13.07.2015 Views

Monographs on teacher.. 9808 v5 - Umeå universitet

Monographs on teacher.. 9808 v5 - Umeå universitet

Monographs on teacher.. 9808 v5 - Umeå universitet

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

LISBETH LUNDAHLTOM POPKEWITZIntroducti<strong>on</strong>Since 1993, a Swedish governmental grant made possible a collaborativearrangement between <strong>Umeå</strong> University and The University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin-Madis<strong>on</strong>.The arrangement was to provide scholarly exchangesbetween the two faculty and graduate students. One aspect of theexchange was to have faculty visit the campus of the other instituti<strong>on</strong>and give seminars related to their <strong>on</strong>going students. Almost thirty facultyfrom the two universities have given such seminars at the otherinstituti<strong>on</strong>s campus and spent at least a week to work with faculty andgraduate students. The exchange has also involved joint symposia at theAmerican Educati<strong>on</strong>al Research Associati<strong>on</strong>´s annual meetings andparticipati<strong>on</strong> in the Thematic Network <strong>on</strong> Teacher Educati<strong>on</strong> in Europe(TNTEE).In 1996-97, the collaborative agreement extended its intellectualinterchange to a seminar for graduate students of the two instituti<strong>on</strong>s.Two seminars were organized to bring together graduate students fromeach of the instituti<strong>on</strong>s. One was held in <strong>Umeå</strong> in December, 1996 andthe sec<strong>on</strong>d <strong>on</strong>e in Madis<strong>on</strong> during April, 1997. The two of us wereresp<strong>on</strong>sible for coordinating the meetings.The purpose of the two seminars was simple. It was to put studentsin a resp<strong>on</strong>sible intellectual positi<strong>on</strong> in which they would have toarticulate the ideas of their research, to make the theoretical positi<strong>on</strong>savailable and understandable, and to maintain a high level of c<strong>on</strong>ceptualand methodological discussi<strong>on</strong>. Our purpose was also to engage in across nati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong> to examine our collective norms of educatingand reading to c<strong>on</strong>sider similarities and differences.The graduate students prepared papers that represented their <strong>on</strong>goingresearch projects. The papers would be written in a manner that wouldallow serious discussi<strong>on</strong> of the ideas and approaches taken in their dissertati<strong>on</strong>program. But the seminar papers were to reflect a differentkind of writing than that of writing a paper for a class. Students weretold that the intent was to prepare a paper that would be eventually7


publishable. The writing needed to be analytically clear but at the sametime, theoretically informed. Further, the paper was to be viewed as <strong>on</strong>eintellectual signative, identifying the problematic from which the studentunderstood the problems of the world of scholarship. In back of allof this, we wanted to make the stakes of the seminar as similar to the stakesthat are c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ted when writing and engaging in intellectual life.The seminar was to provide a forum in which the graduate studentsresearch could be engaged in a small, intellectual circle of peers wherethere was the possibility of an intense discussi<strong>on</strong> about ideas. For thefirst seminar in <strong>Umeå</strong>, five papers were prepared from each of the twoinstituti<strong>on</strong>s that related to the graduate students dissertati<strong>on</strong>s. The paperswere written in English and distributed prior to the seminar.The seminar was scheduled for two and half days, with a relativelysimple organizati<strong>on</strong>. Rather than start with a paper presentati<strong>on</strong>, twostudents were asked to prepare comments and questi<strong>on</strong>s about the paper.These comments began the discussi<strong>on</strong>, followed by the paper writersresp<strong>on</strong>se, and then a general discussi<strong>on</strong> of the problem, methods, resultsand, in some instances, the problematic. The sec<strong>on</strong>d seminar in Madis<strong>on</strong>had the same format. In most instances, the students revised theirfirst papers in ways that were substantive and furthered the dialogueinitiated in the first,<strong>Umeå</strong> seminar.We saw the seminar, from its preparati<strong>on</strong> to the current publicati<strong>on</strong>of the papers, as a potentially important part of intellectual educati<strong>on</strong>of students interested in the scholarship of educati<strong>on</strong> and social science.It is rare that graduate students have the resources available to them toparticipate in a small research seminar such as the <strong>on</strong>e that was held.Further, it is even rarer that such a seminar can be cross-nati<strong>on</strong>al incharacter. We can immediately compare this seminar to the professi<strong>on</strong>almeeting that most of us go to in order to talk about our research. TheAmerican Educati<strong>on</strong>al Research Associati<strong>on</strong>´s annual meeting or theEuropean Educati<strong>on</strong>al Research Associati<strong>on</strong> meetings come to mind.Typically, papers are presented, sometimes with a reactor to frame thepositive and negative of the paper, but with little serious discussi<strong>on</strong>because of the time schedule. One advantage of such meeting for facultyis its invisible colleges, informal meetings with colleagues from otherinstituti<strong>on</strong>s to talk about <strong>on</strong>going work and to (re)establish c<strong>on</strong>tacts.8


For most graduate students, they do not have the c<strong>on</strong>tacts for suchinvisible colleges and the intellectual and communal discussi<strong>on</strong>s that itentails. This seminar provided the time and the organizati<strong>on</strong> to enablethe students to have a sustained and disciplined discussi<strong>on</strong> about theirresearch as well the paradigmatic assumpti<strong>on</strong>s that were made. Thec<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong>s began prior to the meetings as the two groups of studentspaired off to meet and discuss the ideas and organizati<strong>on</strong> of the seminarwith fellow students from another nati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>text.The substantive discussi<strong>on</strong> of the papers at the two symposia produceda reflective process at multiple levels. At a first level was a thinkingabout the different intellectual approaches of the two graduate studentgroups. The Madis<strong>on</strong> group was very much into post-modern socialand historical theories and wrote their papers in ways that reflected thisintellectual traditi<strong>on</strong>.From this first seminar, The University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin-Madis<strong>on</strong>students were part of a weekly seminar called the Wednesday Group. Inadditi<strong>on</strong> to their course work (individual units of study within the Ph.D.program), the students meet each week to read across the disciplinesthat range from political theory, to history and literary theory. It is fromthese readings and c<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong>s that the dissertati<strong>on</strong> topics andmethodologies of the enclosed studies emerged. This emphasis <strong>on</strong> theoryand history is atypical of graduate students within the US but in thisc<strong>on</strong>text provided a way in which the two groups could talk in substantiveways as Swedish literature draw <strong>on</strong> multiple disciplines as well. Wesay this because this particular seminar is not typical of graduate studentsboth in its intellectual closeness and theoretical readings.This intellectual organizati<strong>on</strong> of studies posed a particular gloss tothe c<strong>on</strong>duct of the seminar. The empirical problem of the Madis<strong>on</strong>papers tended to be to relate historical text with theoretical questi<strong>on</strong>s,particularly that of the relati<strong>on</strong> of power and knowledge that is drawnfrom Michel Foucault and feminist theories. The <strong>Umeå</strong> papers, in c<strong>on</strong>trast,tended to move from the empirical problems under investigati<strong>on</strong>and also involved multiple intellectual traditi<strong>on</strong>s. The focus of the initialset of papers from <strong>Umeå</strong> tended to be more c<strong>on</strong>cerned with themoving from the ground up, that is from identifying the ways of handlingand interpreting data than from a discussi<strong>on</strong> of the theoretical9


students seemed to find this less important as they worked together.If we examine the initial discussi<strong>on</strong>, the framing of the seminar inEnglish posed a momentary problem for both groups. For the nativespeakers, it meant that the normal speed of talk and c<strong>on</strong>ceptual andlinguistic nuances related to nati<strong>on</strong>al cultures had to be c<strong>on</strong>sciouslythought about until a flow of communicati<strong>on</strong> could be established. Forthe <strong>Umeå</strong> students, it meant speaking in theoretical languages andcomplexities that were not a first language. At points, frustrati<strong>on</strong> wasexpressed. This frustrati<strong>on</strong> was that when the words came out in English,its seemed so simplistic and c<strong>on</strong>densed the thoughts in a way thatthe Swedish students did not always feel comfortable with. This frustrati<strong>on</strong>,by the end of the first seminar, seemed less of a problem as theflow of ideas and discussi<strong>on</strong> were intense.The differences, we need to stress, were seen by the students as not asgreat as they initially thought. But it required the students to understandthe differences in ways in which students cross-examine, ask questi<strong>on</strong>s,and engage in criticism. Above all the cultural and theoreticaldifferences and the resulting discussi<strong>on</strong>s were seen as highly stimulatingand creative in the subsequent research work of the students.The intellectual dialogue was also helped by the social c<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong>sthat occurred in <strong>Umeå</strong> and Madis<strong>on</strong>. In both seminars, students arrivedearlier than the actual day of the seminar and spent time for sightseeingand meetings in social c<strong>on</strong>texts. While visits to bars and the listeningto music tend not to count in the rec<strong>on</strong>structed logic of science,the social was a part of the intellectual.Then there was the seemingly mundane that was not mundane. Intalking about publishing, for example, we discussed what makes a bookworthwhile to published. How does <strong>on</strong>e go about talking to publishersor sending articles to journals? How do you succeed working towardsdeadlines when there are so many other things to do? These questi<strong>on</strong>swere not <strong>on</strong>ly procedural but also about how ideas come to circulatewithin intellectual communities and the seminar provided a c<strong>on</strong>cretesite to c<strong>on</strong>sider these broader issues of career.11


DAWNENE D HAMMERBERGDisrupted Assumpti<strong>on</strong>s:Social and Historical C<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s of Literacy,Illiteracy, and E-literacyThis paper is meant to disrupt presumptive truths of the present byunsettling c<strong>on</strong>trolling factors of the past which have been understoodas essential to the unfolding of history. As an example, various forms of”technology” have been seen as fundamental to history’s ”development.”However, this paper seeks to disrupt understandings of history whichchr<strong>on</strong>ologically narrate time as a natural progressi<strong>on</strong> through technologicaldevelopments. In additi<strong>on</strong>, the acti<strong>on</strong>s and movements of particularpeople in particular historical moments have also been seen as the basesfor historical change. Yet, this paper disrupts the noti<strong>on</strong> of history as asuccessi<strong>on</strong> of events enacted by human beings who are independentagents outside of time and temporal rati<strong>on</strong>alities. More specifically, thispaper is meant to disrupt present noti<strong>on</strong>s of literacy, illiteracy, andelectr<strong>on</strong>ic literacy (e-literacy) through a history that tells of theassumpti<strong>on</strong>s that have separated and elevated writing and print fromother forms of communicati<strong>on</strong>.In many ways, the realm of c<strong>on</strong>ceivability for disrupting assumpti<strong>on</strong>sof the present comes from a particular reading of the past. Foucault’sgenealogy is a method of reading history which problematizes theassumpti<strong>on</strong>s and generalities that appear as natural or self-evident inthe discourses of the day. While this paper does not attempt to write agenealogy of ”literacy,” it does take as its starting point the facets of agenealogical history which are disruptive to assumpti<strong>on</strong>s of the present1 . Genealogy, as a history of the present, has very real implicati<strong>on</strong>swhen the grounds up<strong>on</strong> which present-day assumpti<strong>on</strong>s are built canbe investigated and appraised for their inclusi<strong>on</strong>ary and exclusi<strong>on</strong>aryprescripti<strong>on</strong>s, their real and imagined promises, their limited and limitingprospects 2 .Through historical examples, this paper problematizes some presentassumpti<strong>on</strong>s about ”literacy.” These assumpti<strong>on</strong>s are grouped together13


which come with an underlying assumpti<strong>on</strong> of cultural and societal”democratizati<strong>on</strong>.”However, this understanding of ”literacy” as necessary and powerfulhas its history, and the ”power” associated with literacy is not anautomatic given. For example, in primary oral cultures, which Ong(1982) defines as ”cultures with no knowledge at all of writing” (p. 1),”literacy” has no power, since there is no knowledge whatsoever of ”it,”or of what it can do. Instead, value and power are attached in thesecultures to accustomed oral traditi<strong>on</strong>s, just as value and power areattached in the dominant cultures of our time to accustomed literatetraditi<strong>on</strong>s. Cultural producti<strong>on</strong> and knowledge circulati<strong>on</strong> can happenboth with and without writing, and in fact, ”literacy” can <strong>on</strong>ly be culturallyproductive when the culture places a value <strong>on</strong> the written word and itsuses. It may be difficult to understand, from a literate standpoint in thepresent, how the ”inventi<strong>on</strong>” of the alphabet had little to no c<strong>on</strong>sequenceto the cultures of the time. And yet, as Whitaker (1996) points out:It is an obvious but sometimes neglected point that, in the eighthcentury, when the alphabet was invented and used for the first time towrite Greek, it had neither a l<strong>on</strong>g traditi<strong>on</strong> of written literature nor anyof the associati<strong>on</strong>s of a dominant culture attaching to it - as it almostalways did when it was used in later periods of history to write otherlanguages. To put it crudely: the first Greek who learned the alphabethad nothing to read. On the c<strong>on</strong>trary, in archaic Greece the culture towhich all the power and prestige bel<strong>on</strong>ged, was the oral <strong>on</strong>e; throughoutmost of this period there was no traditi<strong>on</strong> other than the oral to whichpoets could turn for inspirati<strong>on</strong> and material, nor any audience otherthan listeners to whom they could address themselves. (p. 216)Literacy, in other words, has not always been a necessary form ofcommunicati<strong>on</strong>, and in fact, has been seen as a hindrance to trulycommunicative communicati<strong>on</strong>. Plato’s Socrates, for example, criticizedwriting because it interfered with established habits of communicati<strong>on</strong>,destroying memory rather than enhancing it, and fragmenting socialrelati<strong>on</strong>ships (see Langham, 1994) 4 . Struggles against the technologiesof reading and writing manifested themselves at various points in history,as tensi<strong>on</strong>s between ”literate” ways of being and ”oral” ways ofbeing, as if the two can be separated, divided countries and groups of15


people. For example, Myers (1996) explains that Medieval France”became split between Southern France (le Pays du Droit Écruit), whichacknowledged the written laws of Roman law, and Northern France (lePays du Droit Coutumier), which acknowledged oral societies and localuses” (p. 30). In additi<strong>on</strong>, Myers goes <strong>on</strong> to say that similar tensi<strong>on</strong>sexisted during the Norman invasi<strong>on</strong> (1066-1307) when the ”Normanswanted to eliminate the use of local, oral authenticati<strong>on</strong> of ownershipof property in the England of the Middle Ages because those methodsallowed the local, native Anglo-Sax<strong>on</strong>s of England to c<strong>on</strong>trol their ownproperty through pers<strong>on</strong>al relati<strong>on</strong>s (oaths of witness) and other methodsof local authenticati<strong>on</strong>” (p. 30; see also Street, 1984; Clanchy, 1979).Even later, writing was often viewed as sec<strong>on</strong>dary to oralcommunicati<strong>on</strong>s. For example, during the late 1200s in Europe, writingwas not c<strong>on</strong>sidered ”trustworthy” when compared to face-to-face oralcommunicati<strong>on</strong>s in courts and in daily business interacti<strong>on</strong>s 5 . Even aslate as the Reformati<strong>on</strong> (1600s), in Europe and in the col<strong>on</strong>ies of NorthAmerica, oral c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>s linked people and businesses moreso than”literacy” (see Myers, 1996; Street, 1984; Clanchy, 1979).These tensi<strong>on</strong>s, however, did not occur because of some ”natural”divide between ”literacy” and ”orality.” In fact, how ”literacy” was usedand valued depended up<strong>on</strong> the already established rules of oral traditi<strong>on</strong>s.In other words, understandings of appropriate oral communicati<strong>on</strong>methods and topics were already invested with enough relevance thatthese practices were able to shape understandings of the ”appropriate”methods and topics for reading and writing. For example, when writtenrecords slowly became more customary during the late 1700s in theUnited States, it was due to ”an increasing amount of travel [which]helped to shift social practices from face-to-face interacti<strong>on</strong>s withacquaintances to interacti<strong>on</strong>s with strangers” (Myers, 1996, p. 32), butthese written interacti<strong>on</strong>s were based <strong>on</strong> the preservati<strong>on</strong> of oralagreements. Tensi<strong>on</strong>s between accepted communicati<strong>on</strong>s techniquesoccur when the rules governing how <strong>on</strong>e ”should” communicate in <strong>on</strong>elocal space come in c<strong>on</strong>flict with how <strong>on</strong>e ”should” communicate inanother local space. As writing and print gained leverage in the 1700s,the tensi<strong>on</strong>s between various communicati<strong>on</strong> techniques were lessapparent as print penetrated people’s lives indirectly through an under-16


standing that oral serm<strong>on</strong>s and speeches were written down, and througha general acceptance that writing and print were effective ways to c<strong>on</strong>ductbusiness (see Myers, 1996, p. 33, 39). In other words, the circumstancesof cultures which accept ”literate” techniques are such that various socialneeds are obviously fulfilled through writing and print, not that thetechnologies of writing and print enter the culture <strong>on</strong> vacant grounds 6 .Particular acts of reading and writing, therefore, become viewed as”necessary” in particular social circumstances and discourses of what isworthwhile.The necessity of writing and print for the development of such fieldsas science and history may seem m<strong>on</strong>umental because in many wayswritten records enable a form of thought that allows for a different typeof knowledge formati<strong>on</strong> and organizati<strong>on</strong> (see, for example, MacNevin,1993; Ong, 1982; Clanchy, 1979; Graff, 1979; Diringer, 1948).However, it is not the written records ”themselves,” nor literacy ”itself,”that enable an altered form of thinking. The fact that reading and writinglend themselves well to scientific inquiry or particular tellings of historyhas less to do with ”literacy” than to the social and historical milieuwhich allows certain forms of thought to flourish over others. Sincedefiniti<strong>on</strong>s of ”literacy” are determined by cultural understandings ofwhat is worthwhile, the matters that are recorded in writing, as well asthe c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>al understandings of how written records are to beperceived and read and used and by whom, are also determined bycultural understandings of what is worthwhile. Therefore, it is not”literacy” that is necessary for science or modernity or emancipati<strong>on</strong>.Instead, social and historical circumstances enable shifts in particularversi<strong>on</strong>s of knowledge creati<strong>on</strong> and producti<strong>on</strong>; social and historicalc<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s promote (or repress) changes in patterns and organizati<strong>on</strong>sof thought.For example, a versi<strong>on</strong> of general understanding that enables modernscience involves the distincti<strong>on</strong> between the ”given” world and the”inferences” or ”hypotheses” that are c<strong>on</strong>ceived by human beings. Inpart, this divisi<strong>on</strong> has its roots in the Reformati<strong>on</strong>, when a differentway to think about religious texts emerged (see Ols<strong>on</strong>, 1991). Beforethe Reformati<strong>on</strong>, there was no distincti<strong>on</strong> between what was said in thetext and what was interpreted by the reader. A text’s interpreted meaning17


was seen as exactly the same thing as what the text really said, as in theactual intent of God being taken from scriptural readings. Although Stock(1983) has shown that the ”heretics” of the Middle Ages based their theology<strong>on</strong> a different type of interpretati<strong>on</strong>, Ols<strong>on</strong> (1991) also points out that:...while heretics recognized the interpretati<strong>on</strong>s of the Church asinterpretati<strong>on</strong>s - as man-made - they did not recognize their owninterpretati<strong>on</strong>s as interpretati<strong>on</strong>s. They, like the medieval church, tooktheir interpretati<strong>on</strong>s to be the <strong>on</strong>es intended by God, and hence, theydied, apparently happily, at the stake for them. (p. 153-154)Since ”interpretati<strong>on</strong>” was not viewed as the issue at hand, religiousstruggles were based <strong>on</strong> what God actually meant, as understood intraditi<strong>on</strong>al dogma, as trusted in a larger understanding of text than thegiven/interpreted dichotomy can allow. Even when the Scripture accordingto Aquinas had several layers of meaning in the late 1200s, all meaningswere thought to reside in the given text (see Ols<strong>on</strong>, 1991, p. 154).C<strong>on</strong>victi<strong>on</strong>s and beliefs that may not have been explicitly stated in the textwere nevertheless seen as part of the text and its meaning. It was allintertwined. However, in the first half of the sixteenth century during theReformati<strong>on</strong>, an interpretive break was being made. Ols<strong>on</strong> (1991) writes:The interpretive principle of the Reformati<strong>on</strong>, as expressed forexample in Luther’s attitude to the Scripture, was that Scripture is”aut<strong>on</strong>omous,” it does not need interpretati<strong>on</strong>, it needs reading; it meanswhat it says. All the rest is made up, a product of fancy or traditi<strong>on</strong>. Itwas this distincti<strong>on</strong> between the given and the interpreted that launchedthe Reformati<strong>on</strong> and, a century later, opened ”the book of nature” tomodern scientists.... (p. 154)Ols<strong>on</strong> goes <strong>on</strong> to explain that the metaphor of nature as ”God’s book”that was customary in the Middle Ages took <strong>on</strong> a literal meaning in the1600s when modern scientists such as Galileo, Isaac Newt<strong>on</strong>, and FrancisBac<strong>on</strong> made the distincti<strong>on</strong>s between what was ”given” in the text ofnature (observed facts) and what was theoretically interpreted or inferred.Therefore, according to Ols<strong>on</strong>, ”it may be argued that modern sciencewas the product of applying the distincti<strong>on</strong>s evolved for understandingthe book of Scripture, namely that between the given and the interpreted,to the book of nature” (pp. 154-155). However, the point here is thatthe distincti<strong>on</strong>s between observed facts and imagined hypotheses are18


The rati<strong>on</strong>alizati<strong>on</strong>s for assumpti<strong>on</strong>s such as the <strong>on</strong>es grouped in thisfield are based entirely up<strong>on</strong> the dominant status of cultures which viewthemselves as superior due to the fact that they are ”scientific” or ”modern”or ”democratic.” However, an analysis of the historical and intimaterelati<strong>on</strong>ships between ”orality” and ”literacy” helps to explain thathumankind’s ”development” from ”oral cultures” to ”literate cultures”is not a progressi<strong>on</strong> toward a better way to transmit language, nor a”natural” outgrowth of oral ways of being, but instead an unfolding ofvarious rule-governed c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>s for the circulati<strong>on</strong> of language. Oralcommunicati<strong>on</strong>s never went away or came back; instead, the ways peoplehave been able to communicate orally (and about what, and throughwhat medium), just like the ways people have been able to communicateliterately (and about what and through what medium), have shiftedover time with the discursive practices which name the ”appropriate”means and modes of thought circulati<strong>on</strong>. Once again, genealogy viewsthe history of the ”literate subject” not <strong>on</strong>ly in relati<strong>on</strong> to the technologiesof writing and print, but also in relati<strong>on</strong> to social practices outside ofthe realm of the printed word. Shifts in the definiti<strong>on</strong>s of ”literacy,” inother words, are viewed for their complicity with social and historicalbeliefs and c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>s, not as changes that were ”meant” to happen,nor as changes that will eventually culminate in a final and best way of”being literate.””Orality” is a relatively recent term devised and used by anthropologists,sociologists, and psychologists over the past thirty years as aparallel to ”literacy” (see Ong, 1982, p. 5; Thomas, 1992, p. 6). It ismeant for purposes of analysis and comparis<strong>on</strong> in light of theoverwhelming influence of writing and print 9 . ”Oral” means ”utteredby the mouth” or ”spoken” 10 , and ”orality” is a way of describing, inThomas’ (1992) terms, ”the habit of relying entirely <strong>on</strong> oral communicati<strong>on</strong>rather than written” (p. 6). The term has been useful and positivein the work of Ong and others who mean to dispel the misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>that strictly oral cultures are severely limited in cultural growth andrefinement. It is also meant as a way to describe ”thought and its verbalexpressi<strong>on</strong> in oral culture” as compared to ”thought and expressi<strong>on</strong> inliterature, philosophy and science, and even in oral discourse am<strong>on</strong>gliterates, [which] are not directly native to human existence as such but20


have come into being because of the resources which the technology ofwriting makes available to human c<strong>on</strong>sciousness” (Ong, 1982, p. 1).Yet the term ”orality” can also serve to separate two forms of culturalproducti<strong>on</strong> which are deeply interwoven.When it is presumed that there has been a natural and progressivedevelopment in communicati<strong>on</strong> techniques from the oral to the writtento the printed to the electr<strong>on</strong>ic, the ”differences” between ”orality” and”literacy” that appear in the ”electr<strong>on</strong>ic age” manifest themselves in termsdefined <strong>on</strong> ”literate” grounds which are already presumed to be superior.On this terrain, where writing and print are viewed as necessary forfields of thought such as science, philosophy, and history 11 , where”literacy” is equated with ”civilizati<strong>on</strong>” and ”progress,” it is easy to(mis)understand writing, print, and electr<strong>on</strong>ic communicati<strong>on</strong>s as thetools which have brought about levels of knowledge that are ”higher” or”better” than the wisdom (often viewed as folky 12 ) available in primaryoral cultures 13 . However, it should be remembered that the separati<strong>on</strong>of ”literacy” from ”orality” <strong>on</strong>ly occurs <strong>on</strong> a terrain where ”literacy” isalready overwhelmingly dominant. On this terrain, ”literacy” can beoutlined <strong>on</strong> the rooftops and garden penthouses of a civilized skyline,or electrified in the gated communities of technological advancements,or perpetuated in the ivory towers of scholarship and intellectual racism 14 ,while the c<strong>on</strong>tours of ”primary orality” can barely be glimpsed from a”literate” perspective and most often must be imagined, which makesthem look identical to the c<strong>on</strong>tours of ”illiteracy” 15 .Pattanayak (1991) depicts the c<strong>on</strong>tours represented in particular discoursessurrounding ”literacy” and its ”opposite” by writing: ”Illiteracyis grouped with poverty, malnutriti<strong>on</strong>, lack of educati<strong>on</strong>, and healthcare, while literacy is often equated with growth of productivity, childcare, and the advance of civilizati<strong>on</strong>” (p. 105). However, this c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>of literacy/illiteracy is not without its history, and is completely tiedwith relati<strong>on</strong>s of power. If we were to imagine the terrains of ”primaryorality,” we would have to imagine a land where ”illiteracy” is not aproblem, not an issue by any means. ”Orality,” when it is truly ”primary,”has no visi<strong>on</strong>s of ”literacy” or ”illiteracy,” since the centuries of intellectual”growth” associated with the techniques of writing are not at allsignificant to cultures with no knowledge whatsoever of writing. ”The21


introducti<strong>on</strong> of writing,” writes Hoyles (1977), ”made illiteratesinevitable” (p. 23). However, in our imaginati<strong>on</strong>s, we have to w<strong>on</strong>derhow ”inevitable” the ”illiterates” could have possibly been in cultureswho had been operating for centuries without writing. These cultureslived in what we would term ”illiterate” envir<strong>on</strong>ments, but they didn’tknow these were faulty and inferior envir<strong>on</strong>ments, because they weren’t.There was nothing to be inferior to.When writing was ”invented” around 3100 B. C., probably by theSumerians, with the development of systems for writing occurring sometimebetween 3100-1599 B.C. (MacNevin, 1993; Schmandt-Besserat,1988; Graff, 1987; Diringer, 1948), it was tied directly to spoken ideas,but was not meant to represent all spoken ideas. Writing began withpictures and direct representati<strong>on</strong>, often ic<strong>on</strong>ographic, and then movedto more mnem<strong>on</strong>ic mechanisms which carried the meanings of wholeideas behind the symbol. The representati<strong>on</strong> of ideas then shifted intorepresentati<strong>on</strong>s of syllables am<strong>on</strong>g the Sumerians, Babyl<strong>on</strong>ians, Assyrians,Persians, Aztecs, Mayans, Chinese, Hittites, Egyptians, as well the Indiansystems of writing which greatly influenced South East Asian forms(MacNevin, 1993; Kaestle, 1988; Harris, 1986; Rahi, 1977; Carpenter,1973; Gelb, 1952; Diringer, 1948). Yet early in this history of literacy 16 ,knowledge of hieroglyphics or ic<strong>on</strong>ographs was something available <strong>on</strong>lyto scribal priests and the elite few with whom they shared this tool(MacNevin, 1993, pp. 12-15). As an example, the word ”hieroglyphics”refers in Greek to ”sacred or priestly carvings”, and it was believed thatthe <strong>on</strong>ly way to read the symbols was to have access to the mysticalknowledge of the priests. In spite of this seemingly limited access, it shouldnot be interpreted as a scribal scheme, as Lucas (1972) points out:The m<strong>on</strong>opolistic character of early schooling was not the c<strong>on</strong>sciousresult of a scribal c<strong>on</strong>spiracy to enlist educati<strong>on</strong> for the preservati<strong>on</strong> ofclass privilege. Rather, it was a natural outgrowth of many forces shapingSumerian, Babyl<strong>on</strong>ian, Assyrian and Egyptian life. Because these cultureswere extremely c<strong>on</strong>servative, absolutist, and sancti<strong>on</strong>ed by a highlyauthoritarian ideology, schools also assumed such characteristics. (p. 45)The fact that written knowledge was the property of a few andc<strong>on</strong>veyed to others through oral communicati<strong>on</strong>s is not indicative ofthe ”power” of writing in its technological ”growth,” but instead,22


indicative of the accepted power structures and the dominant modes ofcommunicati<strong>on</strong> in place at the time.The representati<strong>on</strong> of sound/syllables ultimately led to the ”inventi<strong>on</strong>”of alphabetic systems to represent more discrete sounds. The Greek alphabet,”invented” sometime around 650-550 B.C. (MacNevin, 1993;Kaestle, 1988; Graff, 1987; Havelock, 1971), added vowels to 17 andborrowed 19 letters from the (often forgotten) Phoenician alphabet,which was probably the first ”c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal” alphabet (Rahi, 1977, p. 14& 16). However, as great as the Greek alphabet may have been as the”foundati<strong>on</strong>” to all European alphabets in use today (Diringer, 1948),its ”development” and spread had little to do with technological determinismor a ”natural” development in communicati<strong>on</strong> technologies,since ”[t]he script and the very principles of the alphabet were adoptedfrom the Ph<strong>on</strong>ecians of the Levantine coast, with whom Greeks werenow increasingly in c<strong>on</strong>tact” (Thomas, 1992, p. 53). In fact, the alphabetwas not viewed as an essential tool for the general Greek publicright away, as its uses were for commercial services in line with thePh<strong>on</strong>ecians (Thomas, 1992, p. 56), or for poetic purposes (Thomas,1992, p. 57), or ”restricted to a small elite and limited to a few functi<strong>on</strong>s,chiefly religi<strong>on</strong>” (Kaestle, 1988, p. 98). Yet even during this time ofGreek alphabetic expansi<strong>on</strong>, Thomas (1992) points out that ”most Greekliterature was meant to be heard or even sung - thus transmitted orally- and there was a str<strong>on</strong>g current of distaste for the written word evenam<strong>on</strong>g the highly literate: written documents were not c<strong>on</strong>sideredadequate proof by themselves in legal c<strong>on</strong>texts till the sec<strong>on</strong>d half of thefourth century BC” (p. 3).When the first schools in Greece were being formed between 500and 400 B.C., students learned to ”read” (or recite) by heart (Thomas,1992, p. 92) because the ability to memorize and orally recite oral poetryand great philosophical works was of greatest value at the time. As thetools of reading and writing became more wide-spread with the adventof Greek city-states, members of the society were taught to be literatefor specific political and civic functi<strong>on</strong>s such as ”moral c<strong>on</strong>duct, respectfor social order, and participant citizenship” (Graff, 1987, p. 28).Meanwhile, the Greek alphabet was being transferred to the Romansthrough an Etruscan influence (Diringer, 1948, p. 535), and the Latin23


potent: to be ”illiterate” is not to be n<strong>on</strong>human, n<strong>on</strong>intelligent oruncivilized 18 . If, throughout time, illiteracy has been variously equatedwith a savagery or a deficiency or a disease which stands in the way ofprogress, it has not been because these are ”natural” characteristics ofwhat it means to be ”illiterate.” Rather, the ever-shifting noti<strong>on</strong>s of”literacy” or ”illiteracy” are created and defined through mechanisms ofpower that do not exist outside of social and historical relati<strong>on</strong>s.Technological advancements are never merely introduced into a culture,whether or not that culture is primarily ”oral” or already highly ”literate.”Instead, there are specific cultural c<strong>on</strong>texts which always shapehow the technologies of ”literacy” are perceived and how (if at all) theywill fit into the established customs related to the producti<strong>on</strong> andcirculati<strong>on</strong> of thought. Just as the ”electr<strong>on</strong>ic age” (as we know it) dependsup<strong>on</strong> writing and print, the historically c<strong>on</strong>tingent technologies of the”literate” are dependent up<strong>on</strong> tremendously complex interrelati<strong>on</strong>sinvolving oral communicati<strong>on</strong>s.Seemingly ”progressive” shifts in the technologies of ”literacy” appearat moments when whole new technologies are ”invented,” like systemsof writing, or the alphabet, or the printing press, or e-mail. Some of theways in which people have been able to organize thought and knowledgemay not have been thinkable without writing or print or electr<strong>on</strong>icnote passing, and yet, the ways in which people have organized thoughtand knowledge have varied greatly over time even when the sametechnology (writing) was being used. For example, during a time whencultural dialects were seen as a threat to nati<strong>on</strong>al cohesi<strong>on</strong> (the end ofthe eighteenth century in the United States), instructi<strong>on</strong> in ”literacy”involved having students place their toes <strong>on</strong> straight lines (where thesaying, ”toe the line,” came from) while they stuck out and wiggledtheir t<strong>on</strong>gues (see Myers, 1996, pp. 64-65) 19 . This type of ”literacy” wasvalued because it included the appropriate pr<strong>on</strong>unciati<strong>on</strong> of writtenwords and phrases, whereas the kind of ”literacy” valued in another era(say right now) means that students work together in small groups tocompose daily news stories, during a time when businesses areencouraging ”cooperative teaming.” In additi<strong>on</strong>, the type of ”literate”knowledge involved in the development of electr<strong>on</strong>ic technologies wasvalued for its possibilities of better communicati<strong>on</strong> during the first World25


War. These variati<strong>on</strong>s in the values and uses of ”literacy” are notdependent up<strong>on</strong> what literacy ”is,” but instead <strong>on</strong> the demands of socialand historical circumstances. Changes in the meanings and uses of”literacy” shift according to transformati<strong>on</strong>s in the discursive practiceswhich delineate how knowledge is ”best” circulated, valorized, attributed,and appropriated 20 .Therefore, communicati<strong>on</strong> techniques do not merely develop in aprogressive successi<strong>on</strong> from worse to better, but instead, the ways inwhich human beings communicate vary over time due to struggles overpurpose/pedagogies/procedures. This is not a matter of right and wr<strong>on</strong>g,but a matter of history and power. While it is bey<strong>on</strong>d the scope of thispaper to debate whether or not ”advancements” in communicati<strong>on</strong>techniques could have happened (or been ”discovered”) without readingand writing, it is clear that ”literacy,” by itself, did not progressively”develop” <strong>on</strong> its own in a technologically determined dance. This isbecause ”literacy” can not exist ”by itself” outside of cultural and historicalrelati<strong>on</strong>s of power. The ”necessity” of reading and writing fortechnological ”progress” is <strong>on</strong>ly as ”necessary” as cultural and historicalcircumstances will allow.Assumpti<strong>on</strong> Number Three: Literacyand Educati<strong>on</strong>al Understandings of Text, Author, ReaderThe definiti<strong>on</strong> of ”text” entails the printed word. ”Texts” aresomething from which to extract the author’s meaning, and while areader’s interpretati<strong>on</strong> is certainly an interest of educati<strong>on</strong>, there is adivisi<strong>on</strong> between what is actually said, or ”given,” in the text, andthe possible interpretati<strong>on</strong>s a reader can make of it. Educati<strong>on</strong>ally,therefore, we have the resp<strong>on</strong>sibility to teach children how to getmeaning from a text by reading, and how to put meaning into atext by writing. There are particular educati<strong>on</strong>al devices andmaterials regarding the instructi<strong>on</strong> of reading and writing that areessential for <strong>teacher</strong>s to teach and students to learn. Electr<strong>on</strong>ictechnologies would not have come about without literacy; however,many forms of electr<strong>on</strong>ic technologies have nothing to do with26


literacy per se. In fact, ”e-literacies” which deal with n<strong>on</strong>-print(televisi<strong>on</strong>, mass media, hypermedia, virtual reality) may be posinga serious threat to the future of literate cultures and literacy itself.”Text” is <strong>on</strong>e of those c<strong>on</strong>cepts that didn’t exist before writing and print.However, like any c<strong>on</strong>cept, its definiti<strong>on</strong> is subject to change over timeand within particular c<strong>on</strong>texts of thinkability. For example, in certainc<strong>on</strong>texts ”text” has been expanded to include more than the printedword. When ”literates” began to analyze ”oral” cultures, both past andpresent, a re-defined ”text” which has nothing to do with the printedword became usable and thinkable as a way to validate oral culturaltraditi<strong>on</strong>s and producti<strong>on</strong>s. While ”oral text” may seem (to some) likean oxymor<strong>on</strong>, to others, it has stood as a useful way to compare andanalyze language structures and patterns of thought circulati<strong>on</strong>. In additi<strong>on</strong>,and quite recently, the meaning of ”text” is beginning to undergoa wider change in educati<strong>on</strong>al fields, as dem<strong>on</strong>strated by the newlyreleased Standards for the English Language Arts (NCTE & IRA, 1996).In it, text ”refer[s] not <strong>on</strong>ly to printed texts, but also to spoken language,graphics, and technological communicati<strong>on</strong>s”; language ”encompassesvisual communicati<strong>on</strong> in additi<strong>on</strong> to spoken and written forms ofexpressi<strong>on</strong>”; and reading ”refers to listening and viewing in additi<strong>on</strong> toprint-oriented reading.” However, U.S. Nati<strong>on</strong>al Standards or not, thisnew meaning of ”text” is not comm<strong>on</strong>place in U.S. classrooms.Educati<strong>on</strong>ally, ”text” still refers to, for the most part, that which isprinted: text where the author is still in c<strong>on</strong>trol of meaning, text that isnecessarily linear in its flow from beginning to end, text where the reader’srole is to decipher (and possibly use) the meaning. Assessment of astudent’s reading ability revolves around the general comprehensi<strong>on</strong> ofthe author’s meaning, or the particular knowledge of word recogniti<strong>on</strong>and decoding skills used to ”get” meaning from the text.Meanwhile, wider meanings of ”text” which have been talked aboutby thinkers such as Bakhtin 21 , Barthes 22 , Derrida 23 , and Foucault 24 , andwhich are gaining momentum in scholarly circles and technologicalcircuits, have not yet made it to public school classrooms either. Theremay be a reas<strong>on</strong> why: the prospects might look just plain silly in theclassrooms we know and aloofly like. This is, after all, the here-and-27


now, completely equipped with the inertias of the that-which-isthinkable-just-now.It doesn’t fit into the standard curriculum to requirethat students analyze their own interpretati<strong>on</strong>s in terms of a network ofc<strong>on</strong>tingencies, as the theorists menti<strong>on</strong>ed above might advise. The<strong>teacher</strong>-as-lecturer-using-the-English-of-yesteryear doesn’t lend herselfwell to a c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> of the plurality of texts formed at the intersecti<strong>on</strong>of several c<strong>on</strong>sciousnesses. The materials available - the things that wecall ”texts” - do not come embedded in auditory and visual communicati<strong>on</strong>experiences, at least not in class sizes of thirty.The comm<strong>on</strong> understandings of text, author, and reader are based inpart <strong>on</strong> the structures of language in print. There is a given (or fixed)meaning to be discovered in the text, someplace between the beginningand the end; there is the need for the antecedents of c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s to lineup in a coherent order determined by the established customs of”appropriate” reas<strong>on</strong>ing. What is said and the way it is said still need toc<strong>on</strong>form to the c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>s of language in print, which is to say languagec<strong>on</strong>tained within a definitive piece, the word <strong>on</strong> the page, the author incharge. When the author is in charge, the author’s meaning is central tointerpretati<strong>on</strong>. A reader’s interpretati<strong>on</strong> is in jeopardy of being ”wr<strong>on</strong>g”when it departs the ”grounded” text because many of the words <strong>on</strong> thepage still have particular references which do not permit completely freeinterpretati<strong>on</strong>. It is a chicken that crossed the road, for example, not a cowor a goat. Text is understood as a fairly aut<strong>on</strong>omous entity in this viewbecause it holds a distinct meaning (the author’s) for the reader to ”get.”Yet ”text” has not always been so independent, as evidenced in ancientGreek documents which left a lot unsaid, relying instead <strong>on</strong> the rememberedand presupposed knowledge of the reader (Thomas, 1992, p. 76). And”text” may not always be thought of in its linear, self-c<strong>on</strong>tained, and printedsense, with the types of ”texts” available through electr<strong>on</strong>ic communicati<strong>on</strong>s,such as hypertext or virtual reality 25 . The point is that fluctuati<strong>on</strong>s in thecomm<strong>on</strong>ly understood definiti<strong>on</strong>s of text, author, or reader are related tofluctuati<strong>on</strong>s in discursive practices, transformati<strong>on</strong>s which are linked tolarger shifts in understandings that extend bey<strong>on</strong>d any new definiti<strong>on</strong>s of”text” or any new definiti<strong>on</strong>s of what literacy ”is.” Myers (1996) asks:Why does a society decide to change its mind about its literacypractices? Societies do not develop something called intelligence or28


English teaching and then invent new standards of literacy from thepossibilities of that intelligence or English teaching. Instead, a standardof literacy - or what we call a skill - is the result of an interacti<strong>on</strong> am<strong>on</strong>gsuch variables as urbanizati<strong>on</strong> (Lerner 1958), the political interacti<strong>on</strong>sof Protestantism and capitalism (Tyack 1974), the religious beliefs ofCalvinism (Lockridge 1974), secularism (Clanchy 1979), technologylike the printing press (Eisenstein 1979), mass media (Schramm andRuggels 1967), fertility rates (Vinovskis 1981), and a failing and/orgrowing ec<strong>on</strong>omy (Reich 1992). (Myers, 1996, p. 5)However, all of these ”variables” that help to define a standard ofliteracy can also be described as manifestati<strong>on</strong>s of the discursive practicesof the time. If a society thinks it has ”decide[d] to change its mindabout its literacy practices,” it is not without relati<strong>on</strong>s of power alreadyestablished in discursive practices which c<strong>on</strong>stitute taken-for-granteddiscourses of truth 26 . Any changes in the definiti<strong>on</strong> of ”literacy” andany corresp<strong>on</strong>ding instituti<strong>on</strong>al changes in pedagogy do not occur assimply as a ”change in the mind” might imply.The comp<strong>on</strong>ents that help to define a standard of ”literacy” need tobe invested with relevance before whole systems of thought can be shifted,while the noti<strong>on</strong> of ”relevance” is tied not to fertility rates, nor to thepolitical interacti<strong>on</strong>s between Protestantism and capitalism, but rather,and more c<strong>on</strong>sistently, to the discursive practices of the time. This isnot to say that factors such as fertility rates, politics, religious beliefs, orthe printing press have nothing to do with changes in the definiti<strong>on</strong> of”literacy,” but rather, it is to say that factors which are seen as importantin the transformati<strong>on</strong> of ”literacy” are <strong>on</strong>ly valued as c<strong>on</strong>sequentialthrough discursive practices that validate particular perspectives anddisregard others.If the comm<strong>on</strong>ly understood meaning of ”text” expands to includesuch ideas as ”intertextuality,” ”multivocality,” or the ”de-centering” ofa singular author (see, for example, Landow, 1992, pp. 10-13), thisshift will not occur without transformati<strong>on</strong>s in the discursive practicesthat set forth appropriate modes of thought circulati<strong>on</strong>, valorizati<strong>on</strong>,attributi<strong>on</strong>, and appropriati<strong>on</strong>. If the definiti<strong>on</strong> of ”literacy” is currentlyin a state of transiti<strong>on</strong> to include the negotiati<strong>on</strong> of multiple perspectivesand the interpretati<strong>on</strong> of various texts, the factors of importance may29


e a growth in informati<strong>on</strong>al services coupled with wider internati<strong>on</strong>alrelati<strong>on</strong>s 27 . The discursive practices surrounding the tools of ”literacy”(electr<strong>on</strong>ic or otherwise) establish understandings of what text ”is,” whichtexts are more valuable, who has the authority to decide, and what we’resupposed to do with the text in order to be called ”literate,” if we’recalled ”literate” at all. In other words, what it could mean to be ”literate”within the framework of a broadened definiti<strong>on</strong> of ”text” will bedependent up<strong>on</strong> the ”accepted” and valued producti<strong>on</strong>s of a culture,what those producti<strong>on</strong>s require of the ”literate,” and whether thoseproducti<strong>on</strong>s incorporate the wide-spread use of the materials whichenlarge the meaning of text.In the ”electr<strong>on</strong>ic age,” with teleph<strong>on</strong>es, televisi<strong>on</strong>s, movies, filmstrips,hypermedia, and virtual reality (for example), we are living in anage of ”sec<strong>on</strong>dary orality” which depends up<strong>on</strong> writing and print for itsexistence (see Ong, 1982, p. 3). This can mean anything from the factthat oral televisi<strong>on</strong> scripts are written down to the fact that writing wasnecessary for the inventi<strong>on</strong> of the teleph<strong>on</strong>e, <strong>on</strong> which we communicateorally. The use of many of these electr<strong>on</strong>ic communicati<strong>on</strong> devices (televisi<strong>on</strong>,teleph<strong>on</strong>e, radio) is indeed wide-spread. However, the”sec<strong>on</strong>dary” porti<strong>on</strong> of televisi<strong>on</strong>s and teleph<strong>on</strong>es and hypermedia andvirtual reality can also mean that the acts of using these technologieshave little to do with ”literacy” as we understand it today, if we understandit to mean reading or writing a printed text. If writing and print arenot always immediately apparent in the stylistic communicati<strong>on</strong> ofthoughts through sound, the comm<strong>on</strong> understandings of the day maynot be apt to place these acti<strong>on</strong>s within the realm of ”literate”communicati<strong>on</strong>. When n<strong>on</strong>-print electr<strong>on</strong>ic technologies are viewed asn<strong>on</strong>-literate, they are put in a positi<strong>on</strong> outside of ”true” educati<strong>on</strong>alvalue. They are seen as dem<strong>on</strong>strati<strong>on</strong>al extras, appreciated for theirentertainment value, but it’s time to get back to work, boys and girls.Because the factors which change definiti<strong>on</strong>s and tools of ”literacy”do not exist outside of temporarily static definiti<strong>on</strong>s of what counts asimportant, what counts as truth, what counts as valuable knowledge,we are not in the positi<strong>on</strong> to know whether or not communicatingthrough electr<strong>on</strong>ic (including n<strong>on</strong>-print) means will be a focus of”literacy” educati<strong>on</strong>. We are not in the positi<strong>on</strong> to know where things30


may go or what will be the end, since we are not in the positi<strong>on</strong> to maketruth and knowledge ”up.” However, through the active disrupti<strong>on</strong> ofcomm<strong>on</strong> assumpti<strong>on</strong>s surrounding ”literacy,” we could potentially bein a positi<strong>on</strong> to see that there are alternate possibilities.Alternate PossibilitiesIf you are reading this with the technologies of a late twentieth centuryWestern ”literate” 28 , your percepti<strong>on</strong>s of this paper are driven in part byan attempt to tweeze out some kind of knowledge from a text you maynever have seen before; you are silently analyzing its parts, its selfc<strong>on</strong>tainedstructure, its syntax, its semantics, as your unvoiced innervoicegoes about decoding its meaning; you have objectified it in such away that the intelligent producti<strong>on</strong>s transpiring in your mind areoccurring <strong>on</strong> a completely individualized level; you may even have somewell-tuned academic skills for recording or storing any informati<strong>on</strong> thatyour thoughts have brought about.Yet, this has not always been the way that people have ”read” a text.What it means to read, and to read well, as history has shown, iscompletely dependent <strong>on</strong> a culture and a time, if it’s even an issue ofimportance at all. People and cultures, in other words, do not devise ameaning for ”literacy” and then simply ”do” it. The discursive practicesof the time determine what <strong>on</strong>e is to ”do” when <strong>on</strong>e is ”being literate,”and this in turn determines the range of possible interpretati<strong>on</strong>s andpercepti<strong>on</strong>s of whatever is being ”read.”This having been said, the discursive practices of our time may bechanging in such a way that we can imagine a form of ”literacy” whichincludes more than accepting the ”text” as a fixed or given word, morethan accepting writing and print as the superior mode of knowledgecirculati<strong>on</strong>, more than accepting the authority of the author. For example,with electr<strong>on</strong>ic communicati<strong>on</strong>s, we can begin to imagine howpercepti<strong>on</strong>s of ”text” and ”authorship” and ”readership” may be different.When we are able to think of ”text” differently, of ”readership” and”authorship” differently, then the possibilities for the types of knowledgeswhich are valued begin to look different too. Landow (1993) exploresthis line of thinking in relati<strong>on</strong> to an altered understanding of ”text”:31


One tends to think of text from within the positi<strong>on</strong> of the lexia underc<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>. Accustomed to reading pages of print <strong>on</strong> paper, <strong>on</strong>e tendsto c<strong>on</strong>ceive of text from the vantage point of the reader experiencingthat page or passage, and that porti<strong>on</strong> of text assumes a centrality.Hypertext, however, makes such assumpti<strong>on</strong>s of centrality fundamentallyproblematic. . . . Hypertext similarly emphasizes that the marginal hasas much to offer as does the central, in part because hypertext does not<strong>on</strong>ly redefine the central by refusing to grant centrality to anything, toany lexia, for more than the time a gaze rests up<strong>on</strong> it. In hypertext,centrality, like beauty and relevance, resides in the mind of the beholder.(pp. 69-70)In additi<strong>on</strong>, the roles of ”author” and ”reader” in many forms ofelectr<strong>on</strong>ic communicati<strong>on</strong>s are fundamentally rec<strong>on</strong>figured. Withhypertextual c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong>s, ”authorial” c<strong>on</strong>trol is shifted a degree ortwo to the reader, who gets ”to choose his or her way through themetatext, to annotate text written by others, and to create links betweendocuments written by others” (Landow, 1993, p. 71). In <strong>on</strong>-line multimediaexperiences, readers are not c<strong>on</strong>fined to a limited realm of informati<strong>on</strong>such as found in books or <strong>on</strong> hypertextual CD-ROMS, butinstead, the reader can move in an array of visual images and sound,text and n<strong>on</strong>-text, choosing between generalities and specifics presentedby numerous authors and artists. As another example, the c<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong>swhich take place through written <strong>on</strong>-line c<strong>on</strong>ferencing, such as experiencedthrough Multiple-User Dimensi<strong>on</strong>s (MUDs) or MOOs (MUD ObjectOriented), occur in real time and <strong>on</strong> the highly present terrain of thecomputer screen, a place that seems ”real” as the c<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong> is occurring.The lines between author and reader are transparent here since <strong>on</strong>e cantake <strong>on</strong> both identities as the c<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong>, or ”text,” transpires accordingto group interacti<strong>on</strong>, not a singular authority. In additi<strong>on</strong>, digitaltechnologies allow for audiences of <strong>on</strong>e, where the ”reader” can order upextremely pers<strong>on</strong>alized informati<strong>on</strong> (see, for example, Negrop<strong>on</strong>te, 1995);and virtual reality programs make the distincti<strong>on</strong> between author and readerinvisible as the ”reader” (who may not have a written text anywherenearby) ”writes” the acti<strong>on</strong>s and progressi<strong>on</strong>s of the experienced ”text.”When the minds of the literates are informed by discursive practicesthat allow for rec<strong>on</strong>figured versi<strong>on</strong>s of text, author, and reader, there are32


a variety of possible ways to perceive the act of ”being literate.” A relatedset of assumpti<strong>on</strong>s emerges. For example, to negotiate within this understandingof text could require a kind of c<strong>on</strong>fidence and a sense of self,coupled with an ability to take risks (see Myers, 1996, chapter 8). Sincethe uses of ”literacy” in the electr<strong>on</strong>ic circulati<strong>on</strong> and producti<strong>on</strong> ofknowledge are perceived (at this point in time) to be self-m<strong>on</strong>itoredand self-determined, it is possible that the ”literate subject” may beassumed to be an aut<strong>on</strong>omous agent of knowledge producti<strong>on</strong>. This”literate subject” would be <strong>on</strong>e who lives in the intertextuality of languageand interpretati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>on</strong>e who is c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ted by various paths or ”choices”in the producti<strong>on</strong> of knowledge (see, for example, Landow, 1992; Bolter,1991).In line with the assumpti<strong>on</strong> that ”literacy” is a form of ”power,” this”e-literate” subject might be imagined to have a type of individual”power” in choosing ”self-determined” paths of learning and textualexplorati<strong>on</strong> 33 . When the educati<strong>on</strong>al possibilities of a ”literacy” definedin electr<strong>on</strong>ic circumstances include the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of a subject who isassumed to be ”aut<strong>on</strong>omous” with electr<strong>on</strong>ic media, the ”e-literate”subject may also take the form of an ”individual” who is not <strong>on</strong>ly ”selfdetermined,”but also ”self-aware” of his or her own role in the creati<strong>on</strong>of meaning. This subject could possibly be skillful at interrogatingreceived representati<strong>on</strong>s, able to read symptomatically 34 in an increasinglyglobal field, and capable of analyzing positi<strong>on</strong>s and interpretati<strong>on</strong>sthrough the critique of accepted histories.Lest this seems too speculative in the inertias and c<strong>on</strong>straints of thepresent time, these possibilities for ”e-literacies” are not too far off fromwhat the Standards for the English Language Arts (1996) are proposing.Although the use of electr<strong>on</strong>ic communicati<strong>on</strong>s is not necessary for thisversi<strong>on</strong> of ”literacy,” which Myers (1996) calls ”translati<strong>on</strong> literacy,” itstill involves the ”[i]nterpretati<strong>on</strong> of many texts, producing multipletranslati<strong>on</strong>s of many different kinds of texts in many sign systems” (p.57). In numerous classrooms all over the United States 35 , <strong>teacher</strong>s arealready preparing students to find their ways <strong>on</strong> their own, to be risktakersand metacognitive thinkers, to questi<strong>on</strong> themselves at every point,by asking students to keep (for example) journals of the problems andhighlights they encounter while reading, or by encouraging students to33


guess and struggle and try various reading strategies when coming acrossunknown words, or by having students negotiate mathematics textsthrough trial and error. The perceived power of a self-sufficient thinkerand the perceived necessity for comfort in ambiguity and uncertainty asa way of learning to take risks are already an everyday part of manystudents’ schooling. Perhaps we are not thinking about it in terms of ”eliteracy,”which just goes to show that the technology is not determiningwhat we do with it, but if and when ”e-literacies” are perceived to benecessary in comm<strong>on</strong> educati<strong>on</strong>al understanding, then the ”e-literate”subject will already be waiting. This is because ways of thinking aboutand defining the ”literate subject” (”e” or otherwise) do not ”enter”society <strong>on</strong> vacant grounds.Where previously unthinkable, it is now possible (because of the historicalc<strong>on</strong>texts of thinkability, not because of some progressive history)to c<strong>on</strong>sider and play with the idea that spoken and visual expressi<strong>on</strong>scan be within the realm of ”text.” Moreover, it is possible to think of”text” as a c<strong>on</strong>glomerati<strong>on</strong> of ideas, a c<strong>on</strong>glomerati<strong>on</strong> of beginningsand middles and ends, which are interwoven in a web of historicallyc<strong>on</strong>structed thought. It is possible to think of numerous entrances toand exits from this text, where c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>s to a myriad of possibledirecti<strong>on</strong>s open up assorted lines of argumentati<strong>on</strong> and investigativestudy. It is possible to think of ”readings” as filtered through numerousand disparate historically c<strong>on</strong>textualized moments of interpretati<strong>on</strong>,where no reader is a deserted recluse <strong>on</strong> an isolated author’s island.Indeed, the words and/or ideas may unfold <strong>on</strong> the page or the screen orthe Virtual Boy strapped to your head in a pattern that resembles resoluti<strong>on</strong>,but it is now possible to understand their meaning as dependentup<strong>on</strong> various, perhaps unforeseen, social and historical c<strong>on</strong>texts.Irresolute. There is no beginning, middle, and end to a ”text” that isrec<strong>on</strong>figured to include a plurality that goes bey<strong>on</strong>d the writer’s ”exact”meaning, as the illusi<strong>on</strong>s of narrative structure, grammar, and logic arereplaced by the infinity of language and its infinite c<strong>on</strong>notati<strong>on</strong>s.Less reverence for print; no beginning, no middle, no end; lessauthority for the author; no natural evoluti<strong>on</strong>s. Yet let’s not forget thatliteracies will always be embedded in discursive practices and presumedassumpti<strong>on</strong>s. These alternate possibilities are <strong>on</strong>ly as alternative as34


imaginati<strong>on</strong> will allow. ”Possibilities” do not reveal themselves indereistic 32 vacuums someplace outside of time. It must be rememberedthat the ”literate subject” is always a social and historical c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>defined by social and historical c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>s. This is because whateverwe ”do” (or d<strong>on</strong>’t do or can’t do or w<strong>on</strong>’t do) is based up<strong>on</strong> the discursivepractices embedded in our everyday understandings of the world inwhich we live: our understandings of the ordinary operati<strong>on</strong>s of thatworld, our percepti<strong>on</strong>s of the chances and opportunities we see forchanging that world, the daily possibilities of what we think we aresupposed to do in that world, how we see that very world itself. Anytheories or hopes for possibilities (in educati<strong>on</strong>, in life) are interwovenwith the ”reality” of local and social experiences, which in turn areinterwoven with larger historical movements in the history of thoughtitself: what is thinkable in a given time and place, and for what historicallyc<strong>on</strong>tingent purposes.It is important to remember that the possibilities of significance forthe future have not yet been outlined. But there may be allusive forms:the possibilities involved in multi-level interpretati<strong>on</strong>, or the possibilitiesinvolved in displacing the center by clicking <strong>on</strong> the margins, or thepossibilities of creating new centralities through explorati<strong>on</strong>s inintertextuality, or the possibilities of interrogating representati<strong>on</strong>s fromthe standpoint of unheard voices. Each historical c<strong>on</strong>text yields roomfor <strong>on</strong>ly certain possibilities to flourish and expand, as each representati<strong>on</strong>of ”literate behavior” survives for particular social and historicalreas<strong>on</strong>s. Infused with power, possible meanings of ”literacy” take shape,and these meanings have a life and a future, a basis for furtherinterpretati<strong>on</strong>s and additi<strong>on</strong>al possibilities, <strong>on</strong>ly when the accepted rulesof understanding, <strong>on</strong>ce again tied to the moment, are fulfilled. Limitedand limiting, the accepted rules of understanding are the assumpti<strong>on</strong>sof the time, which regulate the possibilities of significance. These arethe assumpti<strong>on</strong>s to be disrupted.35


