strong>on</strong>s, too, have a functi<strong>on</strong>. Because <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>focuses <strong>on</strong> the physical nature of emoti<strong>on</strong>s rather than their functi<strong>on</strong> – the same approachhe adopts in his discussi<strong>on</strong> of instincts – <strong>on</strong>e of the criticisms levied against his account isthat <strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s view, emoti<strong>on</strong>s are functi<strong>on</strong>less (Oatley, 1992; Damasio 1994). 25Showing that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s emoti<strong>on</strong>s have a functi<strong>on</strong> would therefore not <strong>on</strong>ly undercut thiscriticism, but also place <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account of emoti<strong>on</strong>s in line with c<strong>on</strong>temporary researchwhich suggests that the functi<strong>on</strong> of emoti<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sists in “<strong>and</strong> motivating an organism toc<strong>on</strong>tend with challenges in its envir<strong>on</strong>ment” (Palencik, 2007, 776).But what is the nature of this functi<strong>on</strong>? If <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s are instincts, thenthe emoti<strong>on</strong>s’ functi<strong>on</strong> must also centre <strong>on</strong> self-preservati<strong>on</strong>. 26 While the dearth ofdiscussi<strong>on</strong> about the emoti<strong>on</strong>s’ functi<strong>on</strong> precludes establishing with absolute certaintythat this is, in fact, the case, some claims made by <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> in chapter 10 of the Principles


CHASING THE BEAR 86with what <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> seems to want to c<strong>on</strong>vey here, as all four focus <strong>on</strong> our interacti<strong>on</strong>s withour fellow human beings (under normal circumstances).Thus, it seems plausible to accept that the functi<strong>on</strong> of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s centres<strong>on</strong> preserving our well-being – which is c<strong>on</strong>sistent with <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s underst<strong>and</strong>ing of manyemoti<strong>on</strong>s as instincts. This includes both our physical well-being (centred <strong>on</strong> our naturalenvir<strong>on</strong>ment) <strong>and</strong> social well-being (centred <strong>on</strong> our social envir<strong>on</strong>ment). Far from beingthe froth <strong>on</strong> the business of behaviour – to borrow Oatley’s phrase – <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>sdo have a functi<strong>on</strong> – <strong>and</strong> a rather fundamental <strong>on</strong>e at that.One potential worry for this view is that, according to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, emoti<strong>on</strong>s “usuallyterminate in the subject's own body, whilst the instinctive reacti<strong>on</strong> is apt to go farther <strong>and</strong>enter into practical relati<strong>on</strong>s with the exciting object” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 442). This claimseems to undermine the functi<strong>on</strong>al reading of emoti<strong>on</strong>, for if emoti<strong>on</strong> fails to enter intopractical relati<strong>on</strong>s with the world, then how is it to functi<strong>on</strong> in self-preservati<strong>on</strong>?To this, however, <strong>on</strong>e can resp<strong>on</strong>d by making two points. First, it must be notedthat the claim here cited effectively compares apples to oranges. This is because the claimthat is made with respect to emoti<strong>on</strong>s is <strong>on</strong>tological – it describes what emoti<strong>on</strong>s are, viz.states that usually terminate in the body. The claim pertaining to instincts, <strong>on</strong> the otherh<strong>and</strong>, is functi<strong>on</strong>al – it describes what instincts do, namely enter into relati<strong>on</strong>s with theircauses. Thus, the juxtapositi<strong>on</strong> between the emoti<strong>on</strong> claim <strong>and</strong> the instinct claim fails toimply that emoti<strong>on</strong>s do not enter into practical relati<strong>on</strong>s with the world.Sec<strong>on</strong>d – let us suppose that it were the case that the claim made here implied thatemoti<strong>on</strong>s