Notes1. As a method of reading history, genealogies situate the discursive practices which areendemic to historically standard assumpti<strong>on</strong>s, analyzing how those assumpti<strong>on</strong>s regulateacti<strong>on</strong>s and opti<strong>on</strong>s. Foucault (1977a) defines discursive practices in this way:Discursive practices are characterized by the delimitati<strong>on</strong> of a field of objects, the definiti<strong>on</strong>of a legitimate perspective for the agent of knowledge, and the fixing of norms forthe elaborati<strong>on</strong> of c<strong>on</strong>cepts and theories. Thus, each discursive practice implies a play ofprescripti<strong>on</strong>s that designate its exclusi<strong>on</strong>s and choices. (p. 199)For example, and in relati<strong>on</strong> to historical meanings of ”literacy,” the technical processesrequired to be viewed as ”literate” are analyzed in terms of how they are defined andinstituti<strong>on</strong>alized in ordinary discourses regarding the perceived norms and appropriateways to ”be literate.” For my purposes, genealogy serves to dem<strong>on</strong>strate that the exclusi<strong>on</strong>sand choices made over time regarding the meanings of ”literacy” are not a part of ”progress,”but rather, historically situated indicati<strong>on</strong>s of power at work. This in turnproblematizes the educati<strong>on</strong>al discourses surrounding ”literacy” that we take as given,thereby exposing the power and limitati<strong>on</strong>s embedded in the discourses of our day.Foucault (1977a) distinguishes ”discourses” from ”discursive practices” by writing:Discursive practices are not purely and simply ways of producing discourse. They areembodied in technical processes, in instituti<strong>on</strong>s, in patterns for general behavior, in formsfor transmissi<strong>on</strong> and diffusi<strong>on</strong>, and in pedagogical forms which, at <strong>on</strong>ce, impose andmaintain them. (p. 200)With this in mind, I am tying historically specific ways of ”being literate” to theinstituti<strong>on</strong>alized patterns for general behavior, as knowledge about ”literacy” is transmittedthrough the pedagogy which informs the technical processes of what it means to ”beliterate”, or the technical aspects of what <strong>on</strong>e is supposed to ”do” when <strong>on</strong>e is ”beingliterate.” The variati<strong>on</strong>s throughout time in what it means to ”be literate” are dependentup<strong>on</strong> particular discursive practices that define the norms of ”legitimate” literate behavior.While these norms and legitimate ways of being are understood to change over time,Foucault (1977a) also writes that discursive practices ”possess specific modes of transformati<strong>on</strong>”(p. 200). He goes <strong>on</strong> to say:These transformati<strong>on</strong>s cannot be reduced to precise and individual discoveries; and yetwe cannot characterize them as a general change of mentality, collective attitudes, or astate of mind. The transformati<strong>on</strong> of a discursive practice is linked to a whole range ofusually complex modificati<strong>on</strong>s that can occur outside of its domain (in the forms ofproducti<strong>on</strong>, in social relati<strong>on</strong>ships, in political instituti<strong>on</strong>s), inside it (in its techniquesfor determining its object, in the adjustment and refinement of its c<strong>on</strong>cepts, in itsaccumulati<strong>on</strong> of facts), or to the side of it (in other discursive practices). (p. 200)Modificati<strong>on</strong>s and variati<strong>on</strong>s in discursive practices are dependent up<strong>on</strong>, am<strong>on</strong>g otherthings, shifts in the way that knowledge is circulated or produced, changes in the techniqueswhich allocate more or less value to certain forms of knowledge, alterati<strong>on</strong>s in the view ofwho or what may act as an authority or agent of knowledge, and transformati<strong>on</strong>s in thepurposes or uses of knowledge.36


2. Foucault’s noti<strong>on</strong> of genealogy is a method of reading history. It is nothing more nornothing less. It is different from a progressivist reading of history in that it neverassumes that history has c<strong>on</strong>tinually brought forth greater social stability, moreproductive development, or superior means of ec<strong>on</strong>omic growth. It resists the noti<strong>on</strong>that technological developments are, in and of themselves, the driving forces behindrec<strong>on</strong>stituted human thought. It is also different from ”critical” readings of history,which problematize modernist noti<strong>on</strong>s of progress by viewing history from a ”pers<strong>on</strong>al”or ”emancipatory” perspective, without necessarily tying the ”pers<strong>on</strong>al” and the”emancipatory” to historical moments of thinkability. In the ”critical” view, it is as ifthe individual is the instrument of social change, able to overcome the c<strong>on</strong>straints ofhistory, the restraints of a dominant culture, by employing a technique defined bythat very culture, by being ”literate,” for example.Genealogies, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, inform us that there is more to history than arecord of the milest<strong>on</strong>es of productive development, and more also to history than aseries of incidents performed by human beings who float unc<strong>on</strong>strained through historicalmoments. Genealogies, as explained by Foucault (1988a) are ”a form of historywhich can account for the c<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong> of knowledges, discourses, domains ofobjects etc., without having to make reference to a subject which is either transcendentalin relati<strong>on</strong> to the field of events or runs in its empty sameness throughout thecourse of history” (p. 117). Genealogy, then, is a method to critique the ”nature” ofwhat we have become with the hope of exposing that which appears ”natural” and”self-evident” as social and historical c<strong>on</strong>structs.Dean (1994), borrowing from Foucault and Nietzsche, sketches out these threeforms of intellectual approaches to history which I have briefly touched up<strong>on</strong> here.He calls the first a ”progressivist theory” which ”proposes a model of social progressthrough the teleology of reas<strong>on</strong>, technology, producti<strong>on</strong>, and so <strong>on</strong>” (p. 3). This theory”might be called ’high modernism’, and is exemplified by the narratives of theEnlightenment” (p. 3). The sec<strong>on</strong>d form is a ”critical theory” which ”offers a critiqueof modernist narratives in terms of the <strong>on</strong>e-sided, pathological, advance of technocraticor instrumental reas<strong>on</strong> they celebrate, in order to offer an alternative, higher versi<strong>on</strong>of rati<strong>on</strong>ality” (p. 3). This critical reading of history ”promise[s] emancipati<strong>on</strong> andsecular salvati<strong>on</strong>” (p. 3). In this paper, I am associating Dean’s third type of intellectualpractice with Foucault’s noti<strong>on</strong> of genealogy, in that this practice is a ”problematizing”<strong>on</strong>e. Dean writes that ”[t]his form of practice has the effect of the disturbance ofnarratives of both progress and rec<strong>on</strong>ciliati<strong>on</strong>, finding questi<strong>on</strong>s where others hadlocated answers” (p. 4). In additi<strong>on</strong> to associating this approach with Foucault’s (1977b)”effective history”, Dean also points out that ”if the widely used term ’postmodernism’is defined as the restive problematisati<strong>on</strong> of the given, I would be happy toregard this type of history as an exercise of postmodernity” (p. 4). I would be happy tofollow.3. For any<strong>on</strong>e interested in the work d<strong>on</strong>e by UNESCO over the past ten to fifteen yearsin the fields of literacy educati<strong>on</strong>, culture, and communicati<strong>on</strong>s, I have assembled anannotated bibliography that I would be happy to share. Feel free to drop me an e-lineany time: ddhammer@students.wisc.edu4. ”In the Phaedrus,” writes Langham, ”Plato has Socrates deliver what may be the earliest37


protest in Western history against the dehumanizing effects of ’modern’ technology.” InSocrates’ story of writing’s initiati<strong>on</strong> in Egypt, King Thamus illustrates this complaint,as quoted by Langham:The fact is that this inventi<strong>on</strong> will produce forgetfulness in the souls of those whohave learned it. They will not need to exercise their memories, being able to rely <strong>on</strong>what is written, calling things to mind no l<strong>on</strong>ger from within themselves by their ownunaided powers, but under the stimulus of external marks that are alien to themselves.So it’s not a recipe for memory, but for reminding, that you have discovered.See http://sunsite.unc.edu/cmc/mag/1994/jul/moo.html5. Myers (1996) points out that during the late thirteenth century, ”written documentsbecame a support for oral exchanges, not an independent, silent witness” (p. 28).Priority was given to actual witnesses, actual testim<strong>on</strong>ies, actual spoken words. Seealso Graff, 1987, p. 66; Clanchy, 1988, p. 137.6. The grounds up<strong>on</strong> which a type of literacy was able to flourish during the late 1700sand early 1800s in the United States are described by Myers (1996) as follows:Signature and recording literacy became necessary in the United States when moreand more people moved and when they then needed new ways of making informati<strong>on</strong>portable, visible, and storable. During oral face-to-face literacy in the U.S., <strong>on</strong>e livedand traded with people <strong>on</strong>e knew in small, stable, familiar villages. But by the late1700s, more and more people were moving as the Louisiana Purchase opened up thesouthern-central part of the country in 1803, the Erie Canal opened up upper NewYork in 1825, the Baltimore and Ohio railroad opened up the Midwest in 1830, andthe railroad systems opened up the rest. (pp. 42-43)7. Foucault (1990) distinguishes between various understandings of ”power” by writing:[T]he word power is apt to lead to a number of misunderstandings - misunderstandingswith respect to its nature, its form, and its unity. By power, I do notmean ”Power” as a group of instituti<strong>on</strong>s and mechanisms that ensure the subservienceof the citizens of a given state. By power, I do not mean, either, a mode of subjugati<strong>on</strong>which, in c<strong>on</strong>trast to violence, has the form of the rule. Finally, I do not have in minda general system of dominati<strong>on</strong> exerted by <strong>on</strong>e group over another, a system whoseeffects, through successive derivati<strong>on</strong>s, pervade the entire social body. The analysis,made in terms of power, must not assume that the sovereignty of the state, the form ofthe law, or the over-all unity of a dominati<strong>on</strong> are given at the outset; rather these are<strong>on</strong>ly the terminal forms power takes. (p. 92)In relati<strong>on</strong> to my argument, I am viewing any seemingly fixed meaning of ”literacy”as an end result, a temporal terminal resting point, of relati<strong>on</strong>ships of power in acti<strong>on</strong>.8. Foucault (1982) writes:The exercise of power is not simply a relati<strong>on</strong>ship between partners, individual orcollective; it is a way in which certain acti<strong>on</strong>s modify others. Which is to say, of course,that something called Power, with or without a capital letter, which is assumed to existuniversally in a c<strong>on</strong>centrated or diffused form, does not exist. Power exists <strong>on</strong>ly whenit is put into acti<strong>on</strong>, even if, of course, it is integrated into a disparate field of possibilitiesbrought to bear up<strong>on</strong> permanent structures. (p. 219)9. The term ”orality,” as Thomas (1992) suggests, ”was coined deliberately <strong>on</strong> the analogyof ’literacy’ in order to denote this quality [of relying entirely <strong>on</strong> oral communicati<strong>on</strong>]38


in a positive sense: avoiding the implicati<strong>on</strong>s of failure in ’illiteracy’” (p. 6).10. This definiti<strong>on</strong> of ”oral” is from Webster’s New Collegiate Dicti<strong>on</strong>ary. It is also importantto note that another meaning of ”oral” stated here is: ”of, relating to, or characterized bypers<strong>on</strong>ality traits of passive dependency and aggressiveness.” This meaning of ”oral”serves to dem<strong>on</strong>strate how ”oral” ways of being are understood and underestimated incomparis<strong>on</strong> to ”literate” ways of being. But <strong>on</strong>ce again, and genealogically speaking, thisunderstanding is a temporal resting point of relati<strong>on</strong>s of power in acti<strong>on</strong> which haveinvested ”literacy” with meanings of growth and producti<strong>on</strong> and ”orality” with meaningsof ”passive dependence.”11. Ong (1982) writes:Literacy...is absolutely necessary for the development not <strong>on</strong>ly of science but also ofhistory, philosophy, explicative understanding of literature and of any art, and indeedfor the explanati<strong>on</strong> of language (including oral speech) itself. There is hardly an oralculture or a predominantly oral culture left in the world today that is not somehowaware of the vast complex of powers forever inaccessible without literacy. This awarenessis ag<strong>on</strong>y for pers<strong>on</strong>s rooted in primary orality, who want literacy passi<strong>on</strong>ately but whoalso know very well that moving into the exciting world of literacy means leaving behindmuch that is exciting and deeply loved in the earlier oral world. We have to die toc<strong>on</strong>tinue living. (p. 15)However, I would like to make the genealogical point that ”the vast complex ofpowers forever inaccessible without literacy” have little to do with the ”nature” of literacyitself but more to do with the science and governing mechanisms that are invested in ameaning of ”literacy” now taken for granted. While it may be currently ”true” that to”move <strong>on</strong>” requires the ability to read and write, it has not always been this way and itmay not always be.12. Thomas (1992) writes that:[O]rality is often idealized, invested with the romantic and nostalgic ideas c<strong>on</strong>nectedwith folklore, folk culture, and folk traditi<strong>on</strong>, or the ’noble savage’. ’Oral culture’ isoften used interchangeably with folklore, folklore is seen as ’oral traditi<strong>on</strong>’, and withlittle critical examinati<strong>on</strong>, but much idealism, orality and ’oral societies’ take <strong>on</strong> theromantic and exaggerated attributes of folk culture. In other words they become morethan merely descriptive tools and start to imply a whole mentality or world view whichis partly born of a reacti<strong>on</strong> to the modern world. Oral culture is innocent, pure, andnatural, uncorrupted by the written word, or perhaps, depending <strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>e’s standpoint,the pure manifestati<strong>on</strong> of a people’s character. (pp. 6-7)13. Ong (1982) defines a ”primary oral culture” as ”cultures with no knowledge at all ofwriting” (p. 1). He also points out that ”[t]oday primary oral culture in the strict sensehardly exists, since every culture knows of writing and has some experience of its effects.Still, to varying degrees many cultures and subcultures, even in a high-technologyambiance, preserve much of the mind-set of primary orality” (p. 11).14. See Bourdieu (1993), pp. 177-180, for his explanati<strong>on</strong> of ”the racism of intelligence”which ”is what causes the dominant class to feel justified in being dominant: they feelthemselves to be essentially superior” (p. 177).15. Roburn (1994) writes:There is a tendency to describe oral cultures as ’pre-literate’ and to treat the orality/39


literacy intersecti<strong>on</strong> as a unidirecti<strong>on</strong>al progressi<strong>on</strong> towards literate society. This outlookdevalues orality, but also limits literacy; rather than many literacies, with a variety ofpurposes and areas of knowledge, there is <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e literacy, or <strong>on</strong>e path for the evoluti<strong>on</strong>of knowledge. Scholars are finding that there is a plurality of literacies. (paragraph 7)http://cug.c<strong>on</strong>cordia.ca/~mtribe/mtribe94/native_knowledge.html16. With regard to a history of literacy, it should be pointed out that the topic of literacy wasnot of great c<strong>on</strong>cern to historians until as recently as about thirty to forty years ago (Kaestle,1988; Graff, 1979). Before that time, historians were more c<strong>on</strong>cerned with celebrated menwho were already literate (Kaestle, 1988, p. 95). The reas<strong>on</strong>s for even placing literacy’s”progress” in time are because of the prominence the subject has gained today.17. However, Thomas (1992) questi<strong>on</strong>s the noti<strong>on</strong> of ”added vowels” by writing that:the c<strong>on</strong>ceptual significance of the additi<strong>on</strong> of vowels has probably been exaggerated.The Ph<strong>on</strong>ecian alphabet also has letters corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to sounds.... The ph<strong>on</strong>etic principleis hardly a Greek discovery. ... In any case, when the Greeks adapted certain signs asvowel-letters, it is very likely that they thought they were hearing a vowel soundapproximating to their vowels. It is notorious how sounds characteristic of <strong>on</strong>e languagemay be heard very differently by speakers of another, and perhaps what the Greeks heardas vowels were the Ph<strong>on</strong>ecians’ guttural stops. (p. 55)18. See, for example, Pattanayak, 1991. Yet, in a very real way, ”illiteracy” actually can be(and has been) equated with ”n<strong>on</strong>human” or ”uncivilized” through the discourse whichdefines it. As an example, in the beginning of Of Grammatology, Derrida (1976) usesRousseau who writes: ”The depicting of objects is appropriate to a savage people; signsof words and of propositi<strong>on</strong>s, to a barbaric people; and the alphabet to civilized people,”as well as Hegel who writes: ”Alphabetic script is in itself and for itself the most intelligent.”In part, Derrida is ”focus[ing] attenti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> the ethnocentrism which, everywhereand always, had c<strong>on</strong>trolled the c<strong>on</strong>cept of writing” (p. 3).19. In the United States during the late 1800s and into the turn of the century, Myers(1996) writes that:[D]iverse districts, which were often organized around specific ethnic communities,mandated that their own values be taught, thereby increasing the ethnic tensi<strong>on</strong>s am<strong>on</strong>gdifferent groups and providing a c<strong>on</strong>tinuing rati<strong>on</strong>ale for the drive to have schools socializestudents into a ”unified” nati<strong>on</strong>al culture with a unified nati<strong>on</strong>al language. This emphasis<strong>on</strong> nati<strong>on</strong>al unificati<strong>on</strong> helped shape recitati<strong>on</strong> literacy as a uniform way to report toothers what <strong>on</strong>e knows and to create the myth of the U.S. ”melting pot.” (p. 66)20. Foucault (1977d) has called for a historical analysis of discourse, writing that ”[p]erhapsthe time has come to study not <strong>on</strong>ly the expressive value and formal transformati<strong>on</strong>s ofdiscourse, but its mode of existence: the modificati<strong>on</strong>s and variati<strong>on</strong>s, within any culture,of modes of circulati<strong>on</strong>, valorizati<strong>on</strong>, attributi<strong>on</strong>, and appropriati<strong>on</strong>” (p. 137). This isrelated to a historical analysis of the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of the literate subject because the ”literatesubject” exists within particular cultures through the exercise of discursive practices whichdelineate how knowledge is circulated, valorized, attributed, and appropriated.21. Bakhtin (1984) writes about a text which is dialogic and multivocal in that it ”isc<strong>on</strong>structed not as the whole of a single c<strong>on</strong>sciousness, absorbing other c<strong>on</strong>sciousness asobjects into itself, but as a whole formed by the interacti<strong>on</strong> of several c<strong>on</strong>sciousnesses,n<strong>on</strong>e of which entirely becomes an object for the other” (p. 18).40


22. Barthes (1974) writes:This new operati<strong>on</strong> is interpretati<strong>on</strong> (in the Nietzschean sense of the word.) To interpreta text is not to give it a (more or less justified, more or less free) meaning, but <strong>on</strong> thec<strong>on</strong>trary to appreciate what plural c<strong>on</strong>stitutes it. Let us first posit the image of a triumphantplural, unimpoverished by any c<strong>on</strong>straint of representati<strong>on</strong> (of imitati<strong>on</strong>). In this idealtext, the networks are many and interact, without any <strong>on</strong>e of them being able to surpassthe rest; this text is a galaxy of signifiers, not a structure of signifieds; it has no beginning;it is reversible; we gain access to it by several entrances, n<strong>on</strong>e of which can be authoritativelydeclared to be the main <strong>on</strong>e; the codes it mobilizes extend as far as the eye can reach, theyare indeterminable (meaning here is never subject to a principle of determinati<strong>on</strong>, unlessby throwing dice); the systems of meaning can take over this absolutely plural text, buttheir number is never closed, based as it is <strong>on</strong> the infinity of language. The interpretati<strong>on</strong>demanded by a specific text, in its plurality, is in no way liberal: it is not a questi<strong>on</strong> ofc<strong>on</strong>ceding some meanings, of magnanimously acknowledging that each <strong>on</strong>e has its shareof truth; it is a questi<strong>on</strong>, against all in-difference, of asserting the very existence of plurality,which is not that of the true, the probable, or even the possible. (pp. 5-6)23. Landow (1992) uses Derrida as a way to dem<strong>on</strong>strate the c<strong>on</strong>vergence between criticaltheory and hypertextual technology, with particular emphasis <strong>on</strong> a rec<strong>on</strong>figured noti<strong>on</strong>of ”text.” Landow writes:Hypertext blurs the end boundaries of the metatext, and c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>al noti<strong>on</strong>s ofcompleti<strong>on</strong> and a finished product do not apply to hypertext, whose essential noveltymakes difficult defining and describing it in older terms, since they derive from anothereducati<strong>on</strong>al and informati<strong>on</strong>al technology and have hidden assumpti<strong>on</strong>s inappropriateto hypertext. Particularly inapplicable are the related noti<strong>on</strong>s of completi<strong>on</strong> and a finishedproduct. As Derrida recognizes, a form of textuality that goes bey<strong>on</strong>d print ”forcesus to extend...the dominant noti<strong>on</strong> of a ’text,’” so that it ”is henceforth no l<strong>on</strong>ger afinished corpus of writing, some c<strong>on</strong>tent enclosed in a book or its margins but a differentialnetwork, a fabric of traces referring endlessly to something other than itself, to otherdifferential traces.” (Landow, p. 59, ellipses in text, using Derrida, 1979, pp. 83-84)24. Foucault (1972) writes:The fr<strong>on</strong>tiers of a book are never clear-cut: bey<strong>on</strong>d the title, the first lines, and the lastfull stop, bey<strong>on</strong>d its internal c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong>s and its aut<strong>on</strong>omous form, it is caught upin a system of references to other books, other texts, other sentences: it is a nodewithin a network. And this network of references is not the same in the case of amathematical treatise, a textual commentary, a historical account, and an episode in anovel cycle; the unity of the book, even in the sense of a group of relati<strong>on</strong>s, cannot beregarded as identical in each case. The book is not simply that object that <strong>on</strong>e holds in<strong>on</strong>e’s hands; and it cannot remain within the little parallelepiped that c<strong>on</strong>tains it: its unityis variable and relative. As so<strong>on</strong> as <strong>on</strong>e questi<strong>on</strong>s that unity, it loses its self-evidence; itindicates itself, c<strong>on</strong>structs itself, <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong> the basis of a complex field of discourse. (p. 23)In additi<strong>on</strong>, Foucault (1970) also indicates that he would like his own ”work to beread as an open site. Many questi<strong>on</strong>s are laid out <strong>on</strong> it that have not yet found answers;and many of the gaps refer either to earlier works or to others that have not yet beencompleted, or even begun” (p. xii). It is now possible to think of text as an open siteeven after the author’s disappearance.41


25. In the realm of a re-defined ”text,” the reader’s interpretati<strong>on</strong> is not <strong>on</strong>ly about what theauthor means, not <strong>on</strong>ly about the chicken who crossed the road, but also about the roads thereader crosses (and why the reader crosses them). When there are several authors and numeroustextual directi<strong>on</strong>s, when the reader is in charge of the directi<strong>on</strong>s of inquiry, the roads mayintersect in numerous places and a singular author’s linear plan no l<strong>on</strong>ger exists. There is nol<strong>on</strong>ger a singular meaning to ”get.”And yet, even in an intertextual multivocal text, there will probably still remain a meaningto get, at least for a while; it may just not be author-determined. Eco (1992) points out:To say that interpretati<strong>on</strong> (as the basic feature of semiosis) is potentially unlimited does notmean that interpretati<strong>on</strong> has no object and that it ’riverruns’ merely for its own sake. To saythat a text has potentially no end does not mean that every act of interpretati<strong>on</strong> can have ahappy end. (pp. 23-24)In other words, interpretati<strong>on</strong> has a ”public criteria” (p. 25) and a textual basis, no matter howmany roads are crossed. (This too, by the way, has its history.)26. Foucault (1980b) writes:[I]n any society, there are manifold relati<strong>on</strong>s of power which permeate, characterise andc<strong>on</strong>stitute the social body, and these relati<strong>on</strong>s of power cannot themselves be established,c<strong>on</strong>solidated nor implemented without the producti<strong>on</strong>, accumulati<strong>on</strong>, circulati<strong>on</strong> andfuncti<strong>on</strong>ing of a discourse. There can be no possible exercise of power without a certainec<strong>on</strong>omy of discourses of truth.... (p. 93)This quote points out <strong>on</strong>ce again that power cannot circulate or functi<strong>on</strong> without adiscourse, so it is not as if a society can ”decide” to change its mind outside of historicallyappropriate ways to think about problems.27. See, for example, Willinsky (1990); Myers (1996), pp. 56-57 and 106-188, as well as therecently released (1996) Standards for the English Language Arts put out by the Nati<strong>on</strong>alCouncil of Teachers of English and the Internati<strong>on</strong>al Reading Associati<strong>on</strong>.28. I use the term ”technologies of the literate” as a way to describe the historically situated”legitimate” ways of using the materials available at the time to produce a behavior that iscalled ”literate.” These ways of ”being literate” are set in accordance with the discursive practicesof the time which positi<strong>on</strong> the norms and appropriate ways to ”be literate.” For furtherexplanati<strong>on</strong> of this term as it is related to discursive practices, see Hammerberg (in progress)Technologies of the Literate: Historical C<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s of Literacy, Illiteracy, and E-literacy,Chapter Two. (ddhammer@students.wisc.edu)29. ”Inertias and c<strong>on</strong>straints of the present time” is borrowed from Foucault (1988b), when hewrites:The Greek wise man, the Jewish prophet, the Roman legislator are still models that hauntthose who, today, practice the professi<strong>on</strong> of speaking and writing. I dream of the intellectualwho destroys evidence and generalities, the <strong>on</strong>e who, in the inertias and c<strong>on</strong>straints of thepresent time, locates and marks the weak points, the openings, the lines of force, who isincessantly <strong>on</strong> the move, doesn’t know exactly where he is heading nor what he will thinktomorrow for he is too attentive to the present. (p. 124)”The weak points, the openings, the lines of force” are all the topics of this paper, as thespaces, which are opened up through genealogy when history is disrupted, provide a virtualarea in which educators are able to imagine and, yes, even practice.30. And even the understanding of text as ”giving” informati<strong>on</strong> and the reader as ”taking” it42


away (as opposed to ”adding” to it, ”modifying” it, ”memorizing” it, etc.) is indicative of aparticular kind of ”literacy.” Fluctuati<strong>on</strong>s in the definiti<strong>on</strong>s of ”literacy” are related tofluctuati<strong>on</strong>s in the ways that language is circulated, valued, authorized, and used.31. Part of this perceived need is my recogniti<strong>on</strong> that outlining possibilities of significance is adeparture from a historical reading of ”literacy.” However, since possibilities of significanceare represented in discursive practices of what is historically and culturally thinkable, thepossibilities I am outlining here, to my thinking, are a part of the history of the present if<strong>on</strong>ly because they are thinkable in the present.32. According to Webster’s Third New Internati<strong>on</strong>al Dicti<strong>on</strong>ary, Unabridged, ”dereism” as anoun means ”away from reality: thinking directed away from and not following ordinaryrules of logic.” This word is appropriate in this c<strong>on</strong>text because I am attempting to showthat theories are never formed or followed outside of socially/historically situated rules oflogic (reality). While it is possible to break away from (or at least critique) traditi<strong>on</strong>al rulesof reas<strong>on</strong>ing and traditi<strong>on</strong>al hypotheses, all theoretical stances at this point in time need tobe grounded in some form of accepted argumentati<strong>on</strong> if they are to be taken seriously. Inthis way, ”dereistic” theories can exist <strong>on</strong>ly in a Never-land: never imagined, never thought,never accepted. Some may call postmodern theory dereistic in that it aims to problematizetraditi<strong>on</strong>al thought, but I wish to point out its associati<strong>on</strong> with thinkable reality even as itproblematizes ordinary rules of logic.33. However, if it is possible for the ”e-literate” subject to be c<strong>on</strong>structed as an ”individual”capable of making ”choices,” it must always be understood that this ”individual” and these”choices” are also defined and regulated through relati<strong>on</strong>s of power and by the socialc<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>s of the time.34. ”Symptomatic reading” is a way of approaching a text for the purpose of finding insightsand oversights, and seeing those insights and oversights as a symptom of the problem ofsubjectivity, text structure, historical representati<strong>on</strong>s, etc. Questi<strong>on</strong>s to c<strong>on</strong>sider during asymptomatic reading include: What are the intended and unintended messages? Whogains and loses from certain ways of presenting ideas? As an example, T<strong>on</strong>i Morris<strong>on</strong>’s(1992) Playing in the Dark is a book that does a symptomatic reading of American literatureby looking at the time period and ideologies which shaped how authors handled thelanguage, which in turn shaped the ways readers handled ideologies. While she does nottry to pick apart certain author’s attitudes about race, she does look at how the ”Africanistpresence and pers<strong>on</strong>ae have been c<strong>on</strong>structed - invented - in the United States, and of theliterary uses this fabricated presence has served,” (p. 90).35. Myers (1996) explains a typical reading situati<strong>on</strong> involving risk-taking:Translati<strong>on</strong>/critical literacy...requires an active, meaning-making self. Knowledge in thisnew literacy is embodied in the acti<strong>on</strong>s and lives of students. Let’s start with the risk-takingof the first grader who, reading aloud from a text in which Johnny was sent to a home fororphans, first pr<strong>on</strong>ounces the word ”or-puns” and, later, after reading that Johnny had noparents, pr<strong>on</strong>ounces the word ”orfuns.” Literacy in the case of this first grader who shiftsfrom ”or-puns” to ”orfuns” is a form of courage, of risking mistakes, of a willingness to riska guess, to propose a hypothesis or guesstimate, and to try another hypothesis or guesstimateif necessary. One of the purposes of English and English language arts in the new translati<strong>on</strong>/critical literacy is to teach students to develop c<strong>on</strong>fident selves with the courage to engagewith difficulty. (p. 144)43


ReferencesAycock, A. (1992). Post-literacy. Postmodern Culture, 3 (1). http://jeffers<strong>on</strong>.village.virginia.edu/pmc/issue.992/ review-3.992Bakhtin, M. (1984). Problems of Dostoevsky’s poetics. Edited and translated by CarylEmers<strong>on</strong>. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Barthes, R. (1974). S/Z. Translated by Richard Miller. New York: Hill and Wang.Bart<strong>on</strong>, E. L. (1994). Interpreting the discourses of technology. In C. L. Selfe & S.Hilligoss (Eds.) Literacy and computers: The complicati<strong>on</strong>s of teaching and learningwith technology, pp. 56-75. New York: The Modern Language Associati<strong>on</strong>of America.Bolter, J. D. (1991). Writing space: The computer, hypertext, and the history of writing.Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Bourdieu, P. (1993). Sociology in questi<strong>on</strong>. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Sage.Carpenter, E. (1973). Not since Babel. In R. Disch (Ed.), The future of literacy,(pp. 167-173). New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.Cherryholmes, C. H. (1988). Power and criticism: Poststructural investigati<strong>on</strong>s in educati<strong>on</strong>.New York: Teachers College Press.Clanchy, M. T. (1988). Hearing and seeing and trusting writing. In E. R. Kintgen, B. M.Kroll, & M. Rose (Eds.) Perspectives <strong>on</strong> literacy, pp. 135-158. Carb<strong>on</strong>dale:Southern Illinois University Press.Clanchy, M. T. (1979). From memory to written record: England 1066-1307. Cambridge:Blackwell.Dean, M. (1994). Critical and effective histories: Foucault’s methods and historical sociology.New York: Routledge.Derrida, J. (1979). Living <strong>on</strong>. In J. Hulbert (Trans.) Dec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> and criticism. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>:Routledge and Kegan Paul.Derrida, J. (1976). Of grammatology. Translated by G. C. Spivak. Baltimore: JohnsHopkins University Press.Derrida, J. (1972). Structure, sign, and play in the discourse of the human sciences.In R. A. Macksey & E. D<strong>on</strong>ato (Eds.) The structuralist c<strong>on</strong>troversy: The languagesof criticism and the sciences of man, pp. 247-272. Baltimore: Johns HopkinsUniversity Press.Diringer, D. (1948). The alphabet: A key to the history of mankind, 3rd ed. New York:Funk and Wagnalls.Eco, U. (1992). Interpretati<strong>on</strong> and overinterpretati<strong>on</strong>, with R. Rorty, J. Culler and C.Brooke-Rose; S. Collini (Ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.Eisenstein, E. L. (1979). The printing press as an agent of change: Communicati<strong>on</strong>s andcultural transformati<strong>on</strong>s in early modern Europe. 2 Vols. New York: CambridgeUniversity Press.Foucault, M. (1990). The history of sexuality (Volume I): An introducti<strong>on</strong>.New York: Vintage Books.Foucault, M. (1988a). On power. In L. D. Kritzman (Ed.) Michel Foucault - Politics,philosophy, culture: Interviews and other writings 1977-1984, pp. 96-109.New York: Routledge.Foucault, M. (1988b). Power and sex. In L. D. Kritzman (Ed.) Michel Foucault - Politics,philosophy, culture: Interviews and other writings 1977-1984, pp. 110-124.New York: Routledge.44


Foucault, M. (1988c). Truth, power, self: An interview with Michel Foucault, October 25,1982, Rux Martin, Interviewer. In L. H. Martin, H. Gutman, & P. H. Hutt<strong>on</strong>(Eds.) Technologies of the self: A seminar with Michel Foucault, pp. 9-15. Amherst:The University of Massachusetts Press.Foucault, M. (1982). The subject and power. Afterword to H. L. Dreyfus & P. Rabinow,Michel Foucault: Bey<strong>on</strong>d structuralism and hermeneutics, sec<strong>on</strong>d editi<strong>on</strong>, pp.208-226. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.Foucault, M. (1980a). Truth and power. In C. Gord<strong>on</strong> (Ed.) Power/knowledge: Selectedinterviews and other writings by Michel Foucault, 1972-1977, pp. 109-133.New York: Panthe<strong>on</strong>.Foucault, M. (1980b). Two lectures. In C. Gord<strong>on</strong> (Ed.), Power/ knowledge: Selectedinterviews and other writings by Michel Foucault 1972-1977 (pp. 78-108).New York: Panthe<strong>on</strong>.Foucault, M. (1977a). History of systems of thought. In D. B. Bouchard (Ed.), Language,counter-memory, practice (pp. 199-204). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Foucault, M. (1977b). Language to infinity. In D. B. Bouchard (Ed.), Language, countermemory,practice (pp. 53-67). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Foucault, M. (1977c). Nietzsche, genealogy, history. In D. B. Bouchard (Ed.), Language,counter-memory, practice (pp. 139-164). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Foucault, M. (1977d). What is an author? In D. F. Bouchard (Ed.) Language, countermemory,practice, pp. 113-138. Ithica, New York: Cornell University Press.Foucault, M. (1972). The archaeology of knowledge and the discourse <strong>on</strong> language. New York:Panthe<strong>on</strong>.Foucault, M. (1970). The order of things: An archaeology of the human sciences. New York:Vintage Books.Gelb, I. J. (1952). A study of writing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Graff, H. J. (1987). The labyrinths of literacy. New York: The Falmer Press.Graff, H. J. (1979). The literacy myth: Literacy and social structure in the nineteenth-centurycity. New York: Academic Press.Hammerberg, D. D. (in progress). Technologies of the literate: Historical c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>sof literacy, illiteracy, and e-literacy. University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin-Madis<strong>on</strong>, Departmentof Curriculum and Instructi<strong>on</strong>. (ddhammer@students.wisc.edu)Harris, R. (1986). The origin of writing. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Duckworth.Havelock, E. A. (1971). Prologue to Greek literacy. Ohio: The University of Cincinnati.Heim, M. (1988). The technological crisis of rhetoric. Philosophy and rhetoric, 21 (1), pp.48-59.Hoyles, M. (Ed.) (1977). The politics of literacy. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Writers and Readers PublishingCooperative.Kaestle, C. F. (1988). The history of literacy and the history of readers. In E. R. Kintgen,B. M. Kroll, & M. Rose (Eds.), Perspectives <strong>on</strong> literacy, pp. 95-126. Carb<strong>on</strong>dale:Southern Illinois University Press.Landow, G. P. (1992). Hypertext: The c<strong>on</strong>vergence of c<strong>on</strong>temporary critical theory andtechnology. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Langham, D. (1994). The comm<strong>on</strong> place MOO: Orality and literacy in virtual reality.Computer-mediated communicati<strong>on</strong> magazine, vol. 1, no. 3. http://sunsite.unc.edu./cmc/mag/ 1994/jul/moo.htmlLockridge, K. (1974). Literacy in col<strong>on</strong>ial New England: An enquiry into the social c<strong>on</strong>textof literacy in the early modern west. New York: Nort<strong>on</strong>.Lucas, C. J. (1972). Our western educati<strong>on</strong>al heritage. New York: Macmillan.45


MacNevin, D. (1993). The mass producti<strong>on</strong> of literate man: An introducti<strong>on</strong> to the evoluti<strong>on</strong>of educati<strong>on</strong> in the Western historical traditi<strong>on</strong> and the American experience.Needham Heights, MA: Ginn.Marshall, B. (1992). Teaching the postmodern: Ficti<strong>on</strong> and theory. New York: Routledge.Morris<strong>on</strong>, T. (1994). The Nobel lecture in literature, 1993. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Morris<strong>on</strong>, T. (1992). Playing in the dark: whiteness and the literary imaginati<strong>on</strong>. Cambridge:Harvard University Press.Myers, M. (1996). Changing our minds: Negotiating English and literacy. Urbana, IL:NCTE.Nati<strong>on</strong>al Council of Teachers of English and the Internati<strong>on</strong>al Reading Associati<strong>on</strong>.(1996). Standards for the English language arts. Urbana, IL: NCTE.Negrop<strong>on</strong>te, N. (1995). Being digital. New York: Vintage Books.Ols<strong>on</strong>, D. R. (1991). Literacy and objectivity. In D. R. Ols<strong>on</strong> & N. Torrance (Eds.),Literacy and orality (pp. 149-164). New York: Cambridge University Press.Ong, W. J. (1982). Orality and literacy: The technologizing of the word. New York: Methuen.Pattanayak, D. P. (1991). Literacy: An instrument of oppressi<strong>on</strong>. In D. R. Ols<strong>on</strong> & N.Torrance (Eds.), Literacy and orality, (pp. 105-108). New York: CambridgeUniversity Press.Rahi, I. C. (1977). World alphabets: Their origin and development. Allahabad, India:Bhargava Printing Press.Reich, R. B. (1992). The work of nati<strong>on</strong>s: Preparing ourselves for 21st century capitalism.New York: Vintage Books.Roburn, S. (1994). Literacy and the underdevelopment of knowledge.http://cug.c<strong>on</strong>cordia.ca/~mtribe/mtribe94/ native_knowledge.htmlSchmandt-Besserat, D. (1988). From accounting to written language: The role of abstractcounting in the inventi<strong>on</strong> of writing. In B. A. Rafoth & D. L. Rubin (Eds.), Thesocial c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of written communicati<strong>on</strong> (pp. 119-130). New Jersey: Ablex.Schramm, W. & Ruggels, W. L. (1967). How mass media systems grow. In D. Lerner &W. Schramm (Eds.) Communicati<strong>on</strong> and change in the developing countries, pp.57-75. H<strong>on</strong>olulu: East-West Center Press.Scott, J. W. (1991). The evidence of experience. Critical inquiry, 773-797.Stock, B. (1983). The implicati<strong>on</strong>s of literacy. New Jersey: Princet<strong>on</strong> University Press.Street, B. V. (1984). Literacy in theory and practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.Thomas, R. (1992). Literacy and orality in ancient Greece. New York: Cambridge UniversityPress.Tyack, D. B. (1974). The <strong>on</strong>e best system: A history of American urban educati<strong>on</strong>. Cambridge,MA: Harvard University Press.Vinovskis, M. A. (1981). Fertility in Massachusetts from the Revoluti<strong>on</strong> to the Civil War.New York: Academic Press.Whitaker, R. (1996). Orality and literacy in the poetic traditi<strong>on</strong>s of archaic Greece andSouthern Africa. In I. Worthingt<strong>on</strong> (Ed.) Voice into text: Orality and literacyin ancient Greece, pp. 205-220. New York: E. J. Brill.Willinsky, J. (1990). The new literacy: Redefining reading and writing in the schools. NewYork: Routledge.46


SIGURD JOHANSSONChasm Between CodesThe first part of this paper c<strong>on</strong>sists of the theoretical framework with itsrelated c<strong>on</strong>cepts used in an analysis of a project related to the transfer ofknow-how in technical training from Sweden to Egypt. Within the socialsciences this framework can be placed into the field of socialrec<strong>on</strong>structivistic theories and is recognised under the name of the Codetheory.In the paper is a definiti<strong>on</strong> presented of the central c<strong>on</strong>ceptswhen, as in this study, they have been utilised in the analysis of therelati<strong>on</strong>s within the c<strong>on</strong>texts of the organisati<strong>on</strong> of work, as well as thetraining processes where training for the analysed work has been understudy.The sec<strong>on</strong>d part c<strong>on</strong>sists of the results from those analysis. Twoexamples relate to the organisati<strong>on</strong> of the work, <strong>on</strong>e from the PorjusArea of Operati<strong>on</strong> in Luleå River, Sweden, and the sec<strong>on</strong>d from theAswan Two Plant in the Nile. Another two examples are the resultsfrom the analysis when the c<strong>on</strong>cepts have been utilised in the technicaltraining processes at two n<strong>on</strong>-formal training centres. One of them isfrom Jokkmokk Training Centre and the other is from Aswan TrainingCentre. The results from those analysis shed light up<strong>on</strong> the differentprinciple-directing prerequisites, or the chasm between the codes, sincethey c<strong>on</strong>ceptualise the differences in the guiding principles am<strong>on</strong>g thetwo major categories within the project under study.Case under Study:In order to quickly bring the reader into the c<strong>on</strong>text without too muchdetails is the project described below in form of a metaphor. ATC is anabbreviati<strong>on</strong> for Aswan Training Centre and JTC for Jokkmokk TrainingCentre.The case under study can be seen as a theatre scene where the hydropower plants in the upper part of the Luleå river and the River Nileformed the background. Although the equipment in the plants partlywere made by different manufacturers, they were almost identical in49


their c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> principles, design and technology level. In both ofthe rivers all the plants were owned and run by the Swedish and Egyptianstates respectively and both of the states had set up organisati<strong>on</strong>s withthe main task to produce as much energy as possible. To fulfil thosetasks were specialised staff employed to work with the operati<strong>on</strong> andmaintenance of the technical equipment within the plants.Beside those tasks, dealing with the producti<strong>on</strong>, had both of the organisati<strong>on</strong>sin Sweden and Egypt inside themselves, in order to supplythemselves with competent staff, set up specific organisati<strong>on</strong>s for thetechnical training. The tasks of the those latter organisati<strong>on</strong>s also hadthe equal aim in both of the organisati<strong>on</strong>s to train the existing and futurestaff in the specific competencies related to the operati<strong>on</strong> andmaintenance of the plants. In Sweden the training was organised as aschool formed, n<strong>on</strong> formal, technical training centre (JTC) while it inEgypt was organised as lecturing combined with <strong>on</strong>-the -job training.When the curtains of the scene were withdrawn, the Egyptians weregoing to change, with support from the c<strong>on</strong>sultants, <strong>teacher</strong>s at JTC,their form of the training by implementing their own training centre,ATC, and thereby to become more like how the organisati<strong>on</strong> and theprocess of the training was made in Sweden.On the scene there were the participants of the project. One group wasc<strong>on</strong>stituted by the staff at ATC, at the stage to be implemented. Theyc<strong>on</strong>sisted of Engineers and Technicians with l<strong>on</strong>g experiences from work inthe power plants in the River Nile. The other group was the c<strong>on</strong>sultants,staff from JTC with experiences both from work in the power plants in theLuleå River and from <strong>teacher</strong> work at their centre. Those two groups werethe main actors. From time to time there were also guest actors performing<strong>on</strong> the scene, I judge myself as a such. The time of the study was from thelast part of 1992 until the end of 1996.The stage was built by the Egyptian company, properties were boughtby a loan from the World Bank and finally the fees and travels for thec<strong>on</strong>sultants and guest actors were financed by resources from the SwedishAid Authority. The Producer of the play was formally the Terms of Referencesand Scope of Services in the c<strong>on</strong>tract made between SwedPower, a Swedishc<strong>on</strong>sultant company, and the Egypt Electricity Authority. But lurking belowthe surface were other and str<strong>on</strong>ger forces more directing the play in reality.50


Code theory:The British sociologist Basil Bernstein has, during nearly four decadesc<strong>on</strong>tinuously refined his theory which set out to describe what issuesthere are which make it possible for the society to reproduce itself. (Bernstein1971, 1973, 1977, 1990 and 1996)The basic stand for this theory is firstly, that due to the divisi<strong>on</strong> oflabour the society c<strong>on</strong>sists of different classes and sec<strong>on</strong>d, that the societyreproduces itself as a such. Furthermore that there are inequalitiesbetween those classes, and in order to sustain the inequalities and keepthe order there are forces in form of power and c<strong>on</strong>trol in acti<strong>on</strong>. In histheory those c<strong>on</strong>cepts are central but Bernstein means that in the realitythey are interrelated to such a degree that they can <strong>on</strong>ly be distinguishedin a theoretical analysis. In order to make this distincti<strong>on</strong> betweenpower and c<strong>on</strong>trol are the c<strong>on</strong>cept of Classificati<strong>on</strong> and Framing used.But, and this is in my opini<strong>on</strong> the ingenious part, they are then broughttogether again under the c<strong>on</strong>cept of Code. However, the c<strong>on</strong>sequenceis that the three c<strong>on</strong>cepts are so interrelated with each other that inorder to define <strong>on</strong>e of them, the others has to be used.Classificati<strong>on</strong>:If we agree that the society c<strong>on</strong>sists of different categories of people, thec<strong>on</strong>cept of classificati<strong>on</strong> is used to describe how strict those categoriesare kept apart. The c<strong>on</strong>cept classificati<strong>on</strong> refer to power and that thispower is used in order to c<strong>on</strong>tinuously reproduce the borders betweenthe different categories. But in order to exercise power, there has to besome underlying principles <strong>on</strong> which this power can rely. So, as a result,classificati<strong>on</strong> is the strengths of the principles maintaining the boundarylines between the different categories. If there are str<strong>on</strong>g boundariesthe classificati<strong>on</strong> is said to be str<strong>on</strong>g and if the boundaries are blurredand the categories more integrated the classificati<strong>on</strong> is said to be weak.Framing:The c<strong>on</strong>cept of framing refer to c<strong>on</strong>trol in the same way as classificati<strong>on</strong>refer to power. Bernstein means that power al<strong>on</strong>e can not explain thereproducti<strong>on</strong> of the society. There is also a factor of c<strong>on</strong>trol maintainingthe boundary lines created by the power. Framing means the internal,51


or external c<strong>on</strong>trol, by which the different categories c<strong>on</strong>trol boththemselves and others. In similar manners as with classificati<strong>on</strong> theframing is c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be str<strong>on</strong>g if there is a strict c<strong>on</strong>trol and limitedpossibilities to cross the boundary lines. With weak framing meansthat there is little c<strong>on</strong>trol of the boundary lines.Code:Code, finally is the c<strong>on</strong>cept which is developed and used to bringclassificati<strong>on</strong> and framing together. Bernstein define the c<strong>on</strong>cept ofcode like this:A code is a regulative principle, tacitly acquired, which selects andintegrates:a) relevant meanings meaningsb) forms of their realisati<strong>on</strong> realisati<strong>on</strong>sc) evoking c<strong>on</strong>texts c<strong>on</strong>textsFrom this definiti<strong>on</strong> also comes that there are illegitimate meanings,inappropriate forms of realisati<strong>on</strong> as well as inappropriate c<strong>on</strong>texts. (Bernstein1990 p. 14)By the use of those c<strong>on</strong>cepts in an analysis and their relati<strong>on</strong>s toeach other will varying code modalities develop. There are a number ofvariati<strong>on</strong>s possible due to reas<strong>on</strong>s that both classificati<strong>on</strong> and framingcan be weak or str<strong>on</strong>g and thus depending <strong>on</strong> their compositi<strong>on</strong> createdifferent modes or variati<strong>on</strong>s of the code.Utilisati<strong>on</strong> of the Code-Theory C<strong>on</strong>cepts in the Present Study:My own way to utilise the c<strong>on</strong>cepts in the theory is shortly describedbelow. But it must be emphasised that it is entirely my ownmethodology. Furthermore it gives the impressi<strong>on</strong> that it can be madein a quite linear way but in reality the steps were highly integrated andthe possible linearity has gradually appeared when analysing my ownwork.The first step in an analysis, aided by the c<strong>on</strong>cepts in the code theory,is to describe the relati<strong>on</strong>s between two categories with help of thecode c<strong>on</strong>cept. If the two categories are kept well apart it is a collecti<strong>on</strong>code, and if they are assumed to be integrated it is an integrated code.52


The code modality, formed by the compositi<strong>on</strong> between the degree ofthe strengths of the classificati<strong>on</strong>, regulating the relati<strong>on</strong> between thetwo categories, and the degree of the framing factors, c<strong>on</strong>trolling thisrelati<strong>on</strong> can then be analysed by finding the principles <strong>on</strong> which thiscode modality rely and by what means it is c<strong>on</strong>trolled. Of course it canbe claimed that the analysis by this way will be circular and at risk to beself-fulfilling. But it can also be claimed that by this way will a higherdegree of understanding be reached as in a hermeneutic circle.Codes within the WorkOrganisati<strong>on</strong>s and in the Training Process:The most essential findings are presented below in an abbreviated form.In this paper are not any descripti<strong>on</strong>s presented or methodological issuesor questi<strong>on</strong>s related to the analysis treated. Shortly it can be menti<strong>on</strong>edthat the results gradually emerged. First they emerged in a more rawform during the participatory time of the study and then to be morerefined during the process of the analysis.The findings revealed that there was an integrated code modalityregulating both the organisati<strong>on</strong> of work in Porjus and the process oftraining at JTC. In Aswan Two plant and ATC was the same mattersregulated by a collecti<strong>on</strong> code.During the analysis was also found that any exclusive principle notexisted <strong>on</strong>ly in <strong>on</strong>e of the places. The differences in the code modalitycan more be explained by the compositi<strong>on</strong> of a number of principleseach recognised in all the places under study but judged to be of differentimportance in the respective places.It seems that when thedifferences of the importance of each single principle were added toeach other the code modality gradually shifted.Porjus Area of Operati<strong>on</strong>:In Porjus Area of Operati<strong>on</strong> principle stated that staff without tasksdue to organisati<strong>on</strong>al changes had to leave the organisati<strong>on</strong>. The trustin the company’s social resp<strong>on</strong>sibility was not so high. The degree ofclassificati<strong>on</strong> between the different categories working in the plantswas weak. Another principle stated that the smooth and c<strong>on</strong>tinuosproducti<strong>on</strong> and the well-being of the equipment was the most important53


and seemed as a pride. Due to those principles an organisati<strong>on</strong> haddeveloped where the boundaries between the different groups at thework and their different tasks were blurred and integrated with eachother. In the plants there were no remarkable boundary between mentaland manual work, although some specialised members had a higherstatus then others. The level of the formal educati<strong>on</strong> was not important,what counted was a high reliability and the ability to perform theirtasks. The changes within the staff between different places of workand with different tasks were not unusual.The work was <strong>on</strong>ly to a small amount c<strong>on</strong>trolled by access to physicalmaterials since all employees had almost unc<strong>on</strong>trolled access to toolsand storage’s. The work was c<strong>on</strong>trolled with respect to time since amarket ec<strong>on</strong>omy approach was applied.Aswan Two Hydro Power Plant:In Aswan Two plant the number of staff was c<strong>on</strong>siderable larger thenin Porjus. There was a very str<strong>on</strong>g principle regulating both the entryand final positi<strong>on</strong> in the hierarchy according to formal educati<strong>on</strong>.The principle stating that mental and manual related work should bekept apart was also very str<strong>on</strong>g. That principle also embraced thatmore pure technical work and n<strong>on</strong> technical work was performed bydifferent categories in the work force. Another principle prescribedthat the resp<strong>on</strong>sibility for specific equipment was a task in itself. Thisprinciple resulted in the physical divisi<strong>on</strong> of the work force into differentplaces. The principle of seniority regulated both the promoti<strong>on</strong>possibility and the salary. The career almost always followed theway from work with operati<strong>on</strong> and then transfer to maintenance work.The work was c<strong>on</strong>trolled by a strict system of written permissi<strong>on</strong>s toget access to tools, spare parts and c<strong>on</strong>sumable material. Due to theprinciple of resp<strong>on</strong>sibility came the work force to have their places ofwork in the plants according to which specific equipment they wereresp<strong>on</strong>sible for. The time within work was less c<strong>on</strong>trolled. The principlefound in Porjus about the unnecessary number of employees were alsofound in Aswan but it was not c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be so important. The trustin the company’s social resp<strong>on</strong>sibility was very high.54


Jokkmokk Training CentreA modality of invisible pedagogy characterised the methodology withinthe process of training within JTC. At the centre all the <strong>teacher</strong>s, <strong>on</strong>equal terms, were involved both in the theoretical and practical orientedparts of the training. The level of their formal educati<strong>on</strong> was notimportant, what counted was the amount of their practical experiencesfrom work and their ability to perform their tasks. With respect to theparticipant of the courses at the centre, there were not any demands forpre knowledge or differences made between the trainees depending <strong>on</strong>their level from formal educati<strong>on</strong>. The c<strong>on</strong>tent of the courses wasc<strong>on</strong>structed across different engineering areas according to the principlethat the trainees should better understand the whole system and theinterrelati<strong>on</strong>s between adjacent equipment within the plants. C<strong>on</strong>nectedto this was the principle that the training should be practical useful inthe c<strong>on</strong>text of work. The methodology was also influenced by the marketec<strong>on</strong>omy approach of the school. In order to satisfy the trainees(customers) the <strong>teacher</strong>s had to negotiate with them, both with respectto variati<strong>on</strong>s in the c<strong>on</strong>tents and the applied methodology in the courses.All of the staff at the centre had free access to the computers, printersand copy machines and all other equipment. The trainees had almostthe same access. The guiding principle was that all types of materialused in the training should be as close to the user as possible. The <strong>teacher</strong>staff at the centre shared their place of work when not occupied withthe courses.Aswan Training Centre:Although all the efforts to influence the opposite the training processwithin ATC, became a visible pedagogy. The argument for thisc<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> is that <strong>on</strong>e category am<strong>on</strong>g the staff performed the theoreticaland another category the practical oriented training, sustained by anintricate b<strong>on</strong>us system. During the training could not the categorieswith different formal educati<strong>on</strong> be mixed, neither was the <strong>teacher</strong>s withinthe centre with lower formal educati<strong>on</strong> allowed to perform training fortrainees with higher formal educati<strong>on</strong>. Furthermore the <strong>teacher</strong>s withhigher formal educati<strong>on</strong> were not allowed to perform training in practicaloriented parts. Yet another principle regulated that the different enginee-55


ing area of knowledge should be kept apart. By this reas<strong>on</strong> a number ofboundaries were c<strong>on</strong>structed between the different areas of engineering,thus creating a number of different categories <strong>on</strong> the same hierarchiclevel. The members of those categories were not allowed to pass theengineering knowledge area in their work as <strong>teacher</strong>s. The <strong>teacher</strong> staffat the centre was also divided into different physical places depending<strong>on</strong> their positi<strong>on</strong> within the hierarchic ladder and their area of engineeringwithin work.The process of the training was under the principles that all traineeswithin a course should do the same thing, with the same pace, at thesame time and under strict c<strong>on</strong>trol from the <strong>teacher</strong>. The c<strong>on</strong>trol overphysical material was such that every machine with it’s accessories, handtools, instrument, or other physical material at the centre was under theresp<strong>on</strong>sibility to explicit assigned individuals. In order to get anyequipment or c<strong>on</strong>sumable from the storage was a written permissi<strong>on</strong>needed. The same was needed if the <strong>teacher</strong>s needed material to beprinted or copied. The trainees were not allowed to handle anyequipment without the permissi<strong>on</strong> of the <strong>teacher</strong>s.Chasm Between the Codes:The result from the analysis claim that the staff at ATC was regulatedby a str<strong>on</strong>g collecti<strong>on</strong> code with str<strong>on</strong>g classificati<strong>on</strong> and with the mainframing factor c<strong>on</strong>stituted by the efforts to c<strong>on</strong>trol that the physicalresources were most securely kept, but with respect to their effort toc<strong>on</strong>trol the time, can the framing be c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be weak. The processof training came to be characterised as a visible pedagogy. Thec<strong>on</strong>sultants, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, were regulated by an integrated codewith weak classificati<strong>on</strong> and with the main framing factor c<strong>on</strong>stitutedby the efforts to c<strong>on</strong>trol how the time could be most ec<strong>on</strong>omical efficientspent. But with respect to the c<strong>on</strong>trol of the physical resources theframing can be c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be weak. With respect to the trainingprocess their efforts were striving toward an invisible pedagogy.In their comm<strong>on</strong> work during the implementati<strong>on</strong> of the in-servicecourses at the centre the code modalities of the two main categoriescame into c<strong>on</strong>flict with each other. Most evident became the effects ofthe different framing factors in the two groups’ views of each other,56


where the staff at ATC claimed that the c<strong>on</strong>sultants planned everythingand became annoyed if the planning had to be changed, and thec<strong>on</strong>sultants became frustrated by the seemingly disrespect for the time.By saying this, it is not claimed that staff at ATC not c<strong>on</strong>trolled thetime at all or that the c<strong>on</strong>sultants not c<strong>on</strong>trolled the physical resourcesbut the amount of trouble and efforts the two categories made to c<strong>on</strong>trolthose matters differed c<strong>on</strong>siderably.Absence of C<strong>on</strong>flicts:Although the two groups were governed by such different code modalitiesvery few c<strong>on</strong>flicts developed between them during the project. Onepossible explanati<strong>on</strong> could be the effect from the same principle directingthe relati<strong>on</strong>ship between a salesman and the customer, namely theprinciple stating that the salesman is supposed to keep the customersatisfied. This principle partly governed the behaviour of the c<strong>on</strong>sultantssince they viewed the project as a trade where they were the salesmenand the staff at ATC were the customers. Partly it can be explained bythe c<strong>on</strong>tractual formulati<strong>on</strong>s since the c<strong>on</strong>sultants could always withdrawfrom a c<strong>on</strong>flict by saying that their advises differed to taken decisi<strong>on</strong>sregarding the matter at stake, but the decisi<strong>on</strong> was not theirs accordingto the c<strong>on</strong>tract. The staff at ATC was, in their turn, directed by theprinciple governing the relati<strong>on</strong> between a d<strong>on</strong>or and a receiver of agift, namely that a receiver is not supposed to criticise the gift but <strong>on</strong>the c<strong>on</strong>trary should try to please the d<strong>on</strong>or. They could, in their turn,also withdraw from a c<strong>on</strong>flict by the claim that the decisi<strong>on</strong> wasn’t theirsto decide but has to be brought to a higher hierarchic level. It mightwell be argued that by this way the two categories were trying to keepeach other satisfied but, without c<strong>on</strong>sciousness, governed by differentprinciples.There were however not a total c<strong>on</strong>sensus about everything, but themain impressi<strong>on</strong> was that both of the groups avoided c<strong>on</strong>flicts betweeneach other as much as possible.There is also the questi<strong>on</strong> why those principles, with so largedifferences in their values, didn’t become evident early during the project.It looks somehow strange but it seemed to be the case that the twocategories wasn’t c<strong>on</strong>scious about what issues the other category put57


their efforts to c<strong>on</strong>trol, whereas what the other part didn’t put such aneffort to c<strong>on</strong>trol became evident quite early. One plausible explanati<strong>on</strong>is due to the invisibility. You can not realise that there is a directingprinciple except as an interpretati<strong>on</strong> from an acti<strong>on</strong> or by a narrative. Inthe discussi<strong>on</strong>s at the project mostly specific practical problems werediscussed and alternative way to solve them treated. The underlyingprinciples were hidden in the arguments, invisible and unknown ofteneven to the messenger. To this argument can be added that since thesame principles at least to some degree regulated both of the groupscould a principle always be acknowledged in a discussi<strong>on</strong> and thus wasn’tdiscussed in depths. Probably, partly because of the language problems,partly to avoid c<strong>on</strong>flicts.Comparis<strong>on</strong>s and Generalisati<strong>on</strong>The aim of the study was never to make a comparative study but todescribe, analyse and plausible explain the outcome of the project. ButI have found that the c<strong>on</strong>tinuos comparis<strong>on</strong>s has been a help whenlooking for the underlying principles and the way they were c<strong>on</strong>trolled.It was during the c<strong>on</strong>tinuos reflecti<strong>on</strong>s in the comparis<strong>on</strong>s aboutsimilarities and differences and how they could be understood that thefindings came to be refined. It might also be claimed that as so<strong>on</strong> assomething is described and analysed there is always some kind ofcomparis<strong>on</strong>s involved.It must also be menti<strong>on</strong>ed that the code modality varied with eachindividual and thereby it’s hard to make any generalisati<strong>on</strong> within orbetween the groups. Since the very definiti<strong>on</strong> of a code says that thecode vary according to the situati<strong>on</strong> and what is assumed to bemeaningful, the results presented here will at the same time be limitedto the situati<strong>on</strong> as it occurred during the project. By those reas<strong>on</strong>s thepossibility to generalise are quite limited. The differences in the directingprinciples were however there but <strong>on</strong>ly when looking at it as a whole.The analyses, although the descripti<strong>on</strong> has been under face validity,must be understood to be my own interpretati<strong>on</strong> from my experiencesas a participatory researcher.58


ReferensesBernstein, B. 1971 Class, Codes and C<strong>on</strong>trol. Volume 1. Theoretical Studies towards aSociology of Language. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Bernstein, B 1973 Class, Codes and C<strong>on</strong>trol. Volume 2. Applied Studies towards aSociology of Language. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Bernstein, B. 1977 Class, Codes and C<strong>on</strong>trol. Volume 3. Towards a Theory of Educati<strong>on</strong>alTransmissi<strong>on</strong>s. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge & Kegan Paul. (First Editi<strong>on</strong> 1975)Bernstein, B. 1990 The Structuring of Pedagogic Discourse. Volume IV. Class, codes andc<strong>on</strong>trol. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-04568-1Bernstein, B. 1996 Pedagogy Symbolic C<strong>on</strong>trol and Identity. Theory, Researc, Critique.L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Taylor and Francis. ISBN 0-7484-0372-859


K E N T L Ö F G R E NTeacher Educati<strong>on</strong>, StatisticalMethodologies and theC<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of KnowledgeThe study of statistics is an indispensable part of many educati<strong>on</strong>alprogrammes, including <strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong>. 1 My standpoint is that thestudy of statistics in <strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong> is focused <strong>on</strong> hypothesis c<strong>on</strong>trol,tests and classical statistics. 2In this article I discuss alternative ways of using statistical methodsin educati<strong>on</strong>al research, including the methodology of the Frenchsociologist Pierre Bourdieu, and other researchers 3 working in the sametraditi<strong>on</strong> of data analysis. I will also give a pers<strong>on</strong>al account of myencounter with Bourdieu’s statistical methodology. 4This article does discuss methods, but statistics is more than widelyapplicable mathematical methodologies. Identical statistical algorithmscan be used in various ways, depending <strong>on</strong> the research setting inquesti<strong>on</strong>. As a counter-example to Bourdieu’s use of a specific statisticaltechnique (corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis), I will present a study (Räty, et al.,1996) which employs a classical statistics approach to the use of thesame statistical technique.Classical statisticsScientists often summarise their findings from both qualitative and quantitativeresearch in the form of cross-tables. There are several methodologicalapproaches to the statistical study of cross-tables c<strong>on</strong>taining categoricaldata. Many are deductive in their design, i.e. prior assumpti<strong>on</strong>s are madeabout the distributi<strong>on</strong> of data. 5 I argue that the use of statistical analyses totest hypotheses — e.g. schemes to test or to check ideas or statistical modelsagainst data sets 6 — is far-reaching, in social science.There are clear advantages in “testing techniques”, using a priorigroups, e.g. the divisi<strong>on</strong> of variables into groups of describing variablesand variables to be described, and advanced modelling, e.g. Jöreskog’sLISREL-based educati<strong>on</strong>al achievement studies.61


However, there are statistical computing envir<strong>on</strong>ments, apart from thoseof quasi-experimentati<strong>on</strong>, log-linear modelling, simple and multiple regressi<strong>on</strong>analyses etc., that accept the existence of graphic and exploratorymethods, e.g. iterative, exploratory and multi-dimensi<strong>on</strong>al approaches usingprincipal comp<strong>on</strong>ent analysis, multi-dimensi<strong>on</strong>al scaling, cluster analysisand corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis. These methodologies and approaches transformthe original data into cross-tables and the interacti<strong>on</strong>s in the tablesare summarised, sometimes in graphic displays, without any a priori, abstractidea about the inter-dependence between rows and columns. 7In the teaching of statistics in undergraduate and graduate programmes,there is clearly a need to discuss classical methods, e.g. methods totest significance, but there is also a need to discuss alternative ways offinding patterns in data.Statistical analysis in the traditi<strong>on</strong> of BourdieuMy first encounter with corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis was through readingBourdieu’s Distincti<strong>on</strong> (1984 [1979]). Encouraged by my graduate studyadvisor Prof. Martin Johanss<strong>on</strong>, I started to look into the possibilities ofusing the method in my own research.Initially, I tried to find out exactly how the corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysismethod should be used to search for and find patterns in data. With myearlier experience of the use of the multivariate descriptive statistics ofcategorical data, I thought I stood a fair chance of discovering quicklywhat the methodological “formula” was for knowing how to analyseand re-analyse cross-table data correctly.This learning process however went slowly as I was making err<strong>on</strong>eousassumpti<strong>on</strong>s. I was searching for the golden rules regardingcorresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis and the key questi<strong>on</strong> of how to identify thecategories to be included, or excluded, in the analyses and re-analysesof cross-tabulated sociological data. Later, as I learnt more aboutcorresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis, I saw that there are no such rules to be found— <strong>on</strong>ly mixed groups of different research traditi<strong>on</strong>s with partly incommensurableideas and recommendati<strong>on</strong>s.Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis per se does not imply, either implicitly orexplicitly, a certain methodology, and the analysis method can be usedinductively as well as deductively. 862


What is corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis?I will show how this technique can be used as a tool in obtaining agraphical representati<strong>on</strong> of the dependence between the columns of across-table. 9 The example data, which are not in themselves the focus ofinterest in this article, and the figures by corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analyses (Figures1 and 3) are based <strong>on</strong> the cross-tabulati<strong>on</strong> of the resp<strong>on</strong>ses to a surveyam<strong>on</strong>g female undergraduate students at <strong>Umeå</strong> University, Sweden. 10Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis assigns co-ordinates to each column so thattheir inter-relati<strong>on</strong>ship can be shown in graphical displays. These figuresresemble scatter-plots, and it is possible to interpret distances betweenthe columns’ positi<strong>on</strong>s in the figures.In terms of the method used here, the results from the survey weresummarised in frequency counts and a multiway table with eight variableswas created (Table 1). The variables were: Favourite pastime, Subjectgrouping, Age, Civil status, Odd job — how many hours per week doesthe student work <strong>on</strong> the side, e.g. to help finance her/his studies, Memberof sports/exercise club, Member of an organisati<strong>on</strong> — other than sportsclub — and Number of hours spent doing sport/exercise per week(defined as activities where <strong>on</strong>e has to change clothes and/or take ashower afterwards). The purpose was to analyse what the students didduring their leisure time in terms of physical exercise and sport, and tocoordinate their habits with other data.My view tends be that the world is a ”relati<strong>on</strong>al” and ”c<strong>on</strong>structed”place. In other words, as a social theorist, I see the individual as a receptorand generator of social meaning. The human body, for instance, issomehow shaped, c<strong>on</strong>trolled and c<strong>on</strong>strained by society 11 and is centralto human life — not just in terms of biology. Furthermore, thesignificance of the body is determined in part by social structures whichexist bey<strong>on</strong>d the reach of individuals.I argue that any discussi<strong>on</strong> of academic life from a student perspective,must acknowledge the importance of subject groups. The academicdisciplines are not <strong>on</strong>ly a major organising basis for higher educati<strong>on</strong>but also provide a powerful social framework which affects the lives ofboth students and staff (Becher, 1994, 151, and Kuh, 1995).However, even if the differences between disciplines are importantenough to warrant general recogniti<strong>on</strong>, it is hard to know prior to an63


Table 1. The first ten and last three rows of a 47 x 230 indicator matrix showing demographic and lifestyle data for 230 female students attending<strong>Umeå</strong> University, Sweden. Coding: 0 = The individual does not bel<strong>on</strong>g to this category; 1 = The individual bel<strong>on</strong>gs to this category.IndividualAge Civil status Subject group Odd jobs Favorite pastime Time spent doingexercise,a)sports-1929-2425-2930-3435-3940+Living al<strong>on</strong>eAl<strong>on</strong>e, with child(ren)MarriedMarried, with child(ren)CohabiteeCohabitee, with child(ren)Teacher Educati<strong>on</strong> (TE)Natural Science (NA)Humanities (HU)Phys.Educati<strong>on</strong>/Kinesiology (PK)1-8 hours/week9-16 hours/week17+ hours/weekPlay an instrumentReading literatureTo do sportsTo go to café, pub, restaurantBeing out in natureDealing with animalsHandicraft, art-workTo be with friendsTo be with partner, family0 (nil) hours/week0,01-3,59 hours/week4,00-7,59 hours/week8,00+ hours/weekOrg.memberA student-nati<strong>on</strong> (Stud.org)"SNF" (Swedish Nati<strong>on</strong>al Trust)Amnesty Internati<strong>on</strong>alUni<strong>on</strong>Political partyA student organisati<strong>on</strong> (other than Stud.-nati<strong>on</strong>)Religious organisati<strong>on</strong>, churchGreenpeace"Humlan" (Cultural organisati<strong>on</strong>)"IKSU" (Intramural sports)Sport org.memberHorseback ridingMartial artsGolf clubFootballFloorball640 0 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 00 0 2 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 00 0 3 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 00 0 4 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 00 0 5 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 00 0 6 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 00 0 7 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 00 0 8 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 00 0 9 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 00 1 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0..2 2 8 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 02 2 9 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 02 3 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0a) The 230 female students who participated in the survey were divided into four subject groups, based <strong>on</strong> the their major fieldof study and the courses they attended.Humanities (HU)Teacher Educati<strong>on</strong> (TE)Engelska B (English course)Lärarutbildning. 1-7 (Program for elementary school <strong>teacher</strong>, grade 1-7) Nordiska språk B (Course in the Swedish language)Lärarutbildning. 4-9 (Program for elementary school <strong>teacher</strong>, grade 4-9) Historia B (History course)Historia A/B (History course)Etnologi B (Ethnology course)Natural Science (NA)Biokemi B (Biochemistry course)Organisk kemi B (Organic Chemistry course)Biologi B (Biology course)Info.behandl. B (Computer Science course)Physical Educati<strong>on</strong>/Kinesiology (PK)Idr.ped. B-nivå (Program for sports pedagogics)Idr.lärar. B-nivå (Program for physical educati<strong>on</strong> <strong>teacher</strong>)


investigati<strong>on</strong> just how important such a factor as subject group will be,and to what extent this variable would c<strong>on</strong>stitute a ”descriptive variable”.In order to investigate the relati<strong>on</strong>ships between study, leisure andsports habits, without making too many assumpti<strong>on</strong>s about the interrelati<strong>on</strong>shipbetween variables, I explore the data using a multiple (Ktable)corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis.In terms of the results, Figure 1 provides a wealth of informati<strong>on</strong>. Itis a c<strong>on</strong>versi<strong>on</strong> and re-presentati<strong>on</strong> of the informati<strong>on</strong> from Table 1.Age 40+Sports club:Golf clubOdd job:1-8 h/wCohabitee,no childSports activities:0,00 h/wOrg.member:Political partyMarried,no childSports club:Martial artsFavorite pastime:readingSubject group: NAOdd job:9-16 h/wCohabitee, withchild(ren)Favorite pastime:handicraft, art-workFavorite pastime:being with family, partnerSubject group: PKSports activities:4,00-7,59 h/wAge 25-29Favorite pastime:play an instrument/to singOrg.member:SNF (Swe.Nati<strong>on</strong>al Trust)Age 35-39Org.member:A student clubOrg.member:"Humlan"(Cultural org.)Sports club:FootballSingle,no childSubject group: TEOrg.member:Uni<strong>on</strong>Favorite pastime:being with friendsSports activities:0,01-3,59 h/wFavorite pastime:sports activitiesSports club:FloorballFavorite pastime:being out in natureFavorite pastime:dealing with animalsOrg.member:GreenpeaceOrg.member:Amnesty Int.Odd job:17+ h/wOrg.member:Religious, church org.Age 20-24Sports club:"IKSU" (Intramural)Married withchild(ren)Age 30-34 Sports activities:8,00+ h/wSingle, withSports club: child(ren)Horseback ridningSubject group: HUFavorite pastime:going to café, pub, restaurantAge -19Org.member:"Nati<strong>on</strong>"Figure 1. Graphical representati<strong>on</strong> of 47 categories. Female students (<strong>Umeå</strong> University,Sweden), n=230. The result of a corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis of Table 1, a 47 x 230 cross-table.65


As a rule, categories that are adjacent to each other often co-occurfor the same individual, i.e. if many individuals in the sample haveindicated that they bel<strong>on</strong>g, as an example, to the category ”Age: 35-39”and the category “I am a member of the cultural organisati<strong>on</strong> Humlan”,then these two categories will be relatively close to each other inthe figure. 12The positi<strong>on</strong> of each category, or column, in the figures is based <strong>on</strong>the column profile across the 230 rows of Table 1. The c<strong>on</strong>cept of aprofile is fundamental to corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis, and implies, in general,that columns with similar profiles, i.e. appearances across the rows,are grouped together in corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis figures.How does Bourdieu use corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis?To c<strong>on</strong>clude my attempt to illustrate how Bourdieu uses corresp<strong>on</strong>denceanalysis, I will move <strong>on</strong> from the initial analysis by removing some ofthe categories from the original cross-table and re-analysing the data.This process of exclusi<strong>on</strong> is partly based <strong>on</strong> a study of the geometricalc<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>, or more precisely the lack thereof, to Figure 1 for each ofthe categories. The 12 categories thus removed from the original table,are excluded before the re-run of the analysis (and, as a c<strong>on</strong>sequence,they are no l<strong>on</strong>ger found in Figure 3) because they are deemed by theresearcher — based <strong>on</strong> the output of the corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysisalgorithms — to be of less importance. The choice of which categoriesare removed is based <strong>on</strong> how much each category, each point in thefigure, c<strong>on</strong>tributes to the latent structures in the figure. 13 The categoriesare not excluded because they do not fulfil statistical requirements neededto perform the analysis. Hence, categories that are theoretically interestingbut do not achieve a specific quality level do not have to be omittedfrom the analysis simply because of poor data quality.From a sociological point of view, the categories might also of coursebe aggregated to form new categories if the researcher finds it necessary(but this is not d<strong>on</strong>e in this example). For instance the example data for“Married, without children” and “Cohabitee, without children” (SeeFigure 2) can be aggregated to form the category: “Married/Cohabitee,without children”.66


Data are arranged in a cross-tabulati<strong>on</strong>The corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis algorithms create a multi-dimensi<strong>on</strong>al spread ofcategories but the dimensi<strong>on</strong>ality is reduced, often into a two-dimensi<strong>on</strong>al figure.In this operati<strong>on</strong> (The projecti<strong>on</strong> of the categories <strong>on</strong>to a flat plane) somecategories will "travel far", compared to others, when the multidimensi<strong>on</strong>alityis reduced.In additi<strong>on</strong> to the figure, the algorithms also produce numerical output and it ispossible for the researcher to see how "far" each category "travels" when thedimensi<strong>on</strong>ality is reduced, i.e. how well the figure adequately represents thetrue locati<strong>on</strong> of a category.Using this numerical output together with careful sociological c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>sthe figure is scrutinized.The figure is deemed adequateFindings are used for the generati<strong>on</strong>of ideas, hypotheses and futureresearchThe figure is deemed inadequateData are re-analysedResearch assumpti<strong>on</strong>s, the collecti<strong>on</strong> of dataFigure 2. The order flow in the process of creating knowledge through a repeated use ofcorresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis and the c<strong>on</strong>cept of c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong> and adequate representati<strong>on</strong>, inthe traditi<strong>on</strong> of Bourdieu.Categories can also be removed for other, more pragmatic, reas<strong>on</strong>s:in some of Bourdieu’s figures in Distincti<strong>on</strong> (1984 [1979], 340), thecategories for office workers are excluded in an analysis of petit bourgeoistaste, because they are, as Bourdieu puts it, ...too widely dispersed... [inthe figure]. 14Bourdieu also uses the technique of “supplementary categories”. Theuse of such categories, from a mathematical and statistical point of view,is the applicati<strong>on</strong> by the researcher of an additi<strong>on</strong>al formula to thecorresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis algorithms, allowing categories to take spatialpositi<strong>on</strong>s in the figures without influencing the positi<strong>on</strong>s of the othercategories. See for instance Bourdieu’s The State Nobility — Elite Schoolsin the Field of Power (1996 [1989], 143), where two sets of data forschools are used simultaneously in corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analyses. The firstset of data is used to form a variable and the sec<strong>on</strong>d set as a supplementaryvariable. On page 155 in the same book (Bourdieu, 1996 [1989]) thereis a further descripti<strong>on</strong> of the circumstances under which variables (e.g.sex) are used as supplementary points in the corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysisfigures.The repeated analysis of Table 1, as described above (Figure 2), mayc<strong>on</strong>tinue with a third analysis, a fourth, a fifth and so <strong>on</strong>, should I67


choose to work in the style and traditi<strong>on</strong> of Bourdieu. It is important toacknowledge that in the literature there is no fixed number of repetiti<strong>on</strong>srecommended for this knowledge-creating process. The overall purposeis to identify structures in the data and to create interpretative figures.Married,no childAge 40+Cohabitee,no childSports activities:0,00 h/wSports club:Golf clubOdd job:1-8 h/wOrg.member:Political partySubject group: NAOdd job:9-16 h/wSports activities:4,00-7,59 h/wSports activities:8,00+ h/wSubject group: PKAge 25-29Sports club:Horseback ridningSubject group: HUAge 35-39Favorite pastime:play an instrument/to singOrg.member:"Humlan"(Cultural org.)Org.member:A student clubSports club:FloorballSports activities:0,01-3,59 h/wSingle,no childOrg.member:Uni<strong>on</strong>Favorite pastime:being with friendsOrg.member:Amnesty Int.Age 20-24Sports club:"IKSU" (Intramural)Favorite pastime:going to café, pub, restaurantOrg.member:"Nati<strong>on</strong>"Age -19Single, withchild(ren)Sports club:FootballSubject group: TEFavorite pastime:sports activitiesMarried, withchild(ren)Figure 3. Graphical representati<strong>on</strong> of 35 categories. Female students (<strong>Umeå</strong> University,Sweden), n=230. The result of a re-analysis (corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis) of Table 1 with 12categories excluded, making it a 35 x 230 cross-table. See text for explanati<strong>on</strong>.It is time to start interpreting some of the results. To the north-west 15in Figure 3, relative to the origin of coordinates (the origin is found inthe middle of the figure, where the horiz<strong>on</strong>tal and vertical axes cross),we find categories such as: “Age 40+” and “Married/Cohabitee withoutchildren”. In the same directi<strong>on</strong>, relative to the origin of coordinates,68


we find “Sports activities: 0,00 hour per week” as well as “Member of agolf club”. This indicates, am<strong>on</strong>g other things, that membership of golfclubs is more frequent am<strong>on</strong>g older female students, than am<strong>on</strong>g youngerfemale students. It is interesting to note that these students relativelyoften indicate that they are members of golf clubs, at the same time astheir answer to the survey questi<strong>on</strong> how many hours per week do youexercise/sport is zero (i.e. the categories “Member of a golf club” and“Sports activities: 0,00 hour per week” are close to each other in thefigure). The survey questi<strong>on</strong> defined exercise/sport as any activityrequiring a change of clothes and/or taking a shower afterwards. Perhapsthese individuals do not c<strong>on</strong>sider their golfing activities as a physicalactivity in this particular sense.To the east of the origin of coordinates we find young students whoenjoy sports activities and participating in activities arranged by studentclubs. 16 These students seem to be great c<strong>on</strong>sumers of sports andphysical activities. There is virtually no distincti<strong>on</strong> between studentsfrom Natural Sciences (NA), Physical Educati<strong>on</strong>/Kinesiology (PK) andHumanities (HU) in this respect.In the southern part of the figure, we find students from the subjectgroup of Teacher Educati<strong>on</strong> (TE). In close proximity we find the category“favourite pastime: sports activities”. At first this is a perplexing result.Should not this latter category be closer to (and therefore more str<strong>on</strong>glyassociated with) the previously discussed student group — found eastof the origin of coordinates — who are such great c<strong>on</strong>sumers of sport?One possible explanati<strong>on</strong> is that although they (the “great sportsc<strong>on</strong>sumers”) prioritise physical exercise, they do not c<strong>on</strong>sider it theirfavourite pastime. Sport is important, but socialising is even moreimportant for them (going to cafés, being with friends etc).The results indicate that students who play golf (the north-west cornerof Figure 3), although living with partners, often have no children. Ifthese couples had children, would the childcare resp<strong>on</strong>sibilities preventthem from c<strong>on</strong>tinuing to pursue their interest in golf? To penetratefurther this and many other questi<strong>on</strong>s raised by the corresp<strong>on</strong>denceanalysis of the cross-tabulated data in Table 1, the analyses here can becomplemented with interview data, e.g. collected in a sec<strong>on</strong>d phase ofan investigati<strong>on</strong>.69


The c<strong>on</strong>cluding figure (Figure 3) does not provide us with the final results— we want to know more about the female students with regard to theirleisure habits, to understand more about the reas<strong>on</strong>s behind the students’choice to c<strong>on</strong>sume sport or to enjoy other leisure activities — but I arguethat the use of corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis makes it possible to show patternsin Table 1 that, albeit <strong>on</strong>ly roughly, portrays these multi-dimensi<strong>on</strong>al andcomplex relati<strong>on</strong>ships in an adequate and very graphic way.Introducing corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis techniques inmethodology coursesAfter this expose of corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis, let us move back to thefundamental questi<strong>on</strong>s raised in this article. When I discuss <strong>teacher</strong>educati<strong>on</strong> and the relevance of statistics, I find it difficult to talk aboutcurricula in singulars. I talk instead about science and knowledge-creatingprocesses in general, and about making <strong>teacher</strong>s <strong>teacher</strong>s rather thanscientists.Apart from reflecting <strong>on</strong> a technical level (which tends to focus <strong>on</strong>what functi<strong>on</strong>s in science and academia) I argue that students shouldalso be guided to develop a understanding of c<strong>on</strong>cepts such asc<strong>on</strong>structivism, multi-culturalism etc. and to reflect <strong>on</strong> a critical level;and they should be given many opportunities to reflect <strong>on</strong> statisticalc<strong>on</strong>cepts, where questi<strong>on</strong>s of fairness, h<strong>on</strong>esty, ethics and democraticvalues are addressed. 17 It is the ability to scrutinize and debate suchc<strong>on</strong>cepts, that should be seen at the end of study programmes. 18Will it be enough to introduce corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis and similartechniques in statistics courses as alternative ways of using statisticaland mathematical analyses of cross-tabulated data? Probably not. It isnot the statistical-mathematical method in itself that determines thec<strong>on</strong>tent and manifestati<strong>on</strong>s of different research discourses, as I willshow in the last part of this article.A single statistical technique — a multitude of epistemologiesAn alternative corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis methodology is presented in Rätyet al. (1996), where the corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis technique is used toinvestigate and explore views of children’s schooling in Finland and toinvestigate the attitudes of parents towards <strong>on</strong>going educati<strong>on</strong>al reforms70


and market-oriented school policies. 19 It is a main aim of the study toinvestigate the relati<strong>on</strong>ships between the parents’ views and attitudes,e.g. regarding individuality, and how these views reflect and c<strong>on</strong>structthe relati<strong>on</strong>ship between the parents and the schools. One aim is torelate attitudes and degrees of satisfacti<strong>on</strong> to the social backgrounds ofthe parents. 20Through a nati<strong>on</strong>-wide sample of 563 parents, the study collecteddata <strong>on</strong> attitudes towards a number of statements (drawn by the researchersfrom current discourses in journals and the Finnish media) andsatisfacti<strong>on</strong> with the school system. Likert scales (resp<strong>on</strong>ses <strong>on</strong> a 1-5scale) were used and statistical analyses were made, to explore therelati<strong>on</strong>ships in the data. (The Likert scale data was categorised as follows:1, 2 and 3 became <strong>on</strong>e category, and 4 and 5 became another. 21 ) Thestudy used corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis to search for patterns in the crosstabulateddata.The results show that there are differences between working-classparents and upper-level-employee parents, in terms of views andopini<strong>on</strong>s.The corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis gave further evidence to the effect that theattitudes investigated form... distinct patterns..., whose endorsement isc<strong>on</strong>nected to the parents’ social positi<strong>on</strong>. The attitude patterns seem tocoincide with fundamental educati<strong>on</strong>al ideologies, such as c<strong>on</strong>servatismand liberalism..., individuality and collectivity..., and related ideasabout the individual and society and about freedom and c<strong>on</strong>straint...Clearly, these ideologies create an influential framework through whichthe <strong>on</strong>going reforms are approached and represented from socialpsychologicalpoints of view... (Räty, et al., 1996, 214.)My comment to the results is that a single corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis(executed <strong>on</strong>ce) 22 of a cross-table c<strong>on</strong>taining, for example, noti<strong>on</strong>s andsocio-ec<strong>on</strong>omic data will always yield results such as ...the vertical axisseems to pull apart white-collar workers from blue-collar workers..., or ...tothe north in the figure, we find attitudes representing the status group ofblue-collar workers...71


Classical statistics, corresp<strong>on</strong>denceanalysis and Bourdieu’s approachThe technique used is similar in Bourdieu’s and Räty et al.’s analyses.From a methodological standpoint, both also aim to identify patternsand structures in data, but the former uses the method to explore relati<strong>on</strong>sbetween a great number of categories in a repeated fashi<strong>on</strong>.Bourdieu also tries to avoid creating new knowledge built <strong>on</strong> the useof a priori assumpti<strong>on</strong>s, e.g. in terms of the distributi<strong>on</strong> of socioec<strong>on</strong>omicbackground data. He does summarise socio-ec<strong>on</strong>omic backgrounddata in variables, but he does not hesitate if deemed necessaryto exclude categories from these background variables in the statisticalanalyses. The background variables are not seen as independent variables23in a search for direct relati<strong>on</strong>ships.Some c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>sI have shown that similar techniques can be used in different waysdepending <strong>on</strong> who is using them. I have also argued that students needto develop an articulated intellectual interest in questi<strong>on</strong>s about statisticsand the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of knowledge about social phenomena (e.g.the inclusi<strong>on</strong> and exclusi<strong>on</strong> of categories), rather than a <strong>on</strong>e-sided focus<strong>on</strong> questi<strong>on</strong>s about the use of techniques, the data requirements of thesetechniques, levels of significance etc. I emphasise this because thescientific methodology of statistics has a wide applicati<strong>on</strong> and greatlyinfluences our thinking about social phenomena. Modern statistics, withits many intellectual roots, influences our understanding of social factsand normal schemes of distributi<strong>on</strong>s and engenders c<strong>on</strong>cepts andclassificati<strong>on</strong>s (Hacking, 1991, 181).I cannot say that the corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis technique is our saviour,but I argue that Bourdieu’s statistical epistemology is an unutilizedcomplement to classical statistics in methodology courses. 24In <strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong>, we might have a resp<strong>on</strong>sibility to be morereceptive to alternative ways of using statistical analyses of cross-tabulateddata and there are a number of reas<strong>on</strong>s for taking a closer look atBourdieu’s investigati<strong>on</strong>s. Quantitative methods are often criticised fortheir use of pre-c<strong>on</strong>structed questi<strong>on</strong>s and fixed resp<strong>on</strong>se alternatives(Rosén & Wernerss<strong>on</strong>, 1996, 11) and while Bourdieu’s statistical72


epistemology is no different in this case, it does not imply the use ofpre-c<strong>on</strong>structed variables, that form a priori c<strong>on</strong>structed status groups.The aim is rather to use corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis to transform surveydata into theoretical relati<strong>on</strong>s....if I make extensive use of corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis, in preference tomultivariate regressi<strong>on</strong> for instance, it is because corresp<strong>on</strong>denceanalysis is a relati<strong>on</strong>al technique of data analysis whose philosophycorresp<strong>on</strong>ds exactly to what, in my view, the reality of the social worldis. It is a technique which “thinks” in terms of relati<strong>on</strong>, as I try to doprecisely with the noti<strong>on</strong> of field. (Bourdieu & Wacquant, 1992, 96.)In other words, the statistical method is used as a thinking tool (to usea term from Wittgenstein) for experimentati<strong>on</strong>, in a sense, instead of asa way to c<strong>on</strong>struct and to verify the existence of solid relati<strong>on</strong>s.Finally, my focus <strong>on</strong> the lack of a Bourdieuean perspective was topropose that the discourses in <strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong> are not neutral. Therule of methodologies in methodology courses should not be regardedas natural but need to be investigated at all times as to what is beingneglected.Acknowledgements and a technical noteI thank my colleagues at the Department of Educati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>Umeå</strong> University,Sweden, for support, especially Erik, Christina and Tommy whoprovided helpful suggesti<strong>on</strong>s at the draft stage of this article. I wish tothank Torborg and Anneli for translati<strong>on</strong>s of French statistical texts andhelp in making my illustrati<strong>on</strong>s presentable. Thanks also to BirgittaTörnkvist, Department of Statistics, <strong>Umeå</strong> University, for comments<strong>on</strong> my drawing of Figure 2. My special thanks go to Lisbeth Lundahl(<strong>Umeå</strong>) and Thomas Popkewitz (Madis<strong>on</strong>), and the <strong>on</strong>-going graduatestudent/<strong>teacher</strong> exchange programme between <strong>Umeå</strong> University, Departmentof Educati<strong>on</strong>, and University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin-Madis<strong>on</strong>, Schoolof Educati<strong>on</strong> (I also received support in my work from the Bank ofSweden’s Tercentenary Foundati<strong>on</strong>).Details about the arithmetical calculati<strong>on</strong>s for corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysisare to be found in the standard reference literature. 25 All the corresp<strong>on</strong>denceanalyses in this article were performed using the program73


SimCA2 written by Greenacre. 26 Figures 1 and 3 show the results in theform of so-called symmetric figures. The amount of total inertia(explained variance) represented in these figures is 12 and 15%. 27ReferencesBecher, T. (1994). The Significance of Disciplinary Differences. Studies in HigherEducati<strong>on</strong>, 19, 151-161.Benzécri, J.-P., et al. (1973). L´Analyse des D<strong>on</strong>nées. Tome 1-3. Paris: Dunod.Bourdieu, P. (1984 [1979]). Distincti<strong>on</strong>. A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste, Englishtranslati<strong>on</strong>. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Bourdieu, P. (1988 [1984]). Homo Academicus, English translati<strong>on</strong>. Cambridge: PolityPress.Bourdieu, P. (1996 [1989]). The State Nobility — Élite Schools in the Field of Power,English translati<strong>on</strong>. Cambridge: Polity Press.Bourdieu, P., & Wacquant, L.J.D. (1992). An Invitati<strong>on</strong> to Reflexive Sociology. Cambridge:Polity Press.Broady, D. (1988). Jean-Paul Benzécri och korresp<strong>on</strong>densanalysen [Jean-Paul Benzécri andcorresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis. In Swedish]. Forskning och utveckling för högskolan, 4,Stockholm: UHÄ.Broady, D. (1990). Sociologi och epistemologi. Om Pierre Bourdieus författarskap och denhistoriska epistemologin [Sociology and Epistemology. On Pierre Bourdieu’s Workand the Historical Epistemology. Academic dissertati<strong>on</strong>, in Swedish with asummary in English]. The Department of Educati<strong>on</strong>al Research, StockholmInstitute of Educati<strong>on</strong>, Stockholm: HLS Förlag.Broady, D., & Heyman, I. (1997). Omvårdnadsforskning. Ett vetenskapligt fält ivardande? [Caring and Nursing Research. An Emerging Scientific Field? InSwedish with a summary in English]. Pedagogisk Forskning i Sverige, 4, 193-209.Broady, D., & Palme, M. (1992). Högskolan som fält och studenternas livsbanor [Highereducati<strong>on</strong> as a field and the social trajectories of students. In Swedish]. Rapporterfrån forskningsgruppen för utbildnings- och kultursociologi, 1, Stockholm:Stockholm Institute of Educati<strong>on</strong>, the Department of Educati<strong>on</strong>al Research.Böckenholt, U., & Böckenholt, I. (1990). Can<strong>on</strong>ical Analysis of C<strong>on</strong>tingency Tableswith Linear C<strong>on</strong>straints. Psychometrika, 55, 633-639.Böckenholt, U., & Takane, Y. (1994). Linear C<strong>on</strong>straints in Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence Analysis, in:Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence Analysis in the Social Sciences, eds. Michael Greenacre and JörgBlasius. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Academic Press, 112-127.Gifi, A. (1990). N<strong>on</strong>-linear Multivariate Analysis. Chichester, UK: Wiley.Graue, M.E. (Forthcoming). Through a Very Small Window. How Standardized TestsShape Early Childhood Research. Prepared for B. Spodek, et al. (Eds.), Yearbookof Early Childhood Educati<strong>on</strong>.Greenacre, M.J. (1984). Theory and Applicati<strong>on</strong> of Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence Analysis. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>:Academic Press.Greenacre, M.J. (1986). SimCA — A Program to Perform Simple Corresp<strong>on</strong>denceAnalysis. Psychometrika, 51, 172-173.Greenacre, M.J. (1988). Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence Analysis <strong>on</strong> a Pers<strong>on</strong>al Computer. Chemometricsand Intelligent Laboratory Systems, 2, 233-234.Greenacre, M.J. (1993). Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence Analysis in Practice. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Academic Press.74


Greenacre, M.J., & Blasius, J. (eds.) (1994). Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence Analysis in the Social Sciences.L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Academic Press.Hacking, I. (1991). How Should We do the History of Statistics?, in: The Foucault Effect.Studies in Governmentality, eds. Graham Burchell, Colin Gord<strong>on</strong> & Peter Miller.L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 181-198.Heyman, I. (1996). Gånge hatt till... Omvårdnadsforskningens framväxt i Sverige —Sjuksköterskors avhandlingar 1974-1991 [The Emergence of Nursing Research inSweden. Doctoral Theses Written by Nurses 1974-1991. Academic dissertati<strong>on</strong>,in Swedish with a summary in English]. The Department of Educati<strong>on</strong>alResearch, Stockholm Institute of Educati<strong>on</strong>. Stockholm: Daidalos.Kennedy, J.J., & Tam, H.P. (1994). Log-Linear Models, in: The Internati<strong>on</strong>alEncyclopaedia of Educati<strong>on</strong>, eds. Torsten Husén and T. Neville Postlethwaite.Oxford: Elsevier Science, 3499-3508.Kuh, G.D. (1995). Cultivating ‘High-Stakes´ Student Culture Research. Research in HigherEducati<strong>on</strong>, 36, 5, 563-576.Lautrey, J., & Cibois, P. (1991). Applicati<strong>on</strong> of Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence Analysis to a L<strong>on</strong>gitudinalStudy of Cognitive Development, in: Problems and Methods in L<strong>on</strong>gitudinalResearch, eds. D. Magnuss<strong>on</strong>, L.R. Bergman, G. Rudinger, & B. Törestad.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 190-211.Lebart, L., Morineau, A., & Warwick, K.M. (1984). Multivariate Descriptive StatisticalAnalysis. Chichester, UK: Wiley.Rosén, M. & Wernerss<strong>on</strong>, I. (1996). Kunskapsmönster och kön. Om nödvändigheten avkvantitativ feministisk forskning i pedagogik [Patterns of knowledge and gender.The need for feminist quantitative research in educati<strong>on</strong>al science. In Swedish].Pedagogisk forskning i Sverige, 1, 8-24.Räty, H., Snellman, L., Mantysaari-Hetekorpi, H., & Vornanen, A. (1996). Parents’Views <strong>on</strong> the Comprehensive School and its Development: A Finnish Study.Scandinavian Journal of Educati<strong>on</strong>al Research, 4, 3, 203-215.Schiltz, M.-A. (1990). A French Re-analysis of a British Survey. Comparative Study ofStatistical Methods Applied to Social Science Data. CAMS (Centre d’Analyse et deMathématique Sociales), report P.055, Paris.Shilling, C. (1993). The Body and Social Theory. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: SAGE.Sikula, J. (Ed.) (1996). Handbook of Research <strong>on</strong> Teacher Educati<strong>on</strong>. Sec<strong>on</strong>d editi<strong>on</strong>.L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Prentice Hall Internati<strong>on</strong>al.Takane, Y., Bozdogan, H., & Shibayama, T. (1987). Ideal Point Discriminant Analysis.Psychometrika, 52, 371-392.Törnkvist, B., & Lundquist, B. (1997). Hur kan man undervisa i statistik [How is itpossible to teach statistics. In Swedish]. Utbildning i förändring, Universitetspedagogiskk<strong>on</strong>ferens i <strong>Umeå</strong> 20-21 februari, k<strong>on</strong>ferensrapport, <strong>Umeå</strong> Universitet,Enheten för pers<strong>on</strong>alutveckling, 92-102.Notes1Although it plays no great part in their main study programme for the majority ofstudents, they are quite often required to study statistics for an examinati<strong>on</strong> (Törnkvist& Lundquist, 1997, 92).2I argue that the focus is <strong>on</strong> methods of sampling, the computati<strong>on</strong> of mean values andcorrelati<strong>on</strong>s, the normal (“bell shaped”) curve etc. (See also Graue, forthcoming). In75


statistics textbooks used in programmes for <strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong> (and also in graduateprogrammes at schools of educati<strong>on</strong> and pedagogy), the debate seems to centre, in myview, <strong>on</strong> such questi<strong>on</strong>s as what to do when the example data set from a study violatessample size or other requirements needed to perform classical statistics, rather than <strong>on</strong>discussi<strong>on</strong>s about graphical and exploratory alternatives, which exploit the flexibility ofinteractive computing and graphic displays.3Am<strong>on</strong>g the scholars with an exploratory and iterative approach to the use of statisticalanalysis in educati<strong>on</strong>al research <strong>on</strong>e can list D<strong>on</strong>ald Broady and Michael Palme (Broady,1988 & 1990, 501, 505-506, and Broady & Palme, 1992) and Ingrid Heyman (1996;Broady & Heyman, 1997).4I will introduce corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis (a statistical technique used by Bourdieu) to thereader who is not familiar with this method (this brief and n<strong>on</strong>-mathematical introducti<strong>on</strong>will simultaneously dem<strong>on</strong>strate the graphical aspects of corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis, andindicate how the results of such investigati<strong>on</strong>s can be presented) and discuss Bourdieu’sstatistical epistemology. Bourdieu uses corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis in several of his books,e.g. Distincti<strong>on</strong> (1984 [1979]) and Homo Academicus (1988 [1984]). Bourdieu picturesand interprets a “social space”, by using corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis, in Distincti<strong>on</strong> (1984[1979]). In Homo Academicus (1988 [1984]) the “social space” of French professors isdescribed in cross-tables with categories that describe “marital status”, “membership infaculty”, “occupati<strong>on</strong> of parents” etc., and by subsequent analyses using corresp<strong>on</strong>denceanalysis.5Here I refer to statistical methods based <strong>on</strong> the idea that the interplay in a table can bedescribed by linear relati<strong>on</strong>ships, so-called linear models (Kennedy & Tam, 1994),discriminant analysis, that classifies data according to selected criteria (Takane, Bozdogan& Shibayama, 1987), statistical methods based <strong>on</strong> Pears<strong>on</strong>’s familiar chi-square value(chi-square is based <strong>on</strong> the idea, or the statistical model, that the differences betweenexpected and empirical values in a cross-table can be used as an overall measure of variati<strong>on</strong>in the data) and similar techniques.6I refer to investigati<strong>on</strong>s and studies that try to fit data to a model, and that often bearsuch titles as ...testing a statistical model of socialisati<strong>on</strong> am<strong>on</strong>g..., or a mathematical modelfor integrati<strong>on</strong> in... etc.7One such approach is the data analysis approach which emerged in the 1960s and -70sin France. The theories and practices of this data analysis traditi<strong>on</strong>, often referred to asanalyse des d<strong>on</strong>nées in French, as interesting complements to those of classical statistics(Schiltz, 1990), have in my opini<strong>on</strong> by and large been met with polite ignorance bysocial science communities outside France. The classical statistical tools, such as factoranalysis and log-linear analysis, are by far the most popular statistical techniques atuniversities and colleges and in undergraduate and graduate studies today, includingeducati<strong>on</strong>al research and <strong>teacher</strong> training.8At this point it is a good thing to make clear that the statistical algorithms that performthe analyses do not interpret the figures. That is left to the user. It is not too much to saythat the name corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis can be seen as being somewhat misleading, as thefigures describe rather than analyse the data.9Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis can be used to investigate the inter-relati<strong>on</strong>ship between therows, the columns or both the rows and columns simultaneously of a cross-table. Origi-76


nal data can be <strong>on</strong> a categorical or ordinal level and the matrices do not have to besymmetric, as in some classical analyses. The technique is multidimensi<strong>on</strong>al, in the sensethat it operates <strong>on</strong> tables with <strong>on</strong>e variable, two variables or K-variables (K ≥ 3). In thisarticle, the focus is <strong>on</strong> the analysis of columns and K-tables.10The survey is a part of an <strong>on</strong>-going research project, run by myself, Christer J<strong>on</strong>ss<strong>on</strong> andheaded by Prof. Martin Johanss<strong>on</strong>, at the Department of Educati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>Umeå</strong> University,Sweden. Eventually, I will report parts of the investigati<strong>on</strong> as my thesis.11An opposite view would be to c<strong>on</strong>sider it possible to investigate the body purely as abiological phenomen<strong>on</strong>. For a discussi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of bodies, see Shilling,1993.12It is not the main purpose of this article to discuss in detail how figures in corresp<strong>on</strong>denceanalyses can be interpreted. For further reference see the literature, e.g. Greenacre &Blasius (eds.), 1994, 45-52.13The use of cut-off limits, for categories that do not c<strong>on</strong>tribute well enough to a figure, isbriefly discussed in Bourdieu, 1984 [1979], 266, figure 13. An account of the c<strong>on</strong>ceptof c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong> is given in Broady 1990, 495, and Greenacre & Blasius (eds.) 1994, 35,51, 66, 69 & 263.14In Distincti<strong>on</strong>, (1984 [1979], e.g. 127-130), Bourdieu interprets a “social space” (whichis his synthesis of a “space of social positi<strong>on</strong>s” and a “space of lifestyles”), by usingcorresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis. This analysis of the data is based <strong>on</strong> a multi-resp<strong>on</strong>se table(similar to Table 1 above) where the rows and columns represent professi<strong>on</strong>al positi<strong>on</strong>sand categories of lifestyles (See also Greenacre & Blasius, eds., 1994, 133-134).15When a figure is interpreted, the middle point, the origin of coordinates, is often used asa point of reference, e.g. in terms of the angular directi<strong>on</strong> of categories relative the origin.See Lautrey & Cibois, 1991, 190-211.16In Swedish academia, a “Nati<strong>on</strong>”, a category found to the south-east in the figure, nearthe origin of coordinates, is a type of student club that arranges social meetings, parties,trips etc.17See also Sikula, 1996, 473, and Törnkvist & Lundquist, 1997.18I argue that it takes some time to develop these abilities (they will not necessarily manifestthemselves at the end of methodology courses).19An increased market orientati<strong>on</strong> in educati<strong>on</strong> has been discernible since the 1980-90s,according to the authors. Individual choice, reform, giftedness and the opening of moreand more private schools are some of the c<strong>on</strong>cepts and agendas c<strong>on</strong>tributing to thistrend.20Socio-ec<strong>on</strong>omic status was categorised using the Finnish statistical office’s censuscategories: entrepreneurs, upper-level employees, lower-level employees and workers.The number of school-age children the parents had and the gender of these childrenwere also used as variables in the statistical analyses.21This transformati<strong>on</strong> is made with no further explanati<strong>on</strong>. I am not arguing against this— the authors are admitting to no more than the comm<strong>on</strong>place pragmatism of all research—, but as a reader I would like to know more about the reas<strong>on</strong>s behinds thiscategorisati<strong>on</strong>. Why are not 1 and 2 fused into <strong>on</strong>e category, 3 another (which could, insome cases, be excluded, based <strong>on</strong> the distributi<strong>on</strong> of data) and 4 and 5 a third?22The style and c<strong>on</strong>tent of Räty, et al. (1996) suggests, at least to me, that the authors77


work in a traditi<strong>on</strong> and in an envir<strong>on</strong>ment — a certain paradigm, to paraphrase Kuhn—, where the heritage from classical statistic methodology is str<strong>on</strong>g. The dispositi<strong>on</strong> ofthe study, with its subject headings: Background, Method, Result and Discussi<strong>on</strong>, is in thestyle and format of traditi<strong>on</strong>al, “quality c<strong>on</strong>trol”, hypothesis testing analyses. Räty, et al.(1996) might have tried different ways of categorising and analysing attitudes andsatisfacti<strong>on</strong> variables (in analysing and re-analysing the data — similar to Bourdieu’smethodology, as described in my Figure 2 above), but no evidence of that is given in thestudy.23That would result in a figure by corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis with variables to be described(attitudes and satisfacti<strong>on</strong> variables) and descriptive variables (e.g. socio-ec<strong>on</strong>omic data),similar to Räty et al.’s results (1996).24An implementati<strong>on</strong> of Bourdieu’s statistical epistemology does not imply that classicalstatistics should be aband<strong>on</strong>ed. Some statistical articles and books <strong>on</strong> corresp<strong>on</strong>denceanalysis (See for instance Böckenholt & Böckenholt, 1990, and Böckenholt & Takane,1994) discuss the possibility of combining corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis with other, classical,statistical method (significance testings, so-called statistical c<strong>on</strong>straints etc.) in the searchfor structural relati<strong>on</strong>ships and in the analysis of the strength and nature of theserelati<strong>on</strong>ships. Further, to be able to find pleasure in using quantitative analysis, a certainamount of respect, intuiti<strong>on</strong> and an ability to interpret is needed. The difference isminor in this respect between the use of classical statistics or Bourdieu’s statisticalepistemology (or between quantitative or qualitative methods for that matter. See Rosén& Wernerss<strong>on</strong>, 1996, 12.).25Benzécri et al., 1973 — a “classic” reference for readers who have a good command ofFrench —, Greenacre, 1984 & 1993, Lebart, Morineau, & Warwick, 1984, Gifi, 1990and Greenacre & Blasius, (eds.), 1994 are some of the more frequently cited statisticalbooks which focus more or less <strong>on</strong> corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis and its applicati<strong>on</strong>s for thesocial sciences.26Michael Greenacre, “SimCA2”: Michael Greenacre, Departament d’Ec<strong>on</strong>omia i Empresa,Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Ram<strong>on</strong> Trias Fargas, 25-27, 08005 Barcel<strong>on</strong>a, Spain. Theprogram is discussed by Greenacre in two articles: Greenacre, 1986 & 1988.27This amount is a measure of how well a two-dimensi<strong>on</strong>al figure of a simple or a multiplecorresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis depicts the true, multidimensi<strong>on</strong>al spread of all its categories,from a geometrical point of view. For reference to explained variance, or inertia as it isreferred to in the literature <strong>on</strong> corresp<strong>on</strong>dence analysis, see Greenacre & Blasius (eds.)1994, 12-14. Symmetric and asymmetric figures are discussed <strong>on</strong> pages 10, 18-21 and259 in the same book.78


EVA ÅSTRÖMComputers as Panoptic<strong>on</strong> -The Face of The Market in anEducati<strong>on</strong>al SettingComputers in distance educati<strong>on</strong> - electr<strong>on</strong>ic Panoptic<strong>on</strong>s - might be regardedas expressi<strong>on</strong>s of market ideology within the educati<strong>on</strong>al system, transformedinto educati<strong>on</strong>al practice. And this market ideology is manifested inmore than <strong>on</strong>e way. It does not <strong>on</strong>ly show itself in the form of computersserving as devices of c<strong>on</strong>trol and fosterers of flexibility. The ideology of marketsand modern capitalism can also be traced in the role that distance educati<strong>on</strong>plays today, as a ”test bed” offering possibilities to test and apply telecommunicati<strong>on</strong>technology within (especially) higher educati<strong>on</strong>. The informati<strong>on</strong>technology has created the boundlessness necessary to pave the way for forcesof the market place and competiti<strong>on</strong> inside the system.When it comes to theintroducti<strong>on</strong> of informati<strong>on</strong> technology and distance educati<strong>on</strong> ineducati<strong>on</strong>al settings, there is also a close c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> between this discourseand ec<strong>on</strong>omical/political str<strong>on</strong>g interests. But this c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> is most oftenobscured, the power interests behind it and supporting it are kept hidden.Instead the discourse in questi<strong>on</strong> - informati<strong>on</strong> technology, open learning -is presented as ”natural” and ”inevitable” in our c<strong>on</strong>temporary and futuresociety.”Structure” and ”Dialogue” in Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>In the early 70s a theory was developed by M. Moore <strong>on</strong> distanceeducati<strong>on</strong> in which ”distance” was defined as a functi<strong>on</strong> of two variables,namely ”dialogue” and ”structure”. The definiti<strong>on</strong>s of the two c<strong>on</strong>ceptsthat were compiled by Rumble are cited in Moore (1990): 1 ”Dialoguedescribes the extent to which, in any educati<strong>on</strong>al programme, learner andeducator are able to resp<strong>on</strong>d to each other. This is determined by the c<strong>on</strong>tentof subject-matter which is studied, by the educati<strong>on</strong>al philosophy of theeducator, by the pers<strong>on</strong>alities of educator and learner, and by envir<strong>on</strong>mentalfactors, the most important of which is the medium of communicati<strong>on</strong>.””Structure is a measure of an educati<strong>on</strong> programme’s resp<strong>on</strong>siveness to learners’81


individual needs. It expresses the extent to which educati<strong>on</strong>al objectives, teachingstrategies, and evaluati<strong>on</strong> methods are prepared for, or can be adapted to, theobjectives, strategies, and evaluati<strong>on</strong> methods of the learner.” (p. 10)Based <strong>on</strong> these definiti<strong>on</strong>s, the most ”distant” educati<strong>on</strong> is the <strong>on</strong>ewithout both dialogue and structure, that is, it is completely self-directed.The least distant educati<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sists of much dialogue and littleprefabricated structure. The distance–the functi<strong>on</strong> of ”structure” and”dialogue”–is called ”transacti<strong>on</strong>al distance”. The form of educati<strong>on</strong>that we normally refer to as ”distance educati<strong>on</strong>” becomes characterizedby more structure, less dialogue and thereby more transacti<strong>on</strong>al distancethan other educati<strong>on</strong>al forms.In the above article, Moore also refers to the research c<strong>on</strong>ducted bySaba, which, according to Moore, has ”...c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ted the problems presentedto distance educati<strong>on</strong> theory by interactive telecommunicati<strong>on</strong>s andexpanded the c<strong>on</strong>cept of transacti<strong>on</strong>al distance by using systems dynamics.” 2Saba talks about ”integrated telecommunicati<strong>on</strong>s systems” and statesthat by maximizing dialogue via integrated systems the transacti<strong>on</strong>aldistance is minimized. The relati<strong>on</strong> between the degrees of structureand dialogue is c<strong>on</strong>sidered dynamic: when dialogue increases, structuredecreases and when structure decreases, dialogue in turn increases tostabilize the system. Moreover, ”integrated systems provide a flexible meansfor decreasing structure through increased dialogue.” 3While Saba speaks of integrated telecommunicati<strong>on</strong>s systems as a meansof increasing dialogue in distance educati<strong>on</strong>, Wagner (1994), Lauz<strong>on</strong> (1992)and J<strong>on</strong>assen et al. (1995) discuss the ”comm<strong>on</strong> percepti<strong>on</strong>” that the potentialof the new technology–specifically computer c<strong>on</strong>ferencing systemsand electr<strong>on</strong>ic mail, according to the latter authors–lies in its ability toimprove interacti<strong>on</strong> and dialogue in (distance) educati<strong>on</strong>. It is presumedthat the new technology will cause dialogue c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s to increase indistance educati<strong>on</strong>, which, according to the above theory, in turn causesthe degree of structure to decrease. In other words, flexibility and individualadaptability increases, and the end result is that transacti<strong>on</strong>al distance ineducati<strong>on</strong> decreases. The distance decreases between <strong>teacher</strong> and learnerand in the distance educati<strong>on</strong>, while proximity increases.The fact that this is a beneficial development is both explicitly and tacitlyexpressed by the authors in their respective articles.82