usually fail to enter into practical relati<strong>on</strong>s in the world. We must note that thequalificati<strong>on</strong> ‘usually’ suggests that not all emoti<strong>on</strong>s are thought to be problematic here.Running away from a bear in fear for <strong>on</strong>e’s life certainly does seem to enter into practicalrelati<strong>on</strong>s with the world. What could be c<strong>on</strong>sidered more problematic here, perhaps, areemoti<strong>on</strong>s like shame or sympathy. However, here we can advert to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s distincti<strong>on</strong>between physical self-seeking <strong>and</strong> social self-seeking. Even emoti<strong>on</strong>s like shame orsympathy, whose interacti<strong>on</strong>s with the world appear more muted than the running awayfrom a bear, can advance social self-seeking. This could be accomplished if, for example,they serve to communicate a shared moral code. Subtleness of the interacti<strong>on</strong>s with the


ANNA STOKLOSA 87world – which may be termed a failure to interact with the world in a practical way –need not, therefore, preclude emoti<strong>on</strong>s from fulfilling their functi<strong>on</strong>.VIII. CONCLUSION<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s theory of emoti<strong>on</strong>s thus seems overdue for a re-evaluati<strong>on</strong>.While some re-evaluati<strong>on</strong> of the tenability of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s theory appears to be taking place,philosophers generally c<strong>on</strong>tinue to dismiss <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s theory, <strong>on</strong> account of its beingclassified as a feeling theory of emoti<strong>on</strong>s. A closer examinati<strong>on</strong> of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s (generallyneglected) account of sensati<strong>on</strong>s, however, shows this categorisati<strong>on</strong> to be questi<strong>on</strong>able.A similar examinati<strong>on</strong> of his (likewise generally neglected) account of instincts,moreover, reveals that for <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, many emoti<strong>on</strong>s are actually instincts. This recategorisati<strong>on</strong>of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>s as instincts undercuts an oft-levied charge against<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account, that his emoti<strong>on</strong>s are functi<strong>on</strong>less. <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s emoti<strong>on</strong>s indeed do have afuncti<strong>on</strong> – a self-preservative <strong>on</strong>e. Thus, far from deserving dismissal or recogniti<strong>on</strong> asvaluable <strong>on</strong>ly as a starting point for research <strong>on</strong> emoti<strong>on</strong>s, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s account of emoti<strong>on</strong>smerits bringing back into the fold of legitimate inquiry. 28University of Tor<strong>on</strong>to & University of Sydneyanna.stoklosa@utor<strong>on</strong>to.caREFERENCES1. Barbalet, J.M. (1999). “<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s Theory of Emoti<strong>on</strong>s: Filling in thePicture”. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, vol. 29, no. 3, pp. 252-266.2. Boring, Edwin. (1942). “Human Nature vs. Sensati<strong>on</strong>: <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>and</strong> thePsychology of the Present.” The American Journal of Psychology, vol. 55, no. 3,pp. 310-3273. Calhoun, Cheshire <strong>and</strong> Robert Solom<strong>on</strong> (1984). What is an emoti<strong>on</strong>: Classicreadings in Philosophical Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.4. Cann<strong>on</strong>, Walter B. (1927). “The <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>-Lange Theory of Emoti<strong>on</strong>s: A CriticalExaminati<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> an Alternative Theory”. The American Journal of Psychology,vol. 39, no. 1/4, pp. 106-124