But, is ”increased proximity” in distance educati<strong>on</strong> really (<strong>on</strong>ly)beneficial? May (1993) states, for example, that increased interacti<strong>on</strong> isnot necessarily a positive educati<strong>on</strong>al goal. In her article she refers toCook, 4 who calls attenti<strong>on</strong> to such questi<strong>on</strong>s as, which interactiveelements in educati<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>stitute ”c<strong>on</strong>tact” and what is in fact ”c<strong>on</strong>trol”or is at least apprehended as c<strong>on</strong>trol by the student. She also refers toHughes and Kennedy, 5 who suggest that a str<strong>on</strong>g relati<strong>on</strong>ship betweenthe <strong>teacher</strong> and the student might c<strong>on</strong>stitute a circle of dependency.Moore (1990) draws the c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> that when there is little dialogueand structure it is difficult for the instructor to c<strong>on</strong>trol the learner, andthat with more structure and, above all, more dialogue the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>sthat c<strong>on</strong>tribute to instituti<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>trol increase. Other authors placeeven more stress <strong>on</strong> specifically dialogue as an instrument of c<strong>on</strong>trol indistance educati<strong>on</strong> settings. In this c<strong>on</strong>text, Juler (1990) points to thefact that both oral and written dialogue (discourse) are often <strong>teacher</strong>dominated, which seriously limits the degree and nature of the interacti<strong>on</strong>that can take place in a distance course. He refers to ”the apparentc<strong>on</strong>flict between interacti<strong>on</strong> and independence.” 6Dialogue–or interacti<strong>on</strong>–can therefore be regarded as both anexpressi<strong>on</strong> and a means of c<strong>on</strong>trol in a distance educati<strong>on</strong> setting. Incomputer-mediated communicati<strong>on</strong>, dialogue as a potential for c<strong>on</strong>trolis related to the visibility of text-based communicati<strong>on</strong> and thesurveillance that is facilitated by this visibility <strong>on</strong> both an individualand a group level.The C<strong>on</strong>trol SocietyIn his book Discipline and Punish, Michel Foucault discusses thereplacement of the sovereign society by a new disciplinary society. Thissociety is characterized by discipline as the prevailing principle of c<strong>on</strong>troland educati<strong>on</strong>, and the disciplinary exercise of power for maintainingrelati<strong>on</strong>s of power and dominance.Foucault dates the emergence of the disciplinary society back to theseventeenth and eighteenth centuries of Europe, to the genesis of industrialismand a sharp populati<strong>on</strong> increase for that time–the growing,costlier and more complex producti<strong>on</strong> apparatus needed to become moreefficient and ever-growing numbers of landless and propertyless citizens83


needed to be c<strong>on</strong>trolled and governed. Signs of the disciplinary exerciseof power could first be recognized in the French sec<strong>on</strong>dary grammarschools and elementary schools. Discipline as a mechanism of powerthen spread over to hospitals, to the military organizati<strong>on</strong>, to the rest ofthe school system, and to the manufactories.This course has been maintained up to our times. The disciplinary societyhas c<strong>on</strong>tinued to spread and develop and the attending disciplinarypower is exercised <strong>on</strong> most levels and within most areas of society.Discipline, according to Foucault, is a political technology that canbe described with the help of Panoptic<strong>on</strong> as a metaphor: Bentham’sPanoptic<strong>on</strong> refers to a circular building surrounding an open area witha high tower placed in the center of the area. This tower has large windowsfacing the inner side of the building. The circular building is dividedinto traversing cells. Each cell has two windows, <strong>on</strong>e facing the insideand the windows of the tower, and the other window facing the outside,letting in the light that penetrates the cell from <strong>on</strong>e side to the other.From the top of the tower it is possible to supervise all the cellssimultaneously and each of them individually without being visible.The <strong>on</strong>ly thing that can be seen from the cells is a tower with large,blind, and an<strong>on</strong>ymous windows at the top. The main effect of thePanoptic<strong>on</strong> is created through this c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>: The inhabitant of thecell is visible all the time, but he or she has no way of knowing if anysurveillance is actually taking place. The surveillance thus becomes permanentin its effect, and power becomes so complete that it does nothave to be exercised.In theory, the Panoptic<strong>on</strong> is a schedule showing the mechanism ofpower in its ideal form. It describes how power is made perpetuallypresent in the c<strong>on</strong>sciousness of people and how it governs and thereforedisciplines without having to use very str<strong>on</strong>g means, threats, orpunishments. Power does not become a burden placed up<strong>on</strong> thepowerless; instead it becomes a subtle, an<strong>on</strong>ymous, and ever-presenteye, staring at the individual, studying him, analyzing and judging him.Perhaps. This is the point. Exposed to the panoptical way of exercisingpower, the individual can never be sure if he or she is being watched ornot. The <strong>on</strong>ly sure thing is that surveillance–total and permanent–ispossible all the time. There is no place to hide.84


The practical/physical processes up<strong>on</strong> which disciplinary power(illustrated in the form of Panoptic<strong>on</strong>) primarily rests are hierarchizedsurveillance and normalizing sancti<strong>on</strong>s, the methods of which arecombined in the examinati<strong>on</strong> process. Hierarchized surveillance is anarrangement that works like a network of relati<strong>on</strong>ships where every<strong>on</strong>einvolved is c<strong>on</strong>stantly visible. Every<strong>on</strong>e can be seen and can see every<strong>on</strong>eelse at all times. The normalizing sancti<strong>on</strong>s are the system’s punishmentmechanism. Its functi<strong>on</strong> is to correct all deviati<strong>on</strong>s from (the established)order, all negligence and all rule violati<strong>on</strong>s. Normalizati<strong>on</strong> isbegotten by way of comparis<strong>on</strong>, differentiati<strong>on</strong>, hierarchizati<strong>on</strong>,standardizati<strong>on</strong> and exclusi<strong>on</strong>. The examinati<strong>on</strong> process is central tothe disciplinary processes. C<strong>on</strong>tinuous examinati<strong>on</strong> shapes the individualas the effect of and the subject for knowledge. During this process thepower structure both collects (individualized) knowledge andimplements (legitimizing) knowledge.According to Deleuze (1992), Foucault’s disciplinary society ischaracterized by c<strong>on</strong>finement–it is a closed system. It is a society wherec<strong>on</strong>centrati<strong>on</strong>, organizati<strong>on</strong> of time and distributi<strong>on</strong> of space are usedto gather productive strength within this time-space dimensi<strong>on</strong>, theeffect of which will be greater than the sum of its comp<strong>on</strong>ents. Thedisciplinary society individualizes, and individual deviati<strong>on</strong>s anddysfuncti<strong>on</strong>s that become visible in this way are defined and correctedaccording to the standards of normality. The predominant goal insociety’s educati<strong>on</strong> is unanimity and homogenous groups that functi<strong>on</strong>as comp<strong>on</strong>ents of a well-functi<strong>on</strong>ing societal machine. The factory–theoperati<strong>on</strong> of which depends <strong>on</strong> machines that require energy–is themode of producti<strong>on</strong> of the disciplinary society and most aspects of sociallife can be described symbolically by the metaphors that spring fromthis type of producti<strong>on</strong> mode.Foucault himself was aware of the precarious nature of this model.He described the disciplinary society as the successor to the sovereignsociety. Deleuze maintains that, at least during the entire post-war period,development has caused the disciplinary society to change and toin turn be replaced by a new type of society today. Deleuze speaks of thec<strong>on</strong>trol society, 7 a new regime within which liberating and oppressiveforces meet in a new way, under new c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s.85


In the c<strong>on</strong>trol society, efficiency is no l<strong>on</strong>ger necessarily associated withhuge like-minded masses, but rather more so with the flexible and smoothadaptati<strong>on</strong> of the individual parts to changing c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s. The factoryhas lost its validity as a metaphor, now it is the ”company” and the”market” that decides and governs what ideas about society and lifedominate. Deleuze designates the computer as the machine that bestcharacterizes the new c<strong>on</strong>trol society. He identifies c<strong>on</strong>tinuous c<strong>on</strong>troland c<strong>on</strong>tinuing educati<strong>on</strong> as typical of its school and educati<strong>on</strong> systems.It is a limitless and ever-changing society, with a power mechanism thatfuncti<strong>on</strong>s freely–independently of time and space. Its goal is to createc<strong>on</strong>tinuous and everlasting adaptati<strong>on</strong> and change with respect to shiftingand perpetually changing c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s. The purpose of individualizati<strong>on</strong>is no l<strong>on</strong>ger to find the most effective place for the individual am<strong>on</strong>gthe greater masses, but rather primarily to create independence,competitiveness and mutual competiti<strong>on</strong> by developing a broad rangeof pers<strong>on</strong>al capabilities and qualificati<strong>on</strong>s.The three types of society menti<strong>on</strong>ed so far in the paper, differdistinctly from each other with reference to their ways of relating andhandling individual and collective freedom of thought and acti<strong>on</strong>. Theforms of governing and c<strong>on</strong>trol are fundamentally different in thesouvereign society, the disciplinary society and the c<strong>on</strong>trol societyrespectively. Also the ”c<strong>on</strong>tent” of government - which thoughts andwhat behaviour to c<strong>on</strong>trol - are different. However, the fundamentalpurpose of governing remains the same in all three of them. Foucaultdefines ”government” as an art ”for acting <strong>on</strong> the acti<strong>on</strong>s of individuals,taken either singly or collectively, so as to shape, guide, correct and modifythe ways in which they c<strong>on</strong>duct themselves.” 8 The joint purpose of steeringand c<strong>on</strong>trol for every and each of the three societies thus becomes to actup<strong>on</strong> and influence the thoughts and acti<strong>on</strong>s of its citizens, in thedirecti<strong>on</strong> and by the means provided and c<strong>on</strong>sidered appropriate ineither society.Therefore it involves no c<strong>on</strong>tradicti<strong>on</strong> to find the panoptic principleat work both in the disciplinary society and in the c<strong>on</strong>trol society. ThePanoptic<strong>on</strong> has survived the society’s transformati<strong>on</strong>, it has developedand adapted to the needs of the new times. Possibly the most obviouschange is the <strong>on</strong>e that is taking place with regard to the normalizati<strong>on</strong>86


principle of the disciplinary society. Normality as a c<strong>on</strong>cept and a qualitybecomes less important in a world with weak norms. In the c<strong>on</strong>trolsociety, little emphasis is placed <strong>on</strong> established or enduring norms. Thec<strong>on</strong>trol that is carried out within the panoptic structure of this societyaims to counteract the emergence of these types of closed thought andbehavior patterns. They inhibit dynamics, obstruct flexibility andcompliance, and in this way halt development.With less emphasis put <strong>on</strong> the establishing and submissi<strong>on</strong> to norms,the forms of supervisi<strong>on</strong> need to develop too. They have to be smoother,more flexible and more all-seeing than ever. New techniques for examinati<strong>on</strong>develop - the use of for example auditing and accounting forexaminati<strong>on</strong> and as methods for steering at a distance becomes morewide-spread. And the products of examinati<strong>on</strong>, the knowledge c<strong>on</strong>veyedand knowledge c<strong>on</strong>structed in this process, becomes more detailed andat the same time more general.With norms, supervisi<strong>on</strong> and examinati<strong>on</strong> - steering and c<strong>on</strong>trol -more invisible than ever, the Panoptic<strong>on</strong> of the c<strong>on</strong>trol society of todayis hidden under a cover of ”freedom”. But according to Foucault, freedomis just another formula of rule. It is not <strong>on</strong>ly a hindrance togovernment, but also a resource for it. ”Freedom, in a liberal sense, shouldthus not be equated with anarchy, but with a kind of well-regulated and’resp<strong>on</strong>sibilized’ liberty.” 9 In today’s Panoptic<strong>on</strong> the governing of individualsaims at no particular external directi<strong>on</strong>, but to the creati<strong>on</strong> of thefree subject, vol<strong>on</strong>tarily and freely c<strong>on</strong>ducting himself or herself inaccordance with society’s priorities. It is also a questi<strong>on</strong> of creating awillingness to change - the individual’s willingness to change in any givenway. Freedom and flexibility are apprehended as both goals and meansin this c<strong>on</strong>temporary discourse of c<strong>on</strong>duct, at the same time as they areeffects of the governing process itself.The Computer As Panoptic<strong>on</strong>Deleuze suggests that different types of machines can be matched todifferent types of societies, since the machines, in his view, reflect howthe social forms that design and use them appear. Accordingly, he designatesthe computer as the machine of our times (of the c<strong>on</strong>trol society).The plausibility of Deleuze’s view <strong>on</strong> the computer is further reinforced87


y Poster’s (1990) descripti<strong>on</strong> of electr<strong>on</strong>ic (computer-based)communicati<strong>on</strong>: ”Writing is framed by space/time coordinates of booksand sheets of paper. Both are available to logics of representati<strong>on</strong>. Electr<strong>on</strong>iclanguage, <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>trary, does not lend itself to being so framed. It iseverywhere and nowhere, always and never. It is truly material/immaterial.” 10This free-flowing and omnipresent communicati<strong>on</strong> fits well into thelimitless, ever-changing and individualizing c<strong>on</strong>trol society that Deleuzedescribes above.What, then, is the role of communicati<strong>on</strong>? According to Foucaultcommunicati<strong>on</strong> is fundamentally about exercising power. ”Our societyis not <strong>on</strong>e of spectacle, but of surveillance; under the surface of images, <strong>on</strong>einvests bodies in depth; behind the great abstracti<strong>on</strong> of exchange, therec<strong>on</strong>tinues the meticulous, c<strong>on</strong>crete training of useful forces; the circuits ofcommunicati<strong>on</strong> are the supports of an accumulati<strong>on</strong> and a centralizati<strong>on</strong> ofknowledge; the play of signs defines the anchorages of power...” 11 Earlier inthe text there is also discussi<strong>on</strong> about how (computer-based)communicati<strong>on</strong> can more c<strong>on</strong>cretely be used/functi<strong>on</strong> as governing andc<strong>on</strong>trol instruments in educati<strong>on</strong>al settings.The picture that has been painted in the text this far thus describesthe computer as a central panoptic structure in our times.Zuboff (1988) elaborates <strong>on</strong> this idea further: ”Informati<strong>on</strong> systemsthat translate, record, and display human behavior can provide the computerage versi<strong>on</strong> of universal transparency with a degree of illuminati<strong>on</strong> thatwould have exceeded even Bentham’s most outlandish fantasies. Such systemscan become informati<strong>on</strong> panoptic<strong>on</strong>s that, freed from c<strong>on</strong>straints of spaceand time, do not depend up<strong>on</strong> the physical arrangement of buildings or thelaborious record keeping of industrial administrati<strong>on</strong>. They do not evenrequire the mutual presence of objects of observati<strong>on</strong>. They do not even requirethe presence of an observer. Informati<strong>on</strong> systems can automatically andc<strong>on</strong>tinuously record almost anything their designer want to capture, regardlessof the specific intenti<strong>on</strong>s brought to the design process or the motives thatguide data interpretati<strong>on</strong> and utilizati<strong>on</strong>. The counterpart of the centraltower is a video screen.” 12Panoptic<strong>on</strong> is a c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> that above all aims to make the powerlessvisible and power invisible. Through this c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> power is madeever-present in the c<strong>on</strong>sciousness of all, thereby rendering the actual88


exercise of power unnecessary. These effects are also produced by theelectr<strong>on</strong>ic interacti<strong>on</strong> of computers. In computer-based communicati<strong>on</strong>,both the individual and those processes that take place between individualsbecome visible. Edenius (1996), for example, talks about how in anelectr<strong>on</strong>ic mail system <strong>on</strong>e can get a quick glimpse at large quantities ofinformati<strong>on</strong>; 13 while J<strong>on</strong>assen et al. (1995) discuss how the electr<strong>on</strong>icmedium promotes the visibility of the normally c<strong>on</strong>cealed processesand strategies that are used in the interacti<strong>on</strong>/c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of knowledgein which the group is engaged.The practical processes that the panoptic principle rests up<strong>on</strong> is, ashas been stated before, (hierarchized) surveillance, examinati<strong>on</strong> andnormalizati<strong>on</strong>. All these processes are easily detected in a computerisedstudy/teaching situati<strong>on</strong>.The surveillance functi<strong>on</strong> is built into the computer as a medium. Forexample, in the text-based electr<strong>on</strong>ic c<strong>on</strong>ferencing system, everythingthat is said is made visible to all and is furthermore saved for posterity.The written comments or c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s that are generated, are stored<strong>on</strong> everybody’s computer. This automatic registrati<strong>on</strong> makes it possibleto measure all activity. Such methods of detailed book-keeping are typicalfeatures of the panoptical scheme. Both actual communicati<strong>on</strong> andsilence are recorded. Every<strong>on</strong>e can read what every<strong>on</strong>e else has written;every<strong>on</strong>e can find out who has read the c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s of others, withouthaving written anything themselves; and every<strong>on</strong>e can see who has beencompletely inactive. All communicative acti<strong>on</strong>s or n<strong>on</strong>acti<strong>on</strong>s becomevisible and all the students eventually become aware of this. Activity orpassivity, it makes no difference, the panoptic principle works in eithercase. And it does not work <strong>on</strong>ly for the students. The <strong>teacher</strong>’s behaviouris also made visible and the interacti<strong>on</strong> processes between <strong>teacher</strong> andstudent are registered and stored. In the computerised (virtual) classroomall participants are trapped in a web of looks, mutual supervisi<strong>on</strong> andpotential accountability.Hierarchized surveillance is attended by the normalizati<strong>on</strong> of theindividuals’ behavior. In the collective electr<strong>on</strong>ic communicati<strong>on</strong>s systemthe students educate <strong>on</strong>e another. According to J<strong>on</strong>assen et al.(1995), the visibility of otherwise invisible processes c<strong>on</strong>tributes to theformati<strong>on</strong> of a ”collaborative mental model”; and MacC<strong>on</strong>nell (1994)89


discusses the sense of collective ownership over the c<strong>on</strong>ference thatdevelops in a well-functi<strong>on</strong>ing computer c<strong>on</strong>ference. Tagg (1994) arguesfor a goal-oriented leadership in computer c<strong>on</strong>ferences and proposesthat the students themselves should assume that leadership.The fact that the computer itself becomes the very goal of computerusage–technology for technology’s sake–is not a new phenomen<strong>on</strong>. Today,the fact that the computer and computer literacy are favorablephenomena in society and educati<strong>on</strong> is taken for granted almosteverywhere. Articles by both Goods<strong>on</strong> & Mangan (1996) and Beyn<strong>on</strong>& Mackay (1989) describe and discuss how the computer automaticallyand indiscriminately is credited with possessing (practically unlimited)promise in educati<strong>on</strong>al settings. This anticipated value calls for studentengagement in the electr<strong>on</strong>ic device offered. It also implies a call foreach group member to go further into the fold and to further subordinatehimself to governance and supervisi<strong>on</strong>.In the examinati<strong>on</strong> process, the methods of the hierarchizedsurveillance–authoritative directi<strong>on</strong>/instructi<strong>on</strong>– are ultimatelycombined with the methods of the normalizing sancti<strong>on</strong>s–assessment/judgment. It is in this process that truth and knowledge are produced.”We are subjected to the producti<strong>on</strong> of truth through power and we cannotexercise power except through the producti<strong>on</strong> of truth”. 14 The examinati<strong>on</strong>–thecreati<strong>on</strong> of discursive truth–thus becomes central to thepanoptic exercise of power.In Deleuze’s c<strong>on</strong>trol society–or in the postmodern society, the fundamentalnature of which c<strong>on</strong>forms to that of the c<strong>on</strong>trol society and inmany respects can be recognized in our daily lives–the c<strong>on</strong>tent of theexaminati<strong>on</strong> is nevertheless unclear. It is not even clear whether it hasany c<strong>on</strong>tent at all. The c<strong>on</strong>trol in and of itself often becomes the sole, orat least the dominant objective of both surveillance and assessment.The significance of governing in a decided directi<strong>on</strong> is subordinate tothe significance of c<strong>on</strong>trol and its attendant governing potential. Thispotential of governing lies in its impact <strong>on</strong> society’s citizens, by the waythat it ”...c<strong>on</strong>cerns them at the very heart of themselves by making itsrai<strong>on</strong>ality the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of their active freedom”. 15This c<strong>on</strong>trol is made possible and the governing potential emergesthrough the establishment of an analytical space in which the individual90


ecomes susceptible to being governed and c<strong>on</strong>trolled. According toFoucault (1987), in the disciplinary society the analytical space is a closedenvir<strong>on</strong>ment without c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>s to other places, that is enclosed withinitself. In the space, each individual is put in a specific place, the locati<strong>on</strong>of which is functi<strong>on</strong>al in relati<strong>on</strong> to others and with regard to a task thatis to be performed. The analytical spaces cut out individual segments andestablish operative relati<strong>on</strong>s, they designate places and state values. In theanalytical space every<strong>on</strong>e is also c<strong>on</strong>trolled with regard to time. The scheduleof the disciplinary society is built primarily <strong>on</strong> three principles: theintroducti<strong>on</strong> of time rhythms, required tasks and recurrent lapses. Thisversi<strong>on</strong> of the analytical space correlates with the factory and an industrialmode of producti<strong>on</strong> as prevailing societal metaphors.In the c<strong>on</strong>trol society, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, closed systems are no l<strong>on</strong>gersuitable and accordingly neither are the analytical spaces that structureand hold and lock in place. Computers do not functi<strong>on</strong> this way either.It functi<strong>on</strong>s independently of spatial and temporal boundaries; it permitscommunicati<strong>on</strong>/interacti<strong>on</strong> to take place whenever and wherever.Computers are utilised to increase the degree of dialogue andcommunicati<strong>on</strong> in an educati<strong>on</strong>, and by that to decrease the transacti<strong>on</strong>aldistance between <strong>teacher</strong> and student, or between students. The virtualproximity that is created in this way is a prec<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of the instituti<strong>on</strong>alc<strong>on</strong>trol that takes place in a computerised educati<strong>on</strong>al setting. Asinstruments of c<strong>on</strong>trol, computers establish a virtual analytical spacewithin which it is attenti<strong>on</strong> that is c<strong>on</strong>trolled and not so much the bodyand the deeds. Attenti<strong>on</strong> is directed at the medium and access is created–for practically any message at all.In this way, in a virtual analytical space, both surveillance andnormalizati<strong>on</strong> are aimed at the student’s (active) participati<strong>on</strong> in theelectr<strong>on</strong>ic communicati<strong>on</strong> process; in this way, the very technologyand use thereof are defined in the examinati<strong>on</strong> process as the discursivetruth of the day.Post-Fordism, Open Learning and ComputersA large porti<strong>on</strong> of the scientific literature describes the kind of societythat we live in today in the West, or that we seem to be heading towards.Deleuze speaks of the c<strong>on</strong>trol society. Others call it the postmodern society91


or the informati<strong>on</strong> society, while Edwards (1991), Farnes (1993), Razzol(1993), Raggatt (1993) and Rumble (1995a and 1995b), for example,assume the prevailing producti<strong>on</strong> system as the point of departure intheir analyses and accordingly dub the new society post-Fordist. 16In his article, Edwards (1991) refers to Robin Murray 17 and hisdescripti<strong>on</strong> of Fordism and post-Fordism respectively. According toMurray, Fordism was the prevailing principle of producti<strong>on</strong> and distributi<strong>on</strong>in the West from the late nineteenth century until sometimeinto the 50s and 60s. Similar to Deleuze above, he paints a picture oflarge bureaucratic organizati<strong>on</strong>s where power is centralized and whichare characterized by authoritative relati<strong>on</strong>s–the factory and the welfarestate–that mass produce goods and services for the public. The c<strong>on</strong>sumerdoes not have freedom of choice or influence over the producti<strong>on</strong>process or its products, with the excepti<strong>on</strong> of a small rich minority.There is no freedom within the workforce either. Producti<strong>on</strong> is c<strong>on</strong>trolledfrom the top and, literally or figuratively speaking, modeled after Taylor’sassembly line principle.Murray, however, states that today Fordism has more or less wornout its functi<strong>on</strong>. The principles that drive the ec<strong>on</strong>omy today can insteadbe attributed to the development of technology and specifically to thedevelopment that has taken place within the informati<strong>on</strong> technologyfield, and to the post-Fordist producti<strong>on</strong> system which becomes possible,and is created and established thanks to this development. Technologicalprogress has led to an increase in both the amount of informati<strong>on</strong> andthe speed with which the informati<strong>on</strong> can be gathered and disseminated.Thus, producti<strong>on</strong> (of both goods and services) becomes able to react tomarket demands in a different way than before. One outcome of this isa small-scale, specialized producti<strong>on</strong> process with a short life span whichrelies <strong>on</strong> designs, is based <strong>on</strong> market research and is dependent <strong>on</strong> marketingfor its survival. 18The greater flexibility and susceptibility to change within producti<strong>on</strong>and the ec<strong>on</strong>omy in turn leads to the establishment of new organizati<strong>on</strong>alforms. The large factory where all producti<strong>on</strong> is realized is replaced toan increasingly greater extent by companies to which entrepreneurs orother c<strong>on</strong>tract-bound ”sub-companies” are tied, which provide manyof the services and products that are needed in the company’s primary92


producti<strong>on</strong>. Authoritative bureaucracies are replaced by flat organizati<strong>on</strong>s,specializati<strong>on</strong> by flexibility, and the ideal worker today shouldeither possess specialized, up-to-date knowledge or come equipped withthe most general qualificati<strong>on</strong>s possible.Farnes (1993) suggests that the historical stages of development thatproducti<strong>on</strong> has underg<strong>on</strong>e corresp<strong>on</strong>d to various stages of developmentwithin educati<strong>on</strong>. 19 According to this reas<strong>on</strong>ing, apprenticeships isassociated with the preindustrial society; mass educati<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> the primaryand lower sec<strong>on</strong>dary school level takes place in the early industrial society;in the Fordist society, upper sec<strong>on</strong>dary educati<strong>on</strong> became theobjective of a mass educati<strong>on</strong>, and higher educati<strong>on</strong>, c<strong>on</strong>tinuingeducati<strong>on</strong> and various other forms of educati<strong>on</strong> and instructi<strong>on</strong> areemphasized during the development of the post-Fordist society. Thegoal today is that every individual develop and maintain an extensive,broad and flexible range of professi<strong>on</strong>al qualificati<strong>on</strong>s, and it is the labormarket and the demands of that market that best determine theknowledge and skills that those qualificati<strong>on</strong>s should comprise.The visi<strong>on</strong> of the flexible and well-educated worker as an actor in thelabor markets of the present and future, and of a school and educati<strong>on</strong>system that is shaped in accordance with this visi<strong>on</strong>, is a recognizabletheme in several c<strong>on</strong>texts and articles besides those previously menti<strong>on</strong>ed.Edwards (1991) refers to the British situati<strong>on</strong>, for example thedemands for a flexible workforce and desires to create a closer relati<strong>on</strong>between educati<strong>on</strong> and ec<strong>on</strong>omic demands, while Apple (1987) talksabout a link between curricula and producti<strong>on</strong> needs–which today arecloser than ever (in the U.S.)–and warns that c<strong>on</strong>cepts such as effectiveness,producti<strong>on</strong>, job skills, and work discipline will come to dominate the waywe think about school. An article by Goods<strong>on</strong> & Mangan (199?) describeshow the predominating discourse in educati<strong>on</strong> today focuses <strong>on</strong> theec<strong>on</strong>omic significance of educati<strong>on</strong> for the individual and society.A similar line of reas<strong>on</strong>ing has been followed in Sweden. In the late1980s and early 1990s several commissi<strong>on</strong>s were appointed to focus <strong>on</strong>the significance of educati<strong>on</strong> with respect to Sweden’s competitivenessas a driving force for the country’s (ec<strong>on</strong>omic) development. 20 Thepicture that these commissi<strong>on</strong>s paint of the state of Sweden’s nati<strong>on</strong>alec<strong>on</strong>omy and of the present and future needs of the Swedish labor market93


are strikingly unambiguous. The commissi<strong>on</strong> reports speak, in generalterms, of how the internati<strong>on</strong>alizati<strong>on</strong> and integrati<strong>on</strong> of the ec<strong>on</strong>omiesof nati<strong>on</strong>s lead to increased competitive pressures in most sectors ofsociety. They speak of knowledge developing at a faster pace, theincreased knowledge-c<strong>on</strong>tent of many professi<strong>on</strong>s and jobs, and theincreased complexity of this knowledge-c<strong>on</strong>tent. At least <strong>on</strong>e comm<strong>on</strong>c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> was reached, namely that the Swedish workforce needs todevelop with respect to qualificati<strong>on</strong>s. The idea is that in order to raisethe level of Swedish competitiveness, create flexibility and efficiency,and to increase the individual’s potential to survive in a changing labormarket, a str<strong>on</strong>g emphasis must be placed <strong>on</strong> the primary and sec<strong>on</strong>daryeducati<strong>on</strong>, as well as the in-service training and c<strong>on</strong>tinuing educati<strong>on</strong>of primarily the adult and professi<strong>on</strong>ally active segments of society.At a time when the predominant discourse <strong>on</strong> educati<strong>on</strong> involves anemphasis <strong>on</strong> higher educati<strong>on</strong>, c<strong>on</strong>tinuing educati<strong>on</strong> the demands ofthe labor market, flexibility and diverse forms of educati<strong>on</strong>, distanceeducati<strong>on</strong> has become more popular than ever. According to Farnes(1993), Thorpe (1995) and a number of reports by Swedishcommissi<strong>on</strong>s, 21 with the help of distance educati<strong>on</strong> it should be possibleto increase the number of students in the existing educati<strong>on</strong>al systemwithout having to spend (much) more m<strong>on</strong>ey, to make educati<strong>on</strong>spatially and temporally accessible to a greater porti<strong>on</strong> of (the adult andprofessi<strong>on</strong>ally active) populati<strong>on</strong>, and to create a flexible form ofeducati<strong>on</strong> and flexible educati<strong>on</strong>al opti<strong>on</strong>s.But then this would not be just any distance educati<strong>on</strong>. Edwards(1991) describes ”open learning” ”...as the post-Fordist approach to theeducati<strong>on</strong> and training....” 22 Farnes (1993) is <strong>on</strong> the same track. Hestates that within the area of distance educati<strong>on</strong>, the post-Fordisteducati<strong>on</strong>al ideal is shaped in the form of a computer-based open anddistance educati<strong>on</strong>. In this descripti<strong>on</strong>, the c<strong>on</strong>cepts of ”open” and”computer-based” are central in that they illustrate two lively discussi<strong>on</strong>sthat are currently taking place in distance educati<strong>on</strong>. These encompassissues of open learning versus distance learning, as well as the role ofelectr<strong>on</strong>ic media in distance teaching.Distance educati<strong>on</strong> is often described as ”...an industrialized form ofeducati<strong>on</strong> and teaching” 23 –characterized by industrial producti<strong>on</strong>,94


ati<strong>on</strong>alizati<strong>on</strong>, mass producti<strong>on</strong>, mechanizati<strong>on</strong>, planning andcentralizati<strong>on</strong>. [This discussi<strong>on</strong> is referred to in, am<strong>on</strong>g others, Farnes(1993), Rumble (1995a), Raggatt (1993) and Thorpe (1995).] Todaythe c<strong>on</strong>cept of open learning is sometimes used in the c<strong>on</strong>text of (distance)educati<strong>on</strong> as a counterbalance or alternative, but often just to indicate aform of educati<strong>on</strong> that is more flexible than usual.However, the questi<strong>on</strong> of exactly what type of educati<strong>on</strong> this c<strong>on</strong>ceptembraces is not particularly clear. Paine (1990), for example, states thatthe definiti<strong>on</strong> of open learning varies between two extremes. On the<strong>on</strong>e hand, open learning is perceived as an educati<strong>on</strong>al form where thegeographical distance between <strong>teacher</strong> and student is bridged. On theother, open learning is so broadly defined that it becomes a genericc<strong>on</strong>cept that includes any educati<strong>on</strong> that is even slightly related to studentcentering. Some authors more or less place distance learning in thesame category as open learning, while others, e.g. Kember & Murphy(1990), make a clear distincti<strong>on</strong> between the two forms of educati<strong>on</strong> bypointing out that there are distance courses that are not particularlyopen and many open learning courses that do not take place at a distance.The most comm<strong>on</strong> percepti<strong>on</strong> nevertheless seems to be that open learningshould be regarded as a generic c<strong>on</strong>cept for a number of educati<strong>on</strong>al forms,the primary characteristic of which is a striving for openness. ”Openness”can be regarded in several different ways: from the point of view of thestudent’s access to studies, his freedom of choice with regard to the c<strong>on</strong>tentof the studies, or openness based <strong>on</strong> the ability to adapt the instructi<strong>on</strong>alform to different needs and goals. According to Lewis (1990) it was morecomm<strong>on</strong> in the past than it is now to express degrees of openness in termsof educati<strong>on</strong>al accessibility. Today openness is more often about creatingindependence in learning, and freedom of choice–about openness withrespect to instructi<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>tent and form. Today the c<strong>on</strong>cept of openlearning is also comm<strong>on</strong>ly associated with corporate or c<strong>on</strong>tinuingeducati<strong>on</strong>. According to Edwards (1991), this relati<strong>on</strong> is an indicati<strong>on</strong> ofhow c<strong>on</strong>trol over upper sec<strong>on</strong>dary and higher educati<strong>on</strong> is turned over toemployers and how educati<strong>on</strong> is an agent of the new vocati<strong>on</strong>alism.The same kind of changes have taken place in Sweden too. Firstly,the aim and purpose of distance educati<strong>on</strong> have been changed: Whendistance educati<strong>on</strong> was introduced into higher educati<strong>on</strong> in the95


eginning of the 70s, it was primarily c<strong>on</strong>cieved as a means to c<strong>on</strong>tributeto social and geographical equality and this was expected to be d<strong>on</strong>e bythe increased physical accessibility created by new distance-bridgingeducati<strong>on</strong>al methods. In practice, distance educati<strong>on</strong> was during its firstten or fifteen years as part of the university system regarded as similarto, or even the same as, decentralized educati<strong>on</strong>. Today this view <strong>on</strong>distance educati<strong>on</strong> is regarded as old-fashi<strong>on</strong>ed and inadequate. At thesame pace as ideas of life-l<strong>on</strong>g learning and educati<strong>on</strong> as a driving forcefor Sweden’s ec<strong>on</strong>omic development have gained comm<strong>on</strong> and publicacceptance, the role of distance educati<strong>on</strong> has been revised. Focus is nol<strong>on</strong>ger <strong>on</strong> equality, but <strong>on</strong> ec<strong>on</strong>omy. Distance educati<strong>on</strong> is valued moreas a means to fulfill the diversified needs of the labour market, than asan instrument in the struggle for equlity between regi<strong>on</strong>s and socialgroups. Accessibility means less today, while flexibility, efficiency andthe potential to create individualized studies means more.At the same time as this change has taken place, the label put <strong>on</strong> thisparticular form of educati<strong>on</strong> is being discussed. ”Distance educati<strong>on</strong>” ispresently felt as a perhaps too limited c<strong>on</strong>cept to cover the whole arrayof different forms of courses and studies that is developed in its name.Instead ”open learning” is brought forward as <strong>on</strong>e possible alternativealso in the Swedish setting, or maybe ”open flexible learning” 24 .The other comp<strong>on</strong>ent in Farnes’ descripti<strong>on</strong> of post-Fordist distanceeducati<strong>on</strong> was the c<strong>on</strong>cept of ”computer-based”.Today it can almost be c<strong>on</strong>sidered a truism that distance educati<strong>on</strong>–or open learning–should be implemented with the help of electr<strong>on</strong>icmedia, and then preferably with computers.This perspective is not <strong>on</strong>lyrendered by Farnes, but even Duning 25 states that distance educati<strong>on</strong> isstarting to become syn<strong>on</strong>ymous with telecommunicati<strong>on</strong>sdelivery.Farnes also cites Rumble who states that ”there is a real possibilitythat we are <strong>on</strong> the threshold of the third generati<strong>on</strong> distance educati<strong>on</strong>systems which combine access to mass-produced informati<strong>on</strong> with realinteractive communicati<strong>on</strong>.” 26 This is a distance educati<strong>on</strong> which, Farnesbelieves, will entail a great deal of resp<strong>on</strong>sibility being placed <strong>on</strong> boththe <strong>teacher</strong> and the individual student.During the last 5-10 years there has been an increased emphasis <strong>on</strong>electr<strong>on</strong>ic media in Swedish distance educati<strong>on</strong> too. During its first two96


decades, distance educati<strong>on</strong> was in general performed practically withoutany help at all from technical or electr<strong>on</strong>ic equipment. The courseswere based mainly <strong>on</strong> books, written instructi<strong>on</strong>s and a travelling /visiting<strong>teacher</strong> or recurrent gatherings at the university. The most advancedtechnical aid used were teleph<strong>on</strong>es. But the new focus and new demandsbrought forward by the present educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse require newpedagogical methods in distance educati<strong>on</strong>. Computers and otherelectr<strong>on</strong>ic distance-bridging media are presented as indispensable in thedevelopment of modern flexible and individualized distance educati<strong>on</strong>courses.C<strong>on</strong>cluding discussi<strong>on</strong> - talking politics and m<strong>on</strong>eyVia a discussi<strong>on</strong> about the computer as a panoptic structure and ananalysis of the ec<strong>on</strong>omic and educati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>text within which thispanoptic potential is exploited, the discussi<strong>on</strong> ends in a computerisededucati<strong>on</strong>al situati<strong>on</strong> where educati<strong>on</strong> is defined in terms of openlearning, the distance educati<strong>on</strong> of our (and future?) days, characterisedby prestige words such as openness, flexibility and efficiency.The characteristics of the ”openness” in open learning has changedduring the last decades. This change is described earlier in the text; achange from emphasis <strong>on</strong> openness in terms of accessibility, to a kind ofopenness that today to a greater extent is defined as learner independenceand flexibility - freedom for the learner to choose c<strong>on</strong>tent and decidewhen, where and how to carry out his or her studies. Today openness indistance educati<strong>on</strong>/open learning is primarily a matter of freedom ofchoice regarding the methodology of educati<strong>on</strong> and executed by the useof computer technology.This change has ideological implicati<strong>on</strong>s. For example Paine (1990)argues, apropos the questi<strong>on</strong> of which the real qualities of open learningare, that the increasing customer centeredness of the educati<strong>on</strong>al instituti<strong>on</strong>shas been w<strong>on</strong> at the expense of equality of opportunity - that”the ability to be flexible and demand-led has been based up<strong>on</strong> the ec<strong>on</strong>omicreality of the market place”. 27 Richards<strong>on</strong> (1990) refers to Rumble whoquesti<strong>on</strong>s if it is adequate to refer to an educati<strong>on</strong> as ”open” if it isavailable <strong>on</strong>ly to limited groups of people and if the c<strong>on</strong>tent has beenselected by somebody else - an employer - than by the prospective97


learners. Open learning is often described as a progressive educati<strong>on</strong>and ascribed a potential to improve both life- and vocati<strong>on</strong>al chancesfor most people, but referring to Richards<strong>on</strong>, Rumble says that openlearning, as it is presently apprehended, does not c<strong>on</strong>tribute to freedomor social progress. Today it indoctrinates and encourages c<strong>on</strong>formism,more than it fosters independence and stimulates a critical discussi<strong>on</strong>.It is to this c<strong>on</strong>text that the dialogue, the electr<strong>on</strong>ic communicati<strong>on</strong>and the panoptic principle bel<strong>on</strong>g. In a time when demands for flexibilityand customer- and market adjustment make structural (firm and fixed)c<strong>on</strong>trol improductive and even counterproductive, the electr<strong>on</strong>icdialogue offers <strong>teacher</strong>s and producers of educati<strong>on</strong> possibilities of amore adequate form of c<strong>on</strong>trol. To tie educati<strong>on</strong> to closed rooms, fixedhours, pre-selected literature and thereby creating possibilities of directobservati<strong>on</strong>, c<strong>on</strong>trol and examinati<strong>on</strong> is no l<strong>on</strong>ger c<strong>on</strong>sidered appropriate- in a flexible and variable educati<strong>on</strong>al situati<strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>trol has to bemore adaptable and smooth. This is a situati<strong>on</strong> that fits the computer asPanoptic<strong>on</strong>. Using the computer as a medium, all educati<strong>on</strong>al acts, bothactive and passive <strong>on</strong>es, are perpetually m<strong>on</strong>itored and registered. Andthis registrati<strong>on</strong> is not <strong>on</strong>ly executed by the <strong>teacher</strong>; when it comes tocomputer c<strong>on</strong>ferencing systems, all participants’ acti<strong>on</strong>s are visible toall other participants in a study group. There is no place to hide. The<strong>teacher</strong> is visible and c<strong>on</strong>trolled to the same extent as the learners are.This supervisi<strong>on</strong> also takes place in a defined social and educati<strong>on</strong>alc<strong>on</strong>text that is characterized by special norms of acceptable thinkingand behaviour. The observance of these norms is prompted by a neverendingexaminati<strong>on</strong> process combined with mechanisms of punishmentand correcti<strong>on</strong>. In the study situati<strong>on</strong> itself, the mere use of informati<strong>on</strong>technology is often c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be a prominent norm of goodbehaviour. The electr<strong>on</strong>ic media should be made use of - this is correctacti<strong>on</strong>.The more general picture of normality put forward in and by acomputer-based open learning-setting, is about c<strong>on</strong>trol as a principle. Ina computerised educati<strong>on</strong>al situati<strong>on</strong> the learners are made accustomedto c<strong>on</strong>tinuous c<strong>on</strong>trol and to a form of c<strong>on</strong>trol that is executed withoutany steering in a particular or visible directi<strong>on</strong> taking place. It is a c<strong>on</strong>trolwithout norms - no definiti<strong>on</strong> of normality is specified and this is actually98


the catch. The result is a learner that is used to and comfortable withbeing c<strong>on</strong>trolled, not steered in a particular directi<strong>on</strong>, but used to andready to be steered in any directi<strong>on</strong>. After this educati<strong>on</strong>al experiencethe participants is supposed to be prepared for and competent to handlea broad spectrum of vocati<strong>on</strong>al tasks and situati<strong>on</strong>s. The purpose is tocreate flexible thinking and flexible acting, i. e. the kind of floatingcompetence that the Market - c<strong>on</strong>cretised in the form of the modernlabour market - is supposed to demand. In an article, Goods<strong>on</strong> & Mangan(199?) analyse computer technology as educati<strong>on</strong>al device and theyreach the c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> that ”The installati<strong>on</strong> of computers in a classroom isnot a neutral technological act. It is an act which partakes of the symbolic tobecome an act of ideological penetrati<strong>on</strong> and c<strong>on</strong>versi<strong>on</strong>.” 28 In their opini<strong>on</strong>,the computer represents a visi<strong>on</strong> of schooling and educati<strong>on</strong> whereeducati<strong>on</strong>al and cultural policies coincide with the goals of the industrialdevelopment.Computers in distance educati<strong>on</strong> - electr<strong>on</strong>ic Panoptic<strong>on</strong>s - mightc<strong>on</strong>sequently be regarded as expressi<strong>on</strong>s of a market ideology withinthe educati<strong>on</strong>al system, transformed into educati<strong>on</strong>al practice. And thismarket ideology is manifested in more than <strong>on</strong>e way. It does not <strong>on</strong>lyshow itself in the form of computers serving as devices of c<strong>on</strong>trol andfosterers of flexibility. The ideology of markets and modern capitalismcan also be traced in the role that distance educati<strong>on</strong> plays today, as a”test bed” offering possibilities to test and apply telecommunicati<strong>on</strong>technology within (especially) higher educati<strong>on</strong>. The informati<strong>on</strong>technology has created the boundlessness necessary to pave the way forforces of the market place and competiti<strong>on</strong> inside the system. Thorpe(1995) c<strong>on</strong>cludes that distance educati<strong>on</strong> today is more or lesssyn<strong>on</strong>ymous with transference via telecommunicati<strong>on</strong> and accordingto her ”The expansi<strong>on</strong> of Open and Distance Learning over the last decaderepresents not so much the triumph of ideologies of open access, more theimpact of market forces and government policies, heightened by recessi<strong>on</strong>aryc<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s.” 29 She calls distance educati<strong>on</strong> the ”Trojan horse” of highereducati<strong>on</strong>, by the way that it has opened <strong>on</strong>e of the last basti<strong>on</strong>s of notentirely capitalistic relati<strong>on</strong>s to the forces of market ec<strong>on</strong>omy. Informati<strong>on</strong>technology and distance educati<strong>on</strong> creates c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s suited tocompetiti<strong>on</strong> at the same time as both technology and this special99


pedagogic soluti<strong>on</strong> are made necessary to every producer of educati<strong>on</strong>that aspires to participate in the competiti<strong>on</strong>. The means of the marketcreates a further need for the means of the market, in an endless andaut<strong>on</strong>omous process.Market ideology is <strong>on</strong>e prominent feature of liberalism. In an interpretati<strong>on</strong>of Foucault, Barry, Osborne and Rose c<strong>on</strong>cludes that liberalism,as ”an ethos of government” 30 is not about the absence of governingor about the state governing less. The government is still there, but notvery visible at first sight, surrounded as it is by ”flexibility”, ”individualaut<strong>on</strong>omy” and ”freedom” as words of h<strong>on</strong>our and executed by thepromoti<strong>on</strong> of quasi-ec<strong>on</strong>omic models - based up<strong>on</strong> a competitive”market” logic - for individual, collective and instituti<strong>on</strong>al acti<strong>on</strong>.Liberalism means state governing that is cautious, ec<strong>on</strong>omic andmodest. But liberalism as we know it today is not the same kind ofliberalism that Foucault saw emerging as a mentality of government inthe early nineteenth century. Burchell, for example, distinguishesbetween early liberalism and neo-liberalism. 31 What the two forms ofliberalism have in comm<strong>on</strong>, analyzed as governmental activities ratherthan instituti<strong>on</strong>s, is their mutual c<strong>on</strong>cern with the market and with thepromoti<strong>on</strong> of market ideology and market functi<strong>on</strong>ing. But while theearly liberalism’s primary c<strong>on</strong>cern was to secure the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s necessaryfor the ”natural” market mechanisms to operate and develop, by reducingstate and other limitati<strong>on</strong>s/obstacles, the neo-liberal governing strategiesare more active, more offensive/aggressive. The questi<strong>on</strong> for neo-liberalismis to actively c<strong>on</strong>struct or rec<strong>on</strong>struct a state and a civil society <strong>on</strong>the basis of liberal (ec<strong>on</strong>omic) freedom. This means to deploy ”...organizati<strong>on</strong>al forms and technical methods in order to extend the fieldwithin which a certain ec<strong>on</strong>omic freedom might be practiced in the form ofaut<strong>on</strong>omy, enterprise and choice”. 32The enterprise-based - market competi<strong>on</strong>-oriented - practice refersto both instituti<strong>on</strong>al and individual/collective acti<strong>on</strong>. To the liberalstylegoverned individual the main less<strong>on</strong> becomes to learn the properuse of individual freeedom. Burchell refers to D<strong>on</strong>zelot (1991) 33 in thisrespect and to the procedures of ”c<strong>on</strong>tractual implicati<strong>on</strong>”. Theseprocedures means the offering of possibilities to active involvement insocial areas by traditi<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sidered being the state’s or society’s areas of100


esp<strong>on</strong>sibility to individuals and groups, in exchange for individual andcollective active resp<strong>on</strong>sibility for these acti<strong>on</strong>s, for the acti<strong>on</strong>s themselvesand for them being carried out in accordance with approved models ofacti<strong>on</strong>.According to Burchell, different systems of goverment, put intopractice for instance in the shape of instituti<strong>on</strong>al/organizati<strong>on</strong>al formsand behaviour, individual and collective dispositi<strong>on</strong>s and behaviour andby the aid of different technical methods and means, interc<strong>on</strong>nect andlink up with each other. And procedures of auditing, accountabilityand management - features of the modern administrative panopticscheme - promote c<strong>on</strong>sistency between the systems as well as they alsoc<strong>on</strong>tribute to the survival and success of liberal government.And there we are, in modern society, facing a pedagogical liberaldiscourse put into practice in the shape of an educati<strong>on</strong>al form namedopen learning and and with new computer-based educati<strong>on</strong>al tools servingas devices for supervisi<strong>on</strong>, normalizati<strong>on</strong> and examinati<strong>on</strong>. Barry 34argues a propos communicati<strong>on</strong> networks and liberal goverment that”... communicati<strong>on</strong> networks have increasingly been seen as enhancing theself-governing capacities of society itself.” 35 and he describes the functi<strong>on</strong>of communicati<strong>on</strong>s structures as ”... perfect embodiments of the liberalpolitical imaginati<strong>on</strong>”. 36 This descript<strong>on</strong> of communicati<strong>on</strong> networksalso counts for the educati<strong>on</strong>al situati<strong>on</strong>. Informati<strong>on</strong> technology providespossibilities to maximize the density, intensity and extensi<strong>on</strong> ofinteracti<strong>on</strong>s at the same time as it minimizes the direct/outspokendemands <strong>on</strong> the students. Instead learning is taking place under slogansas freedom, flexibility and individual resp<strong>on</strong>sibility.When it comes to the introducti<strong>on</strong> of informati<strong>on</strong> technology anddistance educati<strong>on</strong> in educati<strong>on</strong>al settings, there is also a close c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>between this discourse and ec<strong>on</strong>omical str<strong>on</strong>g interests. ”There has beenhuge ec<strong>on</strong>omic pressure behind the introducti<strong>on</strong> of new informati<strong>on</strong>technology [IT] because IT is not just an educati<strong>on</strong> tool (as were, for example,the programmed learning machines of an earlier decade). IT is now pervasivein all ec<strong>on</strong>omic sectors. The pressure has come from statements <strong>on</strong> the ’needsof industry’, skill shortage and <strong>on</strong> the ’growing demand for IT skills’...”. 37But this c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> is most often obscured, the power interests behindit and supporting it are kept hidden. Instead the discourse in questi<strong>on</strong> -101


informati<strong>on</strong> technology, open learning - is presented as ”natural” and”inevitable” in our c<strong>on</strong>temporary and future society.That is what happens. According to Foucault, power is productiveand it usually disguises itself as ”truth”. ”What makes power holdgood, what makes it accepted, is simply the fact that it doesn’t <strong>on</strong>lyweigh <strong>on</strong> us as a force that says no, but that it traverses and producesthings, it induces pleasure, forms knowledge, produces discourses. Itneeds to be c<strong>on</strong>sidered as a productive network which runs through thewhole social body, much more than as a negative instance whosefuncti<strong>on</strong> is repressi<strong>on</strong>.” 38 .Educati<strong>on</strong>al discourses shall not and can not be seen <strong>on</strong>ly as neutraldescripti<strong>on</strong>s of reality, they are also productive. They represent particularimages of ”normality”, particular views <strong>on</strong> the role of educati<strong>on</strong> inec<strong>on</strong>omic and social life. They are integrated in the exercise of powerand are therefore strategically important for the <strong>on</strong>going anduninterrupted struggles for power that are going <strong>on</strong> in all social c<strong>on</strong>texts.ReferencesApple, M. W.: Mandating Computers: The Impact of the new Technology <strong>on</strong> the LabourProcess, Students an Teachers. In: Walker, S. & Bart<strong>on</strong>, L. (Eds): ChangingPolicies, Changing Teachers. Open University Press, 1987.Barry, A.: Lines of communicati<strong>on</strong> and spaces of rule. In Barry, A., Osborne, T., Rose, N.(Eds): Foucault and political reas<strong>on</strong>. Liberalism, neo-liberalism and rati<strong>on</strong>alities ofgovernment. The University of Chicago Press, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> 1996.Barry, A., Osborne, T., Rose, N.: Introducti<strong>on</strong>. In Barry, A., Osborne, T., Rose,N. (Eds):Foucault and political reas<strong>on</strong>. Liberalism, neo-liberalism and rati<strong>on</strong>alities ofgovernment. The University of Chicago Press, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> 1996.Burchell, G.: Liberal government and techniques of the self. In Barry, A., Osborne, T.,Rose, N. (Eds): Foucault and political reas<strong>on</strong>. Liberalism, neo-liberalism andrati<strong>on</strong>alities of government. The University of Chicago Press, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> 1996.Beyn<strong>on</strong>, J. & Mackay, H.: Informati<strong>on</strong> technology into educati<strong>on</strong>: towards a criticalperspective. Journal of educati<strong>on</strong> policy. Vol 4, No 3, 1989.Ds 1992:3: Långt borta och mycket nära - En förstudie om svensk distansutbildning. (Far Awayand Very Close - A Pre-study of Swedish Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>) Utbildningsdepartementet.Allmänna Förlaget, Stockholm 1992.Deleuze, G.: Postscript of the societies of c<strong>on</strong>trol. October, 1992: winter, s 3-7.Edenius, M.: Ett modernt dilemma. (A modern dilemma.). Akademisk avhandling förfilosofiedoktorsexamen. Företagsek<strong>on</strong>omiska instituti<strong>on</strong>en, Stockholms<strong>universitet</strong>, 1996.102


Edwards, R.: The inevitable future? Post-Fordism and open learning. Open Learning, Vol 6,No 2, 1991.Farnes, N.: Modes of producti<strong>on</strong>: Fordism and distance educati<strong>on</strong>. Open learning, Vol 8,No 1, 1993.Foucault, M.: Övervakning och Straff (Discipline and Punish). Arkiv förlag, Lund 1987.Goods<strong>on</strong>, I.F. & Mangan, M.: Computers in schools as symbolic and ideological acti<strong>on</strong>:the genealogy of the Ic<strong>on</strong>. The Curriculum Journal, Vol 3, No 3, 199?.Goods<strong>on</strong>, I.F. & Mangan, J. M.: Computer literacy as Ideology. British Journal of Sociologyof Educati<strong>on</strong>, Vol 17, No 1, 1996.J<strong>on</strong>assen, D. et al: C<strong>on</strong>structivism and Computer-Mediated Communicati<strong>on</strong> in DistanceEducati<strong>on</strong>. The American Journal of Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>, Vol 9, No 2, 1995.Juler, Ph.: Promoting interacti<strong>on</strong>; maintaining independence: swallowing the mixture.Open Learning, Vol 5, No 2, 1990.Kember, D. & Murphy, D.: A synthesis of open, distance and student centered learning.Open Learning, Vol 5, No 2, 1990.Lauz<strong>on</strong>, A. C.: Integrating Computer-Based Instructi<strong>on</strong> with Computer C<strong>on</strong>ferencing: AnEvaluati<strong>on</strong> of a Model for Designing Online Educati<strong>on</strong>. The American Journal ofDistance Educati<strong>on</strong>, Vol 6, No 2, 1992.Lewis, R.: Open learning and the missuse of language: a resp<strong>on</strong>se to Greville Rumble.Open Learning, Vol 5, No 1, 1990.May, S.: Collaborative Learning: More Is Not Necessarily Better. The American Journal ofDistance Educati<strong>on</strong>, Vol 7, No 3, 1993.Mcc<strong>on</strong>nell, D.: Managing Open Learning in Computer Supported Collaborative LearningEnvir<strong>on</strong>ments. Studies in Higher Educati<strong>on</strong>, Vol 19, No 3, 1994.Moore, M.: Recent c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s to the theory of distance educati<strong>on</strong>. Open Learning, Vol5, No 3, 1990.Mosco, V.: Informati<strong>on</strong> in the Pay-per Society. In: Mosco, V. & Wasko, J.: The PoliticalEc<strong>on</strong>omy of Informati<strong>on</strong>. The University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin Press, Madis<strong>on</strong> 1988.Paine, N.: Open learning and the misuse of language: some comments <strong>on</strong> the Rumble/Lewis debate. Open Learning, Vol 5, No 2, 1990.Phelps, R. H., Wells, R. A., Ashworth, R. L. & Hahn, H. A.: Effectiveness and Costs ofDistance Educati<strong>on</strong> Using Computer-Mediated Communicati<strong>on</strong>. The AmericanJournal of Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>, Vol 5, No 3, 1991.Poster, M.: The mode of informati<strong>on</strong>. Polity press. 1990.Raggatt, P.: Post-Fordism and distance educati<strong>on</strong> - a flexible strategy for change. OpenLearning, Vol 8, No 1, 1993.Razzol, N.: Post-Fordism? Technology and New Forms of C<strong>on</strong>trol: the case of technologyin the curriculum. British Journal of Sociology of Educati<strong>on</strong>, Vol 14, No 3, 1993.Richards<strong>on</strong>, M.: Open learning and the misuse of language: some comments <strong>on</strong> theRumble/Lewis debate. Open Learning, Vol 5, No 2, 1990.Rumble, G. (a): Labour market theories and distance educati<strong>on</strong> I: Industrialisati<strong>on</strong> anddistance educati<strong>on</strong>. Open Learning, Vol 10, No 1. 1995.Rumble, G. (b): Labour market theories and distance educati<strong>on</strong> III: Post fordism - the wayforward? Open Learning, Vol 10, No 3, 1995.SOU 1993:23: Kunskapens kr<strong>on</strong>a. (The Crown of Knowledge) Huvudbetänkande avutredningen om effektivare vuxenutbildning. Utbildningsdepartementet.Stockholm 1993.103


Tagg, A. C.: Leadership from Within: Student Moderati<strong>on</strong> of Computer C<strong>on</strong>ferences. TheAmerican Journal of Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>, Vol 8, No 3, 1994.Thorpe, M.: The Expansi<strong>on</strong> of Open and Distance Learning - A reflecti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> marketforces. Open Learning, Vol 10, No 1, 1995.Wagner, E. D.: In Support of a Functi<strong>on</strong>al Definiti<strong>on</strong> of Interacti<strong>on</strong>. The American Journalof Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>, Vol 8, No 2, 1994.Wellingt<strong>on</strong>, J. J.: The impact of IT <strong>on</strong> the school curriculum: downwards, sideways,backwards and forwards. Journal of Curriculum Studies, Vol 22, No 1, 1990.Notes1Rumble, G. (1989) ’Open learning’, ’distance learning’ and the misuse of language.Open Learning, Vol. 4, No. 2, pp. 28-35.2Moore (1990), p. 14.3Ibid.4Cook, J. 1989. The liberati<strong>on</strong> of distance: teaching women’s studies from china. InCritical Reflecti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>, eds. T. Evans and D. Nati<strong>on</strong>, 23-37. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>:The Falmer Press.5Hughes, M. and M. Kennedy. 1985. New Futures. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge & Kegan Paul.6p. 32.7It is possible to compare the meaning that Deleuze gives to this c<strong>on</strong>cept to the societycalled ”postmodern” in other scientific and philosophical literature.8Burchell in Barry, Osborne, Rose (1996), p. 19.9Barry, Osborne and Rose (1996), p. 8.10Poster (1990), p. 85.11Foucault, M. Discipline and Punish. Translated by Alan Sheridan. New York: Panthe<strong>on</strong>,1977, p. 24. Cited in Poster (1990), p. 93.12Zuboff, S. 1988. In the Age of the Smart Machine. New York: Basic Books, p. 322.Citati<strong>on</strong> excerpted from Edenius (1996).13p. 192.14Michel Foucault cited in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972-1977. Colin Gord<strong>on</strong>, ed. New York: Panthe<strong>on</strong>, 1980, p. 93. Citati<strong>on</strong> excerpted fromPoster (1990)., p.87.15Burchell (1996), p. 30.16These analyses also agree when it comes to describing the Fordist, as well as the post-Fordist society. The descripti<strong>on</strong> that is given in the text is shared by all the above authors,even though in the following text I <strong>on</strong>ly refer to <strong>on</strong>e of them.17Murray, R. (1989). Fordism and Post-Fordism. In New Times: The Changing Face ofPolitics in the 1990s. S. Hall and M. Jacques, eds. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Lawrence and Wishart,pp. 38-53.18Mosco (1988) talks about the pay-per society in which ”large business... use the computercommunicati<strong>on</strong>s to increase profit and extend c<strong>on</strong>trol over workers and c<strong>on</strong>sumers.” (p 8).19This thesis is questi<strong>on</strong>ed by Rumble (1995b), for example. But since Rumble’s challengeleads to a variati<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> Farnes theory instead of knocking it down, I have decidednot to refer to his argument in this c<strong>on</strong>text.104


20For example, the Commissi<strong>on</strong> for Competence appointed by the Labor Market Ministryand the Commissi<strong>on</strong> for Higher Educati<strong>on</strong>, the Commissi<strong>on</strong> for Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>, theCommissi<strong>on</strong> for a More Effective Adult Educati<strong>on</strong>, and Agenda 2000: Knowledge andCompetence in the Next Century (the Ministry of Educati<strong>on</strong>).21For example, SOU 1993:23 The Crown of Knowledge, Ds1992:3 Far Away and VeryClose - A Pre-study of Swedish Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>.22p. 38.23Rumble (1995a), p. 14.24See for example the dicussi<strong>on</strong> in the report presented by the Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>Committee (the Ministry of Educati<strong>on</strong>) presented in May 199825Duning, B. 1990. The coming of the new distance educators in the United States: Thetelecommunicati<strong>on</strong>s generati<strong>on</strong> takes off. In Distance Educati<strong>on</strong>. Internati<strong>on</strong>al Journal,11, 1, pp 24-49. Referred to in Thorpe (1995).26Rumble, G. (1989). Interactivity, Independence and Cost. In Interacti<strong>on</strong> andIndependence, ICDE C<strong>on</strong>ference papers, ICDE, A. Tait, ed..27p.44.28p. 273.29p. 21.30p. 8.31Burchell, G. (1996): Liberal government and techniques of the self.32Barry, Osborne and Rose (1996), p. 10.33Burchell (1996), p. 29.34Barry, A. (1996): Lines of communicati<strong>on</strong> and spaces of rule.35p. 128.36p. 128.37Wellingt<strong>on</strong> (1990), p. 61.38Foucault, M. (1980) Power/Knowledge, Bright<strong>on</strong>, Harvester Press. Quoted in Edwards(1991), p. 36105


106


L Y N N F E N D L E RMaking Trouble: Predictability,Agency, and Critical Intellectuals”All reificati<strong>on</strong> is a forgetting.“Theodore AdornoCritical theories since those of the Frankfurt School have begun withthe assumpti<strong>on</strong> that social relati<strong>on</strong>s are infused with injustices, and thatit is the resp<strong>on</strong>sibility of intellectuals to recognize and address powerrelati<strong>on</strong>s. Power relati<strong>on</strong>s have changed dramatically throughout historyin accordance with shifting c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s from governmental,ec<strong>on</strong>omic, religious, aesthetic, scientific, philosophical and technologicalsectors.It is not easy to recognize emerging forms of power because the socialtechnologies--including educati<strong>on</strong>al pedagogies--are enacted beforethe exercise of power is recognized as such. For example, it is <strong>on</strong>ly recentlythat critical theorists have begun to analyze the ways in which the shiftto liberal democratic forms of government necessitated a self-disciplinedcitizenry and the ”reform [of] individuals at the level of their pers<strong>on</strong>alskills and competencies” (Barry, Osborne & Rose, 1996, p. 1). In aneffort to identify emerging forms of power relati<strong>on</strong>s, it becomes necessaryto problematize the analytical categories of previous critical theories,and to c<strong>on</strong>sider how new social technologies may require new analyticaltools of critique.The task of critical research in educati<strong>on</strong> is to provide theoreticalmechanisms which allow for radical change in social relati<strong>on</strong>s. In orderto allow for change, it is useful to understand what is taken for grantedas unchangeable in any given system of thought. In this chapter I askthree questi<strong>on</strong>s in attempt to discern what is taken for granted in variousstrands of c<strong>on</strong>temporary educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse: 1) What is the organizingschema (also called the system of reas<strong>on</strong>ing or principle of coherence)?2) How is the subject c<strong>on</strong>stituted (especially in relati<strong>on</strong> to the ”object”and to the social)? 3) What is the role of the critical intellectual?107


For each of these questi<strong>on</strong>s, I first characterize the most comm<strong>on</strong> paradigmof educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse in terms of its assumpti<strong>on</strong>s. Then Iexamine two other strands of educati<strong>on</strong>al research which proposeapproaches which are critical of the most comm<strong>on</strong> forms of discourse.The first strand is critical modernism, in which I c<strong>on</strong>sider Marxian,Frankfurt School, and Habermasian c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s; the sec<strong>on</strong>d is postmodernism,in which I c<strong>on</strong>sider the historicizing approaches such asthose of Foucault and poststructural feminists. For each of the threequesti<strong>on</strong>s, I examine the ways in which the various ”alternative” strandsof educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse interrupt and/or perpetuate the assumpti<strong>on</strong>sof comm<strong>on</strong> educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse.The Trouble with PredictabilityIn general, educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse in the present historical moment isorganized around a totalizing principle in a paradigm which is called”analytic”, ”rati<strong>on</strong>alistic”, or ”scientific”--in the sense of proceeding byexperimental method. That is, the criteria by which research practicesare evaluated are those which can be generalized and whose results canbe validated in terms of statistical testing. Most importantly, in thisschema, the generalizable principle is privileged over individuals; generalprinciples, in other words, are held to be more valid, and perhapsmore true, than particular cases, ”excepti<strong>on</strong>s”, or ”deviati<strong>on</strong>s.” Specifically,in this organizing schema, making sense entails evaluati<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>the basis of logical-analytical coherence which can be related to someempirical referent. In other words, it is generally c<strong>on</strong>sidered reas<strong>on</strong>ableto reject an asserti<strong>on</strong> if it can be dem<strong>on</strong>strated to c<strong>on</strong>tradict some widelyaccepted premise. In this organizing schema, the criteria of evaluati<strong>on</strong>are generalizable and abstract, not aesthetic or theological.An example of a analytical organizing schema in much educati<strong>on</strong>aldiscourse is the assumpti<strong>on</strong> of developmentalism, as in the study of”child development.” It is widely assumed that there is a discernablepattern of growth which is delimited by age. The developmental patternis a generalizable principle, and it is validated in terms of statistical testing.The developmental theories of Piaget, Kolberg, and Gilligan arewidely debated in educati<strong>on</strong>al circles, but the scholarly arguments aregenerally limited to questi<strong>on</strong>s of periodizati<strong>on</strong> (e.g. What are the criteria108


of a ”stage” of development?) and applicability (e.g. Can a singledevelopmental scale be applied to various races, ethnicities and genders?).Educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse generally takes it for granted that children’s growthcan be understood as c<strong>on</strong>forming (or not c<strong>on</strong>forming) to a generalizable(i.e. developmental) pattern. Moreover, if a child’s growth does not c<strong>on</strong>formto a given pattern of development, then the child is judged to be”abnormal.”This sort of judgement is significant because in an analytical organizingschema, the theory of developmentalism is held to be ”true” andthe child is held to be ”deviant.” That which is generalizable is believedto be normal, and the lives of individual children are evaluated withreference to a statistical norm. The analytical generalizati<strong>on</strong> takesprecedence over the broad range of variati<strong>on</strong>s by calling some children”normal” and some children ”abnormal.” In order to understand theimplicati<strong>on</strong>s of these assumpti<strong>on</strong>s, c<strong>on</strong>sider what could have been thecase in an alternative schema: In another schema, the theory ofdevelopmentalism might be judged faulty because it cannot account forthe range of empirical data--namely the wide variati<strong>on</strong>s in the wayschildren grow. That is, the wide variati<strong>on</strong>s in the ways children growmight be c<strong>on</strong>sidered sufficient evidence to invalidate--or at leastweaken--the assumpti<strong>on</strong> of generalizable norms in development.An analytical organizing schema is taken for granted in much currentdiscourse; however, historically, Descartes’ seventeenth century formulati<strong>on</strong>of an analytic method was a critical interrupti<strong>on</strong>. A formalizedanalytical method effected an epistemological break from thestranglehold of medieval theological assumpti<strong>on</strong>s. Descartes is oftencredited with birthing the age of reas<strong>on</strong>. His systematic methods ofhypothesis testing have been heralded as paving the way for an”enlightened” view of the universe. Interestingly, however, Descarteswas fundamentally an idealist who grounded the justificati<strong>on</strong> for hismethod <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>tent of his dreams. His Discourse <strong>on</strong> Method was anearly formulati<strong>on</strong> of abstract, rati<strong>on</strong>al inquiry; and the Discourse isremarkable precisely because it was the mutant offspring of formalmetaphysical idealism.The formalizati<strong>on</strong> of an analytical method was a critical c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>in the early seventeenth century, but it gradually entered general discourse109


and has since attained the status of an unquesti<strong>on</strong>ed assumpti<strong>on</strong> inc<strong>on</strong>temporary thought. Historical hindsight reveals that the originalformulati<strong>on</strong>s of Descartes’ rati<strong>on</strong>al method were debated for a while;after a time the method was tentatively employed in analyses, such analysesbecame widespread in philosophical discourse (for reas<strong>on</strong>s of historicalhappenstance; see e.g. Toulmin, 1990), the method becameformalized and c<strong>on</strong>ceptualized, the validity of the c<strong>on</strong>ceptualizati<strong>on</strong>ceased to generate c<strong>on</strong>troversy, the c<strong>on</strong>troversy was forgotten, the practiceof analytic rati<strong>on</strong>ality became a habit, the habit eventually becameembedded in discourse as an ”ism”, and the habitualized assumpti<strong>on</strong> ofrati<strong>on</strong>alism became comm<strong>on</strong>sense.An examinati<strong>on</strong> of comm<strong>on</strong> educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse suggests that therules of ”rati<strong>on</strong>ality” have changed dramatically over time, and thechanges were unpredictable. Current analytical discourse tends to assumethat a generalizable method is grounds for truth; that is, if a researchmethod obeys a set of formal procedural rules, then the c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s canbe c<strong>on</strong>sidered valid. This analytical schema is based <strong>on</strong> principles (orlaws) of repeatability, generalizability, and rati<strong>on</strong>al coherence. In thisdiscourse, the ”truth” of a principle (e.g. developmentalism) is str<strong>on</strong>genough to label some events (or some children) deviant (rather thanvice versa).Assumpti<strong>on</strong>s of an analytical principle in educati<strong>on</strong> are evident inthe extent to which analytical and experimental methods informeducati<strong>on</strong>al discourse. It is widely taken for granted that human behaviorand learning can be understood and/or explained <strong>on</strong> the basis of experimentaltesting and generalizable laws of development. A c<strong>on</strong>siderablenumber of research projects in educati<strong>on</strong> are justified under theassumpti<strong>on</strong> that teaching, learning, cogniti<strong>on</strong>, behavior and dispositi<strong>on</strong>are accessible to ”scientific” observati<strong>on</strong>, explicable in terms ofdevelopmentalism, and susceptive to interventi<strong>on</strong> based <strong>on</strong> experimentaldata. Moreover, such an analytical schema tends to accept c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>ssolely <strong>on</strong> the basis of their methodological (i.e. experimental) validity,and without regard to their social, political, or historical c<strong>on</strong>text.Critical discourses in educati<strong>on</strong> have argued that an analytical approachto educati<strong>on</strong> ignores sociological and political factors which havesignificant impact <strong>on</strong> schooling. Critical modernist discourses--including110


Marxian, Frankfurt School and Habermasian threads--have offered analternative organizing schema which maintains some features of analyticdiscourse, but also departs somewhat from the assumpti<strong>on</strong> of ananalytical schema. The modernist organizing schema can be characterizedas dialectical. The dialectical schema departs from the analytical principleby positing c<strong>on</strong>flicting (or oppositi<strong>on</strong>al) positi<strong>on</strong>s to make sense of theworld. An analytical approach assumes a unified principle of coherence;however, the dialectical approach assumes (at least) two opposing forcessuch as ”oppressive/liberatory” and ”marginalized/empowered”, as in,for example, liberatory pedagogy. Moreover, while analytical schemaare generally justified <strong>on</strong> formal methodological grounds, the moderncriteria of evaluati<strong>on</strong> are generally sociological (in Kantian terms,”synthetic”) because modern asserti<strong>on</strong>s are typically justified <strong>on</strong> the basisof socio-political (and/or ideological) referents.Critical Marxian discourse arose in the historical c<strong>on</strong>text of nineteenthcentury modernizati<strong>on</strong> which entailed the development of nati<strong>on</strong>alisms,social organizati<strong>on</strong>s, bureaucracies, ec<strong>on</strong>omic instituti<strong>on</strong>s, Darwinianlaws of nature, and collective forms of governance. Such social, politicaland ec<strong>on</strong>omic circumstances made it possible to think about powerrelati<strong>on</strong>s in terms of populati<strong>on</strong>al entities such as ”class” and bureaucracy.These c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s of modernity formed the historical matrix whichengendered and sustained Marx’s theories of ec<strong>on</strong>omic determinism andcollective c<strong>on</strong>sciousness.One prominent group to extend Marx’s work was the Frankfurt Schoolin Germany (ca. 1923-1950). The historical circumstances of the FrankfurtSchool, however, included aspects unknown to Marx, most notablythe rise and fall of fascism, the emergence of psychology as a socialscience, and the influence of Sigmund Freud. Historically speaking,the Frankfurt School faced two strands of established discourse. Thefirst strand was the analytical schema (which the Frankfurt School termed”instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing”) because the analytical approach replacedthe humanist subject (in its multiple variati<strong>on</strong>s) with the rati<strong>on</strong>alizedsubject (which c<strong>on</strong>formed to a generalizable pattern); moreover, theanalytical schema devalued subjective reflecti<strong>on</strong> while it privileged formalprocedural methodology. The sec<strong>on</strong>d strand was Marxian historywhich posited class relati<strong>on</strong>s as the ”motor” of history, thereby111


decentering the individual subject and replacing the humanist subjectwith a noti<strong>on</strong> of modern social, political, and ec<strong>on</strong>omic ”role.” TheFrankfurt School targeted both the technologies of ”instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing”and the decentered subject of Marxian history in an effort toundo the determinism and loosen the restricti<strong>on</strong>s imposed when theanalytical schema was (mis)applied to human history.The Frankfurt School argued against instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing byexplaining instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing as a product of the Enlightenmenttaken to unreas<strong>on</strong>able extremes. In resp<strong>on</strong>se they sought to interruptinstrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing through an emphasis <strong>on</strong> aesthetics. It was positedthat aesthetics was not reducible or explicable in terms of rati<strong>on</strong>ality,and therefore the aesthetic realm offered the possibility of escape fromthe dominati<strong>on</strong> of instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing. Herein lay the emancipatorypotential of Critical Theory for the Frankfurt School.Eventually, a grandchild of the Frankfurt School, Jürgen Habermas,asked the questi<strong>on</strong>: How can the aesthetic realm be c<strong>on</strong>sideredaut<strong>on</strong>omous if the moral realm and the scientific realm were ”col<strong>on</strong>ized”by instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing? On what basis could the aesthetic realm beset apart? Habermas logically c<strong>on</strong>cluded that it could not. However,rather than aband<strong>on</strong> the emancipatory project of Critical Theory,Habermas then defended the aut<strong>on</strong>omy of each of the realms--aesthetic,moral, and scientific. This was an interesting move because it historicizedthe subject by acknowledging that modern subjectivity was characterizednot by transcendent unity but by dispersal am<strong>on</strong>g various social ”roles.”Habermas’ theory then endowed the dispersed subjectivity of modernitywith emancipatory potential. That is, Habermas recognized the historicalc<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong> of the subject--namely that it had been dispersedinto modern roles; and then he used that separability to insulate partsof human nature from dominati<strong>on</strong> by instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing. TheFrankfurt School argued that the modern subject was not the same asthe traditi<strong>on</strong>al subject. To that extent, the Frankfurt School historicizedthe subject, and that historizati<strong>on</strong> of the subject was a critical breakfrom an analytical schema. However, there are also significant c<strong>on</strong>tinuitiesbetween analytic and critical modernist schemas. Mostimportantly, the critical modernist explanati<strong>on</strong> of history still assumes akind of logical causality in events. A modern dialectical organizing112


schema posits relatively formal relati<strong>on</strong>s am<strong>on</strong>g historical events andphenomena; specifically, critical modernist analyses tend to posit causal”reas<strong>on</strong>s” to explain social relati<strong>on</strong>s. For example, a child’s ability tolearn may be ”explained” according to a generalizable pattern which isattributed to his or her socio-ec<strong>on</strong>omic status. Thus, the theory takesprecedence over the multiple variati<strong>on</strong>s of historical events; generalizabilityis favored over multiplicity of explanati<strong>on</strong>s.When a theory assumes that history obeys some rati<strong>on</strong>al or logicallaws--whether those be syllogistic, causal, or progressive--that theory isanalytic insofar as it privileges a generalizable pattern over multiplevariati<strong>on</strong>s. C<strong>on</strong>comitantly, that theory limits possibilities for the futureaccording to what is rati<strong>on</strong>ally predictable. If an historical analysisassumes that a sequence of events in history could be explained as logicallypredictable cause and effect, then it follows that events in the futureought to be predictable in terms of cause and effect. Therefore, in thisorganizing schema, possibilities for the future are theoretically limitedto what can be rati<strong>on</strong>ally argued in the present. This c<strong>on</strong>straint isproblematic in terms of an emancipatory agenda because untoldpossibilities for the future are foreclosed. Ir<strong>on</strong>ically, it was Marx whosaid that true freedom could not be envisi<strong>on</strong>ed by people who were notyet free.Another organizing schema of critical educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse is characteristicof postmodernist histories, namely historical c<strong>on</strong>tingency. Apostmodern premise is that systems of reas<strong>on</strong>ing do not exist objectivelyor evolve progressively; rather, systems of reas<strong>on</strong>ing have their bases inhistorical happenstance. Systems of thought are themselves products ofpower relati<strong>on</strong>s; that is, it is possible to think in a given way <strong>on</strong>ly becausea specific history of power relati<strong>on</strong>s has made it possible to think in thisway. There are no systems of thought that are ”pure”, ”natural”, orseparable from human history.Following Foucault, many postmodern historicizing critiques searchfor amalgamati<strong>on</strong>s of social technologies (e.g. linguistic transformati<strong>on</strong>s,instituti<strong>on</strong>al reorganizati<strong>on</strong>s, legal precedents, ec<strong>on</strong>omic redistributi<strong>on</strong>s,disciplinary regimens, artistic innovati<strong>on</strong>s, religious movements, andacademic redefiniti<strong>on</strong>s) which--when taken together--generate, sustain,and inscribe a given rati<strong>on</strong>al system. We can think of these as social113


technologies because through social engagement, people’s thoughts,acti<strong>on</strong>s, speech, and percepti<strong>on</strong>s are shaped by the existing practicalsystems. For example, the inventi<strong>on</strong> of the c<strong>on</strong>cept of ”race” and itsdiffusi<strong>on</strong> through social and educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse, has made it possibleto think that children require different pedagogies depending <strong>on</strong> howthey are racially classified (see e.g. Young, 1990).Postmodern historicizing critiques examine social technologies inorder to analyze the ways in which particular social technologies produceparticular kinds of thinking. This postmodern organizing schema oftenemploys the c<strong>on</strong>cept of ”discourse” in the examinati<strong>on</strong> of technologiesin order to indicate that when we think of them as discursive technologies,theory and practice are indistinguishable.The organizing principle of historical c<strong>on</strong>tingency asserts that principlesof reas<strong>on</strong>ing change, and that there is no necessary or predictablerelati<strong>on</strong>ship between the present and the past, or between the presentand the future. Accordingly, justificati<strong>on</strong> for historically c<strong>on</strong>tingentasserti<strong>on</strong>s is generally based in references to social c<strong>on</strong>texts such asec<strong>on</strong>omic c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s, political reorganizati<strong>on</strong>s, legal enactments, culturaltrends, aesthetic expressi<strong>on</strong>s, and pedagogical technologies. Historicallyc<strong>on</strong>tingent social analyses are neither rati<strong>on</strong>alistic nor arbitrary; that is,history is neither determined nor random. Rather, history can beexplained by reference to particular amalgamati<strong>on</strong>s of social, political,ec<strong>on</strong>omic, aesthetic, and technological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s.For example, in educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse today, it is comm<strong>on</strong> to thinkof children as members of populati<strong>on</strong>al groups such as Hispanic, gifted,or learning disabled. However, the identificati<strong>on</strong> of children accordingto populati<strong>on</strong>al criteria is a relatively new way of thinking. Populati<strong>on</strong>alclassificati<strong>on</strong> is characteristic of the Progressive era in the United Stateswhen it was used as a means for managing large groups of immigrantchildren in the school systems (see e.g. Popkewitz, 1991). Populati<strong>on</strong>althinking in the Progressive era was embedded not <strong>on</strong>ly in educati<strong>on</strong>aldiscourse, but in an amalgamati<strong>on</strong> of social technologies includingec<strong>on</strong>omic, legal, and political.Critical postmodern historicizing has focused <strong>on</strong> comm<strong>on</strong>placeassumpti<strong>on</strong>s--such as populati<strong>on</strong>al thinking--and analyzed the technologieswhich inscribe and perpetuate those assumpti<strong>on</strong>s--such as114


ace-based or gender-based pedagogies, curriculum for the ”gifted andtalented”, I.Q. testing, populati<strong>on</strong>ally defined state policy, and ethnicallyspecific dress codes.In postmodern educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse, historical c<strong>on</strong>tingency isadvocated <strong>on</strong> two grounds. First, historical c<strong>on</strong>tingency does not embedthe theoretical mechanisms of predictability which c<strong>on</strong>strain historicaland future possibilities. A c<strong>on</strong>tingent organizing schema allows an analysisto un-determine future possibilities. This is a departure from criticalmodernist histories which tend to paint a picture of a better future as ameans of offering ”soluti<strong>on</strong>s.”Sec<strong>on</strong>d, historical c<strong>on</strong>tingency is a critical move in the face of currentsocial and political c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s. Arguments which assert historicalc<strong>on</strong>tingency fly in the face of an analytical schema. An analytical schemaseeks generalizable laws and predictable relati<strong>on</strong>s in its analyses. Criticalmodernists seek causal relati<strong>on</strong>s for social circumstances. However,historically c<strong>on</strong>tingent arguments seek to explain that currentcircumstances did not arise as inevitable, necessary, natural, or predictableeffects of previous circumstances; and furthermore, social technologieshave shaped subjectivity to the extent that <strong>on</strong>e can no l<strong>on</strong>ger assume an”authentic humanist” (i.e. pure and unsocialized) subject.Postmodern historicizing takes an assumed Truth of the universe andexplains it as a historical happenstance, and then examines thec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of that Truth as embodied in social technologies andtechnologies of the self. When assumed Truths are rec<strong>on</strong>stituted as beinghistorically specific, those Truths lose their reins <strong>on</strong> thought; and whenthe c<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong> of the subject is problematized, the effects of power <strong>on</strong>the self can be critiqued. Herein lies the critical potential of postmodernhistoricizing.C<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong> of the SubjectThe subject assumed in most educati<strong>on</strong>al discourse is not the Cartesiansubject whose ”subjective” experiences of dreams and revelati<strong>on</strong>s formedthe basis for c<strong>on</strong>jecture. Rather, the subject of most current discourseresembles the Kantian subject who can be studied objectively. Moreover,it is generally assumed that ”I” (as subject) am ”knowable” (asobject), so that objective-subjectivity also functi<strong>on</strong>s to c<strong>on</strong>stitute identity.115


The ability to study the ”self” (as subject/object) has been c<strong>on</strong>sideredto be a legacy of the Enlightenment, of which Kant’s work can be c<strong>on</strong>sideredthe culminati<strong>on</strong>. That is, the ”self” is no l<strong>on</strong>ger transcendent ormystical, but rather the ”self” is now knowable through the objective”light” of science.The Frankfurt School attacked the dominance of an analytical schemaby calling it ”instrumental” or ”subjective reas<strong>on</strong>ing” (meaning,ir<strong>on</strong>ically, the form of reas<strong>on</strong>ing imposed <strong>on</strong> the subject from theoutside), and advocated instead the value of ”objective reas<strong>on</strong>ing”(meaning, again ir<strong>on</strong>ically, the form of reas<strong>on</strong>ing innate to humansubjects). Adorno’s Minima Moralia (1951), for example, attacked”abstract, coherent, architect<strong>on</strong>ic systems”, and promoted ”subjective,private reflecti<strong>on</strong>” (quoted in Jay, 1972, p. 277). The agenda of theFrankfurt School was to reinsert possibilities for ”authentic humanist”resp<strong>on</strong>ses to counteract the dominance of instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing. Thisform of critique is characteristic of the Frankfurt School’s place in relati<strong>on</strong>to Marxian theories of history and Freudian theories of innate humanism.The modus operandi of the Frankfurt School was a c<strong>on</strong>certed campaigndirected against the loss of the subject and against the proliferati<strong>on</strong> ofinstrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing (or the Eclipse of Reas<strong>on</strong>, in Horkheimer’s terms).the Enlightenment’s overemphasis <strong>on</strong> logical formalism and itsassumpti<strong>on</strong> that all true thought tended towards the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of mathematicsmeant [to Horkheimer and Adorno] that the static repetiti<strong>on</strong>of mythic time had been retained, thwarting the dynamic possibility ofhistorical development. ...The instrumental manipulati<strong>on</strong> of nature byman [sic] led inevitably to the c<strong>on</strong>comitant relati<strong>on</strong>ship am<strong>on</strong>g men.(Jay, 1973, p. 261)On this point, critical modernists and postmodernists agree; the targetof all these critical theories has been the ”loss” of the subject throughobjectificati<strong>on</strong> and col<strong>on</strong>izati<strong>on</strong> by instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing. What theFrankfurt School calls, ”the overemphasis <strong>on</strong> logical formalism”,Habermas calls, ”the ’col<strong>on</strong>izati<strong>on</strong>’ of the life-world by an instrumentallogic that focuses exclusively <strong>on</strong> technique” (quoted in Kloppenberg,1994, p. 86), and Foucault (1979) calls ”governmentalisati<strong>on</strong>.” Thesecritical theorists began their social analyses with the same historical116


postulate, namely that throughout the twentieth century, the spread ofinstrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing and technologies of surveillance (such aspsychology) inscribed a new form of governance and c<strong>on</strong>comitant shiftsin power relati<strong>on</strong>s. Many recent critical theories argue that modern formsof governance could not exist unless individual subjects wereself-disciplined; current ec<strong>on</strong>omic and social systems depend up<strong>on</strong> theinculcati<strong>on</strong> of particular tastes, desires and aspirati<strong>on</strong>s am<strong>on</strong>g thecitizenry. Modern and postmodern critical projects as a whole weredirected against the loss of the subject, the col<strong>on</strong>izati<strong>on</strong> of the subject,or the discipline of the subject through technologies of the self.Remarkably, then, there is c<strong>on</strong>siderable similarity am<strong>on</strong>g modernistsand postmodernists c<strong>on</strong>cerning the loss of the subject in history. Theyagree that forms of reas<strong>on</strong>ing and power relati<strong>on</strong>s have problematizedthe assumpti<strong>on</strong> of an authentic subject. Finally, critical modernist andpostmodernist theories have focused <strong>on</strong> the loss of the subject as thecentral problem of modernity to be critiqued.While the modernists and postmodernists share the problem of theloss of the subject, they disagree significantly <strong>on</strong> what to do about it.The Frankfurt School rec<strong>on</strong>stituted a humanist subject by assuming atranscendent subject throughout their historical analyses. For example,in his appeal to ”subjective, private reflecti<strong>on</strong>”, Adorno assumed withoutquesti<strong>on</strong> that an individual is capable of authentic reflecti<strong>on</strong>. ”Aestheticexperience” served as evidence for the humanist subject, and the definiti<strong>on</strong>of ”beauty” was analyzed as implying a ”n<strong>on</strong>-identical” relati<strong>on</strong>between subject and object. In other words, the Frankfurt School deniedthat subjectivity was socially (or discursively) c<strong>on</strong>structed.The assumpti<strong>on</strong> of the ”authentic humanist” subject is the basis formodernist asserti<strong>on</strong>s of agency. The transcendent subject of the FrankfurtSchool is <strong>on</strong>e who is unadulterated by instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing andis therefore an agent capable of resistance. This theoretical positi<strong>on</strong> isbased <strong>on</strong> an a priori aut<strong>on</strong>omous subjectivity, in which an ”authentic”subject must be first assumed in order to provide a theoretical mechanismfor escaping the total dominati<strong>on</strong> of instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing.By not problematizing a priori subjectivity, the Frankfurt School tacitlyc<strong>on</strong>structed a stable, ahistorical, and n<strong>on</strong>-objectifiable agent positi<strong>on</strong>,in the traditi<strong>on</strong> of humanism and commensurate with Freud. Frankfurt117


School critical theory did not ask questi<strong>on</strong>s about where this sort ofhumanist subject might have come from, or what its relati<strong>on</strong> to historyor power might be; it assumed that there must be human agency whichwas pure, free, and capable of resistance. Therefore, even as the FrankfurtSchool painted a bleak picture of the dominance of instrumentalreas<strong>on</strong>ing, there was throughout their social analyses, the assumpti<strong>on</strong>of agency for a ”humanist” subject.While the earlier Frankfurt School theorists assumed a transcendenthumanist subject, Habermas problematized the subject. In this sense,Habermas’ resp<strong>on</strong>se to the ”’col<strong>on</strong>izati<strong>on</strong>’ of the life-world by instrumentallogic” departed somewhat from that of his <strong>teacher</strong>, Adorno.Habermas’ resp<strong>on</strong>se to the loss of the subject was to invoke asemi-aut<strong>on</strong>omous humanist subject in theory according to his postulatethat the moral, aesthetic, and scientific realms were semi-aut<strong>on</strong>omous.That is, in order to combat the dominance of instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing,Habermas (re)inserted a capacity for resistance into history by invokingan agentive, humanist subject which was asserted to be (to a degree)independent from the dominance of instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing. Habermasrecognized a problem in assuming a transcendent subject (e.g. Wheredid it come from?) and opted (in a move which some have argued isreminiscent of German idealism) to write a subject into the text, that isto c<strong>on</strong>struct a (semi-) aut<strong>on</strong>omous subject in terms of language. InHabermasian theory, the subject is made (semi-)aut<strong>on</strong>omous, that ismade (semi-) independent, from social dynamics in order to ”resist”col<strong>on</strong>izati<strong>on</strong> by social forces.In sum, the critical modernist (including the Frankfurt School andHabermas) project was to write history in such a way that acknowledgedmodern collective forms of social power, and at the same time, providea theoretical account of possibilities for human resistance. Adorno didthis by assuming an individual capable of aesthetic experience andmeaningful reflecti<strong>on</strong>; and Habermas did this by theoreticallyc<strong>on</strong>structing an aut<strong>on</strong>omous subject in dialectical relati<strong>on</strong> to instrumentalrati<strong>on</strong>ality.The trouble with this modernist assumpti<strong>on</strong> of agency is that it doesnot c<strong>on</strong>sider the possibility that ”subjective” experience has already beenshaped by historical circumstances and social technologies. There is no118


satisfactory mechanism in critical modernist theory for discriminatingbetween ”authentic” experience and ”socially c<strong>on</strong>structed” experience,no way to investigate which practices may be ”free” and which may beeffects of dominati<strong>on</strong>, and no theory which can discriminate betweenacts of resistance and acts of compliance.Furthermore, the reliance <strong>on</strong> agency and aesthetic experience tendsto deny <strong>on</strong>e of the primary c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s of the Frankfurt School, namelythat social technologies--such as instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing--shapesubjectivity. Critical modernist analyses do not account for the wayssubjective percepti<strong>on</strong>, tastes, desires, and hopes are effects of historicalc<strong>on</strong>texts. Critical modernist analyses generally do not acknowledge thecurrent historical c<strong>on</strong>text which entails the self-discipline of theindividual.Therefore, insofar as subjective experience is not problematized,critical leverage is lost. That is, without questi<strong>on</strong>ing the ways in whichsubjectivity is an effect of power, it is impossible to criticize the effectsof power at the subjective level. In this way, the transcendent,unproblematized, subject may inadvertently perpetuate existing powerrelati<strong>on</strong>s.Dehistoricized Subject. The work of Louis Althusser (Foucault’s<strong>teacher</strong>) began to point to a significant analytical difficulty in the FrankfurtSchool theory. This analytical difficulty can be called the problemof the dehistoricized subject. Briefly, the problem was that the FrankfurtSchool had granted dominant status to socio-ec<strong>on</strong>omic power inorder to account for the massive scale of modern instituti<strong>on</strong>s. However,if socio-ec<strong>on</strong>omic power was made so dominant, then the theoreticalpossibility of a resisting subject--an agent--must necessarily be ahistorical.In other words, if socio-ec<strong>on</strong>omic forces of history are so powerful, howis agentive resistance in history possible?The problem of the dehistoricized subject is exemplified in somepedagogies which are based <strong>on</strong> a discourse of ”democracy.” Suchpedagogies rest <strong>on</strong> the assumpti<strong>on</strong> that students--as a populati<strong>on</strong>algroup--are oppressed vis-à-vis the educati<strong>on</strong>al system. This approachrecognizes that <strong>teacher</strong>s and administrators are vested with instituti<strong>on</strong>alpower because of their positi<strong>on</strong>s in the instituti<strong>on</strong>al structure; the historicalc<strong>on</strong>text includes power relati<strong>on</strong>s, and a structural historical c<strong>on</strong>-119


text includes structural power relati<strong>on</strong>s. The emancipatory task of thedemocratic pedagogue, then, becomes to ”empower” students throughsuch technologies as ”giving students voice” and introducing democraticdecisi<strong>on</strong>-making procedures.The analytical difficulty with this theory is that it makes studentsoppressed and empowered at the same time: If students are by definiti<strong>on</strong>oppressed, how can they become empowered? And if students areempowered, how can they still bel<strong>on</strong>g to the (necessarily) oppressedgroup of students? The critical modernist resp<strong>on</strong>se to this difficulty hasbeen to assert that students have the subjective capacity for resistance,and this capacity is independent of historical power relati<strong>on</strong>s--hencedehistoricized.This is why, in critical modernist theory, the human agent is describedas dehistoricized. That is, in critical modernism, history was understoodas the story of ec<strong>on</strong>omic, social, and cultural oppressi<strong>on</strong>; and agentiveresistance was postulated to be independent of historical relati<strong>on</strong>s.Therefore, the work of the Frankfurt School critical intellectual hadbecome to author the agent and thereby the possibilities for resistance.Eventually, following Habermas, the possibilities for agency came tomean the sort of agency that could be objectively and literally c<strong>on</strong>structedin a text; possibilities for agency were authored by the critical intellectual.In other words, critical modernist theorists have tended to define”agency” according to a Habermasian traditi<strong>on</strong>, which means to inserta resisting subject into the text by declaring explicitly that subjects areendowed with agency, and that a history of oppressi<strong>on</strong> has no bearing<strong>on</strong> the capacity for resistance.Descripti<strong>on</strong> and Performativity. There are many similarities betweenHabermas’ linguistic analyses and those of critical postmodernists (e.g.Lyotard, 1984). Habermas’ remarkable Theory of Communicative Acti<strong>on</strong>elaborated the linguistic distincti<strong>on</strong>s between instrumental rati<strong>on</strong>alityand communicative rati<strong>on</strong>ality. This distincti<strong>on</strong> does not refer torelatively superficial changes in vocabulary and terminology. Rather, itrefers to paradigmatic shifts in what linguists have called ”speech acts.”For example, c<strong>on</strong>sider the descriptive act of the statements, ”The harvestwas abundant” and ”They got married”, in c<strong>on</strong>trast to the performativeact of the statements, ”Bless this harvest” and ”I now proclaim you120


husband and wife.” These are examples of two (of many) different speechacts which c<strong>on</strong>struct two different ”realities” in terms of language. Understandingthe first statement as descriptive requires an acceptance of astructural reality in which language can represent something. And understandingthe sec<strong>on</strong>d statement as performative requires an acceptanceof a c<strong>on</strong>structed reality in which language can effect something.Recent postmodern feminists (e.g. Butler, 1990) have critiquedHabermasian theories of communicative acti<strong>on</strong> and c<strong>on</strong>tributed aninnovative perspective which interrupts previous assumpti<strong>on</strong>s aboutdescriptive and performative rhetoric.The c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong> of Butler regarding ”performativity” can be understoodby drawing an analogy to an earlier historical shift. The shift from”traditi<strong>on</strong>al” to ”modern” discourses entailed differences between whatstatements were understood to be descriptive acts, and what statementswere understood to be performative. For example, in the sixteenthcentury, when the pope said, ”Luther is a heretic”, that was understoodas a performative act: The power of the sovereign was to pr<strong>on</strong>ouncereality. Then, modernity broke with that epistemological model andmade it possible that authoritative pr<strong>on</strong>ouncements could be understoodas descriptive, rather than performative.Modernity entailed an historical shift in the heuristic of ”interpretati<strong>on</strong>.”It is not difficult to imagine the emancipatory potentials of thismodern discursive shift: a word from the sovereign would no l<strong>on</strong>gernecessarily ”make it so”; the sovereign could ”get it wr<strong>on</strong>g”; or theremight be an ”alternative interpretati<strong>on</strong>.” Power took <strong>on</strong> new meaningsbecause the noble power to perform reality shifted to the scientific powerto describe and interpret reality.Recent critical work can be characterized as effecting an analogous(but inverse) shift in power. That is, recent critical theorists have beensuggesting that modern descriptive categories of discourse--like race,class and gender--have been functi<strong>on</strong>ing as disciplinary technologies.If we assume, for example, that any characteristic of race or gender is”descriptive”, then we assume a certain ”truth” about race or gender.That is, if we assume that ”better at language and worse at math” isdescriptive of a woman, then we have assumed that the ”true” identityof a woman is <strong>on</strong>e who is better at language and worse at math. The121


analytical difficulty in this descriptive heuristic is that any pers<strong>on</strong> whois ”worse at language and better at math” cannot be a ”true” woman. Inthis way, descriptive language functi<strong>on</strong>s to determine (discursively) howa woman can be.In some multiculturalist pedagogies there is an elaborati<strong>on</strong> ofdifferences am<strong>on</strong>g various ”cultures”--usually racially, but sometimesethnically, defined. Multiculturalist pedagogies use a language whichdistinguishes and identifies students according to cultural descriptors.Generally speaking, the language is understood to be descriptive ofsomething ”real.” That is, the descriptors are usually derived throughempirical research, and they are justified <strong>on</strong> the basis of appeals toobservable evidence. These cultural descriptors have several effects: thecultural descriptors correlate particular cultures with particular activities,propensities, tastes, and problems; the language sets up culture-basedexpectati<strong>on</strong>s regarding students’ behaviors and abilities; the descriptorsrender race, class and gender as significant determinants of identity; thelanguage c<strong>on</strong>structs specific ways for students to understand themselvesand identify themselves; and the language descriptors--by virtue ofomissi<strong>on</strong>--obliterate alternative percepti<strong>on</strong>s of identity which are notbased <strong>on</strong> ”culture.” In other words, race, class and gender are assumedto be descriptive of subjectivity.Multiculturalist discourses can call attenti<strong>on</strong> to the ways educati<strong>on</strong>alpractices which are assumed to be universal are actually historically orgeographically specific. Moreover, there are situati<strong>on</strong>s in which culturallyspecific language can be very useful for addressing injustices in theclassroom and in society at large. However, postmodern critical theorieshave called attenti<strong>on</strong> to the ways discourses c<strong>on</strong>struct subjectivity inmultiple ways, some of which may undermine the intended objectivesFor example, if a discourse identifies students as ”at risk” or”disenfranchised” or ”privileged”, then that language ascribes to studentsthose characteristics as descriptive of self and identity. Postmodern criticaltheorists have recognized that there is a problem when these identitiesare assumed to be descriptive of subjectivity. That is, when culturalidentities are assumed to be descriptive, then those descriptors stabilizesubjectivity and reinscribe existing power relati<strong>on</strong>s. An example of thisis when the definiti<strong>on</strong> of a feminist is a woman who believes that women122


are oppressed. In that definiti<strong>on</strong>, it is theoretically impossible to be awoman and be emancipated at the same time. When subjectivity isstabilized and power relati<strong>on</strong>s are reinscribed, then the theory does notallow for significant breaks from the status quo.Many postmodern critical theories have problematized the descriptivefuncti<strong>on</strong> of language. In postmodern theories, categories (such as race,class and gender) are no l<strong>on</strong>ger assumed to be necessarily descriptive ofidentity, but rather are regarded as performative of identity--in a similarsense as when speech acts are descriptive or performative. This theoreticalmove introduces possibilities for subjectivity which go bey<strong>on</strong>d what can bedescribed in the text. That is, subjectivity is no l<strong>on</strong>ger objectified as a functi<strong>on</strong>of textual descripti<strong>on</strong>; identity is no l<strong>on</strong>ger stipulated by descriptors. Rather,another form of performative subjectivity has been introduced.In order to c<strong>on</strong>ceive of the subject which is no l<strong>on</strong>ger text-bound, itmay be helpful to think of the subject-as-reader as being part of the text.This performative (reading) subject is not described in the text, is notpredictable, and is not stable. There exists the theoretical possibilitythat multiple texts and multiple subjects can exist. The noti<strong>on</strong> of aperformative subject opens theoretical possibilities for profound breaksfrom existing power relati<strong>on</strong>s.For example, in her creative critical resp<strong>on</strong>se to the objectified subject,Butler (1990) theorized gender as performance. When subjectivity is castas performance, self-presentati<strong>on</strong> functi<strong>on</strong>s as a presence in an active, ratherthan a passive way; a student’s identity is not seen as ”representative” ofher gender or his race. In performative subjectivity, ”the subject presentsitself” (active tense), which is different from ”the subject is visible” (passivetense). For example, a student who is female would not necessarily carrythe identity as <strong>on</strong>e who is ”better at language and worse at math.”The critical aspect of this move is that it does three things simultaneously:it effects an epistemological break by shifting from a descriptive to aperformative mode; it opens up possibilities for changing existingpatterns of power by challenging assumed structures; and it theoreticallyforecloses the possibility of determinism by invoking the improvisati<strong>on</strong>alaspects of performance.Herein lies <strong>on</strong>e of the significant distincti<strong>on</strong>s between critical modernistand postmodernist work. On the <strong>on</strong>e hand, modernist theories123


have insisted that there must be an indomitable essence of subjectivitywhich can serve as the source or agent for an emancipatory visi<strong>on</strong>; thisoccurs when a pedagogical approach calls for ”voice” and ”resistance.”This denial that subjectivity can be totally dominated is often perceivedas an ”optimistic” or ”hopeful” stance.On the other hand, postmodernist theories have been skeptical aboutthe extent to which subjectivity has been disciplined. Postmodernhistoricizing resp<strong>on</strong>ses generally assume that social technologies (includinggovernmental, legal, ec<strong>on</strong>omic, aesthetic, and pedagogical) have workedto c<strong>on</strong>stitute subjectivity in a particular way which then makes it problematicto assume that the subject is necessarily capable of agency from an”uncol<strong>on</strong>ized” place. This skepticism is not to insist that the subject hasbeen totally dominated and there is no agent. Rather it is to suspendjudgment in analyses of social situati<strong>on</strong>s in order to be able to examine thecomplex--and seemingly c<strong>on</strong>tradictory--ways power operates to c<strong>on</strong>structsubjectivity; it is to problematize the ways in which thinking may alreadyhave been disciplined. Postmodern critical theories assume that there areways subjectivity has already been c<strong>on</strong>stituted (i.e. ways power operates) ofwhich we are not aware. Furthermore, if an agentive resisting subject isassumed, then some disciplinary effects of power may go undetected anduncriticized.In sum, recent postmodern critical projects, in skeletal syllogistic form,have argued something like this:Assumpti<strong>on</strong>: Critical intellectual work is not deterministic.First premise: If intellectual work makes history predictable, then it makessubjectivity determined, unless the theory assumes or invokes a (semi-)aut<strong>on</strong>omous (”resisting”) subject.Sec<strong>on</strong>d premise: The present day subject has been instrumentalized,col<strong>on</strong>ized, or objectified (i.e. ”lost”) through technologies ofgovernmentality (or instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing).Q.E.D.: In the current moment: 1) if intellectual work is predictive, itinscribes determinism; 2) if a subject is either assumed or invoked, thatsubject is always already an effect of power, and therefore it is notaut<strong>on</strong>omous.Foucaultian and other postmodern historicizing projects depart fromFrankfurt School traditi<strong>on</strong>s by refusing to assume--and refusing to124


insert--an aut<strong>on</strong>omous subject. This refusal by postmodern accountsto insert a subject (or c<strong>on</strong>struct a textual subject) has been attackedby critical modernists as being ”nihilistic.” However, the refusal toinsert subjectivity has had other c<strong>on</strong>sequences. One effect has beento historicize the subject; that is, in postmodern historicizing thesubject is understood within the historical c<strong>on</strong>text of governmentality(i.e. subjectivity is not analyzable separately from history). Anothereffect has been that the subject is no l<strong>on</strong>ger textually (objectively)determined in the writing (i.e. the text works instead to dec<strong>on</strong>structdiscursive c<strong>on</strong>straints <strong>on</strong> subjectivity). That is, research does not havethe job of envisi<strong>on</strong>ing or stipulating possibilities for subjectiveidentities. Further c<strong>on</strong>sequences of postmodern historicizing <strong>on</strong> therole of the intellectual is the focus of the following secti<strong>on</strong>.The Trouble with Intellectual Work: Examplesof Pedagogical Critiques“There is no knowledge that is not power.”Mortal Kombat IIIThe first part of this chapter discussed the political c<strong>on</strong>sequences oftheories which assume predictability in historical analysis. The sec<strong>on</strong>dpart analyzed the effects related to assumpti<strong>on</strong>s of agency. This thirdpart questi<strong>on</strong>s the implicati<strong>on</strong>s for the role of the intellectual given thetroubles with predictability and agency.Recently, the problem has been to figure out how intellectual workcan effect political critique and at the same time eschew intellectualvanguardism. The issue is: What is the political role of critical workwhich does not validate itself <strong>on</strong> the basis of generalizable principle,which does not foreclose possibilities for radical breaks in the future,which does not presume authority over (i.e. determine) subjectivity,and which does not usurp resp<strong>on</strong>sibility for explaining and predictinghistory and social relati<strong>on</strong>s?Critical modernist and postmodernist intellectuals in educati<strong>on</strong> haveoffered various critiques of current pedagogies. Variati<strong>on</strong>s in the role ofthe critical intellectual can be illustrated through the differences in theirrespective critiques of a given pedagogical practice.125


The example of current pedagogical practice offered here is journalwriting. Requiring students to write in journals is a pedagogical techniqueof increasing popularity which is being used not <strong>on</strong>ly in language artsclasses for compositi<strong>on</strong> practice, but also in mathematics and sciencesclasses in order to facilitate metacognitive awareness of methods,procedures and problem-solving strategies. Students are often requiredto keep ”double-entry” journals in which <strong>on</strong>e entry reflects the curriculumc<strong>on</strong>tent of a less<strong>on</strong>, and the sec<strong>on</strong>d entry reflects the students’ feelingsand resp<strong>on</strong>ses to the c<strong>on</strong>tent of the less<strong>on</strong>. In another variati<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> thistechnique, students are asked to use a journal as an outlet to express andrecord private thoughts or pers<strong>on</strong>al experiences. The assumpti<strong>on</strong> is thatjournals not <strong>on</strong>ly facilitate literacy, but also allow the students to engagedirectly and pers<strong>on</strong>ally with the material.Critical intellectuals affiliated with modernist traditi<strong>on</strong>s (e.g. Marxian,Frankfurt School, or Habermasian) offer various critiques of journal-keepingas a pedagogical technique. The critiques tend to highlight three themes:voice/silence, representati<strong>on</strong>/empowerment, and solidarity/transformativity.For example, modernist critiques of pedagogy are c<strong>on</strong>cerned with the degreeto which classroom power dynamics c<strong>on</strong>tribute to the ”silencing” or togiving ”voice” to marginalized and/or oppressed people. These critiquespoint out the ways in which students’ journals sometimes serve to facilitateexpressive voices, and sometimes serve to recapitulate a deferential attitudetowards the authority of the <strong>teacher</strong>. Modernist critiques analyzemulticultural variati<strong>on</strong>s in subject matter and rhetorical form in order toreveal the ethnocentrism of certain topics or writing styles. These critiquescall attenti<strong>on</strong> to power differentials am<strong>on</strong>g different groups of people, andstrive to empower those groups who have less power than others.In additi<strong>on</strong>, modernist literary analyses have criticized prescriptivistgrammatical expectati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the grounds that dialectical variati<strong>on</strong>s ingrammatical form ought to be represented. Finally, modernist criticshave been c<strong>on</strong>cerned with the transformative potential of journal writing;therefore, studies are d<strong>on</strong>e to determine whether the practice of writingjournals actually results in any transformati<strong>on</strong> of prejudicial behavioror attitudes, or alternatively, in any sense of empowerment.In general, current modernist social analyses do not simply criticizeoppressive practices. Modernist critics tend to employ a dialectical frame-126


work of analysis, and therefore, the analyses tend to explain relati<strong>on</strong>s interms of opposing forces. Moreover, this traditi<strong>on</strong> has recently tendedto inscribe a Habermasian strategy of interpolating aut<strong>on</strong>omoussubjectivity. Therefore, in the face of dominant power, such analysestypically c<strong>on</strong>clude with a call for agentive resistance as the dialogicalalternative. They may close with an appeal to a spirit of freedom, andan exhortati<strong>on</strong> to reform oppressive practices and empower thedisenfranchised. Some analyses include specific suggesti<strong>on</strong>s for reformwhich may be methodological, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual, political, or attitudinal. Thetenor of such critical analyses tends to be <strong>on</strong>e of hopeful revoluti<strong>on</strong>, asif to say, ”Oppressi<strong>on</strong> is real, but here is a way to end oppressi<strong>on</strong> andmake the world better.”In these critical analyses, the modernist intellectual assumes the roleof the liberated and the liberator, but not the powerful. Assuming anoptimistic (but often oppressed) stance, the critical intellectual providesa visi<strong>on</strong> of a better world as the dialogical counterpoint to oppressi<strong>on</strong>.The modernist intellectual has the moral resp<strong>on</strong>sibility to bring the lightof hope to those whose visi<strong>on</strong> has been denigrated, and whose spirit hasbeen demoralized. In the face of oppressi<strong>on</strong>, the role of the intellectual is toboost morale and provide a directi<strong>on</strong> of hope for the future.By assuming this role, the modernist intellectual assumes a peculiarplace in relati<strong>on</strong> to history and in relati<strong>on</strong> to subjectivity. That is, ifhistory is theorized in terms of sovereign power (i.e. some people haveit and some people d<strong>on</strong>’t), then that same history cannot account forchanges in who has power. Rather, the aut<strong>on</strong>omous resisting subject--inthis case the critical intellectual--can account for changes in who haspower. The intellectual must take a subject positi<strong>on</strong> outside of historyin order to ”resist” dominant forces. This relati<strong>on</strong> suggests that a theoryof history which rests <strong>on</strong> the assumpti<strong>on</strong> of sovereign power requiresaut<strong>on</strong>omous (ahistoric) subjectivity. Furthermore, any possibility ofemancipati<strong>on</strong> requires the interventi<strong>on</strong> of the critical intellectual in orderto write the aut<strong>on</strong>omous subject into theory. The modernistintellectual is central in history.How have postmodern critics analyzed the pedagogical practice of journalkeeping? Themes of postmodern critique have been those of language,discipline, power, and subjectivity. Regarding journals, the postmodern127


critic has asked, ”How have the technologies of journal writing operated toc<strong>on</strong>stitute the subject of educati<strong>on</strong>?” Postmodern critics have investigatedthe possibilities that journal-keeping be a means of surveillance, and/or itmay be a means of disrupti<strong>on</strong>. That is, journal-keeping may be a technologywhich m<strong>on</strong>itors students’ intimate thoughts and makes the students’ privatelives accessible to the <strong>teacher</strong>, and/or journal-keeping may be a technologywhich interrupts existing power dynamics.Postmodern critique does not assume that any<strong>on</strong>e can know inadvance how power will be expressed at any given moment. Therefore,postmodern analyses of pedagogical practices such as journal-keepinghave tended to highlight multiple and c<strong>on</strong>tradictory ways in which powerwas exercised: the <strong>teacher</strong> encroached <strong>on</strong> the private life of a studentand then intervened; a student used the journal to develop an opini<strong>on</strong>;a <strong>teacher</strong> interrupted a destructive prejudice; a student used the journalto explain to the <strong>teacher</strong> that journals were intrusive and manipulative.Other postmodern critics have taken journal-writing as a piece ofevidence which gives clues to the history of schooling and how itspedagogical practice has shifted from training behaviors, to educatingminds, to disciplining souls.Postmodern critics have been influenced by Foucault, and tend toregard all social practices and systems of reas<strong>on</strong>ing with great suspici<strong>on</strong>.Furthermore, in the traditi<strong>on</strong> of Foucault, postmodern critics--unlikeHabermasian critics--generally refuse to offer a visi<strong>on</strong> of the future. Postmoderncritical intellectuals refuse to offer a visi<strong>on</strong> of the future (suchas providing a soluti<strong>on</strong>, ideal, or utopian hope) because to do so wouldset limits <strong>on</strong> possibilities for the future.This point is irresistibly ir<strong>on</strong>ic: Foucault is often called (and has calledhimself) a pessimist. However, he refused to offer a visi<strong>on</strong> of the future infear that he might inadvertently foreclose--a presumably better--future.That is, when systems of reas<strong>on</strong>ing are unjust, it becomes counterproductiveto offer a visi<strong>on</strong> of the future based <strong>on</strong> those existing systems of reas<strong>on</strong>ing.Furthermore, to offer a visi<strong>on</strong> of the future is to assume a positi<strong>on</strong> of politicalauthority (”intellectual as center”), which is a positi<strong>on</strong> that Foucaultand many feminist theorists have generally declined <strong>on</strong> ethical grounds.Rather than a visi<strong>on</strong> of the future, postmodern critics tend to offer ahistory of the present (often called genealogy). The political agenda of128


genealogies is generally to dem<strong>on</strong>strate that there is nothing necessary orinevitable about our present circumstances. The purpose of genealogicalcritique is to render events and circumstances historically c<strong>on</strong>tingent. AsFoucault says, it is to ”restore chance to its rightful place in history.” Postmoderncritics offer a visi<strong>on</strong> of the past because, at this historical momentin which principled rati<strong>on</strong>ality is seen as pervasive (the critical legacy of theFrankfurt School), a visi<strong>on</strong> of the past serves to divest that principledrati<strong>on</strong>ality of its natural, assumable comm<strong>on</strong>sense. Moreover, when the”laws of nature” and the ”progress of science” are shown to be inadequateor invalid (i.e. when they are dec<strong>on</strong>structed) in the face of historical evidence,then there is a theoretical possibility for a (unforeseeable) radical break.The role of the critical intellectual in this traditi<strong>on</strong> is not <strong>on</strong>e offorecasting, it is <strong>on</strong>e of remembering: ”All reificati<strong>on</strong> is a forgetting.”The ethical positi<strong>on</strong> is <strong>on</strong>e of ”pessimistic activism”, in which morefaith rests <strong>on</strong> the unforeseen and unc<strong>on</strong>trolled possibilities for the futurethan <strong>on</strong> the ability of intellectuals to solve social problems.The critical leverage of genealogical critique is historically limited;genealogies can be characterized as critical <strong>on</strong>ly insofar as they challengea significant level of comm<strong>on</strong>sense assumpti<strong>on</strong>s at this historicalmoment. Whenever the approach of genealogy becomes formalizedand instrumentalized, critical intellectuals will be called up<strong>on</strong> tointerrupt that approach, too.In ClosingIn sum, critical intellectuals since the Frankfurt School have targetedthe ”col<strong>on</strong>izati<strong>on</strong> of the life-world” by instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing. Modernistcritics have traditi<strong>on</strong>ally resp<strong>on</strong>ded to this col<strong>on</strong>izati<strong>on</strong> by invokingan objectified versi<strong>on</strong> of an aut<strong>on</strong>omous, humanist subject as part ofthe text. This invocati<strong>on</strong> of an agent has several effects, including: 1)dehistoricizing the subject, 2) circumscribing and delimiting possibilitiesfor subjectivity, 3) recapitulating existing power hierarchies by appealingto established principles of verificati<strong>on</strong>, 4) establishing a relati<strong>on</strong> of alienati<strong>on</strong>between the textual subject and the subject-as-reader, and 5)presupposing the loss of the subject.The postmodernist resp<strong>on</strong>se to this col<strong>on</strong>izati<strong>on</strong> has challenged themodernist resp<strong>on</strong>se at several dimensi<strong>on</strong>s, including: 1) problematizing129


the assumpti<strong>on</strong> of aut<strong>on</strong>omous subjectivity, thereby reuniting historyand subjectivity, 2) dec<strong>on</strong>structing the textually objectified subject, 3)historicizing the systems of reas<strong>on</strong>ing which have become naturalizedassumpti<strong>on</strong>s, 4) shifting analytical perspective so as to undermine thedichotomous relati<strong>on</strong> between textual subject and subject-as-reader, and5) rejecting the inevitability of the loss of the subject by explaining thecurrent state of the subject as a product of particular social practiceswhich have disciplined and shaped possibilities for subjectivity.The critical political project then, involves making power andsubjectivity functi<strong>on</strong>s of history--which is theoretically mutable--ratherthan functi<strong>on</strong>s of generalizable principle--which is theoreticallyimmutable. An interrupti<strong>on</strong> of the status quo is made possible <strong>on</strong>ly ifthe theoretical explanati<strong>on</strong>s of history (as change) allow for genuineinnovati<strong>on</strong> including radical breaks. If theories of history make changepredictable, regular, calculable, or determined, then there is no theoreticalmechanism for breaking the existing power hierarchies. On the otherhand, if theories of history explain change as an effect of unpredictablesocial and historical practices, then existing power hierarchies lose theirpositi<strong>on</strong> of privilege.130