CHASING THE BEAR 885. Carroll, Noel (2001). Bey<strong>on</strong>d aesthetics: philosophical essays. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press6. Damasio, Ant<strong>on</strong>io (1994). Descartes’ Error: Emoti<strong>on</strong>, Reas<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> the HumanBrain. New York: Grosset/Putnam.7. Deigh, John. (1994). “Cognitivism in the theory of emoti<strong>on</strong>s.” Ethics, vol. 104, pp.824-8548. Dember, <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1990). “<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> Sensati<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> Percepti<strong>on</strong>.”Psychological Science, vol. 1, no. 3, pp. 163-1669. Dewsbury, D. A. (1992). “<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>and</strong> instinct theory revisited” in D<strong>on</strong>nelly, M.E. (ed.), Reinterpreting the legacy of <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>. Washingt<strong>on</strong>, DC: American Psychological Associati<strong>on</strong>. 10. Dix<strong>on</strong>, Thomas M. (2003). From passi<strong>on</strong>s to emoti<strong>on</strong>s: the creati<strong>on</strong> of a secularpsychological category. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press11. Ellsworth, P. (1994) “<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>and</strong> emoti<strong>on</strong>: is a century of fame worth acentury of misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing?” Psychological Review, vol. 101, 222-229.12. Feinstein, Howard (1970). “<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> the Emoti<strong>on</strong>s.” Journal of theHistory of Ideas, vol. 31, no. 1, pp. 133-14213. Golightly, Cornelius (1953). “The <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>-Lange Theory: A logical post-mortem”.Philosophy of Science, vol. 20, no. 4, pp. 286-29914. Harlow, H. F. (1969). “<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>and</strong> instinct theory” in MacLeod, R.B.(ed.), <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>: Unfinished business. Washingt<strong>on</strong>, DC: AmericanPsychological Associati<strong>on</strong>.15. Hatzimoysis, Anth<strong>on</strong>y (2003). “Emoti<strong>on</strong>al Feelings <strong>and</strong> Intenti<strong>on</strong>ality” inHatzimoysis, Anth<strong>on</strong>y (ed.) Philosophy <strong>and</strong> the Emoti<strong>on</strong>s. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.16. <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1879). “Are we Automata,” Mind, vol. 4, pp. 1-22.17. <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1884). “What is an Emoti<strong>on</strong>?” Mind, vol. 9, pp. 188-20518. <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g>. (1887a) “What is an Instinct.” Scribner’s Magazine, vol. 1, pp.355-365.19. <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1887b) “Some human instincts” Popular Science M<strong>on</strong>thly, vol.31, pp. 666-681


ANNA STOKLOSA 8920. <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1890). Principles of Psychology. Vols. 1 & 2 (reprinted 1950).New York: Dover Publicati<strong>on</strong>s.21. <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1894/1994). “The Physical Basis of Emoti<strong>on</strong>”. PsychologicalReview, vol. 101, no. 2, pp. 205-21022. Johns<strong>on</strong>, Samuel (1755-56.). A dicti<strong>on</strong>ary of the English language: in which thewords are deduced from their originals, <strong>and</strong> illustrated in their differentsignificati<strong>on</strong>s by examples from the best writers, to which are prefixed, a historyof the language, <strong>and</strong> an English grammar. Volumes I & II. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>.23. Kenny, Anth<strong>on</strong>y (1963). Acti<strong>on</strong>, Emoti<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Will. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge & K.Paul.24. Laird, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>and</strong> Charles Bresler (1990). “<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>and</strong> the Mechanisms ofEmoti<strong>on</strong>al Experience.” Pers<strong>on</strong>ality <strong>and</strong> Social Psychology Bulletin, vol. 16, pp.636-651.25. Lang, Peter J. (1994). “The Varieties of Emoti<strong>on</strong>al Experience: A Meditati<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong><str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>-Lange Theory.” Psychological Review, vol. 101, no. 2, pp. 211-221.26. Ly<strong>on</strong>s, <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1980). Emoti<strong>on</strong>. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.27. M<strong>and</strong>ler, George (1990). “<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>and</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of Emoti<strong>on</strong>.”Psychological Science, vol. 1, no. 3 (May), pp. 179-18028. Myers, Gerald. (1986) <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>: His Life <strong>and</strong> Thought. New Haven: YaleUniversity Press.29. Nussbaum, Martha. (2001) Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emoti<strong>on</strong>s..Cambridge: Cambridge University Press30. Oatley, Keith (1992). Best Laid Schemes: The Psychology of Emoti<strong>on</strong>. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press31. Palencik, Joseph T. (2007). “<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>and</strong> the Psychology of Emoti<strong>on</strong>:From 1884 to the Present”. Transacti<strong>on</strong>s of the Charles S. Peirce Society, vol. 43,no 4. pp. 769-8632. Pinker, S. (1994). The language instinct. New York: W. Morris <strong>and</strong> Company.33. Ratcliffe, Matthew (2005). “<str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> Emoti<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> Intenti<strong>on</strong>ality.”Internati<strong>on</strong>al Journal of Philosophical Studies, vol. 13, no. 2, pp. 179-20234. Solom<strong>on</strong>, Robert C. (1976). The Passi<strong>on</strong>s. New York: Doubleday


CHASING THE BEAR 9035. Solom<strong>on</strong>, Robert (1993) Not Passi<strong>on</strong>s’ Slave: Emoti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Choice. Oxford:Oxford University Press.36. Suplizio, Jean (2007) “On the significance of <str<strong>on</strong>g>William</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> to a C<strong>on</strong>temporaryDoctrine of Evoluti<strong>on</strong>ary Psychology.” Hum Stud, vol. 30, pp. 357-37537. Tooby, J., <strong>and</strong> Cosmides, L. (1992). “The psychological foundati<strong>on</strong>s of culture.”In Barkow, J. H., L. Cosmides, <strong>and</strong> J. Tooby (eds.), The adapted mind: Evoluti<strong>on</strong>ary psychology <strong>and</strong> the generati<strong>on</strong> of culture. New York: OxfordUniversity Press38. Yanal, Robert J. (1999) Paradoxes of emoti<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> ficti<strong>on</strong>. Pennsylvania StateUniversity Press.NOTES1 <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s theory of emoti<strong>on</strong>s is often referred to in the literature as the <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>-Lange theory. <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> himself was aware of the similarities between his <strong>and</strong> Lange’s views,acknowledging them in “The Physical Basis of Emoti<strong>on</strong>” (1894/1994). C.f. Lang (1994)<strong>and</strong> M<strong>and</strong>ler (1990), who argue that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s <strong>and</strong> Lange’s accounts have differentemphases.2 See also M<strong>and</strong>ler (1990) for a versi<strong>on</strong> of this argument.3 See, e.g.: Deigh (1994), Yanal (1999), Dix<strong>on</strong> (2003), Ly<strong>on</strong>s (1980), Kenny(1963), Damasio (1994) <strong>and</strong> Nussbaum (2001). Calhoun <strong>and</strong> Solom<strong>on</strong> (1984) identify<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s theory as a “physiological theory” while defining physiological theories muchlike feeling theories are defined here, <strong>and</strong> thus should be counted here, as well. Cf.Ellsworth (1994) who ascribes to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> a cognitive theory of emoti<strong>on</strong>s.4 Philosophers of emoti<strong>on</strong> have now generally ab<strong>and</strong><strong>on</strong>ed feeling theories forcognitivist theories of emoti<strong>on</strong>s. Briefly, cognitivist theories hold that our emoti<strong>on</strong>s arejust like other mental states which are intenti<strong>on</strong>al. See Deigh (1994) for a discussi<strong>on</strong> ofcognitivist theories, <strong>and</strong> some of the problems underlying feeling theories of emoti<strong>on</strong>s.5 In “What is an emoti<strong>on</strong>?” (1884) this distincti<strong>on</strong> is drawn in terms of ‘st<strong>and</strong>ard’<strong>and</strong> ‘intellectual’ emoti<strong>on</strong>s. The definiti<strong>on</strong>s of each are identical to ‘coarse’ <strong>and</strong> ‘subtle’emoti<strong>on</strong>s, respectively.