ReferencesBerger, P., Berger, B. & Kellner, H. (1973). The homeless mind: Modernizati<strong>on</strong> andc<strong>on</strong>sciousness. New York: Vintage.Bernstein, R. (1992). The new c<strong>on</strong>stellati<strong>on</strong>: The ethical-politicalhoriz<strong>on</strong>s of modernity/postmodernity. Cambridge: MIT.Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversi<strong>on</strong> ofidentity. New York:Routledge.Burchell, G., Gord<strong>on</strong>, C. & Miller P. (Eds.). (1991). The Foucault effect:Studies ingovernmentality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Cherryholmes, C. (1992 August-September). Notes <strong>on</strong> Pragmatism andscientific realism.Educati<strong>on</strong>al Researcher, 21. pp. 13-17.Cherryholmes, C. (1994a January-February). More notes <strong>on</strong> pragmatism.Educati<strong>on</strong>alresearcher, 23, (1), pp. 16-18.Cherryholmes, C. (1994b). Pragmatism, poststructuralism, and sociallyuseful theorizing.Curriculum Inquiry, 24 (2). pp. 193-213.Crary, J. (1992). Techniques of the observer: On visi<strong>on</strong> and modernity inthe nineteenthcentury. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Descartes, R. (1980). Discourse <strong>on</strong> the method of rightly c<strong>on</strong>ducting <strong>on</strong>e’sreas<strong>on</strong> andof seeking truth in the sciences. (D.A. Cross, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett.Dreyfus, H.L. & Rabinow, P. (1983). Michel Foucault: Bey<strong>on</strong>d structuralismandhermeneutics. (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Foucault, M. (1970). The order of things: An archaeology of the humansciences.New York: Random House.Foucault, M. (1972a). The archaeology of knowledge and the discourse <strong>on</strong>language.(A.M. S. Smith, Trans.). New York: Panthe<strong>on</strong>.Foucault, M. (1972b). Power/knowledge: Selectec interviews and otherwritings,1972-1977. (C. Gord<strong>on</strong>, Ed.; C. Gord<strong>on</strong>, L. Marshall, J. Mepham,K. Soper,Trans.). New York: Panthe<strong>on</strong>.Foucault, M. (1977). Language, counter-memory, practice: Selected essays and interviews.(D. F. Bouchard, Ed.; D. F. Bouchard & S. Sim<strong>on</strong>, Trans.).Ithaca: CornellUniversity Press.Foucault, M. (1978). The history of sexuality: An introducti<strong>on</strong>. (R. Hurley, Trans.).New York: Random House.Foucault, M. (1979). Governmentality. Ideology and C<strong>on</strong>sciousness, 6, 5-22.Foucault, M. (1984). The Foucault reader. (P. Rabinow, Ed.). New York: Panthe<strong>on</strong>.Foucault, M. (1988a). The political technology of individuals. In L.H.Martin, H.Gutman, & P.H. Hutt<strong>on</strong> (Eds.). Technologies of the self: Aseminar with MichelFoucault,. (pp. 145-162). Amherst: The University of Massachusetts Press.Foucault, M. (1988b). The care of the self. (R. Hurley, Trans.). Vol. III of the Historyof sexuality. New York: Random House. Foucault, M. (1990). The useof pleasure. (R. Hurley, Trans.). Vol. 2 of the History of sexuality. New York:Random House.Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s development.Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Habermas, J. (1981). The theory of communicative acti<strong>on</strong>. Vol. 2. Lifeworld and system:A critique of functi<strong>on</strong>alist reas<strong>on</strong>. (Trans. Thomas McCarthy). Bost<strong>on</strong>: Beac<strong>on</strong>.Horkheimer, M. (1947). Eclipse of reas<strong>on</strong>. New York: Oxford University.131


Jay, M. (1973). The dialectical imaginati<strong>on</strong>: A history of the Frankfurt School and theInstitute of Social Research, 1923-1950. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Heinemann Educati<strong>on</strong>al Books.Kant, I. (1949). Fundamental principles of the metaphysic of morals. (T.K. Abbott,Trans.). Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Kant, I. (1950). Prolegomena to any future metaphysics. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Lasch, C. (1979). The culture of narcissism: American life in an age of diminishingexpectati<strong>on</strong>s. New York: W.W. Nort<strong>on</strong>.Lyotard, J-F. (1984). The postmodern c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>. St. Paul: University of Minnesota.O’D<strong>on</strong>nell. J.M. (1985). The origins of behaviorism: American psychology, 1870-1920.New York: New York University Press.Popkewitz, T.S. (1991). A political sociology of educati<strong>on</strong>al reform. New York: TeachersCollege Press.Riley, D. (1988). ”Am I that name?” Feminism and the category of ’women’ in history.Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Toulmin, S. (1990). Cosmopolis: The hidden agenda of modernity. New York: The FreePress.Wagner, P. (1994). A sociology of modernity: Liberty and discipline. New York:Routledge.Young, R. (1990). White mythologies: Writing history and the west. New York: Routledge.132


Notes1Carol Gilligan (In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development, 1982)outlines a theory of development specific for women.2Foucault (1972) designates chr<strong>on</strong>ology in terms of ”thresholds”: ”The moment at whicha discursive practice achieves individuality and aut<strong>on</strong>omy, the moment therefore at whicha single system for the formulati<strong>on</strong> of statements is put into operati<strong>on</strong>, or the moment atwhich this system is transformed, might be called the threshold of positivity [e.g. systematicmedieval investigati<strong>on</strong>s into empirical observati<strong>on</strong>]. When in the operati<strong>on</strong> of a discursiveformati<strong>on</strong>, a group of statements is articulated, claims to validate (even unsuccessfully)norms of verificati<strong>on</strong> and coherence, and when it exercises a dominant functi<strong>on</strong> (as amodel, a critique, or a verificati<strong>on</strong>) over knowledge, we will say that the discursive formati<strong>on</strong>crosses a threshold of epistemologizati<strong>on</strong> [e.g. Descartes’ articulati<strong>on</strong> of the Discourse<strong>on</strong> Method]. When the epistemological figure thus outlined obeys a number of formalcriteria, when its statements comply not <strong>on</strong>ly with archaeological rules of formati<strong>on</strong>, butwith certain laws for the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of propositi<strong>on</strong>s, we will say that it has crossed athreshold of scientificity [e.g. assumpti<strong>on</strong> of experimental hypothesis-testing as ”the scientificmethod.”]. And when this scientific discourse is able, in turn, to define the axiomsnecessary to it, the elements that it uses, the propositi<strong>on</strong>al structures that are legitimateto it, and the transformati<strong>on</strong>s that it accepts, when it is thus able, taking itself as astarting-point, to deploy the formal edifice that it c<strong>on</strong>stitutes, we will say that it hascrossed the threshold of formalizati<strong>on</strong>” [e.g. positivistic foundati<strong>on</strong>s of social science] (pp.186-187).3Although the Frankfurt School placed great emphasis <strong>on</strong> aesthetics, it is an aspect whichhas been virtually ignored in recent years, even by Frankfurt School adherents. Whetherthe aesthetic realm could be c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be ”aut<strong>on</strong>omous” from the influences ofinstrumental reas<strong>on</strong>ing was a significant c<strong>on</strong>troversy in Frankfurt School debates.4Moreover, they analyze uses of language and c<strong>on</strong>crete social practices in order to understandthe loss of the subject.5This assumpti<strong>on</strong> about subjectivity is often called ”essentialism” or the ”essential subject.”6It is interesting to note that while the Frankfurt School was committed to outlining atheory of emancipati<strong>on</strong>, they explicitly denied that reas<strong>on</strong> could or should suggest praxis:”The age needs no added stimulus to acti<strong>on</strong>. Philosophy must not be turned into propaganda,even for the best possible purposes” (Horkheimer, quoted in Jay, 1973, p. 266).7What is interesting to note is that critical theories, including modernists andpostmodernists, have generally accepted the validity of the assumpti<strong>on</strong>, the first, and thesec<strong>on</strong>d premises. However, modernists tend to c<strong>on</strong>clude that critical theories musttherefore deny totalizing dominati<strong>on</strong> and c<strong>on</strong>struct (or ”empower”) a resisting subject.133


134


I N G V A R R Ö N N B Ä C KScience and Evaluati<strong>on</strong> :Critical research or instrument fordestructiveness?Introducti<strong>on</strong>On August 6, 1945 the first atomic bomb was dropped over Hiroshimain Japan. In a split sec<strong>on</strong>d some 120,000 people were killed by a bombcalled ”the little boy”. The repugnant name given to this m<strong>on</strong>strousweap<strong>on</strong> could nevertheless be said to c<strong>on</strong>tain a grain of truth. The natureof this weap<strong>on</strong> was anything but little and innocent, but it wassomething new, something qualitatively different. A new world had beenborn. Never before in the history of the world had it been possible todestroy an entire city with <strong>on</strong>e bomb. It was a technological masterpiecebut a horror for humanity. No l<strong>on</strong>ger was it possible to seek shelterfrom falling bombs. The atomic bomb guaranteed the total destructi<strong>on</strong>of the people and material that happened to be at the point of impact.With time, the range of the atomic bomb expanded to encompass morethan just a single city. The inc<strong>on</strong>ceivable explosive power of present-daynuclear arsenals is sufficient to reduce the whole planet to a smokingpile of ashes. 1The c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of this ”doomsday weap<strong>on</strong>” requires knowledge, avery special kind of knowledge. Practical skills are not enough, <strong>on</strong>e needsto be able to understand the theory produced by talented scientists.This scientific framework was a prerequisite to the manufacture of theatomic bomb. The military and political establishments needed helpwith this technological challenge. They turned to the leading researchersof the day, who agreed to create a whole new type of weap<strong>on</strong>, theatomic bomb. 2The moral of this brief account? That science is not value-neutral, ofcourse. Science and ethics bel<strong>on</strong>g together, they are inseparable. Theresearchers who participated in the producti<strong>on</strong> of the atomic bomb couldhave said no, we do not want to be involved in the creati<strong>on</strong> of such a135


weap<strong>on</strong>. 3 The clear-cut divisi<strong>on</strong> between ”existence” and ”value” whichhas been <strong>on</strong>e of science’s hallmarks is therefore a misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> whichshould be challenged. 4 Scientific results and the applicati<strong>on</strong> of theseresults can always be discussed and should be discussed. The abovementi<strong>on</strong>edaccount also shows that research and science stand in relati<strong>on</strong>to other social instituti<strong>on</strong>s and exist in a social, ec<strong>on</strong>omic and politicalc<strong>on</strong>text. Scientific knowledge may thus be used by instituti<strong>on</strong>s,organizati<strong>on</strong>s and groups with dubious and inhumane goals in mind.This is a fact which each researcher needs to keep in mind. The aim ofthe above account is to provide a brief background to the problems andissues which will be addressed in this paper. The atomic bomb illustrateshow research and science are neither free from politics nor from valuesand morals. All research is involved in and a part of society.More specifically, this paper examines four problem areas closely linkedwith each other. The first problem area c<strong>on</strong>sidered c<strong>on</strong>cerns thesimilarities and differences that obtain between research and evaluati<strong>on</strong>.Within the sec<strong>on</strong>d problem area, the main focus is <strong>on</strong> how the evaluatorshould view ”development”. The third problem area addresses what ischaracteristic of the scientific c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the world and thec<strong>on</strong>sequences this c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> has for society in general. The fourth andfinal problem area deals with the relati<strong>on</strong> between the evaluator and the”client” who has commissi<strong>on</strong>ed the knowledge produced by theevaluator. The thesis pursued in this paper is that there is no greatdifference between research and evaluati<strong>on</strong>, that evaluati<strong>on</strong> is closelyc<strong>on</strong>nected with the idea of development, that the classical scientificworld-view c<strong>on</strong>tains a number of misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s and that the evaluatormust always think about ethical questi<strong>on</strong>s when given a commissi<strong>on</strong>.The paper should be viewed as a critical inquiry of scientific rati<strong>on</strong>ality,a rati<strong>on</strong>ality that has developed since the 17th century with effects <strong>on</strong>the ”modern” and ”postmodern” world 5 . This inquiry have led me to adiscussi<strong>on</strong> of what the c<strong>on</strong>sequenses are for ”evaluators” or scientists ingeneral in terms of ethical c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s. The paper should not beviewed as a ”program for change”. My main c<strong>on</strong>cern has been to discussthe ethical difficulties that all researchers and evaluators are c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>tingwhen given a commissi<strong>on</strong> or a scientific task.136


Research and evaluati<strong>on</strong>Research and evaluati<strong>on</strong> are not the same thing, even though there aresimilarities and points of c<strong>on</strong>tact. The aim of research and evaluativeactivity is ideally <strong>on</strong>e and the same, namely the truth. Even if ”truth” isa complex c<strong>on</strong>cept resistant to facile interpretati<strong>on</strong>, it neverthelesscomprises the ultimate goal of both research and evaluati<strong>on</strong>. Theresearcher and the evaluator seek knowledge about ”existence” and arec<strong>on</strong>sequently also forced to decide whether humans can gain ”reliable”knowledge about this ”existence”. In scientific terminology these arecalled <strong>on</strong>tological and epistemological issues. Such issues are fundamentalto subjects like philosophy and the theory of science but are addressedwithin other disciplines as well - in fact within all forms of scientificactivity. 6 It is my c<strong>on</strong>tenti<strong>on</strong> that evaluati<strong>on</strong> is also a scientific activity. 7The main difference between research and evaluati<strong>on</strong> is the object ofstudy. In principle, researchers can study anything they want, a fly, asociety, a historical event or pers<strong>on</strong>, a natural object, a philosophicalsystem, etc., etc. As regards evaluati<strong>on</strong> the situati<strong>on</strong> is somewhat different.Evaluati<strong>on</strong> is first and foremost about studying goal-oriented humanactivities; <strong>on</strong>e of its fundamental assumpti<strong>on</strong>s is the idea that ahuman being has a c<strong>on</strong>sciousness and that this c<strong>on</strong>sciousness can choosebetween various acti<strong>on</strong>s in the search to attain <strong>on</strong>e or more goals.Evaluati<strong>on</strong> is also about appraising the goals set up by humans as well asthe acti<strong>on</strong>s aimed at achieving these goals. 8 Thus in the c<strong>on</strong>cept ofevaluati<strong>on</strong> the aspect of value occupies a central positi<strong>on</strong>.What I attempt to say with the above distincti<strong>on</strong> between researchand evaluati<strong>on</strong> is that both are about trying to grasp ”truth”. This is alsothe ”credo” or highest goal of science. 9 All the philosophical andmethodological problems c<strong>on</strong>tained within a scientific work can thusbe found in both research and evaluative activity.The fundamental difference thus lay in evaluati<strong>on</strong>’s clearer c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>with human activities when compared to research. It is not possible to”evaluate” the quality of precipitati<strong>on</strong> or whether a beaver has built itsdam according to acceptable building standards. Nor is it possible to”evaluate” human scriptures such as the Bible or the Koran, or the politicalsituati<strong>on</strong> which prevailed in the Europe of the 1800s. It is possible<strong>on</strong> the other hand to study and research these phenomena. The c<strong>on</strong>cept137


of evaluati<strong>on</strong> incorporates the idea that humans hold a unique positi<strong>on</strong>am<strong>on</strong>g the species of the earth, and that this unique positi<strong>on</strong> meansthat humans have a c<strong>on</strong>sciousness which allows them to make choices.A human being can thus do something ”better” or ”worse”, and it isthe task of evaluati<strong>on</strong> to determine which value applies. Naturally, theterms ”good” and ”bad” can mean very different things to differentpeople. How can <strong>on</strong>e determine what is ”good” and ”bad”, and who isto make this determinati<strong>on</strong>? The evaluator? It is clear that the role ofevaluati<strong>on</strong> is not entirely unc<strong>on</strong>troversial. The Finnish philosopherGeorg Henrik v<strong>on</strong> Wright, to whose work and thought I will makefurther reference, says for example the following:”Here I should like to briefly comment <strong>on</strong> two particular ways in whichthe State’s approach to research, and partly also industry’s, has changed.Both are aimed at ensuring that the sums invested in science are effectivelyremunerative. The first is the assessment of the work of <strong>on</strong>e’s colleagues,which has become known by the name of ”evaluati<strong>on</strong>”. A group from <strong>on</strong>ecircle of instituti<strong>on</strong>s comments <strong>on</strong> the quality of the research being carriedout at certain other instituti<strong>on</strong>s. Or it may be a matter of a multinati<strong>on</strong>aljury given the task of judging the level of their discipline in a particularcountry. The idea is of course not so much to praise those being evaluated fortheir competence as it is to force them to raise their standards after theequivalent of an intellectual flogging. The simple awareness that such anexaminati<strong>on</strong> is in the offing should have an stimulating effect <strong>on</strong> researchthreatened by apathy, or so the thinking goes. I thoroughly disapprove of thisphenomen<strong>on</strong>. Perhaps I am <strong>on</strong>e of science’s l<strong>on</strong>e, lost wolves, but neverthelesswhen I speak about the prerequisites for creative work I do so from theexperience of a lifetime and not as a hesitant beginner fearing criticism”. 10That evaluati<strong>on</strong> could in some way be ”revoluti<strong>on</strong>ary” in relati<strong>on</strong> toestablished paradigms is inc<strong>on</strong>ceivable to v<strong>on</strong> Wright. Rather it is thecase that the evaluator or evaluators (if it is a group) c<strong>on</strong>tribute to thestreamlining of science inasmuch as researchers who do not proceedfrom established viewpoints are branded as ”eccentrics” playing futilegames in the backyards of science. 11 The fact that directi<strong>on</strong>s of researchand approaches diverging from the norm fail to receive the attenti<strong>on</strong>and support they perhaps should have naturally has far-reachingc<strong>on</strong>sequences for the shape and evoluti<strong>on</strong> of society. For v<strong>on</strong> Wright138


the evaluator becomes the technological and dehumanizing society’sdefender and c<strong>on</strong>troller. Whether this is correct will be c<strong>on</strong>sidered withinthe scope of the following heading.Evaluati<strong>on</strong> and developmentAs previously indicated, evaluati<strong>on</strong> is based <strong>on</strong> the idea that the c<strong>on</strong>cepts”better” and ”worse” can be applied to the form and functi<strong>on</strong> of society. Itmust also be based <strong>on</strong> a belief that a pers<strong>on</strong> can choose between differentacti<strong>on</strong>s and thereby create a better society. Evaluati<strong>on</strong> and the belief that abetter society can be created are thus closely linked. The questi<strong>on</strong> is, betterfor whom? And what c<strong>on</strong>stitutes a good society? To be able to reflect <strong>on</strong>these questi<strong>on</strong>s, it is necessary to look back in history in the hopes of findingout what was previously c<strong>on</strong>sidered a good society and what the c<strong>on</strong>ceptof ”development” actually stood for. How else are we to determine thevalue of that which was and the society we now live in? It is particularlyimportant to crystallize the roots and c<strong>on</strong>tent of the modern c<strong>on</strong>cept ofdevelopment. In c<strong>on</strong>trast, a retrospective analysis where relevant facts areidentified and described is no simple matter. To which historical sourcesdo we turn, whom do we listen to in order to ensure a correct descripti<strong>on</strong>and analysis of this gigantic mound of informati<strong>on</strong> that is our history?As previously menti<strong>on</strong>ed, I make use of Georg Henrik v<strong>on</strong> Wright’sthoughts with regard to these questi<strong>on</strong>s. He is by no means al<strong>on</strong>e in hisanalysis, but the authority he brings to bear <strong>on</strong> it is hard to equal. Thereas<strong>on</strong> why v<strong>on</strong> Wright’s analysis in particular is of import in this c<strong>on</strong>textis because he devoted his time to trying to understand the world-viewthat characterizes the modern society, a world-view which can be saidto be a scientific <strong>on</strong>e. If, as has been said, evaluati<strong>on</strong> is a scientificactivity, it seems reas<strong>on</strong>able to try and determine just what science is. Italso seems important to try and delineate the c<strong>on</strong>sequences this visi<strong>on</strong>of the world has had for the society we live in, i.e. modern society.The scientific world-view and its c<strong>on</strong>sequences for societyWhat is science? This is a questi<strong>on</strong> which many have tried to answer,and the answers vary depending <strong>on</strong> which period of time we are talkingabout. Shall <strong>on</strong>e attempt to describe the scientific world-view in termsof the scientific disciplines, or shall <strong>on</strong>e try to ascertain the main139


assumpti<strong>on</strong>s up<strong>on</strong> which science is based? If <strong>on</strong>e attempts the first, thatis, to understand science in terms of the disciplines extant at the world’suniversities, <strong>on</strong>e will probably get a rather fragmented picture of whatscience actually is. A physicist, a biologist and a psychologist, for example,have very different objects of study. Moreover, even within the individualdisciplines there are differences in focus and method. In spite of thefragmented picture of knowledge produced and exhibited by science,v<strong>on</strong> Wright still tries to say something about the core of the scientificworld-view, especially the world-view that emerged during what is calledthe Renaissance and which has been evolving up until the present day.It is true that the roots of the viewpoint that ”blossomed” during the1600s are found in the Greek-antique culture and in the Christian <strong>on</strong>e 12 ,but <strong>on</strong>e can n<strong>on</strong>etheless say that it was during the Renaissance that thescientific world-view began to seriously compete with the religiousc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s that dominated at that time. A series of scientific discoveriesupset the world-view that was primarily advanced by the church.Giordano Bruno, Johannes Kepler and Galileo Galiei are famous namesin the history of science. Blood flowed and dissenting opini<strong>on</strong>s werebranded as heresy. The power which the church wielded was howeverfated to wane: the process of secularizati<strong>on</strong> had begun.Naturally there are a lot of interesting things to say about this time,when the power of the church decreased and other outlooks secured afoothold. But it would seem more important to focus <strong>on</strong> what v<strong>on</strong>Wright believes is characteristic of the scientific world-view. By sciencehe does not mean all the disciplines that employ scientific methodology,rather it is the natural sciences which attract his attenti<strong>on</strong>. The reas<strong>on</strong>for this is that these fields in particular are making enormous progress.The humanities and the social sciences are left to try and imitate theunprecedented achievements of the natural sciences. Nature is charted,classified, examined and stripped of its mysteries by men such as Carlv<strong>on</strong> Linné, Isaac Newt<strong>on</strong> and Charles Darwin. It is reduced to an objectover which humans can increasingly exercise c<strong>on</strong>trol, and the scientificexperiment becomes the tool whereby human dominance of the plantand animal kingdoms is attained. Armed with the discoveries andknowledge acquired through the scientific method, human beings assumea new role. They become the measure of all things, and the ideas which140


informed Greek philosophy, namely the c<strong>on</strong>cept of equilibrium betweenhumans and nature, are now replaced by an exploitative standpoint.According to v<strong>on</strong> Wright this attitude is pure arrogance. The scientificspirit bears the signs of hubris. Humans believe they are God, that theirpower permits them to dominate the envir<strong>on</strong>ment in which they live.This hubris can <strong>on</strong>ly lead to the goddess of revenge, nemesis, strikingback with full force. 13 We have <strong>on</strong>ly an inkling of what will happenwhen the majority of the earth’s inhabitants demand the same materialstandard of living that we in the rich, industrialized countries enjoy.The wear and tear <strong>on</strong> the envir<strong>on</strong>ment would be enormous. And wehave <strong>on</strong>ly an inkling of what will happen to the already deterioratingoz<strong>on</strong>e layer when refrigerators and freezers are found in every home.The lifestyle that has emerged in the so-called civilized part of the world,in the West, is not ecologically sustainable and thus not a workable”developmental model” for the l<strong>on</strong>g run. The mechanical-deterministicschema <strong>on</strong> which science has leaned is an illusi<strong>on</strong>. Natural events andprocesses are not as predictable as has previously been supposed; ratherthere is a large degree of unpredictability in the ecosystem. The worldviewcreated by science was thus a gross simplificati<strong>on</strong>, to be found <strong>on</strong>lyin laboratories. Far more complex c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>s obtain in the real world,with phenomena dynamically interacting in a way that is hard to grasp. 14Not <strong>on</strong>ly does the scientific world-view embody a dominating andexploitative c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of nature, it forces its way into the social instituti<strong>on</strong>swhich are evolving simultaneously with the growth of science,in politics and in the ec<strong>on</strong>omy. Thus even humans become objects whichcan be manipulated and subjected to various forms of influence. 15 Onesource of influence is the group of instituti<strong>on</strong>s whose task is to informcitizens about what is right and proper, for example the school system,the mass media and different types of agencies bel<strong>on</strong>ging to the apparatusof the State. One might also menti<strong>on</strong> the advertising which proceedsfrom industry’s push to survive and increase its capital. The informati<strong>on</strong>is often geared towards c<strong>on</strong>vincing people that ec<strong>on</strong>omic growth isnecessary for society and that the divisi<strong>on</strong> and specializati<strong>on</strong> of labor issomething good. Society must be efficient in its manufacturing of anever-ending stream of more or less useless products. Human beings inthis society become means, things to be used - indeed used up if necessary.141


The fundamental rati<strong>on</strong>ality of modernized and technicalized societymay be described as ”goal-oriented” and is summarized by v<strong>on</strong> Wrightin the following way:”The type of rati<strong>on</strong>ality which prevails in a society freed from the religiousand social prejudices of previous generati<strong>on</strong>s and based <strong>on</strong> the credo of reas<strong>on</strong>c<strong>on</strong>sists first and foremost of a mastery of the means for achieving variousgoals. It is an instrumental or technical, goal-oriented rati<strong>on</strong>ality, whichrequires an increased efficiency in the producti<strong>on</strong> of goods and theorganizati<strong>on</strong> of services, the services of society. It ”streamlines” our lives. Onthe other hand it stands bewildered before the value-based premises whichare supposed to legitimize the goals for societal acti<strong>on</strong>. As a result, respect forthe individual (”human dignity”) declines, and new forms of repressi<strong>on</strong> andunfreedom are possible in a society where power lies in the hands of thosewho run the ”state apparatus”, as it is revealingly named. Thus emancipati<strong>on</strong>from outmoded relati<strong>on</strong>s leads to new c<strong>on</strong>straints in the modern world.Wrapped in the straitjacket of technological rati<strong>on</strong>ality, humans are led in asociety governed by unreas<strong>on</strong> and primitive instincts, where power andviolence have superseded humanity as ideals. 16V<strong>on</strong> Wright’s summary can be traced back to the so-called FrankfurtSchool. He believes that the representatives for the Frankfurt School,including Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer and Jürgen Habermas,made a good diagnosis of modern society but were less successful atfinding a way out of this society marked by technological rati<strong>on</strong>ality.Nor did v<strong>on</strong> Wright feel able to show how this enslavement under ”themyth of progress” and technology could be broken. He says for examplethat:”Of course the problems need solving! But how? Protecting the envir<strong>on</strong>mentagainst the polluti<strong>on</strong> and pois<strong>on</strong>ing caused by industries is expensive. Thuswe must get richer to be able to afford the cost. The cure for unemploymentis new workplaces. But if these do not pay for themselves by increasedproducti<strong>on</strong> they become unprofitable. In short: c<strong>on</strong>tinued ec<strong>on</strong>omic growthis a prerequisite to the soluti<strong>on</strong> of the problems which an intensified andrati<strong>on</strong>alized industrial producti<strong>on</strong> itself creates. Social progress enters into acircle whose c<strong>on</strong>tinued movement is dependent <strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tinued growth. This isa slightly caricatured picture of what I mean by growth as an all-embracingpolitical ideology. I do not wish to criticize policies professing this ideology,142


as I realize how difficult it is to be free of it. Nevertheless, I believe suchpolicies are short-sighted and that the obstacles which they may at first overcomewill return in greater size. Pers<strong>on</strong>s engaged in practical affairs maynot think so, or perhaps <strong>on</strong>ly in their hearts. But I have yet to meet with <strong>on</strong>ewell-reas<strong>on</strong>ed and c<strong>on</strong>vincing argument in favor of such optimism. It is inthis regard that my own opini<strong>on</strong> can truly be called pessimistic. I find itdifficult to believe that those trends which are moving us closer to the loomingdanger will weaken or change. The force of these trends is referred to inVetenskapen och Förnuftet as the dictatorship of circumstances, a straitjacketwrapped around society by an accelerating and relatively aut<strong>on</strong>omoustechnological evoluti<strong>on</strong> and the c<strong>on</strong>comitant need for uninterrupted ec<strong>on</strong>omicgrowth and expansi<strong>on</strong>ism. Naturally this is not a questi<strong>on</strong> of absolute necessity,let al<strong>on</strong>e predestinati<strong>on</strong>. Humans create their own history, and it is up tothem to free themselves from the c<strong>on</strong>straints imposed by their own senselessacti<strong>on</strong>s”. 17V<strong>on</strong> Wright is desperately looking for a new attitude am<strong>on</strong>g people,and particularly am<strong>on</strong>g the groups that wield power in society,comprising some form of self-c<strong>on</strong>trol and basic solidarity towards otherhumans and living creatures. Not everything which can be d<strong>on</strong>e shouldbe d<strong>on</strong>e. The atomic bomb neither has to be used nor manufactured,even if we have the technological capacity and knowledge to producesuch a weap<strong>on</strong>. The sense of solidarity which v<strong>on</strong> Wright proposes extendsbey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>on</strong>e’s immediate family or even nati<strong>on</strong>. The less fortunate inhabitantsof the poorer countries and c<strong>on</strong>tinents must become part of <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong>alresp<strong>on</strong>sibility. Above and bey<strong>on</strong>d that, those alive now must feel a sense ofobligati<strong>on</strong> towards the unborn. As v<strong>on</strong> Wright says:“Solidarity can no l<strong>on</strong>ger be limited to a narrow circle of blood relati<strong>on</strong>sor mutual family ties or professi<strong>on</strong>al interests. It must transcend all nati<strong>on</strong>al,racial and religious boundaries and become a sense of global resp<strong>on</strong>sibility- global also in the sense that it extends to those who will walk the earthafter us. At heart, this is nothing else than the fulfilment of the Christiancommandment to love others as we love ourselves”. 18The practical c<strong>on</strong>sequences of this solidarity might take the followingforms:”A development of the kind proposed here means am<strong>on</strong>g other thingsthat the inhabitants of the industrialized countries would have to change143


their lifestyle, c<strong>on</strong>sent to live rather more frugally and renounce the desiresthat they have become used to satisfying but which can be d<strong>on</strong>e without. Wein the industrialized countries must quite simply become poorer, so that thegrowing polarizati<strong>on</strong> between First and Third World countries, but alsobetween the have and have-nots in the former, does not completely destabilizethe globe”. 19The global sense of solidarity which v<strong>on</strong> Wright is looking for iscounteracted by the fact that we, as he puts it, sit at other tables andnegotiate pay raises, tax breaks and various measures designed to stimulatethe ec<strong>on</strong>omy and strengthen the internati<strong>on</strong>al competitiveness of ourcompanies. 20 One can <strong>on</strong>ly agree. There are a lot of paradoxes in ourworld. The internati<strong>on</strong>al community, led by the UN, has throughoutthe war in the former Yugoslavia supported and imposed a weap<strong>on</strong>sembargo <strong>on</strong> all sides in the c<strong>on</strong>flict. Despite this, a massive arms tradehas been carried out, with weap<strong>on</strong>s flowing in from all corners of theglobe. 21 Similarly, it can be said that the Swedish weap<strong>on</strong>s export policyis an equivocal phenomen<strong>on</strong> that brings shame <strong>on</strong> Sweden. We havethe most restrictive legislati<strong>on</strong> in the world in this regard but havemanaged <strong>on</strong> several occasi<strong>on</strong>s to supply weap<strong>on</strong>s to areas where armedc<strong>on</strong>flicts are raging. In spite of these legal restricti<strong>on</strong>s, there is no realwill am<strong>on</strong>g Swedish politicians to address this problem. The reas<strong>on</strong> issimple enough: nati<strong>on</strong>al interest weighs more heavily than moralprinciples. 22The diagnosis which v<strong>on</strong> Wright makes regarding modern hypertechnologicalsociety is anything but naive and unrealistic. We knowthat there is an enormous wear and tear <strong>on</strong> the nature off which we live.We know that the gap between poor and rich countries and betweenpoor and rich people is increasing. We also know that a fracti<strong>on</strong> of theworld’s military arsenal could reduce the earth to an uninhabitable, sterilewasteland. And we know that the majority of humans have no c<strong>on</strong>trolwhatsoever over their own lives. Our highly compartmentalized andhierarchical society with its enormous bureaucratizati<strong>on</strong> of the socialapparatus is anything but democratic, for all the formally democraticnature of system.Our hopes lie in the ability of humankind to choose a different path.With respect to research, this means that ”the search for truth” must144


also encompass ethical dimensi<strong>on</strong>s; researchers, too, need to ”do theright thing”. The questi<strong>on</strong> remains, however, whether research andevaluati<strong>on</strong> can be anything else than servants of the rati<strong>on</strong>ality which isdestroying the planet we live <strong>on</strong> and thus human society as well. Thisissue will addressed in the final part of the paper.Power, evaluati<strong>on</strong> and ethicsAs previously indicated, research does not exist in a societal vacuum.There has to be a demand for the type of knowledge which researchproduces for there to be any scholastic instituti<strong>on</strong>s at all. Of course, it istheoretically possible for a l<strong>on</strong>e wolf with a passi<strong>on</strong>ate thirst for truth tocreate new types of knowledge. But it is presumably unc<strong>on</strong>troversial tostate that practically all research is greatly dependent <strong>on</strong> ec<strong>on</strong>omic supportfrom well-heeled instituti<strong>on</strong>s and organizati<strong>on</strong>s in society. Thisbegs the following questi<strong>on</strong>s: what kind of rati<strong>on</strong>ality informs theseinstituti<strong>on</strong>s and organizati<strong>on</strong>s? Have researchers any chance at all topursue a dialogue and influence the social instituti<strong>on</strong>s’ self-c<strong>on</strong>sciousness?Or is it the bitter truth that research is so imbued with the goal-orientedrati<strong>on</strong>ality described by v<strong>on</strong> Wright that no other type of discourse ispossible?It could be the truth, but probably not the whole truth. Historyitself is proof that human society and self-understanding changesc<strong>on</strong>stantly. Today an increasing number of people have access to informati<strong>on</strong>about the problems v<strong>on</strong> Wright describes. Issues like the thinningof the oz<strong>on</strong>e layer, the devastati<strong>on</strong> of the forests, energy supply andpopulati<strong>on</strong> growth are public property in a whole different way thanbefore. It would be strange if researchers did not also take these threatsseriously and look to understand the causes underlying the problemsand find soluti<strong>on</strong>s. It would also be strange if the issues of global survivaldid not leave their mark <strong>on</strong> the areas of politics and the ec<strong>on</strong>omy. Perhapsthe biggest cause for alarm is the short time we have to deal with manyof the problems facing humanity. Perhaps it is already too late. Is theglobal destructi<strong>on</strong> of the envir<strong>on</strong>ment irreversible, or can a change inpolicy alleviate the wear and tear <strong>on</strong> Mother Earth. It could be that theenvir<strong>on</strong>mental destructi<strong>on</strong> is too far advanced, and perhaps it isimpossible to stop the explosive populati<strong>on</strong> growth, and perhaps hu-145


man selfishness is too great. But as v<strong>on</strong> Wright himself says, the <strong>on</strong>lyreply to the questi<strong>on</strong> whether there is hope for the future is this: let uswork to ensure that there is <strong>on</strong>e!! 23For the evaluator this would mean being critically aware of thec<strong>on</strong>sequences following the advance of the so-called technosystem. 24C<strong>on</strong>cepts like progress, growth and development would thus need tobe closely examined, which would allow evaluators to be more activelyaware of the explicit or implicit demands their ”clients” make <strong>on</strong> theresearcher to affirm the premises up<strong>on</strong> which science is based. Naturally,this awareness <strong>on</strong> the part of the evaluators might compromise them inthe eyes of their clients. Those who have power in society presumablylook for loyal underlings who will not criticize too much. This is perhapsalso the greatest problem for individual researchers, the threat of losingtheir jobs because of their views and enduring sceptical looks from more”realistic” colleagues. The solidarity which v<strong>on</strong> Wright speaks of is no”fair-weather” solidarity. Instead it demands that people be prepared todie for ”the others”, the unborn, the victims. There are examples ofpeople who have been excluded from their communities because theyhave defended the rights of others and fought <strong>on</strong> their behalf. Manyhave been thrown into pris<strong>on</strong>, tortured and executed for such acts ofc<strong>on</strong>science, acts far different from those of researchers defending therights of the powerful and who believe solely in technological soluti<strong>on</strong>sto social problems.146


ReferencesAgrell, Villhelm, (1981). Rustningens drivkrafter. Studentlitteratur.Agrell, Willhelm, (1989). Vetenskapen i försvarets tjänst. Lund University Press.Barash, David P, (1991). Introducti<strong>on</strong> To Peace Studies. Wadsworth Publishing Company.Bauman, Zygmunt, (1989). Auschwitz och det moderna samhället. Daidalos.Bernstein, Richard J, (1987). Bortom objektivism och relativism. Röda bokförlaget.Fischer, Dietrich, Nolte, Willhelm & Öberg, Jan, (1990). Vinn freden - strategier och etikför en kärnvapenfri värld. Pax förlag.Guba, Eg<strong>on</strong> G (ed.), (1990). The Paradigm Dialog. Sage Publicati<strong>on</strong>s.House, Ernest R, (1993). Professi<strong>on</strong>al Evaluati<strong>on</strong>. Sage Publicati<strong>on</strong>s.Johanss<strong>on</strong>, Ingvar & Liedman, Sven-Eric, (1987). Positivism och marxism. Norstedts.Karlss<strong>on</strong>, Svante, (1994). Freds- and k<strong>on</strong>fliktkunskap. Studentlitteratur.Ofstad, Harald, (1987). Vi kan ändra världen. Prisma.Selander, Staffan, (1992). Forskning om utbildning. Brutus Östlings Bokförlag.Selander, Staffan, (1986). Kunskapens villkor. Studentlitteratur.Westander, Henrik, (1995). Vapenexport - svenskt stål biter. SÄK-häfte. Svenska freds- andskiljedomsföreningen.v<strong>on</strong> Wright, Georg Henrik, (1978). Humanismen som livshållning. Månpocket.v<strong>on</strong> Wright, Georg Henrik, (1986). Vetenskapen och förnuftet. Månpocket.v<strong>on</strong> Wright, Georg Henrik, (1993). Myten om framsteget. B<strong>on</strong>niers.Öberg, Jan, (1994). Liten Guide till stort krig - Korta svar på svåra frågor om Jugoslavien.Transnati<strong>on</strong>ella stiftelsen för freds- och framtidsforskning.Notes1For a discussi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> nuclear weap<strong>on</strong>s see e.g. Karlss<strong>on</strong>, S, (1994) Freds- och k<strong>on</strong>fliktkunskapor Barash, D, (1991) Introducti<strong>on</strong> to Peace Studies.2One scholar who has studied in detail the links between science, research and the militaryis Willhelm Agrell. Two books can be menti<strong>on</strong>ed in this regard: Agrell, W, (1981) Rustningensdrivkrafter and Agrell, W, (1989) Vetenskapen i försvarets tjänst.3I do not say that the researchers involved in the ”atomicbombproject” didn´t have otherinterests than scientific <strong>on</strong>es. Winning the ”war” were surely a str<strong>on</strong>g motivati<strong>on</strong> forparticipating in this project. What I want to say is that science leans str<strong>on</strong>gly towards aninstrumentalistic and objectivistic view of knowledge. Science are therefore running therisk of being an instrument for inhuman purposes. For a discussi<strong>on</strong> of this issues, see e.gFischer, D, Nolte, W & Öberg, J (1990). Vinn freden - Strategier och etik för en kärnvapenfrivärld och Ofstad, H (1987). Vi kan ändra världen. It´s also important to have inmind that there were scientists with the capability and skills required to produce such aweap<strong>on</strong> who protested against the ”atomicbombproject”.4It should perhaps be noted that ethical questi<strong>on</strong>s are not absent in intra-scientic debate.See e.g. Guba, E G, (ed.) (1990) The paradigm dialog, House, E R, (1993) Professi<strong>on</strong>alEvaluati<strong>on</strong>, Bernstein, R J, (1987) Bortom objektivism och relativism and Selander, S,(red.) (1986) Kunskapens villkor. But I think it´s right to say that scientific results to alarge extent are presented and used as ”objective” informati<strong>on</strong>.147


5With this I d<strong>on</strong>´t say that science can be seen as homogenus activity and phenomen<strong>on</strong>.I just say that scientific rati<strong>on</strong>ality holds a set of assumpti<strong>on</strong>s that makes it differentfrom other types of ”rati<strong>on</strong>alities” and therefore ”appears” to the world as ”science”.With other words, science is a beliefsystem that can be interpreted in many ways but stillis science. Within this ”scientific beliefsystem” there is a struggle between different actorsabout the meaning of science. I think it´s possible to compare science with otherbeliefsystems in these aspects.This paper stresses that science, so far, has c<strong>on</strong>tributed tothe ”crise-like” situati<strong>on</strong> for mankind.6For an expositi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> the foundati<strong>on</strong>s of science, see e.g. Johanss<strong>on</strong>, I & Liedman, S-E,(1987) Positivism och marxism.7It is perhaps particularly important in this respect to point out that the legitimacy ofevaluati<strong>on</strong> is based precisely <strong>on</strong> this claim, that it is scientific. See House, E R, (1993)Professi<strong>on</strong>al Evaluati<strong>on</strong>, p 30.8The above descripti<strong>on</strong> of the c<strong>on</strong>cept of evaluati<strong>on</strong> is perhaps c<strong>on</strong>troversial as it does notdescribe the various evaluative models that do exist. The debate am<strong>on</strong>g researchers ofevaluati<strong>on</strong> is missing in my report, but I believe that the ”mainstream” within evaluati<strong>on</strong>research can be reas<strong>on</strong>ably described in the above manner. Another approach is the socalledtheory-oriented evaluati<strong>on</strong> which is based <strong>on</strong> social research and theory. Thisapproach is characterized by a scientific focus <strong>on</strong> knowledge and analyses which do notattract as much attenti<strong>on</strong>. It could be that this theory-oriented evaluati<strong>on</strong> is a modelparticularly well suited for the kind of critical reflecti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> the resp<strong>on</strong>sibility of researcherswhich I am looking for. One criticism of theory-oriented evaluati<strong>on</strong> is that it ought tobe called research pure and simple, a viewpoint which I wholeheartedly share. See Lindensjö,B & Lundgren U P: in Selander, S (red.) Forskning om utbildning.9This statement could perhaps be questi<strong>on</strong>ed by some (or several?) researchers. I amaware of the ”paradigmdebate” and the critic of the ”modern project”, but, even if ”truth”has become more ”relative” since this types of questi<strong>on</strong>s has come up, I d<strong>on</strong>t think thatany researcher can escape from the fact that every statement they do about the ”world”is a statement about how they think the ”world” looks like. So, even if the try to breakdown or questi<strong>on</strong> every possible theory or ”truth”, that in it self becomes a truth.10v<strong>on</strong> Wright, G-H (1986), Vetenskapen och förnuftet, pp. 125-126. In my opini<strong>on</strong>, thisbook is an excellent c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong> to the debate <strong>on</strong> the rati<strong>on</strong>ality that characterizes modernsociety. v<strong>on</strong> Wright is a critic of civilizati<strong>on</strong> in the sense that he calls into questi<strong>on</strong>the so-called ”idea of progress”, which according to him c<strong>on</strong>sists of an exaggerated beliefin technology’s ability to create a better society.11Ibid. p. 127. For a discussi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>cept of paradigms, see also Guba, E G, (1990)The paradigm dialog, Bernstein, R J, (1987) Bortom objektivism och relativism and Selander,S, (red.) (1986) Kunskapens villkor.12It is difficult to summarize the c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s made by the Greek and Christian culturesto the evoluti<strong>on</strong> of science and society. As v<strong>on</strong> Wright points out, Greek philosophypaved the way for both the development of theory and the search for knowledge based<strong>on</strong> observati<strong>on</strong>. During antiquity the ”theoretical human” was born, the <strong>on</strong>e who asksquesti<strong>on</strong>s and tests, embodying an attitude that had far-reaching c<strong>on</strong>sequences for theevoluti<strong>on</strong> of science. The Greeks also emphasized the need to base knowledge <strong>on</strong> observedfacts, laying the ground for the traditi<strong>on</strong> within scientific theory called empiricism.148


This, too, was an important aspect of scientific epistemology. Another seed was found inChristian culture. In the first chapter of the Bible it is written that God created theworld and said: ”Let us make humans in our own likeness, to be our equal; and theyshall have domini<strong>on</strong> over the fish in the sea and over the birds under the heavens andover the herds and the whole earth”. Nature was thus supposed to serve humankind andnot vice-versa, an attitude very much in evidence today.13Hubris and nemesis are c<strong>on</strong>cepts which derive from the Greek mythology. These areessential c<strong>on</strong>cepts to v<strong>on</strong> Wright. He has also analysed his view <strong>on</strong> other mythologiesand folk-tales with the focus <strong>on</strong> the analysis of the paradise myth of the Bible, thePrometheus myth form the Greek mythology and the story of Dr Faust. All three storiesgive topical interest to the problem whether humans are fitted to handle their inherentabilities. V<strong>on</strong> Wright´s analysis of these stories can be found in ”Humanismen som livshållning”from 1978.14v<strong>on</strong> Wright discusses these problems both in ”Vetenskapen och förnuftet” and ”Myten omframsteget”. The realizati<strong>on</strong> that the mechanical-deterministic world-view is collapsing,according to v<strong>on</strong> Wright, has caused a crisis in classical science. In c<strong>on</strong>trast, he takes nopositi<strong>on</strong> as to whether the world really is unpredictable or whether it is just our own lackof knowledge, that is, whether the limitati<strong>on</strong>s are <strong>on</strong>tological or epistemic.15One scholar who has discussed in an interesting fashi<strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>sequences of scientificrati<strong>on</strong>ality for the modern society’s social structure is Zygmunt Bauman. See Bauman, Z(1989). Auschwitz och det moderna samhället. He argues that scientific morals is insufficientto stop genocide, they rather facilitate the exterminati<strong>on</strong> of large ethnic groups.Bauman also argues that modern society is so thoroughly bureaucratized it itself fostersimmorality. No <strong>on</strong>e knows what any<strong>on</strong>e else is doing and the ”victims” of bureaucracy’sobsessi<strong>on</strong> with efficiency remain invisible.16v<strong>on</strong> Wright, G-H, (1986) Vetenskapen och förnuftet, pp. 17-18.17v<strong>on</strong> Wright G-H, (1993) Myten om framsteget, pp. 9-10.18Ibid. p. 55.19Ibid. p. 146.20Ibid. p. 151.21See Öberg, J (1994) Liten Guide till stort krig - Korta svar på svåra frågor om Jugoslavien.22Se Westander, H, (1995) Vapenexport - svenskt stål biter.23v<strong>on</strong> Wright, G-H, (1993) Myten om framsteget, p. 56.24By technosystem v<strong>on</strong> Wright means an alliance between science, technology and industry.149


150


M A R Y B A U M A N NThinking the young woman’sbleeding: early discursiveinvestigati<strong>on</strong> of menarche”In order to make the story tellable, <strong>on</strong>e has toseparate and put into sequence events which inreality were so entangled as to be inexplicable.”(Wolf 1970, 64)Medicine, psychology, sociology, history, educati<strong>on</strong>, and commercialenterprises, while historically excluding women from the process of thecreati<strong>on</strong> of discourses, have each assembled a large amount of materialwhich has attempted and c<strong>on</strong>tinues to endeavor to ”understand,””regulate,” ”define,” and ”c<strong>on</strong>trol” young women. This multiplicati<strong>on</strong>of discourses about young women requires problematizati<strong>on</strong>.Menarche, a young woman’s first menstrual bleeding, exemplifiesthis process of intellectual ownership and ’resp<strong>on</strong>sible’ investigati<strong>on</strong> byexperts within fields based <strong>on</strong> a male-developed rati<strong>on</strong>ality. Never simplya biological episode, menarche is a discursive event, a material andlinguistic reality, which frames and forms the young woman as a sexualbeing and places her within a binary—male/female—in which she isthe inferior element. It is at this event that a young woman encountersher body, not simply as materially different and limited, but as a surface,signified by taboos and transgressi<strong>on</strong>s (Lee 1994). When a youngwoman begins to bleed, she c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ts the material reality of her body,located and defined within a cultural c<strong>on</strong>text.Using menarche, I want to c<strong>on</strong>sider how the body of a young womanis made intelligible, can be thought about. Through a suspensi<strong>on</strong> of anycommitment to the noti<strong>on</strong> of a materiality unaffected by thought, I wantto problematize the term ”menarche,” to open it to c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s whichrec<strong>on</strong>ceptualize the bodily process as something other than ’natural’ or’biological.’ I want to explore ideas about the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of bodiesthrough discourses which c<strong>on</strong>solidate and c<strong>on</strong>ceal power relati<strong>on</strong>s.151