ANNA STOKLOSA 916 <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> offers identical (or nearly identical) accounts of emoti<strong>on</strong> in “What is anemoti<strong>on</strong>?” (1884) <strong>and</strong> Chapter 25 (“The Emoti<strong>on</strong>s”) of Principles of Psychology (1890).References to both sources are therefore given where applicable.7 Feinstein points out that some evidence exists that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> was committed to thisview even prior to his 1884’s “What is an emoti<strong>on</strong>?”, as <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> wrote <strong>on</strong> his copy ofLotze’s Medicinische Psychologie (which he is thought to have read in 1867-68):“emoti<strong>on</strong>s due to bodily reverberati<strong>on</strong>s” (Feinstein, 1970, footnote 10)8 In other words, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> was committed to this view for at least a decade, <strong>and</strong>possibly for as l<strong>on</strong>g as 27 years, if Feinstein’s speculati<strong>on</strong> is correct.9 These lines are cited, for example, by Palencik (2007), Laird <strong>and</strong> Bressler (1990),Feinstein (1970), Golightly (1953), Ellsworth (1994), Cann<strong>on</strong> (1927), Deigh (1994),Myers (1969), Ratcliffe (2005), Barbalet (1999).10 For the first type of criticism, see Damasio (1994) <strong>and</strong> Oatley (1992). For thesec<strong>on</strong>d type of criticism, see Damasio (1994). For the third <strong>and</strong> fourth types of criticisms,see Cann<strong>on</strong> (1927).11 See, however, Dember’s (1990) argument that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s writings <strong>on</strong> sensati<strong>on</strong>s<strong>and</strong> percepti<strong>on</strong>s manifest themselves in several str<strong>and</strong>s of c<strong>on</strong>temporary psychologicalresearch.12 He refers the reader specifically to Martin’s “Human Body,” Bernstein’s “FiveSenses of man,” Wundt’s “Physiological Psychology” or Hermann’s “H<strong>and</strong>buch derPhysiologie” volume 3 (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 3, footnote 3).13 The terminology used here is mine; <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> does not discuss sensati<strong>on</strong>s’ functi<strong>on</strong>as either direct or indirect. It is worth noting, however, that this entails that even ifemoti<strong>on</strong>s were sensati<strong>on</strong>s for <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> (as it is comm<strong>on</strong>ly understood), <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian emoti<strong>on</strong>swould have a functi<strong>on</strong>, pace Oatley <strong>and</strong> Damasio.14 Ellsworth (1994) goes as far as to argue that when <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> used the term‘percepti<strong>on</strong>’ he meant to c<strong>on</strong>vey something more akin to a cognitive appraisal than to asensati<strong>on</strong>. Palencik (2007), similarly, attributes to <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> the view that percepti<strong>on</strong> is anevaluative underst<strong>and</strong>ing of a situati<strong>on</strong>.


CHASING THE BEAR 9215 Admittedly, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cedes that we do refer to our complex experientialamalgams as sensati<strong>on</strong>s. However, according to him, this is simply a shorth<strong>and</strong> (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>,1890, 77).16 Moreover, interpreting ‘feeling’ to be syn<strong>on</strong>ymous with <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian ‘sensati<strong>on</strong>’would be problematic since, as Myers (1986) notes, <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s use of the term ‘feeling’ isinc<strong>on</strong>sistent in his writings.17 Cf. Suplizio (2007), who argues that evoluti<strong>on</strong>ary psychologists lack basis forpositive comparis<strong>on</strong>s between their own views <strong>on</strong> instincts <strong>and</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s views.18 <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> thinks that this is the case generally but not always. In other words, hethinks that some instincts cannot be explained by adverting to survival. For example, ourfear of heights is instinctive but not survival-related; he thinks it is “a mere incidentalpeculiarity of the nervous system” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 419). The example seems to be ratherpoorly chosen, as avoiding precipices <strong>and</strong> heights does seem rather relevant to increasing<strong>on</strong>e’s odds of survival, but <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s general point is well taken – some instincts may haveoutgrown their evoluti<strong>on</strong>ary utility in modern times.19 In c<strong>on</strong>text of his c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> of the two types of acti<strong>on</strong>s that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> classifiesas instincts, he notes that “<strong>on</strong> the whole it is best to be catholic, since it is very hard todraw an exact line” between the acti<strong>on</strong>s that go no further than our bodies <strong>and</strong> <strong>on</strong>es thattake effect up<strong>on</strong> the outer world (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 403).20 Fear is also identified as an emoti<strong>on</strong> at (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1887b, 672), <strong>and</strong> as an instinct at(<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1887b, 666).21 <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> uses here the term ‘impulse’ rather than ‘instinct.’ <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> thinks that thetwo terms are equivalent, pointing out that “every instinct is an impulse. Whether weshall call such impulses as blushing, sneezing, coughing, smiling, or dodging, or keepingtime to music, instincts or not, is a mere matter of terminology. The process is the samethrough-out” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 385, emphases added).22 It is bey<strong>on</strong>d the remit of this paper to establish which of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s emoti<strong>on</strong>s,precisely, are not instincts, <strong>and</strong> why. One possible explanati<strong>on</strong> here is that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> isadverting to his distincti<strong>on</strong> between coarse <strong>and</strong> subtle emoti<strong>on</strong>s.


ANNA STOKLOSA 9323 Although these suggesti<strong>on</strong>s are c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the argument I am here puttingforth, n<strong>on</strong>e benefit from an exp<strong>and</strong>ed discussi<strong>on</strong>, <strong>and</strong> n<strong>on</strong>e draw out the c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> that(many) emoti<strong>on</strong>s are instincts for <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>.24 Although whether they categorise <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s emoti<strong>on</strong>s as <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ian sensati<strong>on</strong>s oras sensati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> some type of a c<strong>on</strong>temporary account of sensati<strong>on</strong>s, is difficult todiscern due to the dearth of discussi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> this point.25 Ratcliffe (2005) goes as far as to claim that <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s failure to elaborate anexplicit account of the functi<strong>on</strong>s of emoti<strong>on</strong>s justifies the interpretati<strong>on</strong> of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>ianemoti<strong>on</strong>s as functi<strong>on</strong>less.26 I am here in agreement with Barbalet who notes that for <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> the functi<strong>on</strong> ofemoti<strong>on</strong>s is evoluti<strong>on</strong>ary in that they “prompt particular types of acti<strong>on</strong>s, especiallyacti<strong>on</strong>s associated with self-seeking <strong>and</strong> self-preservati<strong>on</strong>” (Barbalet, 1999, 260). As faras I can tell, Barbalet is the <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e who takes his view of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s emoti<strong>on</strong>s; Barbaletcites no other sec<strong>on</strong>dary literature sources in agreement with his claim. Where we dodiffer, however, is in the emphasis <strong>on</strong> the instinctive nature of emoti<strong>on</strong>s. Barbalet notesthat the import of <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s claim that “the emoti<strong>on</strong>al reacti<strong>on</strong> usually terminates in thesubject’s own body” is that emoti<strong>on</strong> is not like instinct (Barbalet, 1999, 254). Given<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s divisi<strong>on</strong> of instincts into those that “go no further than our own bodies” <strong>and</strong>“those which take effect up<strong>on</strong> the outer world” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g>, 1890, 443), I do not think thatBarbalet’s interpretati<strong>on</strong> is tenable. Unfortunately, the focus of Barbalet’s article isprimarily <strong>on</strong> the relati<strong>on</strong>ship between emoti<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sciousness, <strong>and</strong> this point does notbenefit from an exp<strong>and</strong>ed discussi<strong>on</strong>.27 <str<strong>on</strong>g>James</str<strong>on</strong>g> also includes here spiritual self-seeking as the third category. Becausespiritual self-seeking centres <strong>on</strong> our psychic or religious progress, it will be set aside here.28 Thanks are due to Paul Griffiths, Charles Wolfe, Tobias Cheung, Marga Vicedo,<strong>and</strong> Mark Solovey, for their very helpful comments <strong>and</strong> suggesti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> earlier versi<strong>on</strong>s ofthis paper.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!