I ask: In what c<strong>on</strong>crete ways are young women, their bodies and theirsexuality produced and reas<strong>on</strong>ed about in the discursive c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>sof menarche? What are the implicati<strong>on</strong>s of these public discussi<strong>on</strong>sfocused <strong>on</strong> young women’s bleeding? What are the governing principlesin public discourse <strong>on</strong> menarche? How are these ways of telling the”truth” about menarche the effects of power? Through what regulatorynorms is the young woman’s sex materialized?I will investigate the explosi<strong>on</strong> of informati<strong>on</strong> about and examinati<strong>on</strong>of menarche in the 19th and early 20th centuries, its pathologizati<strong>on</strong>by medical, psychological, and commercial expertise and its integrati<strong>on</strong>into educati<strong>on</strong>al science and practice, utilizing Michel Foucault’s noti<strong>on</strong>s(1978) of the productive power of discursive regimes and feministpoststructural thought about the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of the body and its sex.This selective historical overview of the intersecti<strong>on</strong>s and interacti<strong>on</strong>sof discursive sites—medicine, psychology, educati<strong>on</strong> and commerce—will interrogate the cultural frames and screens through which this materialexperience of beginning to bleed has been made intelligible.Imagining the female body: the fabricati<strong>on</strong> of a separate, inferiorfemale sex”To the extent there is a perceived need for the male/femaledistincti<strong>on</strong> to be c<strong>on</strong>stituted as a deep and significant <strong>on</strong>e, thebody must ’speak’ this distincti<strong>on</strong> loudly, that is, in every aspectof its being. The c<strong>on</strong>sequence is a two-sex view of the body”(Nichols<strong>on</strong> 1995, 9).The human body has been c<strong>on</strong>sidered a c<strong>on</strong>crete reality whose specificityand authenticity seem not to require interrogati<strong>on</strong>. However, thecomm<strong>on</strong>sense noti<strong>on</strong>s of the pure existence and apparent unqualifiedmateriality of the body have been transformed over centuries. Ideas abouthuman bodies have g<strong>on</strong>e through many changes, making different bodiesthinkable, illuminating previously invisible c<strong>on</strong>tours, and focusingattenti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> formerly indiscernible elements. Certainly, the materialityof the body is irrefutable. However, the matter of the body is unthinkableother than through the management of ideas. Materiality exists in c<strong>on</strong>certwith discursive investments, incorporating the disciplines and norms152


in the society around it (Foucault 1978). The assignment of sex to abody is a regulatory practice compelling the materializati<strong>on</strong> of that bodyin specific ways (Butler 1993).The discursive technologies previous to the eighteenth century framed<strong>on</strong>e essential human body with variati<strong>on</strong>s. Sexual differences werenoted but were c<strong>on</strong>sidered variati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> a theme, elements of <strong>on</strong>e sex.The ”organs, processes, and fluids we think of as distinctive to male andfemale bodies were rather thought of as c<strong>on</strong>vertible within ..a moregeneric unity” (Nichols<strong>on</strong> 1995, 47). The inferiority of woman’s bodieswas a matter of degree rather than <strong>on</strong>e of fundamental distincti<strong>on</strong>s.Male and female were two poles <strong>on</strong> a bodily c<strong>on</strong>tinuum, a ”medicalregister passing from female, cold, passive, and weak to male, hot, str<strong>on</strong>gand engaged...(forming) a scale of ascending human worth; it treatedmales as superior to females made of the same material” (Sennett 1994,43). Both shared the same organs in different dimensi<strong>on</strong>s and sizes.The discursive image of a menstruating woman of the time was of animperfect man, a creature closer to the earth, passi<strong>on</strong>ate, bleedingm<strong>on</strong>thly in order to rid herself of excess fluids. These medical andscientific ”truths” lasted two thousand years.By the eighteenth century the body had become a site of politicalstruggle within a distinct technology of territorial and populati<strong>on</strong>algovernance. With the earlier dissipati<strong>on</strong> of sovereign regimes in manylocalities, the discipline and management of the social body becameindispensable, requiring a quantificati<strong>on</strong> of informati<strong>on</strong> about the populati<strong>on</strong>as a whole and an analytical discernment of the individualbody (Foucault 1978). Sexuality assumed an importance in matters ofregulati<strong>on</strong>. The body became a source of understanding and discipliningof the individual; sex became a thing to be managed (Foucault 1978).Reproductive anatomy acquired foundati<strong>on</strong>al status for the explanati<strong>on</strong>of differences, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual and the linguistic, between men and women.The postulati<strong>on</strong> of woman as man’s opposite was not a preduscursive’fact’ but was a ”functi<strong>on</strong> of our knowledge” (Scott 1988 as cited inNichols<strong>on</strong> 1995, 39). Situating the female in binary oppositi<strong>on</strong> to themale further enforced the hierarchical positi<strong>on</strong>ing within this relati<strong>on</strong>ship.Her <strong>on</strong>tological separati<strong>on</strong> occurred simultaneously with amore distinct positi<strong>on</strong>ing of private and public space. Women was man’s153


direct c<strong>on</strong>trary and her space was in the home, apart from the civic areawhich was open to men. This sharp differentiati<strong>on</strong> of women as men’santithesis was an effect of power, a productive power which made aninferior subject of the female due to her materiality, her otherness, herdissimilarity to the norm embodied in the male subject.Objectifying the female body: the scientificinvestments of medicine”The human body is always a signified body and as such cannotbe understood as a ’neutral object’ up<strong>on</strong> which science mayc<strong>on</strong>struct ’true’ discourses. The human body and its historypresuppose each other.”(Gatens 1992, 132)The discursive informati<strong>on</strong> about women from the eighteenth andnineteenth centuries was a product of a system of reas<strong>on</strong>ing andgovernance which perceived the social world as rati<strong>on</strong>al, evoluti<strong>on</strong>ary,resp<strong>on</strong>sive to the rati<strong>on</strong>al pursuit of progress (Hunter 1996). Withinthis intellectual climate, human activity was understood as amenable tomanagement and regulati<strong>on</strong> through the interventi<strong>on</strong> of scientificexperts. These authorities were thought to be able to comprehend andeffectively predict the scope and implicati<strong>on</strong>s of human movement,purpose, and operati<strong>on</strong>. Populati<strong>on</strong>al reas<strong>on</strong>ing classified people indiscursive spaces in order to govern change and administer progressthrough the observati<strong>on</strong> and ordering of people as data. The belief inthe perfectibility of society through the merger of science and socialprograms provided the intelligence and directi<strong>on</strong> to social change.A diverse c<strong>on</strong>glomerati<strong>on</strong> of pers<strong>on</strong>s and disciplines, experts andsystems of informati<strong>on</strong>, produced knowledge about women’s bodieswhich would define, categorize, and classify individuals within the fabricof social administrati<strong>on</strong>. The public discussi<strong>on</strong>s about women and theirbodies were the intellectual possessi<strong>on</strong>s of distinctly male enterprises,whose learned specialties and ideologies were inseparable (Lander 1988).These discussi<strong>on</strong>s gave public meanings to the experience of being sexedas a woman, accompanied by norms and regulati<strong>on</strong>s.154


In the early nineteenth century, the female body and its reproductiveorgans became a medical map to be plotted, requiring the gaze ofspecialists, who were able to see clearly what the woman <strong>on</strong>ly understoodvaguely about her body . Initially, therapeutic professi<strong>on</strong>als maintaineda positive view of menstruati<strong>on</strong>. In his Introducti<strong>on</strong> to Midwifery in 1802,Dr. Thomas Denman noted that bleeding <strong>on</strong> a m<strong>on</strong>thly basis was ahealthy activity of the female body and did not require any change inhabit or behavior. It was proper and necessary for women to c<strong>on</strong>tinuewith their physical labor throughout the year, with little or no attenti<strong>on</strong>given to a particular time of the m<strong>on</strong>th.However, as gynecology began to assert itself as a distinct medicalspecialty in the mid-1800’s and as the noti<strong>on</strong>s about women’s labormodified, menstruati<strong>on</strong> and menarche were deemed pathological medicalevents, involving imbalance and afflicti<strong>on</strong>. The noti<strong>on</strong>s of a ”naturalinfirmity” and ”m<strong>on</strong>thly sickness” emerged in medical journals (Lander1988, 49). A.F.A. King, whose Manual of Obstetrics had elevenediti<strong>on</strong>s, portrayed menstruati<strong>on</strong> as the sickness women spent most oftheir time suffering or c<strong>on</strong>valescing from. Asserting the natural stage ofwoman as pregnancy, the time of her best health, King further positedin the Journal of Obstetrics and Diseases of Women and Children thatbleeding was a transgressi<strong>on</strong> of a natural law, a ”result of interferencewith nature, a thwarting of her designs, a violati<strong>on</strong> of her laws, and ispreventable by obedience to these laws” (cited in Lander 1988, 49).The experience of menarche, obviously important to the species, wasn<strong>on</strong>etheless c<strong>on</strong>structed as pathological, requiring extreme cauti<strong>on</strong> anda woman’s passive acceptance of medical management. The doctor al<strong>on</strong>ecould restore the female body to equilibrium. Medical practiti<strong>on</strong>erspromoted a theory in which the body was c<strong>on</strong>sidered a closed systemwith a limited supply of energy. Dr. Edward H. Clarke, professor at theHarvard Medical School in 1873 noted that ”undue and disproporti<strong>on</strong>atebrain activity exerts a sterilizing influence up<strong>on</strong> both sexes...(femalesare more vulnerable because of)...the larger size, more complicated relati<strong>on</strong>s,and more important functi<strong>on</strong>s, of the female reproductiveapparatus. This delicate and complex mechanism is liable to be abortedor deranged by the withdrawal of force that is needed for its c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>and maintenance” (cited in Lander 1988, 34). Within this intellectual155


climate, the c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> of a woman’s educati<strong>on</strong>al and political activityexpressed by gynecologist Laws<strong>on</strong> Tait in 1883 is not surprising: ”Thequesti<strong>on</strong> raised by the advanced advocates of women’s rights are to besettled, not <strong>on</strong> the platform of the political ec<strong>on</strong>omist, but in thec<strong>on</strong>sulting-room of the gynecologist” (cited in Lander 1988, 38).Medical knowledge worked to preserve the advantages of the bourgeoisie.Middle-class culture portrayed the woman as the basti<strong>on</strong> ofrespectability, the beac<strong>on</strong> which illuminated the inherent superiority ofa specific class, system of governing, and race. The noti<strong>on</strong> of ”truewomanhood” (Welter 1976) brought with it an ethical superiority. The”true woman” was white, sculpted and isolated within the depository ofher home. Utility was not a part of the compositi<strong>on</strong> of this ideal female.The placement and deliberate maintenance of her positi<strong>on</strong> away fromthe nastiness of ec<strong>on</strong>omics and politics juxtaposed her with her black orworking class counterpart.Vilifying the female body: the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>of a dangerous female sexuality”(T)he feminine body was analyzed...as being thoroughlysaturated with sexuality; whereby it was integrated into thesphere of medical practices, by reas<strong>on</strong> of a pathology intrinsicto it; whereby, finally, it was placed in organic communicati<strong>on</strong>with the social body (whose regulated fecundity it was supposedto ensure), the family space (of which it had to be a substantialand functi<strong>on</strong>al element), and the life of the children (which itproduced and had to guarantee, by virtue of a biologico-moralresp<strong>on</strong>sibility lasting through the entire period of the children’seducati<strong>on</strong>)”(Foucault 1978, 104).Menarche announced a young woman’s entrance into two separate yetinterrelated positi<strong>on</strong>s within a male-dominated hierarchical structure.Her maturing body located her as the future mother of men’s children.Simultaneously, her newly-found sexuality positi<strong>on</strong>ed her as an objectfor a heterosexual male’s pleasure.156


The public images of the young woman which emerged from thesemedical discourses were c<strong>on</strong>tradictory. One stereotype was of a youngwoman who was passive and fragile. (Lander 1988, Nathans<strong>on</strong> 1991).The c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of menstruati<strong>on</strong> as a time of weakness paralleled thenineteenth century social c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of women as extraneous,ec<strong>on</strong>omically superfluous, situated within the private home, ornamentalwithin bourgeois society. This woman was innocent, passi<strong>on</strong>less,disinterested in and lacking knowledge about sex. Adm<strong>on</strong>ished by asparse resources theory to limit her pursuits, specifically her intellectualendeavors, she was exhorted to avoid any dissipati<strong>on</strong> of her energieswhich might threaten her true vocati<strong>on</strong> as mother of the race, especiallyduring her m<strong>on</strong>thly bleeding. Her fragile nature was threatened fromwithin by the possibility of masturbati<strong>on</strong> and from without by menwho, according to their natures, were less able to c<strong>on</strong>trol themselves.She was c<strong>on</strong>structed as resp<strong>on</strong>sible for arousing the passi<strong>on</strong> of youngmen and as such assumed the positi<strong>on</strong> of gatekeeper in a society inwhich the maintenance of her virginity was required.A sec<strong>on</strong>d, more dangerous image emanated, that of a precocious childbeginning her sexualized embodiment, whose bodily orifices andsecreti<strong>on</strong>s took <strong>on</strong> a sexual c<strong>on</strong>notati<strong>on</strong> (Brumberg 1993, Lee 1995).Menarche dem<strong>on</strong>strated the thorough erotic saturati<strong>on</strong> of her body,establishing her promiscuity and immanent immoral behavior(Gr<strong>on</strong>eman 1994). During mid-nineteenth century scientific explorati<strong>on</strong>of the causes for the beginning of menstruati<strong>on</strong>, it was comm<strong>on</strong>lyassumed that sexuality led to earlier menarche, excessive flow and painfulmenstruati<strong>on</strong>. The timing of menarche was often thought to be apunishment for promiscuity. Reflecting the rati<strong>on</strong>ale which tiedmenarche to overdeveloped sexuality, urbanity, abundant food and drink,Dr. W. W. Bliss, in 1870, noted that bleeding was hastened by ”passi<strong>on</strong>stirringpictures, statues, c<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong>s up<strong>on</strong> love, c<strong>on</strong>stant proximityto and f<strong>on</strong>d toyings of and pers<strong>on</strong>al freedom with, the opposite sex,(involving) the fashi<strong>on</strong>able display of arms and bosom” (cited in Lander1988, 20).The young woman’s sexuality was c<strong>on</strong>structed as dangerous within ahierarchical heterosexual social structure, requiring c<strong>on</strong>stant surveillanceand guidance. Her passi<strong>on</strong> was thought to be a disorder, the cure of157


which was the resp<strong>on</strong>sibility of gynecologists whose opti<strong>on</strong>s includedthe remedy of surgery. Menarche, as a dangerous c<strong>on</strong>flati<strong>on</strong> of sexualityand reproducti<strong>on</strong> (Lee 1996), required the management of a professi<strong>on</strong>alstrategist and a maternal supervisor. The young woman was given ananatomical descripti<strong>on</strong> of menarche which precluded any insinuati<strong>on</strong>of sexuality and a program of obligatory behaviors of hygiene, dress,and exercise. ”The problematic characteristic of the adolescent girl hadbeen recognized by the mid-nineteenth century and the essence of theproblem was the c<strong>on</strong>tainment of sex” (Nathans<strong>on</strong> 1991, 6).Psychologizing the female body: menarcheas beatificati<strong>on</strong> or symbolic castrati<strong>on</strong>Intersecting with medical discourse and augmenting the public explicati<strong>on</strong>of the young woman, the late nineteenth university-baseddiscipline of psychology analyzed the behaviors of individual women inclinical isolati<strong>on</strong> and established ”timeless laws of human behavior byanalysis with the laws of natural science” (Danziger 1990, 146).Influenced by the rise of Darwinism and seeking the status and credibilityavailable to a nineteenth-century physical scientist, early psychologistG. Stanley Hall applied the scientific method to a study of youth. Hec<strong>on</strong>cluded that adolescence was a stage in the recapitulati<strong>on</strong> of the species,the most dangerous, final burst of primitive desire, requiring understandingand managed redempti<strong>on</strong>. Hall c<strong>on</strong>sidered adolescence genericin women, the stage that a woman never outgrows, a ”culminating stageof life...(in which she) lingers, magnifies, glorifies” (Hall 1905, 297).Hall gave early menstruati<strong>on</strong> a religious significance, describing it as a”sentimental period...of instability...(a) sacred time (demanding)exempti<strong>on</strong> from the hard struggle of existence in the world andfrom the mental effort of school...a time to lie fallow... when herhealth for her whole life depends up<strong>on</strong> normalizing the lunarm<strong>on</strong>th, those times which suggest withdrawing to let nature doits beautiful work of inflorescence”(Hall 1905, 285-6).158


Hall promoted the medical belief that mental activity was potentiallydamaging to a woman’s physical and sexual development. In a discussi<strong>on</strong>of the greater likelihood of female college graduates remaining unmarried,he wrote that the educated woman had ”taken up and utilizedin her own life all that was meant for her descendants... (she is) theapotheosis of selfishness” (Hall 1905, 305).Freudian psychoanalytical analyses of menarche did not specificallybegin until the early 1900’s. The ensuing psychological discussi<strong>on</strong>srepresented menstruati<strong>on</strong> with the earlier c<strong>on</strong>ceived ideas associatingwomen with penis envy, oedipal imaginings, and immature orgasms.The pain of menstruati<strong>on</strong> was indicative of the fear associated with theyoung woman’s apprehensi<strong>on</strong> about her mother’s revengeful reacti<strong>on</strong> tothe child’s sexual fantasies of her father (Lander 1988). Within thisphallocentric analysis which defined women by their anatomical lack,menstrual blood represented the castrated penis; the pain of bleedingsymbolized the anxiety of this possibility in a woman who unc<strong>on</strong>sciouslyl<strong>on</strong>ged for a man’s sexual organs. The difficulties that young womenhad with menarche was due to her mother whose c<strong>on</strong>cern with age andher upcoming menopause was made painfully apparent by her daughter’smenarche (Lander 1988).As an emerging science, psychology participated in the process ofgovernmentality, in the disciplining of the populati<strong>on</strong> and of individuals.It asserted that observati<strong>on</strong> and theorizing generated administrativelyuseful knowledge. Insisting that the young woman could be made normalthrough expert interventi<strong>on</strong> and management, it linked redempti<strong>on</strong>to pers<strong>on</strong>al development. This style of reas<strong>on</strong>ing allowed young women’sbodies to be understood in very particular ways and foreclosed differentc<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s. The ideal young woman was thought to be a passiveindividual, whose distinct biology and psyche required that she liveaccording to parameters, which had been established for her own good.The scientific principles which pervaded the times c<strong>on</strong>sidered menarchea weakness and a danger, a sign of inferiority. The young woman wasrequired to follow established ideas which c<strong>on</strong>fined her movement andher access to work, school, and the political sphere. Within a frame ofreference which c<strong>on</strong>ceived of the peril of immigrant genes, the maliceof the urban sphere, and the weakness and inferiority of the female159


physiology, the incarcerati<strong>on</strong> of the young woman within her ownanatomical structure was thought biologically necessary, politicallyexpedient, and philosophically true.Disciplining the female body: the curricularinclusi<strong>on</strong> of menarche and woman’s work”(T)he strategies of regulati<strong>on</strong> that have made up our modernexperience of ’power’ are thus assembled into complexes thatc<strong>on</strong>nect up forces and instituti<strong>on</strong>s deemed ”political” withapparatuses that shape individual and collective c<strong>on</strong>duct in relati<strong>on</strong>to norms and objectives but yet are c<strong>on</strong>stituted as ”n<strong>on</strong>-political”(Rose 1996, 38).At the turn of the century, a variety of voices and pressures from socialworkers, parents, citizens, religious and political leaders, who c<strong>on</strong>sideredthe effects of industry and urbanizati<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> girls as ”outrunning alleducati<strong>on</strong>al and social arrangements,” demanded an educati<strong>on</strong>al resp<strong>on</strong>se.”Perhaps never before have young people been expected to workfrom motives so detached from direct emoti<strong>on</strong>al incentive. Neverhas the age of marriage been so l<strong>on</strong>g delayed; never has the workof youth been as separated from the family life and the publicopini<strong>on</strong> of the community... It (educati<strong>on</strong>) al<strong>on</strong>e has the powerto organize a child’s activity with some reference to the life he willlater lead and of giving him a clue as to what to select and whatto eliminate when he comes into c<strong>on</strong>tact with c<strong>on</strong>temporary socialand industrial c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s. And until educators take hold of thesituati<strong>on</strong>, the rest of the community is powerless”(Addams 1909, 109).Educati<strong>on</strong>al science not <strong>on</strong>ly resp<strong>on</strong>ded to these mandates but was transformedby its participati<strong>on</strong> in the phenomen<strong>on</strong> of industrializati<strong>on</strong>.Throughout the years 1893-1918, a variety of educati<strong>on</strong>al commissi<strong>on</strong>sand nati<strong>on</strong>al associati<strong>on</strong>s summ<strong>on</strong>ed forth a more rati<strong>on</strong>alized, restructurededucati<strong>on</strong>al system, <strong>on</strong>e which would meet the political andec<strong>on</strong>omic injuncti<strong>on</strong> for practical educati<strong>on</strong>, preparing students for160


vocati<strong>on</strong>al and social life-adjustments. A result of these incentives wasthe differentiated curriculum, <strong>on</strong>e which would develop each individualstudent’s knowledge, interests, and habits. According to psychologist A.L. Pechstein, the resp<strong>on</strong>sibility for training youth for social and moralefficiency involved ”intelligent sorting and class placement...flexible anddifferentiated group study, failure preventi<strong>on</strong>, the establishment of moralvalues and right type of habit-reacti<strong>on</strong>s, proper individual and groupc<strong>on</strong>tacts between the sexes, citizenship training, socialized activity,vocati<strong>on</strong>al guidance” (1924, viii).The inclusi<strong>on</strong> of young women within this system of public educati<strong>on</strong>was interrogated. ”(T)he modern community is uncertain as to what itwishes to make of its women...she herself is not at present entirelyqualified to pass judgment...three decades ago she was ast<strong>on</strong>ished tofind she had an intellect” (Slaughter 1911, 91, 95). The prevailing noti<strong>on</strong>was that educati<strong>on</strong> should offer her ”narrow choices...to save her frommany difficult problems and serve to make her course a c<strong>on</strong>tinuous<strong>on</strong>e” (Slaughter 1911, 53). The earlier reluctance of medicine andpsychology about the dangers of educating young women were evidentin the opini<strong>on</strong> that ”we must c<strong>on</strong>stantly keep in mind that we areeducating the mother of the race” (Bennett 1919, 23).In the early 1900’s the Nati<strong>on</strong>al Educati<strong>on</strong>al Associati<strong>on</strong>, the U.S.Bureau of Educati<strong>on</strong>, the Department of Agriculture and eventuallynati<strong>on</strong>al legislati<strong>on</strong> pursued ideas about women’s work which facilitatedthe acceptance of young women as members of the school community.Within these discussi<strong>on</strong>s, home ec<strong>on</strong>omics acquired a scientific statusand was promoted as the foundati<strong>on</strong> of science and business, amicrocosm of government, a model for world affairs. Public instructi<strong>on</strong>in homemaking was encouraged in order to raise standards of living,promote hygienic habits and assure acquisiti<strong>on</strong> of knowledge aboutnourishment and child rearing techniques. By 1920, home ec<strong>on</strong>omicshad become an acceptable comp<strong>on</strong>ent of junior high and high schooleducati<strong>on</strong>.Thus, menstruati<strong>on</strong> no l<strong>on</strong>ger barred the participati<strong>on</strong> of the youngwoman within public educati<strong>on</strong>. Rather, the educati<strong>on</strong>al focus <strong>on</strong> lifeskills allowed menarche and menstruati<strong>on</strong> to become instructi<strong>on</strong>al topics.Reflecting new scientific documentati<strong>on</strong> and nati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cern about161


the c<strong>on</strong>taminating characteristic of menstrual blood, menstrualpreparedness was injected into the health curriculum. C<strong>on</strong>structed as ahygienic crisis, capable of polluting if not carefully safeguarded, woman’sbleeding was taught in ways which effectively incorporated the medicaland psychological formulati<strong>on</strong> of menstruati<strong>on</strong> as debilitating andsignaling inferiority.The educati<strong>on</strong>al organizati<strong>on</strong> of menarche was influenced by anotherexpert knowledge system that merged with science in acommercializati<strong>on</strong> of the young woman’s body. The Kimberly-ClarkCompany and its producti<strong>on</strong> of the revoluti<strong>on</strong>ary disposable sanitarynapkin Kotex assumed knowledge of and resp<strong>on</strong>sibility for theexplanati<strong>on</strong> of menarche and its management. Commercially-developedpamphlets supplied schools with texts, vocabulary, and suitable rati<strong>on</strong>alesfor c<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong>s about menarche with young women. These bookletsutilized medical language, marketing techniques, curricular objectives,mass media stylistics, and familial c<strong>on</strong>cerns in the subjecti<strong>on</strong> of the”newly-bleeding” young woman.In the early decades of the twentieth century, public educati<strong>on</strong> becamea central site in which expert knowledge permeated the home interiorthrough the discipline of the young woman. The scientific approach towork in the home envisi<strong>on</strong>ed the young woman as a distributing agentof a very specific form of governmentality, as a citizen whose subjectivitywould be instrumental in the c<strong>on</strong>tinuati<strong>on</strong> and strengthening of a formof governance. Further, educati<strong>on</strong> sought to redeem the young womanby making her aware of the potential c<strong>on</strong>taminati<strong>on</strong> of her menstrualblood and of commercial means for safeguarding herself and family.Multiple sites outlined a very particular discursive space for the youngwomen and claimed her body within a certain kind of governing.”(T)he meanings associated with menarche in our culture,like sexuality itself, are produce through effects of powerrelati<strong>on</strong>s in order to regulate women’s lives”(Brumberg 1993,90)This investigati<strong>on</strong> into the discursive c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s of the young womanis based <strong>on</strong> a belief that transgressi<strong>on</strong> and resistance to unhealthy cultural,social, political and ec<strong>on</strong>omic c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong>s are made more probable162


through a questi<strong>on</strong>ing of the texts which comprise what is termed”knowledge” about young women. Currently, the situati<strong>on</strong> in whichyoung women find themselves, surrounded by a culture fixated <strong>on</strong> theirbodies, belies the noti<strong>on</strong> of ”You’ve come a l<strong>on</strong>g way, Baby!” Thepositi<strong>on</strong>ing of young women within political, educati<strong>on</strong>al, and socialarenas in which they have diluted status is often attended by drasticacti<strong>on</strong>s—self-starvati<strong>on</strong>, early pregnancy, school failure and suicide. Itis through a recogniti<strong>on</strong> and study of the history of the present, theunveiling of invisible exclusi<strong>on</strong>s and silenced assumpti<strong>on</strong>s, rather thana self-c<strong>on</strong>gratulatory sloganeering, which can open noti<strong>on</strong>s of truth toskepticism and possible transformati<strong>on</strong>.ReferencesAddams, Jane. 1909. The spirit of youth and the city streets. NY: MacMillan & Co.Alaimo, Kathleen. 1992. Shaping adolescence in the popular milieu: Social policy,reformers, and French youth, 1870-1920. Journal of Family History17 (4), 419-438.Bennett, G. Vern<strong>on</strong>. 1919. Junior high school. Baltimore: Warwich & York, Inc.Bordo, Susan. 1993. Postmodern subjects, postmodern bodies, postmodern resistance.Unbearable weight. Berkeley: University of California Press.Brumberg, Joan Jacobs. 1993. “Something happens to girls”: Menarche and theemergence of the modern American hygienic imperative. Journal of theHistory of Sexuality 4, 1. 99-127.Butler, Judith. 1990. Performative acts and gender c<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong>. In Performing feminisms:Feminist critical theory and theatre. Edited by Sue-Ellen Case. Baltimore:The Johns Hopkins University Press._____. 1992. C<strong>on</strong>tingent foundati<strong>on</strong>s: Feminism and the questi<strong>on</strong> of postmodernism.In Feminists theorize the political. Edited by Judith Butler and Joan Scott.NY: Routledge._____. 1993. Introducti<strong>on</strong> to Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of “ex.”NY: Routledge._____. 1995. Subjecti<strong>on</strong>, resistance, resignificati<strong>on</strong>: Between Freud and Foucault.In The dentity in questi<strong>on</strong>. Edited by John Rajchman. NY: Routledge.Danziger, Kurt. 1990. C<strong>on</strong>structing the subject: Historical origins of psychological research.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Delaney, Janice, Mary Jane Lupt<strong>on</strong>, and Emily Toth. 1988 The Curse: A cultural historyof menstruati<strong>on</strong>. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Foucault, Michel. 1977. In Power/knowledge: Selected interviews and other writings, 1972-1977. Translated and edited by Colin Gord<strong>on</strong>. NY: Panthe<strong>on</strong> Books._____. 1978. The history of sexuality, Vol. 1. An introducti<strong>on</strong>. Translated by Robert Hurley.NY: Vintage Books.163


_____. 1980. The Uses of Pleasure. Vol. 2. The history of Sexuality. Translated by RobertHurley. NY: Vintage Books._____. 1982. The subject and power. In Michel Foucault: Bey<strong>on</strong>d structuralism andhermeneutics.By Hubert Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow. Chicago: Universityof Chicago Press._____. 1988 Technologies of the self. In Technologies of the self: A seminar with MichelFoucault. Edited by Luther H. Martin, Huck Gutman, Patrick H. Hutt<strong>on</strong>.Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press._____. 1991. Governmentality. In The Foucault effect: Studies in governmentality. Edited byGraham Burchell, Colin Gord<strong>on</strong>, and Peter Miller. Chicago: University ofChicago Press.Gatens, Moira. 1992. Power, bodies and difference. In Destabilizing theory: c<strong>on</strong>temporaryfeminist debates. Edited by Michele Barrett and Anne Phillips. Stanford: StanfordUniversity Press.Gr<strong>on</strong>eman, Carol. 1994. Nymphomania: The historical c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of female sexuality.Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society. 19, 2. 337-367Hall, G. Stanley. 1905 Youth in educati<strong>on</strong>, regimen and hygiene. NY: D. Applet<strong>on</strong> & Co.Hall, G. Stanley. 1904. Adolescence. NY: D. Applet<strong>on</strong> & Co.Hunter, Ian. 1996. Assembling the school. In Foucault and political reas<strong>on</strong>: Liberalism, neoliberalismand rati<strong>on</strong>alities of government. Edited by Andrew Barry, ThomasOsborne, and Nikolas Rose. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Kliebard, Herbert M. 1995. The struggle for the American Curriculum, 1893-1958. NY:Routledge.Lander, Lois. 1988. Images of bleeding: Menstruati<strong>on</strong> as ideology. NY: Orlando Press.Lee, Janet. 1994. Menarche and the (hetero)sexualizati<strong>on</strong> of the female body. In Genderand Society 8, 3. 343-362.Lee, Janet, and Jennifer Sasser-Coen. 1996. Blood stories: Menarche and the politicsof the female body in c<strong>on</strong>temporary U.S. society. NY: Routledge.McNay, Lois. 1992. Foucault and feminism. Bost<strong>on</strong>: Northeastern University Press.Mohanty, Chandra Talpade. 1995. Feminist encounters: Locating the politics ofexperience. In Social postmodernism: Bey<strong>on</strong>d identity politics. Edited by LindaNichols<strong>on</strong> and Steven Seidman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Nathans<strong>on</strong>, C<strong>on</strong>stance A. 1991. Dangerous passage: The social c<strong>on</strong>trol of sexuality in women’sadolescence. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Nichols<strong>on</strong>, Linda. 1995. Interpreting gender. In Social postmodernism: Bey<strong>on</strong>d identitypolitics.. Edited by Linda Nichols<strong>on</strong> and Steven Seidman. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.Odem, Mary E. 1995. Delinquent daughters. Protecting and policing adolescent femalesexuality in the United States, 1885-1920. Chapel Hill: The University of NorthCarolina Press.Pechstein, L.A. & McGragor, A. Laura. 1924. Psychology of the junior high school pupil.NY: Hought<strong>on</strong> Mifflin.Popkewitz, Thomas. 1996. A changing terrain of knowledge and power: A socialepistemology of educati<strong>on</strong>al research. Unpublished manuscript.Rabinow, Paul. 1984. Introducti<strong>on</strong>. The Foucault reader. Edited by Paul Rabinow. NY:Panthe<strong>on</strong> Books.Riley, Denise. 1988. Am I that name?: Feminism and the category of ”women” in history.Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.164


Rose, Nikolas. 1996. Governing ’advanced’ liberal democracies. In Foucault and politicalreas<strong>on</strong>: Liberalism, neo-liberalism and rati<strong>on</strong>alities of government. Edited byAndrew Berry, Thomas Osborne, and Nikolas Rose. Chicago: Universityof Chicago Press.Scott, Joan. 1992. On Experience. In Feminists theorize the political. Edited by JudithButler and Joan Scott. NY: Routledge.Sennett, Richard. 1994. Flesh and st<strong>on</strong>e: The body and the city in Western civilizati<strong>on</strong>.NY: W. W. Nort<strong>on</strong> & Co.Slaughter, J.W. 1911. The adolescent. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.Terneman, Ann. 1989. Cashing in <strong>on</strong> the curse—Advertising and the menstrual taboo.In The female gaze: Women as viewers of popular culture. Edited by LorraineGamm<strong>on</strong> and Margaret Marshment. Seattle: The Real Comet Press.Treichler, Paula A. 1987. AIDS, homophobia and biomedical discourse: An epidemicof significati<strong>on</strong>. In Cultural Studies 1, 3. 263-305.Welter, Barbara. 1976. The cult of true womanhood: 1800-1860. In Dimity c<strong>on</strong>victi<strong>on</strong>s: TheAmerican woman in the nineteenth century. Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press.Wolf, Christa. 1970. The Quest for Christa T. NY: Farrar, Straus, & Giroux.165


166


H A N N A H T A V A R E SPoststructural Feminisms andAlter-pedagogical Tales“The political task, in a time of closure and danger, is to try to openup what is enclosed, to try to think thoughts that stretch and extendfixed patterns of insistence”.William E. C<strong>on</strong>nolly, Identity/DifferenceAn important intellectual and political encounter has taken place insidethe academy between feminist educators and adherents to ”criticalpedagogies.” Because it is an encounter, as opposed to say a dialogue,the issues that are raised and the rhetorical style in which they are raised,present this encounter as c<strong>on</strong>tentious and acerbic. 1 But, polemicaldiscourses have political purposes too. They are strategic interventi<strong>on</strong>swhich agitate the seemingly natural and neutral order of things. Theywake us from our slumber.Cases in point are the writings issued from poststructuralist feminismsagainst a number of critical educati<strong>on</strong>al research agendas. 2 Their maincritique is aimed at research called ”critical pedagogies,” but alsoimplicated are both neo-marxist analyses and those that come out ofalternative critical traditi<strong>on</strong>s. 3 As an interventi<strong>on</strong> into the encounter, Iwould like to think with, as well against, some of the critiques that arebeing raised. 4 By thinking with, I focus <strong>on</strong> the power of the critiquesespecially in terms of excavating critical pedagogies’ latent assumpti<strong>on</strong>sabout self and world which allow the emergence of an important alterpedagogicaltale. I think against, by raising the questi<strong>on</strong> of rhetoricalcare, especially in relati<strong>on</strong> to imagining an alternative pedagogical visi<strong>on</strong>.Related to the thinking against, I encourage an ambivalentattachment and paradoxical relati<strong>on</strong> toward critical traditi<strong>on</strong>s. 5The anthology, a first in the field of educati<strong>on</strong>, edited by CarmenLuke and Jennifer Gore (1992), Feminisms and Critical Pedagogy (FCP),is an encounter with educati<strong>on</strong>al research that is defined as ”criticalpedagogy.” 6 The circumstances that brought these feminist educatorstogether were similar pers<strong>on</strong>al experiences with critical pedagogical167


practice (Luke & Gore, 1992: 1). Luke and Gore describe some ofthose circumstances as a general dissatisfacti<strong>on</strong> with ”implementingstrategies prescribed by critical pedagogy discourse,” as well a ”skepticism”toward the ”theoretical bases” known as critical pedagogy (Ibid).While the anthology does not claim a unitary feminist epistemologicalorientati<strong>on</strong>, ”feminisms” is key in its approach, it is a book that is markedby its collective endeavor to resist the ”unexamined assumpti<strong>on</strong>sunderlying the discourse of critical pedagogy” (Luke & Gore, 1992: 2).The anthology is situated within an intellectual and political identity:poststructural feminisms. Again, Luke and Gore:A poststructuralist feminism acknowledges its own positi<strong>on</strong> in discourseand in history, and therefore remains critical of its own complicity in writinggender and writing others ... a poststructural feminism does not give up itstheoretical foundati<strong>on</strong>s ... In line with the feminist project of standpoint—standing firm <strong>on</strong> a politics of locati<strong>on</strong> and identity—poststructuralistfeminisms do not disclaim foundati<strong>on</strong>. Instead, they ground theirepistemology <strong>on</strong> the foundati<strong>on</strong> of difference (1992: 7).I understand poststructural feminisms as an eclectic amalgamati<strong>on</strong>of feminist criticism, especially influential are elements from D<strong>on</strong>naHaraway’s (1985) ”cyborg politics,” and elements from poststructuraland postmodern theories. 7 These of course will be elaborated as thisanalysis unfolds. At the outset, however, I will enumerate some of themain themes of the critique that are being waged against educati<strong>on</strong>alresearch called ”critical pedagogy.”The myth of critical pedagogiesFirst, what is critical pedagogy? Patti Lather has a lucid definiti<strong>on</strong> that Ifind exemplary:Within my definiti<strong>on</strong>al web, critical pedagogy is positi<strong>on</strong>ed as thatwhich attends to practices of teaching/learning intended to interruptparticular historical situated systems of oppressi<strong>on</strong>. Such pedagogies goby many names: Freirean, feminist, anti-racist, radical, empowering,liberati<strong>on</strong> theology. With both overlaps and specificities within andbetween, each is c<strong>on</strong>structed out of a combinati<strong>on</strong> of Frankfurt Schoolcritical theory, Gramscian counter-hegem<strong>on</strong>ic practice and Freireanc<strong>on</strong>scientizati<strong>on</strong> (in Luke & Gore, 1992: 121-22).168


As Lather points out critical pedagogues fail to probe the degree towhich <strong>on</strong>e of their main premises, ”emancipati<strong>on</strong>,” actually perpetuatesrelati<strong>on</strong>s of dominance (in Luke & Gore, 1992: 122). For example,emancipati<strong>on</strong> presupposes an ”un-liberated Other” in need of liberati<strong>on</strong>(Ibid). In other words, it is the critical pedagogue who is the possessorof liberated pedagogies and has the ability to empower and free theoppressed. Citing Elizabeth Ellsworth, Lather puts it this way:”’empowerment’ becomes something d<strong>on</strong>e ’by’ liberated pedagogies ’to’or ’for’ the as-yet-unliberated, the ”Other,” the object up<strong>on</strong> which isdirected the ’emancipatory’ acti<strong>on</strong>s” (Ibid). The relati<strong>on</strong>s of dominancethat are implicitly reinforced through critical pedagogies stem from itspassive c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of an ”Other.” It is assumed, according to Latherand Ellsworth, that the possessor of liberated pedagogies (<strong>teacher</strong>), notunlike the intellectual vanguard, knows what is best, that the <strong>teacher</strong>has ”the truth,” and that truth shall set the oppressed (student) free.Lather’s and Ellsworth’s insight is of no small significance. It is an attemptto challenge the ways in which relati<strong>on</strong>s of dominance are perpetuatedthrough seemingly benign emancipatory efforts. They problematizethe discourse of critical pedagogy by placing in sharp relief thepresuppositi<strong>on</strong>s of liberati<strong>on</strong> and emancipati<strong>on</strong>.Yet I think it is worth c<strong>on</strong>sidering whether this particularly str<strong>on</strong>greading of liberati<strong>on</strong> rhetoric, dismisses the ways in which the languageof liberati<strong>on</strong> and emancipati<strong>on</strong> ”interpellates individuals as subjects” inways that act against and divulge reified power relati<strong>on</strong>s. 8 For example,as a Filipina-American attending community collgege, the language ofemancipati<strong>on</strong> is what allowed me to politicize my class and genderedcircumstances. The discourse of critical pedagogies gave me a languageof critique. More importantly, that language encouraged me to imaginea very different ordering of the social. While I heed Lather’s andEllsworth’s insight, I also want to be mindful of the varying circumstancesthrough which power operates and the limited tools I (we) have at my(our) disposal. My sense is that Lather and Ellsworth would agree withme that critical pedagogies are not unambiguous endeavors. 9A sec<strong>on</strong>d criticism articulated succinctly by Ellsworth is that criticalpedagogies ”operate at a high level of abstracti<strong>on</strong> [my emphasis]” (in Luke& Gore, 1992: 92). In her unsuccessful attempt at implementing some169


of the strategies critical pedagogies promote, Ellsworth found that shewas left with a series of abstract words stripped of any useful meaning.She notes:I found ... that educati<strong>on</strong>al researchers who invoke c<strong>on</strong>cepts of criticalpedagogy c<strong>on</strong>sistently strip discussi<strong>on</strong>s of classroom practices of historicalc<strong>on</strong>text and political positi<strong>on</strong> (Ibid).Historical c<strong>on</strong>text and political positi<strong>on</strong> are important dynamics inclassroom practices. In regard to political positi<strong>on</strong>, the discourse ofcritical pedagogy, which uses words such as ”critical,” ”radical educator,””socially resp<strong>on</strong>sible,” disguises what Ellsworth regards as worthy politicalcommitments and agendas—namely, ”antiracism, antisexism, antielitism,anti-heterosexism, anti-ableism, anticlassism, and antineoc<strong>on</strong>servatism”(in Luke & Gore, 1992: 93). Ellsworth prefers naming<strong>on</strong>e’s political agenda so that political and ideological commitmentscan be made accountable. Favoring a language game of testim<strong>on</strong>y, Ellsworthwants an asserti<strong>on</strong> of the political commitments that <strong>on</strong>e regardsas legitimate and imperative goals for educators and for educati<strong>on</strong> (Ibid).I think what Ellsworth finds most disturbing is the overall duplicity ofa critical pedagogy discourse that she c<strong>on</strong>ceives as hiding behind whatshe calls ”code words” necessitating ”a posture of invisibility” (Ibid).But I am w<strong>on</strong>dering whether words can ever be stripped of theircodes given that they are linguistic mediati<strong>on</strong>s occuring in a diverserange of socio-cultural c<strong>on</strong>texts. I think that post-Saussurean approachesto discourse have underscored the indeterminacy of language andmeaning. 10 While I agree with Ellsworth that expressi<strong>on</strong>s such as ”radicaleducator” may be abstract and may disguise worthy political agendasand commitments, I am also uncomfortable with the implicit assumpti<strong>on</strong>regarding the transparency of words in expressi<strong>on</strong>s such as ”anti-racism.”I think we also need to pay attenti<strong>on</strong> to the performativity of theenunciati<strong>on</strong> and c<strong>on</strong>sider the c<strong>on</strong>text in which it is a politicalenactment. 11In additi<strong>on</strong> to the high level of abstracti<strong>on</strong>, a third criticism is thatcritical pedagogy is predicated <strong>on</strong> a noti<strong>on</strong> of fully rati<strong>on</strong>al subjects. AsEllsworth puts it:By prescribing moral deliberati<strong>on</strong>, engagement in the full range ofviews present, and critical reflecti<strong>on</strong>, the literature <strong>on</strong> critical pedagogy170


implies that students and <strong>teacher</strong>s can and should engage each other inthe classroom as full rati<strong>on</strong>al subjects (in Luke & Gore, 1992: 93).The assumpti<strong>on</strong> here is that <strong>teacher</strong>s and students can and shouldnegotiate their views through rati<strong>on</strong>al deliberati<strong>on</strong>. Yet as Ellsworthobserved, based <strong>on</strong> her own teaching experience and working with theMinority Student Coaliti<strong>on</strong> (MSC), some participants hold views thatare ”n<strong>on</strong>-negotiable” (in Luke & Gore, 1992: 94). Their ownexperiences of racism, sexism and marginalizati<strong>on</strong> speak to them in waysthat cannot be articulated in a model of rati<strong>on</strong>al deliberati<strong>on</strong>. She notes,moreover, that rati<strong>on</strong>al deliberati<strong>on</strong> is often used to regulate c<strong>on</strong>flictand/or to calm diss<strong>on</strong>ance.One example Ellsworth describes deals with the demands written bythe MSC delivered to the university administrati<strong>on</strong>. The demands, shenotes, were not written in the spirit of engaging in a rati<strong>on</strong>al or analyticaldebate, or, holding up other views and positi<strong>on</strong>s (in Luke & Gore,1992: 94). In this particular c<strong>on</strong>text, she says, it is inappropriate tosubject the MSC demands to rati<strong>on</strong>alist debate (Ibid). She argues that”words spoken for survival come already validated in a radically differentarena of proof and carry no opti<strong>on</strong> of luxury or choice” (Ibid).She does add to this, however, that the positi<strong>on</strong>s of students of color orany other group should not be taken up unproblematically, an issue shedeals with later in her essay when she moves to advocating pedagogygrounded in the unknowable. Her point, as I see it, is that there may becircumstances in which a model of rati<strong>on</strong>al, analytical deliberati<strong>on</strong> anddebate is simply inappropriate.Although I am sympathetic to critiques aimed at rati<strong>on</strong>al deliberati<strong>on</strong>and agree that in some c<strong>on</strong>texts it is limited and works to c<strong>on</strong>taindiss<strong>on</strong>ance, I w<strong>on</strong>der if the privileging of views advanced as ”n<strong>on</strong>negotiable,”elides a more vexing issue over the reproducti<strong>on</strong> andestablishment of the authoritative voice, be it rati<strong>on</strong>al or n<strong>on</strong>-negotiable.How can both views be entertained legitimately without reproducing astructure of authority? Or is a structure of authority the necessaryc<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> for expressi<strong>on</strong> and intelligibility? If this is the case, whatwarrants <strong>on</strong>e authoritative structure over another, be it rati<strong>on</strong>al or n<strong>on</strong>negotiable?Clearly, Ellsworth’s criticism accentuates the academicauthority operative in a rati<strong>on</strong>al deliberati<strong>on</strong> model, no doubt a valuable171


political insight. Moreover, she illustrates how such a model tends tomute what is not recognized as ”rati<strong>on</strong>al” discourse. Her attempt atresignifing what c<strong>on</strong>stitutes appropriate discourse in an academic settingis an important c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>. I would like to suggest, however,that rather than presenting the problematic as <strong>on</strong>e of antithesis, as tworadically dissociative positi<strong>on</strong>s, that a re-framing of the problematic interms of their mutually c<strong>on</strong>stitutive dependency be c<strong>on</strong>sidered. Theyare mutually dependent in the sense that rati<strong>on</strong>al deliberati<strong>on</strong> requiresits other, that which is ”n<strong>on</strong>-rati<strong>on</strong>al,” for both intelligibility andlegitimacy. 12 The c<strong>on</strong>verse is also true for views that are deemed n<strong>on</strong>negotiable.In other words recognizing what is a ”n<strong>on</strong>-negotiable” viewrequires the recogniti<strong>on</strong> of what is a ”rati<strong>on</strong>al” view. In this way theyare mutually c<strong>on</strong>stitutive for the <strong>on</strong>e requires its other for its intelligibility.Perhaps a rec<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> of the negotiable/n<strong>on</strong>-negotiable relati<strong>on</strong>, interms of their dependency is in order. Such a rec<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> may allowfor a more reflexive and perhaps even more frank discernment of thepower dimensi<strong>on</strong>s generated by both, be they ”rati<strong>on</strong>al” or ”n<strong>on</strong>negotiable.”Moreover, it points to a certain unavoidable paradoxicalrelati<strong>on</strong> that is operative in both views.A fourth criticism issued from poststructural feminisms is that criticalpedagogies have not seriously attended to the masculinist subject in liberaland critical traditi<strong>on</strong>s. Carmen Luke develops this point through ahistorical mapping of critical pedagogy. She identifies its roots in themarxian legacy of historical materialism which assumed <strong>on</strong>ly male wagelabor power (neglecting unpaid domestic labor power of women) andwhich privileged male subjects as the historical and universal actor.Implicated in this critique are gramscian and neo-marxist analyses ofgender. Luke writes:The failure to recognize the gender blindness in marxist theory, aswell as its historical genesis in industrial capitalism, leads c<strong>on</strong>temporaryneo-marxist social theorists to reflect <strong>on</strong> ’gender’ in the post-industrialpresent with a masculinist theoretical template of another age (in Luke& Gore, 1992: 30).Her point is more than simply a failure to recognize gender in marxisttheory. Central to her critique is the way in which gender has beentheorized in marxist oriented social theories. For the most part gender172


is typically analyzed as an appendage to class analysis or simply theresult of the imperatives of industrial capitalism. What is importantand a main c<strong>on</strong>cern for Luke is that the critical pedagogy project ignoresgender by not systematically engaging with ”specific feminist theoreticaland practical c<strong>on</strong>cerns, and by a de facto erasure of women altogether,through appeals to patriarchy’s exclusi<strong>on</strong>ary grand narratives ...” (inLuke & Gore, 1992: 33).Luke’s point of grand and master narratives leads me to the finalcriticism regarding the viability of totalizing systems of explanati<strong>on</strong>. Asnoted in the preceding paragraph, Luke regards critical pedagogy as a”master” narrative. But just what does the expressi<strong>on</strong> ”master narrative”signify? 13 In the foreword to Jean-Francois Lyotard’s (1989) m<strong>on</strong>ographThe Postmodern C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>, Fredric James<strong>on</strong> discusses master narrativein this way:The great master-narratives here are those that suggest that somethingbey<strong>on</strong>d capitalism is possible, something radically different; and theyalso ’legitimate’ the praxis whereby political militants seek to bring thatradically different future social order into being. Yet ... master-narratives... have become peculiarly repugnant or embarrassing to First Worldintellectuals today: the rhetoric of liberati<strong>on</strong> [my emphasis] has ... beendenounced with passi<strong>on</strong>ate ambivalence by Michel Foucault ... whilethe rhetoric of totality and totalizati<strong>on</strong> [my emphasis] that derived from... Germanic or Hegelian traditi<strong>on</strong> is the object of a kind of instinctive orautomatic denunciati<strong>on</strong> by just about everybody (in Lyotard, 1989: xix).Critical pedagogy is regarded as a master narrative insofar as it adheresto a ”liberatory rhetoric.” Recall the unprobed assumpti<strong>on</strong> underlyingliberatory and emancipatory discourse. In order for liberati<strong>on</strong> to occuran ”un-liberated Other” is required. As poststructural feminisms pointout, a political questi<strong>on</strong> remains that eludes the rhetoric of liberati<strong>on</strong>,that is, who shall be designated to the category of ”un-liberated Other”?And who shall be the designated ”liberators”?In many ways the critical pedagogy project revisits a recurring problemin critically oriented educati<strong>on</strong> and social theories. The aim ofthese theories is to emphasize, by way of critique, a social order thatcreates social and ec<strong>on</strong>omic burdens that are asymmetrically distributedam<strong>on</strong>g for example, class, gender and race. Through a critical analysis173


of structural forces, of which the ec<strong>on</strong>omy is central, what often occursis that agents get dissolved in structures, or in other cases, sign anddiscursive systems. In the preceding example, agents are not <strong>on</strong>ly dividedinto two camps, ”liberator” and the ”un-liberated Other,” but are thendissolved into a ”master narrative” without any integrity of their own.Yet there is something very captivating about master narratives,specifically the liberatory and emancipatory kind. That ”something” inliberatory rhetoric is what inspires and motivates <strong>on</strong>e to imagine otherpossibilities for ordering social life; it enables a visi<strong>on</strong> that is ”counter”to what presently is. While poststructural feminisms are right to pointout that unprobed utopian imaginaries of emancipati<strong>on</strong> are rooted indualisms, they have not seriously engaged with its motivating andtransformative power. Master narratives are powerful precisely becausethat ”something” in questi<strong>on</strong> can be aroused.The writings by Thomas Popkewitz (1996) may provide a historicaland cultural c<strong>on</strong>text for what I have deemed the inspirati<strong>on</strong>al power ofmaster narratives. Popkewitz’s analysis, while written in a differentc<strong>on</strong>text than this <strong>on</strong>e, points out that a ”messianic view of progressinscribed a culture of redempti<strong>on</strong>” in social and educati<strong>on</strong>al sciences(1996: 4). 14 The noti<strong>on</strong> of redempti<strong>on</strong> is persistent with the view ofprogress in c<strong>on</strong>temporary reforms and in educati<strong>on</strong>al research. Hiswork offers important historical and political links between a culture ofredempti<strong>on</strong> and c<strong>on</strong>temporary liberatory rhetoric. Within ac<strong>on</strong>temporary c<strong>on</strong>text, he notes, for example, that the professi<strong>on</strong>al expertis likened to a ”modern oracle” who can decode ”social affairs inorder for subjects to act with agency” (1996: 7). His work, moreover,includes an important reminder of the inescapable historicity ofc<strong>on</strong>temporary forms of c<strong>on</strong>duct and their relati<strong>on</strong> to effects of power.I would like to suggest that there is yet another posture that <strong>on</strong>emight c<strong>on</strong>sider when c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ted with the viability of totalizing systemsand the imaginative and motivati<strong>on</strong>al power of master narratives. Thatposture involves accepting a certain ambivalence toward masternarratives. The writings of Michel Foucault (1984), for example, providean important c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>, specifically his ambivalence toward reas<strong>on</strong>and critical thought. He c<strong>on</strong>cedes that <strong>on</strong>e needs to ”accept thissort of spiral, this sort of revolving door of rati<strong>on</strong>ality that refers us to174


its necessity, to its indispensability, and at the same time, to its intrinsicdangers” (1984: 249). It seems to me that Foucault’s posture of”passi<strong>on</strong>ate ambivalence,” to use James<strong>on</strong>’s expressi<strong>on</strong>, encourages a morethoughtful posture toward master narratives particularly thoseemancipatory <strong>on</strong>es which find their import in critical pedagogies, andmore generally, in critical traditi<strong>on</strong>s. My point is not simply to suggestan appreciati<strong>on</strong> of this relati<strong>on</strong>, but to suggest that it is precisely thisambivalence that is also in need of serious engagement.Now that I have presented what I find to be some of the main themesof the critique issued by poststructural feminisms, I would like toturn to what that posture enables in terms of an alternative form ofsocial criticism for educati<strong>on</strong>al research and for pedagogy.Poststructural feminisms and cyborg politicsCentral to poststructural feminisms is a combinati<strong>on</strong> of social criticismand strategic essentialism, the latter operating as a self-c<strong>on</strong>sciousforegrounding of <strong>on</strong>e’s political and ideological commitments. The socialcriticism dimensi<strong>on</strong> is informed by elements from poststructuraltheory and feminist theory; it is what provides the rich theoreticalfoundati<strong>on</strong> for poststructural feminisms. It may be beneficial to elaborate<strong>on</strong> that foundati<strong>on</strong>. In the introducti<strong>on</strong> to FCP Luke and Gore discussthe theoretical foundati<strong>on</strong>s in the following way:The poststructuralist agenda focuses <strong>on</strong> the dec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of takenfor-grantedhistorical structures of socio-cultural organizati<strong>on</strong>s withinwhich various versi<strong>on</strong>s of the ”individual” have been inserted and,importantly, <strong>on</strong> the language and theoretical structures with which theindividual and the social have been written. ... Post-structuralism andpostmodernism take issue with the centuries-l<strong>on</strong>g rule of Enlightenmentepistemology and the ficti<strong>on</strong>s of the individual it spawned. Both rejectthe self certain subject, the truth of science and fixity of language, andthe functi<strong>on</strong>alist order imputed to the social and to theories of the social(Luke & Gore, 1992: 5).Let me highlight the points in this passage that characterize thepoststructural elements of poststructural feminisms. First, historicalstructures of socio-cultural organizati<strong>on</strong>s, which include language andtheoretical structures, cannot be taken-for-granted, they must be175


dec<strong>on</strong>structed, for they not <strong>on</strong>ly produce a particular c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the”individual” (recall the c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the individual in liberal or marxisttheory provided earlier by Luke), but also produce a particularc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the social. Before I proceed perhaps something shouldbe said here about dec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>.Patti Lather, citing Elizabeth Grosz, defines (”uncomfortably”) threesteps of dec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>:Dec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> can be broken down into three steps: 1) identify theboundaries, the oppositi<strong>on</strong>s that structure an argument; 2) reverse/displacethe dependent term from its negative positi<strong>on</strong> to a place that locatesit as the very c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of the positive term; and 3) create a more fluidand less coercive c<strong>on</strong>ceptual organizati<strong>on</strong> of terms which transcends abinary logic by simultaneously being both neither of the binary terms(in Luke & Gore, 1992: 132).It may be helpful, as an example, to remember the ways in whichunprobed emancipatory efforts reinscribe relati<strong>on</strong>s of dominance.Unprobed emancipatory efforts presuppose a liberator and an unliberatedOther. This binary presents a hierarchy which privileges andassigns value to <strong>on</strong>e of the binary oppositi<strong>on</strong>s. In this case the liberatoris valued and the un-liberated Other is devalued. To put it in JacquesDerrida’s (1981) words, ”a violent hierarchy” and ”order of subordinati<strong>on</strong>”is established within these oppositi<strong>on</strong>s. The point of dec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>then is to dem<strong>on</strong>strate the order of subordinati<strong>on</strong> in binary oppositi<strong>on</strong>s.But there is also a sec<strong>on</strong>d phase to dec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> which Grosz rightlyrecognizes. This is what Derrida refers to as ”double writing.” It isimportant to stress, therefore, that dec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> is not just a simpleinversi<strong>on</strong> of the oppositi<strong>on</strong>s but also the ”emergence of a new c<strong>on</strong>cept,that can no l<strong>on</strong>ger be, and never could be, included in the previous[binary] regime” (1981: 42). An example of double writing which ispertinent here is D<strong>on</strong>na Haraway’s (1985) noti<strong>on</strong> of ”cyborg.” 15 Theimagery of cyborg, for example, blurs the distincti<strong>on</strong> between; nature/culture, human/machine, ficti<strong>on</strong>/reality and in so doing it provides analternative to binary logics.The sec<strong>on</strong>d point I want to highlight has to do with enlightenmentepistemology and the ”ficti<strong>on</strong>s of the individual it spawned.” This isrelated to two other points in Luke’s and Gore’s remarks <strong>on</strong> the rejecti<strong>on</strong>176


of ”the self-certain subject,” and the ”truth of science.” Taken togetherthese points refer to what is often credited to the achievements of theseventeenth-century Scientific Revoluti<strong>on</strong>, and the c<strong>on</strong>fidence in humanprogress which characterized the eighteenth-century Enlightenment.While it is true that both were movements more than two centuriesago, the Enlightenment is also a mode of c<strong>on</strong>sciousness; a set ofunderstandings, assumpti<strong>on</strong>s, and presuppositi<strong>on</strong>s about self and worldthat have and c<strong>on</strong>tinue to infiltrate and organize c<strong>on</strong>temporary modesof thought. For example, the Enlightenment is credited with assuminghuman history as an <strong>on</strong>going process of emancipati<strong>on</strong>. Moreover, theretends to be an overc<strong>on</strong>fidence in the ability of human reas<strong>on</strong> to orderindividuals and collectivities. Luke and Gore, influenced by the cauti<strong>on</strong>sencouraged from poststructuralism and postmodernism, promote a deepskepticism toward Enlightenment epistemology and ideals.The final point refers to the treatment of language in poststructuralthought. A poststructural understanding of language is informed by asensitivity to textuality; for example, it discloses the figures, grammaticaland rhetorical tropes that are operative in a text. 16 This emphasis <strong>on</strong>language as a writing practice permits poststructuralists to identifycommitments (forms of authority) that elude the writer partly becausethe writer treats language as a neutral tool and partly because there isalways, in every text, something that is not present to the writer orthinker. In their various excavati<strong>on</strong>s of critical pedagogy, FCPdem<strong>on</strong>strated a series of myths operating in critical pedagogy that eludedits very architects.These are the points which characterize the elements of poststructuraltheory. Now, let me turn to some of the points which characterize theelements of feminist theory. They can be summed up in the followingway. First, there is the issue of a patriarchal regime and the c<strong>on</strong>tinualneed to c<strong>on</strong>test that regime, recognizing, of course, the specificity ofwomen’s oppressi<strong>on</strong> (Luke & Gore, 1992: 7). Sec<strong>on</strong>d, the issue that”knowledge is always provisi<strong>on</strong>al, open-ended and relati<strong>on</strong>al” (Ibid).And lastly, poststructual feminisms ”stand firm <strong>on</strong> a politics of locati<strong>on</strong>and identity” (Ibid). All of these elements from ”post” and feministtheories provide a rich theoretical foundati<strong>on</strong> for poststructuralfeminisms. That foundati<strong>on</strong>, as noted earlier, is a combinati<strong>on</strong> of social177


criticism and strategic essentialism. Thus, poststructural feminisms providean alternative to critical pedagogy and an alternative form of politicsas well.The alternative pedagogy and politics as noted earlier is woven in theimage of the cyborg. D<strong>on</strong>na Haraway’s (1985) cyborg tale is an attemptto ”build an ir<strong>on</strong>ic political myth faithful to feminism, socialism, andmaterialism” (1985: 65). The aspects of that myth that are relevant topoststructural feminisms include a commitment to an epistemology ofprovisi<strong>on</strong>al and partial knowledges and identities. Identities are regardedhere as c<strong>on</strong>tradictory, partial and strategic. What this implies is a breakwith ”essentialist” unities and a b<strong>on</strong>ding based <strong>on</strong> coaliti<strong>on</strong> and affinity.Haraway summarizes this point when she c<strong>on</strong>siders the formati<strong>on</strong> ofthe political identity ”women of color,” she says:This identity marks out a self-c<strong>on</strong>sciously c<strong>on</strong>structed space that cannotaffirm the capacity to act <strong>on</strong> the basis of natural identificati<strong>on</strong>, but<strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong> the basis of c<strong>on</strong>scious coaliti<strong>on</strong> [my emphasis], of affinity, ofpolitical kinship (1985: 73).To regard identities as c<strong>on</strong>tradictory, partial and fractured does not,as Haraway sees it, preclude collective acti<strong>on</strong>. After all, collectivitiesand political unity are based <strong>on</strong> political kinship, as opposed to sayidentificati<strong>on</strong>, which relies <strong>on</strong> a ”logic of appropriati<strong>on</strong>, incorporati<strong>on</strong>,and tax<strong>on</strong>omic identificati<strong>on</strong>” (1985: 74).Cyborgs can also subvert the central myths or master narratives whichinclude the origin tales of western culture (Haraway, 1985: 94). Origintales, like dualisms are seen as the bane of ”western” traditi<strong>on</strong>. Thecyborg challenges these tales and dualisms in a provocative way becauseit has no origins. As Haraway notes:[t]he cyborg does not expect its father to save it through a restorati<strong>on</strong> ofthe garden ... does not dream of community <strong>on</strong> the model of the organicfamily ... the cyborg would not recognize the Garden of Eden; it is notmade of mud and cannot dream of returning to dust (1985: 67).Thus cyborgs are free from the chains of origin tales, they are inHaraways’ words, ”the illegitimate offspring of militarism and patriarchalcapitalism,” of which fathers are ”inessential” (1985: 68). 17Binary regimes in which a hierarchial value gets assigned are alsoseriously impaired with the image of cyborg. The cyborg is neither the178


”<strong>on</strong>e” (self) or its ”other” (n<strong>on</strong>-self) because it is unclear where cyborgresides in a binary regime. As Haraway puts it, ”it is not clear whomakes and who is made in the relati<strong>on</strong> between human and machine”(1985: 97). These aspects of the cyborg are what are so compelling forpoststructuralist feminisms. The cyborg image allows for an alternativepolitics which is not characterized by a subordinate relati<strong>on</strong> found indualistic forms of reas<strong>on</strong>ing in critical pedagogy, and more generally inmarxist oriented social theories. Most of the authors of FCP subscribeto a cyborgian political project and see the potential in it for creating analternative to emancipatory narratives that are ”grand.” A cyborg politicspermits the development of an emancipatory feminist pedagogy,<strong>on</strong>e which insists <strong>on</strong> standing firm <strong>on</strong> its political and ideologicalcommitments. At the same time, a cyborg politics recognizes that thosepolitical commitments are grounded in partial, c<strong>on</strong>tradictory, irreducible,unfinished and imperfect epistemology.In the following secti<strong>on</strong> I would like to remark <strong>on</strong> a tensi<strong>on</strong> betweenstanding firm <strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>e’s political and ideological commitments andadhering to an epistemology that claims to be partial and c<strong>on</strong>tradictory.This tensi<strong>on</strong> is relevant to two overlapping issues. The first has to dowith the rhetorical style in FCP, that is to say, the way political andideological commitments are made present. In other words how thosecommitments are written (their style) as opposed to say what they areabout (their c<strong>on</strong>tent). Attenti<strong>on</strong> to rhetoric presupposes that ”languagecaptures and c<strong>on</strong>structs events,” rather than simply ”refers” to it (Bennett& Chaloupka, 1993: xii). 18 And the sec<strong>on</strong>d, which intertwines withthe first, has to do with the imaginative and motivating power of writingan alternative tale.Rhetorical styleIn her essay, ”Primate visi<strong>on</strong>s and alter-tales” political theorist, JaneBennett (1993), pays attenti<strong>on</strong> to the rhetorical style of D<strong>on</strong>na Haraway’s(1989) Primate Visi<strong>on</strong>s and her crafting of an alter-tale: the cyborg.Bennett notes how the interpretati<strong>on</strong>s offered in Haraway’s text disturbour settled understandings of self and world. But she also points outthat coexisting with that disruptive skepticism is another voice, <strong>on</strong>ethat wants to promote some political claims. Bennett puts it this way:179


Haraway’s texts ... c<strong>on</strong>sistently disturb settled understandings abouthuman (i.e., n<strong>on</strong>animal) identity, about woman, about science, aboutnature. But this disruptive skepticism coexists in the text with anothervoice, <strong>on</strong>e deeply committed to a set of political claims. Theseaffirmati<strong>on</strong>s are repeated as a kind of litany, a cyborg professi<strong>on</strong> of faith[my emphasis] ... and it goes something like this: to idealize perfecti<strong>on</strong>and unity is to suppress anomaly and multiplicity; to define beauty asharm<strong>on</strong>y is to elevate fear of difference into an aesthetic imperative; todream of an original order is to depoliticize the current <strong>on</strong>e; to behomesick for the Father’s land is to be tempted to assign the status ofTruth to the way’s of <strong>on</strong>e own (in Bennett & Chaloupka, 1993: 257).Bennett’s point is that the imaginative power of the alter-tale isovershadowed when <strong>on</strong>e insists to much <strong>on</strong> placing <strong>on</strong>e’s political andideological commitments at center stage. 19 She is right to point outthat there is an uneasy coexistence between a c<strong>on</strong>stant foregrounding<strong>on</strong>e’s politics and trying to create an ”alter-tale,” particularly when thattale is based <strong>on</strong> a deep skepticism toward the knowable. 20In the c<strong>on</strong>text of FCP, cyborg politics is what informs and helps toinduce the alter-pedagogical tale. The rhetorical style of the anthology,unfortunately, diminishes the imaginative power of the alter-tale. Forexample, the c<strong>on</strong>stant insistence <strong>on</strong> making <strong>on</strong>e’s political and ideologicalcommitments present becomes the issue rather than enabling <strong>on</strong>e to seethe appeal of the alter-tale. Bennett suggests that perhaps what is neededis a more thoughtful crafting of Haraway’s rhetoric. Perhaps poststructuralfeminisms is also in need of a more careful crafting of theirrhetoric so that the alter-pedagogical tale—like the tale of the cyborg—is the issue rather than <strong>on</strong>e’s insistence <strong>on</strong> political positi<strong>on</strong>ing. Enhancingthe imaginative power of the alternative pedagogical visi<strong>on</strong> may requirecrafting a rhetoric that is tentative and skeptical. It may also require, andthis leads to the following discussi<strong>on</strong>, an ambivalent posture towards criticalpedagogies and critical traditi<strong>on</strong>s more generally.Ambivalent attachmentsThere are two silences in the critique produced by poststructuralfeminisms that I would like to address. The first has to do with a similarlymotivated critical political project shared by poststructural feminisms180


and critical traditi<strong>on</strong>s. The sec<strong>on</strong>d, which is not unrelated to the first,has to do with an ambivalent attachment that is often elided or notrecognized by both poststructuralist (dec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>/genealogyapproaches) and critical traditi<strong>on</strong>s (hermeneutic/interpretati<strong>on</strong> approaches).21The first point relies <strong>on</strong> political theorist Michael J. Shapiro’s (1984)analysis of textual practices as political interventi<strong>on</strong>. He notes thattextualism, ”’feeds off’ other radical epistemological strategies inasmuchas it is an attack <strong>on</strong> fetishes, <strong>on</strong> objects which enchant to the extent thatthey appear natural, universal or in some way bey<strong>on</strong>d human artifice orinventi<strong>on</strong>” (1984: 225).A fetish, in a politicized interpretati<strong>on</strong>, can be regarded as performingwhat he calls, ”the ideological functi<strong>on</strong> of removing power and authority”from the realm of human practices (1984: 226). Moreover, to revealthe operati<strong>on</strong>s of a fetish in a text is to show how a text can be readpolitically as a product of power rather than merely a benign thing (Ibid).I want to turn now to some examples of ”attacking fetishes.”A feminist approach to the fetish, for example, is to point to thesystem of patriarchy or phallocentrism that is operative in a text. InFCP poststructural feminisms have dem<strong>on</strong>strated cogently in variousways operati<strong>on</strong>s of a masculinist subject in their textual readings ofcritical pedagogy.Similarly, a marxian approach to the fetish is to reveal the humanrelati<strong>on</strong>s lost in the commodity. The hidden text operative in thecommodity fetish is the organizati<strong>on</strong> of human social relati<strong>on</strong>s aroundlabor producti<strong>on</strong>. As Shapiro points out, ”Marx’s reading of societywas, in effect, an attempt to divulge a hidden text” (1984: 226). Marx’sc<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong> was to recover human social processes (labor and its relati<strong>on</strong>s)that are masked in a discourse of things.Poststructuralism offers another approach to attacking fetishes. Apoststructural approach to the fetish pays attenti<strong>on</strong> to, am<strong>on</strong>g otherthings, the style of language. The fetish for poststructuralists operatesin linguistic practices and rhetorical and grammatical tropes. Anunpoliticized view of metaphors and tropes is that they serve asadornments or neutral additi<strong>on</strong>s. Such a view fails to see how metaphorsare productive; they are tied to ideological commitments. A181


poststructural approach tries to dem<strong>on</strong>strate how language is implicatedin the producti<strong>on</strong> of subjects and values. An example of the politicalsignificance of this approach, not unlike the political significance of theother approaches, is dem<strong>on</strong>strated by Michel Foucault in his analysesof discursive formati<strong>on</strong>s. As Edward Said succinctly puts it, ”Foucaultallows the text to assume its affiliati<strong>on</strong> with instituti<strong>on</strong>s, offices, agencies,classes, academics, corporati<strong>on</strong>s, groups, guilds, ideologically definedparties, and professi<strong>on</strong>s” (in Shapiro, 1984: 225). Thus, a textual readingis used to politicize the model of authority and power that isimplicitly operating in the discourse.These illustrati<strong>on</strong>s suggest that these projects are motivated by a similarpolitical orientati<strong>on</strong> toward disclosing reified power relati<strong>on</strong>s. Theseprojects have radically different philosophical and epistemological claimsthat may not be c<strong>on</strong>gruent, but, are aligned around the strategy of”attacking fetishes.” There is, however, a strange silence regarding thisshared affinity. The advocates of both often positi<strong>on</strong> themselves as ifthey were completely dissociative.Yet, feminist and political theorist Kathy Fergus<strong>on</strong> (1991), am<strong>on</strong>gothers, has pointed out in a different c<strong>on</strong>text that ”the two projectsc<strong>on</strong>nect to <strong>on</strong>e another in important ways” (1991: 335). While herfocus is <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>tending strategies of argument between interpretati<strong>on</strong>and genealogy within feminism, what she has to say about theirc<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> emphasizes my point. Her argument is pertinent to theencounter between poststructural feminisms and critical pedagogies.She notes, for example, that both ”can be seen as postures toward powerand knowledge that need <strong>on</strong>e another, while they stand in irreducibletensi<strong>on</strong> and cannot be cordially joined [my emphases]” (1991: 337).Both the ”need” and the ”irreducible tensi<strong>on</strong>” is what could be read asan ambivalent attachment toward each project. That ambivalence mightbe encouraged to problematize the fixed patterns of closure in socialmodes of inquiry by focusing <strong>on</strong> the ir<strong>on</strong>y of that attachment, ratherthan the re-establishment and maintenance of intellectual and politicalboundaries. She writes:The tensi<strong>on</strong> between l<strong>on</strong>ging for and being wary of a secure<strong>on</strong>tological and epistemological home, if handled ir<strong>on</strong>ically, need not bea source of despair; it can instead produce an appropriate humility182


c<strong>on</strong>cerning theory and an ability to sustain in the c<strong>on</strong>trary pull of c<strong>on</strong>tinuingto want what cannot be fully had [my emphases] (1991: 339).In the c<strong>on</strong>text of this analysis producing an appropriate humilitytoward critical pedagogies and poststructural feminisms begins, as I seeit, with acknowledging a similar political purpose. 22 At the same time,however, it would be wr<strong>on</strong>gheaded to read that political affinity as agesture toward integrati<strong>on</strong> and harm<strong>on</strong>y. That is not what I proposenor endorse; rather, I want to emphasize what William E. C<strong>on</strong>nollycalls, ”the code of paradox” (1991: 60) in modes of social inquiry. Thatcode, which I point out as an ambivalent attachment shared by criticalpedagogies and poststructural feminisms, if treated ir<strong>on</strong>ically, mayencourage a politics which works to loosen the patterns of insistenceand closure. Perhaps Patti Lather’s suspici<strong>on</strong> toward c<strong>on</strong>structingoppositi<strong>on</strong>al space via the terms of oppositi<strong>on</strong>, recognizes in part, thecode of paradox that I am trying to promote (in Luke & Gore: 132).I would like to c<strong>on</strong>clude by reiterating that the critiques issued frompoststructural feminisms are of no small significance. They haveproblematized the discourse of critical pedagogy by placing in sharprelief the unprobed presuppositi<strong>on</strong>s of liberatory and emancipatoryefforts. Their move toward a cyborg politics is an attempt to displacemaster narratives that are posited as universal. Yet there is a tensi<strong>on</strong>between an alter-tale based <strong>on</strong> a deep skepticism toward the knowable,and a posture of c<strong>on</strong>stantly foregrounding <strong>on</strong>e’s political and ideologicalcommitments. That c<strong>on</strong>stant foregrounding, as I see it, operates like a”recipe of self-restricti<strong>on</strong>” which tends to diminish the alternative tale. 23As I suggested earlier, with Bennett’s reading of Haraway, <strong>on</strong>e way tomitigate that tensi<strong>on</strong> is to pay more attenti<strong>on</strong> to how <strong>on</strong>e writes. Astrategy of rhetorical care may allow for a n<strong>on</strong>-dogmatic way ofpromoting political commitments and enhancing the ideati<strong>on</strong>al andpolitical power of poststructural feminisms alter-pedagogical tale. Thetensi<strong>on</strong> should not be regarded as precluding the power and richness ofthe critique, after all, polemical and oppositi<strong>on</strong>al discourses are politicalinterventi<strong>on</strong>s; they disturb theoretical complacency.183


ReferencesAlthusser, Louis. 1971. Lenin and philosophy and other essays. Trans. Ben Brewster.New York: M<strong>on</strong>thly Review Press.Apple, Michael W. 1996. Power, meaning, and identity: critical sociology of educati<strong>on</strong>in the United States. British Journal of Sociology of Educati<strong>on</strong> 17, no. 2: 125-44.Bal, Mieke. 1992. Narratology and the rhetoric of trashing. Comparative Literature 44,(Summer 1992): 293-306.Barrett, Michele. 1993. Althusser’s Marx, Althusser’s Lacan. In The Althusserian legacy.Eds. E. Ann Kaplan & Michael Sprinker. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> & New York: Verso.Bennett, Jane. 1993. Primate visi<strong>on</strong>s and alter-tales. In In the nature of things. Eds.Jane Bennett & William Chaloupka. Minneapolis: University of MinnesotaPress.Brown, Wendy. 1995. Wounded attachments: late modern oppositi<strong>on</strong>al politicalformati<strong>on</strong>s. In The identity in questi<strong>on</strong>. Ed. John Rajchman. New York:Routledge.Butler, Judith. 1997. Sovereign performatives in the c<strong>on</strong>temporary scene of utterance.Critical Inquiry 23, no. 2: 350-77.—. 1996. Performativity’s social magic. In The social and political body. Eds.Theodore R. Schatzki & Wolfgang Natter. New York & L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Guilford Press.Carroll, David. 1987. Paraesthetics. New York: Methuen.Clark, Suzanne. 1995. Women, Rhetoric, Teaching. College Compositi<strong>on</strong> andCommunicati<strong>on</strong> 46, no. 1: 108-22.C<strong>on</strong>nolly, William E. 1991. Identity/difference democratic negotiati<strong>on</strong>s of political paradox.Ithaca & L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Cornell University Press.Derrida, Jacques. 1981. Positi<strong>on</strong>s. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Ellsworth, Elizabeth. 1992. Why doesn’t this feel empowering? Working throughthe repressive myths of critical pedagogy. In Feminisms and critical pedagogy.Eds. Carmen Luke & Jennifer Gore. New York: Routledge.Fergus<strong>on</strong>, Kathy E. 1991. Interpretati<strong>on</strong> and genealogy in feminism. Signs 16,no. 2: 322-339.Finke, Laurie. 1993. Knowledge as bait: feminism, voice and the pedagogicalunc<strong>on</strong>scious. College English 55, no. 1: 7-27.Foucault, Michel. 1984. Space, knowledge, and power. In The Foucault reader.Ed. Paul Rabinow. New York: Panthe<strong>on</strong> Books.Haraway, D<strong>on</strong>na. 1989. Primate visi<strong>on</strong>s. New York : Routledge.—. 1985. A manifesto for cyborgs: science, technology, and socialist feminismin the 1980s. Socialist Review 15, no. 2: 64-107.James<strong>on</strong>, Fredric. 1989. Foreword. In The postmodern c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>. Mineapolis:University of Minnesota Press.Jay, Gregory S. 1987. The subject of pedagogy: less<strong>on</strong>s in psychoanalysis and politics.College English, 49, no. 7: 785-800.Kirsch, Gesa E. 1995. Feminist critical pedagogy and compositi<strong>on</strong>. College English 57,no. 6: 723-29.Lather, Patti. 1992. Post-critical pedagogies: a feminist reading. In Feminisms and criticalpedagogy. Eds. Carmen Luke & Jennifer Gore. New York: Routledge.Luke, Carmen & Jennifer Gore. 1992. Feminisms and critical pedagogy. Eds. New York:Routledge.184


Lyotard, Jean-Francois. 1989. The postmodern c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>. Minneapolis: Universityof Minnesota Press.Orner, Mimi. 1992. Interrupting the calls for student voice in ”liberatory” educati<strong>on</strong>:a feminist poststructuralist perspective. In Feminisms and critical pedagogy.Eds. Carmen Luke & Jennifer Gore. New York: Routledge.Oxford English reference dicti<strong>on</strong>ary. 1995. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Popkewitz, Thomas S. 1996. State reforms, educati<strong>on</strong>al sciences and the governingof the <strong>teacher</strong>: some comparative historical notes. Unpublished manuscript.Shapiro, Michael J. 1984. Literary producti<strong>on</strong> as politicizing practice. In Languageand politics. Ed. Michael J. Shapiro New York: New York University Press.Saussure, Ferdinand de. 1974. (First published in French 1916). Course in generallinguistics. Trans. Wade Baskin. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: F<strong>on</strong>tana.Todorov, Tzvetan. 1990. Genres in discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Todd, Shar<strong>on</strong>. 1995. Psychoanalytic questi<strong>on</strong>s, pedagogical possibilities and authority.The Review of Educati<strong>on</strong>/Pedagogy/Cultural Studies 17, no. 1: 15-26.NotesI am indebted to Jane Bennett for answering my queries and for criticisms of an earlierdraft of this paper. Her essay ”Primate visi<strong>on</strong>s and alter-tales,” enabled me to thinkthrough and frame two themes; rhetorical style and ambivalent attachment. I also wantto express my gratitude to Michael W. Apple, Grace Livingst<strong>on</strong>, Glenabah Martinez,Thomas Popkewitz, Michael J. Shapiro and the Friday reading group for their criticismsand insights <strong>on</strong> earlier drafts.1 . I do not what to characterize all the essays as positi<strong>on</strong>ed in oppositi<strong>on</strong> to critical pedagogiesand their architects. Patti Lather’s essay while critical and suspicious of the underlyingassumpti<strong>on</strong>s of critical pedagogies is as suspicious of crafting oppositi<strong>on</strong>al space viaoppositi<strong>on</strong>s (in Luke & Gore: 132).2 . The term ”critical” is being used here to identify analyses broadly associated with variantsof western marxist and gramscian social theories in the field of educati<strong>on</strong> within a northamerican, british and australian c<strong>on</strong>text. In this designati<strong>on</strong> I am bracketing analysesassociated with postmodern and poststructural modes of social inquiry in educati<strong>on</strong>.This artificial bracketing may cause some to squirm, after all ”critical” when broadlyc<strong>on</strong>ceived refers to the discernment of power relati<strong>on</strong>s which suggests a similar politicalpurpose am<strong>on</strong>g these various intellectual and political projects. For now, though, Iwould like to stand by my bracketing in order to clarify, I hope, the social theoreticalorientati<strong>on</strong>s the critique is being waged at.3 . My use of ”critical traditi<strong>on</strong>s” refers, again, to the variants of western marxian andgramscian social theories in the field of educati<strong>on</strong>. See also note 2.4 . For a more critical assessment of the anthology see Shar<strong>on</strong> Todd’s (1995) essay”Psychoanalytic questi<strong>on</strong>s, pedagogical possibilities and authority,” in The Review ofEducati<strong>on</strong>/Pedagogy/Cultural Studies which is issued from a psychoanalytic angle.5. The noti<strong>on</strong> of ”ambivalent attachment” and ”paradoxical relati<strong>on</strong>” was brought to my185


attenti<strong>on</strong> when reading an eloquently written essay by Jane Bennett, ”Primate visi<strong>on</strong>sand alter-tales” in In the nature of things. For more <strong>on</strong> this see especially the secti<strong>on</strong>,”Identificati<strong>on</strong>,” p. 257.6. I have selected this anthology because it is, am<strong>on</strong>g other things, the first and perhapsmost well read representati<strong>on</strong> of a poststructural feminist pedagogy mode of inquiry inthe field of educati<strong>on</strong>. Because my approach is not a ”review” in the c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>al sense,many have d<strong>on</strong>e so already (see Suzanne Clark 1995; Gesa E. Kirsch 1995; and ElisabethHayes 1993 am<strong>on</strong>g others), I have selected <strong>on</strong>ly the chapters which underscore themain tenets of the critique.7. I am a little uncomfortable with my expressi<strong>on</strong> ”eclectic” for often it is used disparaginglyin academic practice; as a trope to ”trash” and dismiss a colleague’s work. That is not myintenti<strong>on</strong> here. For more <strong>on</strong> ”trashing” as a narrative genre see Mieke Bal’s (1992) essay,”Narratology and the rhetoric of trashing.”8. I am using interpellati<strong>on</strong> in the Althusserian sense. For more <strong>on</strong> interpellati<strong>on</strong> seeespecially the secti<strong>on</strong> ”Ideology interpellates individuals as subjects” in Lenin andphilosophy and other essays (1971). For a feminist reading of interpellati<strong>on</strong> as genderedsee Michele Barrett’s (1993) ”Althusser’s Marx, Althusser’s Lacan” in The Althusserianlegacy.9. By ambiguous I am referring to the overdeterminati<strong>on</strong> of critical pedagogies effectivity.Educators writing <strong>on</strong> the structure of desire operative within pedagogical practice is <strong>on</strong>egood example of this overdeterminati<strong>on</strong>. See, for example, Shar<strong>on</strong> Todd (1995), LaurieFinke (1993), and Gregory S. Jay (1987).10. There is the tendency to wr<strong>on</strong>gly c<strong>on</strong>clude from the ”indeterminacy” thesis that allsigns (meanings) equally participate in an endless sign of significati<strong>on</strong>. Clearly, this isnot the case. The criminalizati<strong>on</strong> of certain bodies or the regulati<strong>on</strong> of women’s wombsare but two examples of the indeterminacy determined.11. I would like to thank Glenabah Martinez for this valuable insight. For more <strong>on</strong> languageand performativity see Judith Butler (1996, 1997).12. I take this insight from Ferdinand de Saussure’s (tr. 1974) hypothesis language as asystem of differences which implies meaning or intelligibility is derived out of a relati<strong>on</strong>of differences.13. I had trouble finding a succinct definiti<strong>on</strong> for the expressi<strong>on</strong> ”master narrative” in thetext. Therefore I have taken the liberty to discuss master narrative within the termsoffered by Fredric James<strong>on</strong> which I think fits nicely with how it is being used in FCP.14. Popkewitz’s study is focused <strong>on</strong> the discourses about professi<strong>on</strong>alizati<strong>on</strong> in c<strong>on</strong>temporaryeducati<strong>on</strong>al reform.15. The definiti<strong>on</strong> of cyborg in the Oxford English Reference Dicti<strong>on</strong>ary (1995) says thefollowing: ”a pers<strong>on</strong> whose physical abilities are extended bey<strong>on</strong>d human limitati<strong>on</strong>s bymachine technology (as yet undeveloped) [cybernetic + organism].”16. The essay by Mimi Orner (in Luke & Gore 1992) is sensitive to the issue of textuality.See her essay ”Interrupting the calls for student voice in ’liberatory’ educati<strong>on</strong>: a feministpoststructuralist perspective” especially pp. 79-80.17. Wendy Brown’s essay, ”Wounded attachments,” complicates Haraway’s suggesti<strong>on</strong> thatfathers are ”inessential” when she introduces the structure of desire. She reminds us that”the psyche of the bastard child is hardly independent of its family of origin” (p. 208).186


18. Implicit in such a focus is a critique of the systematic inattenti<strong>on</strong> to rhetoric as a site forpolitical interventi<strong>on</strong> by those political projects which focus soley <strong>on</strong> issues of equityand access. While issues of equity, access, and I might add entitlement, are issues thatmust be part of any political agenda, I also want to suggest that the way in which suchissues are instantiated in language (e.g., patterns of inclusi<strong>on</strong> and exclusi<strong>on</strong>, making ofsubjects and values, and so <strong>on</strong>) is of political importance as well.19. This point was brought to my attenti<strong>on</strong> by Bennett.20. Todd’s (1995) essay characterizes this tensi<strong>on</strong> as a ”precarious relati<strong>on</strong>ship betweenpoststructuralisms’s ’anti-foundati<strong>on</strong>alism’ and feminism’s grounding in a politics oflocati<strong>on</strong>, difference and identity” (pg. 18).21 . This point is made by Michael J. Shapiro’s (1984) essay, ”Literary producti<strong>on</strong> aspoliticizing practice,” and also by Kathy E. Fergus<strong>on</strong>’s (1991) article ”Interpretati<strong>on</strong> andgenealogy in feminism.” They both note that hermeneutic/interpretive strategies createthe c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s of possibility for dec<strong>on</strong>structive and genealogical strategies.22. Mike Apple (1996) suggests a different type of strategy. He recommends that theepistemological and philosophical tensi<strong>on</strong>s between ”neo” and ”posts” rub against eachother. He notes that a ”little tresspassing may be a good thing” (141).23. I borrow this expressi<strong>on</strong> from C<strong>on</strong>nolly (1991:56).187


188


LISA HENNONSpatial Patternsof Inclusi<strong>on</strong>/Exclusi<strong>on</strong>:Governmentality and Urbanismin the USAThe ministers of knowledge have always assumed that the wholeuniverse was threatened by the very changes that affected theirideologies and their positi<strong>on</strong>s. They transmute the misfortune oftheir theories into theories of misfortune. When they transformbewilderment into ”catastrophes,” when they seek to enclose thepeople in the ”panic” of their discourses, are they <strong>on</strong>ce morenecessarily right?—Michel de Certeau, ”Walking in the City” 1Introducti<strong>on</strong>One of the great challenges of the modern nati<strong>on</strong> state is to developstrategies for social inclusi<strong>on</strong> at a time when profound changes haveoccurred in global ec<strong>on</strong>omies, patterns of migrati<strong>on</strong>, and a rise in l<strong>on</strong>gtermunemployment (Silver 1994). Social and educati<strong>on</strong>al policies seekto devise strategies of inclusi<strong>on</strong> through reforms of schooling (see e.g.Istance 1997). In the USA, educati<strong>on</strong>al reform discourses give the problemof inclusi<strong>on</strong> a geographical sense by targeting ”urban” or ”innercity” schools for reform. The discourses present the issue as an ”urbansuburban”dichotomy and claim to be offering ”new” ways to devise aninclusi<strong>on</strong>ary system of schooling.However, as inclusi<strong>on</strong> strategies are sought, patterns of exclusi<strong>on</strong>remain foremost. The binary of ”urban-suburban” articulates a ”panic”about social exclusi<strong>on</strong> (to use de Certeau’s phrase above), but reformcampaigns overlook the ways in which urbanism is part of an oldertrajectory that historically has been a system to exclude. I use the term”urbanism” to refer to discursive c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s of ”urban-ness,” or whatit means to be ”urban.”189


”Urbanism” is a historical and c<strong>on</strong>ceptual tool of analysis to raise thetheoretical questi<strong>on</strong> of how a critical framework can be provided forcomparative approaches to issues of social justice and equality. Discursivedeployment of the ”city” produces political and moral effects bygoverning the ways in which we see, think, feel, aspire, act up<strong>on</strong> anddivide ourselves and others. In other nati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>texts, American urbanismwill not apply, but the social implicati<strong>on</strong>s of urbanism should notbe read as a provincial issue of educati<strong>on</strong> in the U.S. A theoretical readingof the analysis can provide ways to explore the more general questi<strong>on</strong>of how oppositi<strong>on</strong>al spaces are c<strong>on</strong>structed. Underlying my endeavor isan attempt to think theoretically and comparatively through theproblematic of governmentality about how schooling functi<strong>on</strong>s toinclude/exclude.Since the U.S. was first established, educati<strong>on</strong>al reform discourseshave attempted to envisi<strong>on</strong> the entire space of the nati<strong>on</strong> by invoking ageographical divisi<strong>on</strong> in which images of the ”city” are c<strong>on</strong>trasted tosomething which it is not. The historical trajectory of urbanism can beunderstood as undergoing three shifts. In the eighteenth and nineteenthcenturies, urbanism shifted to discourses of land that opposed city tocountry. By the turn of the twentieth century, urbanism shifted to discoursesabout society that opposed urban to rural. Currently, urbanismhas shifted to discourses of community that oppose urban to suburban.While the intent has been to make schooling more inclusive, at eachjuncture (city-country, urban-rural, and urban-suburban) an older formof reas<strong>on</strong>ing—that divides, excludes and reorders c<strong>on</strong>cepts—creates newexclusi<strong>on</strong>s.Urbanism and the Metaphor of Land as Nati<strong>on</strong>From the 1780s to the 1880s in the USA, the discursive space of urbanismtied educati<strong>on</strong>al reform movements to images of land in emergentdiscourses of the nati<strong>on</strong> state. The nati<strong>on</strong> state was given a symbolicand physical order, or ”landscape,” which was mapped <strong>on</strong>to territoryand populati<strong>on</strong>. The landscape served to locate problems and todistribute the comm<strong>on</strong> school based up<strong>on</strong> patterns of inclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong>.190


The Oppositi<strong>on</strong> of City and Country:Cosmopolitan and Pastoral Images 2To understand how the oppositi<strong>on</strong> of city and country was c<strong>on</strong>nectedto discourses of land and to comm<strong>on</strong> school movements, it is helpful torecall the historical significance of ”land” in social thought. A priorimage was the ”heavens.” The theologian St. Augustine divided the worldinto two cities, the heavenly city and the earthly (Davies & Herbert1993). The ”heavenly city” was the theopolis where heaven touchedearth and took physical form in cathedral cities and dioceses. Earthlycities were outside a Christian moral order. Protestantism and col<strong>on</strong>ialismtranslated the divisi<strong>on</strong> into ”heavenly” and ”secular” which took adifferent physical form. In 1710, a Puritan in North America, Cott<strong>on</strong>Mather, declared the col<strong>on</strong>y of Massachusetts a ”heavenly city” (Banfield1970).Discourses of the nati<strong>on</strong> state appropriated the divisi<strong>on</strong> of the worldand transformed the image of the heavenly city by replacing God withNature (Becker 1932; Toulmin 1990). Drawing up<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>ceptualizati<strong>on</strong>sof Greek city states and Roman republics, the religious cosmographywas displaced by a land-based metaphor, geo-graphy. The questi<strong>on</strong> of ademocratic state became how to govern over large distances and <strong>on</strong> ac<strong>on</strong>tinuous and regular basis. Lands and peoples were envisi<strong>on</strong>ed asdivided into nati<strong>on</strong> states which took physical form by dividing surfaceof territory, or land, into bounded and c<strong>on</strong>tiguous entities (see Anders<strong>on</strong>1991). The ”New World” was envisi<strong>on</strong>ed as a project to model ademocracy <strong>on</strong> Nature’s heavenly city.Land was the focus for various interlocking discourses of wealth, stability,and unity (Shefter 1984). Discourses of political ec<strong>on</strong>omy calculateda nati<strong>on</strong>’s wealth in terms of its capacity to be agriculturally selfsustaining.Discourses of political philosophy, however, rejected theinequalities created by feudalism that remained in England and Europe.Social c<strong>on</strong>flicts were seen as inevitable outcomes of failing to rootout vestiges of aristocracy and peasantry. For a republic based <strong>on</strong> citizens’participati<strong>on</strong> in self-government to be stable and to survive, it was believedthat widespread ownership of land was necessary. By owning land,the citizen would have an ec<strong>on</strong>omic incentive to act in nati<strong>on</strong>al inte-191


ests of wealth and stability. The role of government was to encouragethe ownership and cultivati<strong>on</strong> of land and to encourage populati<strong>on</strong>growth to insure a nati<strong>on</strong>’s wealth and stability.Land became a metaphor for nati<strong>on</strong>al unity through discourses ofcartography and populati<strong>on</strong>al reas<strong>on</strong>ing. Land was mapped physicallyand symbolically to make it possible for the individual to act as citizen.Erecting a fr<strong>on</strong>tier and defining the inhabitants of the territory nati<strong>on</strong>allywas a new form of boundary rather than an established traditi<strong>on</strong> (Wagner1994). Map lines and the first census in 1790 inscribed ”America”<strong>on</strong>to land, bodies, and imaginati<strong>on</strong>s (see also Meinig 1986).In discourses of nati<strong>on</strong> as land, nati<strong>on</strong>al space was envisi<strong>on</strong>ed inmultiple ways, for a variety of spatial divisi<strong>on</strong>s were available, such aspost-col<strong>on</strong>ial regi<strong>on</strong>s and c<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong>ally defined states and territories.In thinking about the educated citizen in relati<strong>on</strong> to land, however, thebinary between city and country tended to neatly capture ”all” of nati<strong>on</strong>alspace (see also Chartier 1988). Country had the double meaning ofboth the symbolic territory of the nati<strong>on</strong>, and the forests, mountains,pastures and agricultural settlements within it (see Williams 1973).Ir<strong>on</strong>ically, images of the city made the country, in both senses, intelligible.The city and country oppositi<strong>on</strong> can be understood in two analyticframes, cosmopolitan and pastoral. Stephen Toulmin (1990) has coinedthe term ”Cosmopolis” to characterize the world order of nati<strong>on</strong> statesand the scaffolding of discourses that went into its c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>. I adapthis term to characterize the cosmopolitan image of city and country.Pastoralism is ordinarily understood as a genre of literature or landscapepainting, but as Leo Marx (1984) has argued, American pastoralismcan be understood as formative of social thought and policy. The pastoralimage of city and country served as a counter-balance to thecosmopolitan in American thought. Each image c<strong>on</strong>tributed keyelements to the American landscape.The cosmopolitan image of city and country established norms of”civilizati<strong>on</strong>.” The cosmopolitan image ordered both administrative andsymbolic representati<strong>on</strong>s of nati<strong>on</strong>al space. The territory outside theoriginal thirteen col<strong>on</strong>ies was c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be ”unsettled” because itlacked an American stamp <strong>on</strong> its terrain. The cosmopolitan view of thecity helped c<strong>on</strong>struct an American landscape by thinking of the ”city”192


as a microcosm of its geographic territory. Mapping proceeded as thoughindividual states were extensi<strong>on</strong>s of the elements found in cities but <strong>on</strong>a larger scale. American cities were seen as serving the surroundingcountryside but also as a way of b<strong>on</strong>ding the country into a nati<strong>on</strong>alsystem of agricultural, cultural, and political interc<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> (Meinig1993). The architectural relati<strong>on</strong>s of the city—with its network of places,systems of movement and exchange, and structures for civic activity—provided a template for administering and regulating the peopling andsettling of territory (see also Foucault 1980, 1984; Gord<strong>on</strong> 1991). Allof nati<strong>on</strong>al space could be understood in its entirety by ”seeing” the”country” through the ”city.”Cosmopolitan urbanism set up a symbolic oppositi<strong>on</strong> between thesavagery associated with a harsh ”wilderness” or ”jungle” in oppositi<strong>on</strong>to ”civilizati<strong>on</strong>.” A ”civilizati<strong>on</strong>” was recognizable by its c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> ofcities. The cosmopolitan image of the city was associated with theachievements of reas<strong>on</strong>, progress, liberty, human perfectability, andcivilizati<strong>on</strong> (Williams 1973). Racial discourses of ”civilizati<strong>on</strong>s” placed”races” al<strong>on</strong>g an evoluti<strong>on</strong>ary road of reas<strong>on</strong> and progress. The destinati<strong>on</strong>(and destiny) of reas<strong>on</strong> and progress was the civilizati<strong>on</strong> that builtcosmopolitan cities (see also Young 1995).The pastoral image of city and country established norms of ”nati<strong>on</strong>.”Images of the countryside were endemic to the American democraticproject. In American pastoralism, land was thought to be unifying ofthe nati<strong>on</strong> by giving the citizen a moral (rather than ec<strong>on</strong>omic) stake innati<strong>on</strong>al interests. Pastoral urbanism adopted Enlightenment beliefs insocial harm<strong>on</strong>y and reas<strong>on</strong> but combined them with a Protestant imageof the Garden of Eden (Marx 1964). Pastoralism linked the ”progressive”element of cosmopolitan urbanism to human moral perfectability. TheAmerican citizen was c<strong>on</strong>structed to have an excepti<strong>on</strong>al relati<strong>on</strong>ship to”native soil” as the site of moral c<strong>on</strong>versi<strong>on</strong>. In 1844, an American philosopher,Emers<strong>on</strong>, expressed this visi<strong>on</strong> succinctly: ”We must regard theland as a commanding and increasing power <strong>on</strong> the citizen, the sanative[redemptive] and Americanizing influence which promises to disclose newvirtues for ages to come” (quoted in Wills 1997, p. 217, my brackets).In the ”New World,” savagery was associated not <strong>on</strong>ly with n<strong>on</strong>-Christians and lesser ”races” of the wilderness; pastoral urbanism193


associated depravity with populati<strong>on</strong>s in European and British cities. Ina Protestant United States, the secular city was seen to functi<strong>on</strong> solelyfor ec<strong>on</strong>omic ambiti<strong>on</strong> which encouraged political abuses andcorrupti<strong>on</strong>. The political upheavals abroad and social c<strong>on</strong>flicts in citiesthreatened the country as a whole. Similar neglect in shepherdingpopulati<strong>on</strong>s in the countryside could be fragmenting and destabilizing.Pastoral urbanism set up a different symbolic field of positive and negativevalues which situated the ”country” as the norm between the wildernessand the secular city.Normalizing Space: Inclusi<strong>on</strong>s/Exclusi<strong>on</strong>sof a Nati<strong>on</strong>al LandscapeThe role of government was to safeguard American democracy byc<strong>on</strong>structing an inclusi<strong>on</strong>ary nati<strong>on</strong>al landscape to instill ”natural” virtuesin its citizens. Discourses of cosmopolitan and pastoral urbanism helpednormalize the space of the nati<strong>on</strong> state to stabilize the making of meaningand the meaning of nati<strong>on</strong>al space as a c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of freedom (see alsoDumm 1996).The ”space” of the nati<strong>on</strong> state has a social dimensi<strong>on</strong> which is distinctfrom empire or territory. One way to think about the ”space” of nati<strong>on</strong>states is suggested by Anth<strong>on</strong>y Giddens (1990) who argues thatpreviously, social practices and social identities were intimately linkedto the place or locale of face-to-face interacti<strong>on</strong>s. Technologies of themap and census, as well as standard calendars, mechanical clocks, nati<strong>on</strong>alcurrencies, and city school timetables began to coordinatemeanings without the negotiati<strong>on</strong> of meaning having to occur in faceto-faceinteracti<strong>on</strong>s. The coordinati<strong>on</strong> of social practices across a nati<strong>on</strong>alspace established new chains of interacti<strong>on</strong>, making it possible for”absent others” to organize and structure meanings for those ”present”in the physical locale.The establishment of chains of interacti<strong>on</strong> between ”absence” and”presence” ”dis-embedded” meanings of particular c<strong>on</strong>texts and ”reembedded”them as general principles. The meanings of normative placesin nati<strong>on</strong>al space, such as the local school, homestead or home, beganto be structured by inserting the locale into discourses of nati<strong>on</strong> statesand of nati<strong>on</strong>al identity. Governing could occur in face-to-face194


interacti<strong>on</strong>s in terms of an ”absent” State; the ”local” could be governed”at a distance” (Rose 1996a). Social identities were uprooted and newcollective c<strong>on</strong>texts were created.The discussi<strong>on</strong> of normalizing the space of the nati<strong>on</strong> state helps usthink of inclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong> as strategies related to the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> ofplaces. In the strategy of enclosing nati<strong>on</strong>al space, there were those whohad no ”place” <strong>on</strong> the map of the citizen. The American Revoluti<strong>on</strong>established a boundary line of exclusi<strong>on</strong>. Mixtures of European, Asian,and pan-American ”Indians” already living in ”unsettled” territory wereexcluded by representing the mapped land as ”empty” (Gitlin 1992).People who were given no place were neither counted as American norassigned to nati<strong>on</strong>al territory. Instead, they were ignored, pushed to the”fr<strong>on</strong>tier,” or destroyed.The strategy of internment immobilized people in <strong>on</strong>e and <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>eplace. The practice of enslaving Africans and interning them in theplantati<strong>on</strong> gave them a place of c<strong>on</strong>tainment in nati<strong>on</strong>al space. We canalso c<strong>on</strong>sider the practice of relocating Indians to sites of ”protecti<strong>on</strong>”in the reservati<strong>on</strong> as a strategy of internment. Missi<strong>on</strong>aries may haveadvocated religious instructi<strong>on</strong> for Indians and slaves, but before the1870s people excluded from political representati<strong>on</strong> were thought to beungovernable and were immobilized in nati<strong>on</strong>al space.To ”include” the governable involved determining their place in thelandscape. Positive and negative values in images of the city and countrycreated a normative pull <strong>on</strong> ”space” in both directi<strong>on</strong>s. The ”city”was the norm for ”civilizati<strong>on</strong>.” The ”country” was the norm for ”nati<strong>on</strong>.”Together, they c<strong>on</strong>stituted an American visi<strong>on</strong> of a nati<strong>on</strong>al landscapeprimarily as small farms in the countryside, country estates isolatedfrom yet having access to a city’s commerce and civic activities, andlocal communities in villages and towns. The reas<strong>on</strong>able AmericanCitizen did not live far from the ameliorative forces of land, eitherthrough owning it, or by being schooled to cherish and spiritually thrivewithin it.Normative inclusi<strong>on</strong>ary categories based <strong>on</strong> discourses of land establishedan included/excluded social status in which citizenship embodiedand mutually implicated both inclusi<strong>on</strong> and exclusi<strong>on</strong>, an in-betweenstatus that goes unrecognized by the binary of inclusi<strong>on</strong> versus exclusi<strong>on</strong>195


in political representati<strong>on</strong>. When normative places began to structurenati<strong>on</strong>al space, systems of social inclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong> were embedded inthe landscape and the mapping of the ”comm<strong>on</strong>” school.Inclusi<strong>on</strong>s/exclusi<strong>on</strong>s of the comm<strong>on</strong> school were mapped <strong>on</strong>to the pastoralcity and local community. Exclusi<strong>on</strong>s effected by urbanism occurredthrough the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of normative places such as the pastoral cityand the local community. Biological discourses about the secular cityand populati<strong>on</strong>al health made it possible for nature to be a part of urban-ness.A healthy pastoral city was compared to the biology of a healthybody: streets and roads were the city’s arteries and veins, parks and gardenswere its lungs (Sennett 1994). The Jeffers<strong>on</strong>ian image of theenlightened citizen referred to the citizen of the countryside, the ”independent,rati<strong>on</strong>al, democratic husbandman” (in Marx 1964, p. 122).We can read the social movements to build public parks, gardens, andthe kindergarten in a pastoral city as applicati<strong>on</strong>s of the same reas<strong>on</strong>ing.However, the normative visi<strong>on</strong> of the pastoral city paled beside thereality. Cities of industry were plagued by not <strong>on</strong>ly sooty air, open sewers,and irregular familial living arrangements, but also by an alarmingunregulated movement of people and neglect of moral c<strong>on</strong>versi<strong>on</strong>.Reformers believed that city dwellers ”outside” the normative visi<strong>on</strong>needed far more than parks and gardens to be included—they neededtechnologies of moral hygiene and mechanisms such as the comm<strong>on</strong>school to enable ec<strong>on</strong>omic and moral citizenship.The c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of the local community in the countryside seemsto capture a universal motif of places where all were <strong>on</strong> an equal footing.Urbanism scaffolded systems of ideas about the nati<strong>on</strong> state, populati<strong>on</strong>alreas<strong>on</strong>ing, and reas<strong>on</strong>ing about geographic scale to hierarchically nestthe ”local” within the enclosure of the ”nati<strong>on</strong>.” From the perspectiveof self-government, the local community was thought to give citizensboth a sense of aut<strong>on</strong>omy over local affairs and nati<strong>on</strong>al representati<strong>on</strong>.The ”local community” embodied nati<strong>on</strong>al relati<strong>on</strong>s am<strong>on</strong>g citizensand of citizens to land. C<strong>on</strong>ceptualizati<strong>on</strong>s of the ”local,” however, wereneither uniform nor unproblematic. In the South, the ”county”represented the ”local community” where small-plot farmers, traders,and plantati<strong>on</strong> owners met infrequently. To the northeast, in c<strong>on</strong>trast,New England practices of ”local community” took the form of the ”town”196


where families from a single Protestant c<strong>on</strong>gregati<strong>on</strong> went to settle, asin migrati<strong>on</strong>s westward (Meinig 1986).The ”town” form of ”local community” became a normative place<strong>on</strong> the map of the citizen. The Land Ordinances of 1785 and 1787inscribed the ”town” form of the ”local.” The ordinances were federalacts to survey land and to lay the administrative groundwork forregulating the settling of territory. The formalizati<strong>on</strong> of discourses ofland mapped territory as ”township” and ”range” to induce populati<strong>on</strong>to form individual counties and states which were then expected to jointhe republic of ”United States.”The more dispersed settlement pattern in the South set up aberrantrelati<strong>on</strong>s. In the northern tier of the U.S. a city system emerged with afar more developed transportati<strong>on</strong> network of ports, canals, stage coachroads, and railways. The network of c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> and exchange gave theNorth an unforeseen advantage by settling people into smaller, moredensely populated areas, and by establishing chains of interacti<strong>on</strong> forindustrial development. The southern regi<strong>on</strong> was excluded geographicallyand symbolically in ”nati<strong>on</strong>al” relati<strong>on</strong>s because southern practicesof the ”local” developed neither a city system nor ”civilized” pastoralcities.The more precise telescopic pinpointing of the individual—withinthe localizati<strong>on</strong> of the ”town” as the normative place of ”localcommunity”—brought the body of the populati<strong>on</strong> into tighter relati<strong>on</strong>s.The visi<strong>on</strong> was a regulative machinery to penetrate all regi<strong>on</strong>sand administer them for the comm<strong>on</strong> good (Rose 1996a). Later, JohnDewey’s thesis <strong>on</strong> ”community” in Democracy and Educati<strong>on</strong> (1916)appropriated and dis-embedded northern practices and meanings andre-embedded them as universal principles of freedom and obligati<strong>on</strong>.The comm<strong>on</strong> school was an ordering comp<strong>on</strong>ent and normative placethat linked the ”local community” to the nati<strong>on</strong>. The land ordinancesof the late 1700s required townships to set aside secti<strong>on</strong>s to fundc<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of schools and wages for a <strong>teacher</strong>, which signaled theremapping of a cosmography of schooling into a geography of governing.197


Inclusi<strong>on</strong>s/Exclusi<strong>on</strong>s of Nati<strong>on</strong>al Identityin the ”Comm<strong>on</strong>” SchoolUrbanism related to a range of inclusi<strong>on</strong>s/exclusi<strong>on</strong>s that were boundto noti<strong>on</strong>s of a ”comm<strong>on</strong>” and ”local” school—in cities, countrysides,regi<strong>on</strong>s, and unsettled territories. The problematic of inclusi<strong>on</strong> in therhetoric of the ”comm<strong>on</strong>” school can be read as a nati<strong>on</strong>alist discourseattempting to define what was comm<strong>on</strong> am<strong>on</strong>g those who were alreadyrecognized as American and to invent strategies for instilling thosecomm<strong>on</strong>alties within the young. The task seem by comm<strong>on</strong> schoolreformers was to transform ”Carolinans” or far away ”Californians,” aswell as ”settlers,” ”immigrants,” and former ”British loyalists,” intoAmericans. The disciplinary role of schooling was to enable men (withthe help of their sisters and mothers) to raise up the next generati<strong>on</strong> ofcitizens for participati<strong>on</strong> in self-government. The systems of inclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong> of urbanism mobilized educati<strong>on</strong>al discourses to c<strong>on</strong>structthe comm<strong>on</strong> school to save a nati<strong>on</strong> careening toward separatism,c<strong>on</strong>flict, and moral depravity; its purposes were transformative andredemptive (see Popkewitz 1996).Specific reforms of comm<strong>on</strong> school movements drew up<strong>on</strong> themapping of the governable citizen: the American Citizen was Protestant.He spoke an ”Americanized” English and practiced Anglo orNorthern European culture. He was ”racially” resp<strong>on</strong>sive to the”civilizing” benefits of educati<strong>on</strong> and was clean and industrious inthought and demeanor. He dem<strong>on</strong>strated his allegiance by being ”settled”within the nati<strong>on</strong>al landscape (or by aspiring to move and then settle).Potential citizens were understood in terms of what they ”lacked” inorder to be governable. Within the in-between of included/excluded,pastoral urbanism was applied to deficiencies of cities, and cosmopolitanurbanism was applied to deficiencies of the countryside.Excluded populati<strong>on</strong>s associated with cities, such as nomadic,indigent, or immigrant city dwellers, and those who lived a precariousexistence <strong>on</strong> the periphery, lacked both an ec<strong>on</strong>omic and moral stake inthe nati<strong>on</strong>. Their ”unsettledness” threatened the stability of the landscape,and their ”uncleanliness” and poor health threatened the nati<strong>on</strong>.Providing schooling for the children of poor, laboring, and immigrantpopulati<strong>on</strong>s in cities would ”include” them by supplementing and198


intervening into their lives to make them more ”stable” and to givethem skills and dispositi<strong>on</strong>s for ec<strong>on</strong>omic participati<strong>on</strong> and moralallegiance (see also Kaestle 1983).A pastoral system of ideas drew together a variety of city schools (e.g.infant, charity, dame, and m<strong>on</strong>itorial), and appropriated variouspedagogies into a system of moral tutelage. For example, m<strong>on</strong>itorialpedagogies unique to cities used ”m<strong>on</strong>itors” instead of ”<strong>teacher</strong>s” because<strong>teacher</strong>s for city populati<strong>on</strong>s were believed to be suspicious and lackingin moral character (see also J<strong>on</strong>es 1990). M<strong>on</strong>itors oversaw predeterminedphysical regimens of precise and standardized routines. Theroutines were thought to instill compliance and punctuality needed forinitiati<strong>on</strong> into ec<strong>on</strong>omic citizenship. Pastoral urbanism appropriatedthe m<strong>on</strong>itorial system to revise the ”urban-ness” of the young intoredeemable souls to include them in moral citizenship.C<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s of the young were tied to rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s of the <strong>teacher</strong>.The ”city” <strong>teacher</strong> was given an evangelical role c<strong>on</strong>sistent with thepastoral visi<strong>on</strong> of the city garden. The new ”normal” school for <strong>teacher</strong>training c<strong>on</strong>structed a moral dimensi<strong>on</strong> of the ”pastoral <strong>teacher</strong>” to c<strong>on</strong>formto standards of female c<strong>on</strong>duct, dress codes, and domestic virtues.She was expected to become the focus of pupils’ attenti<strong>on</strong> and affecti<strong>on</strong>sand to have a refining and moral influence over the development oftheir character (see Murphy 1990).Cosmopolitan urbanism addressed the problem of achieving nati<strong>on</strong>alunity at a time when residents of districts, settlements, and regi<strong>on</strong>sargued for their separate sovereignties. Populati<strong>on</strong>s that maintained aseparateness of identity in the countryside by speaking and practicing”incoherent” languages and cultures ”lacked” moral dispositi<strong>on</strong>s fornati<strong>on</strong>al unity. And residents of southern states who disputed the nati<strong>on</strong>allandscape needed to be ”included” because they ”lacked” allegianceto the republic.”Comm<strong>on</strong>” school movements systematized country schools bycoordinating them with city school timetables and by regulating instructi<strong>on</strong>in language, religi<strong>on</strong>, and nati<strong>on</strong>al identity. Webster’s dicti<strong>on</strong>aries and grammarsdisseminated a unique but standard ”American” English; school textspromoted an interdenominati<strong>on</strong>al Protestantism; and an added curricularcomp<strong>on</strong>ent was the study of nati<strong>on</strong>al geography (Kaestle 1983).199


During the painful dis-embedding of social collective c<strong>on</strong>texts and reembeddingof nati<strong>on</strong>ally nested enclosures, campaigns for the comm<strong>on</strong>school installed a system of supervisory offices at the state, county, andlocal levels. Those who disagreed argued that local parental c<strong>on</strong>trol ofschooling was a fundamental right. Reformers shamed those whoobjected by labeling them as ”provincial” for placing religious or regi<strong>on</strong>alvalues and identities above the ”nati<strong>on</strong>.”To summarize, from the late 1700s to the decades immediatelyfollowing the American Civil War in the 1880s, urbanism and discoursesof the early comm<strong>on</strong> school movement mapped the citizen. Themapping established chains of interacti<strong>on</strong> between the ”local” and the”nati<strong>on</strong>” by solidifying geopolitical ”levels” of state, county, and localsupervisory offices.In the remapping of territory into nati<strong>on</strong>al space, ”problem places”and the included/excluded citizen were c<strong>on</strong>structed at the very momentof their inclusi<strong>on</strong>. Wherever the envisi<strong>on</strong>ed stability and unity ofthe nati<strong>on</strong>al landscape were threatened—by ”unstable” populati<strong>on</strong>s incities or by ”provincialism”—problem places were c<strong>on</strong>structed througha moral and nati<strong>on</strong>alist discourse about identity and its relati<strong>on</strong>s toowning land.Urbanism and the Metaphor of Nati<strong>on</strong> as SocietyIn c<strong>on</strong>trast to the land metaphor of the early 1800s, from the late 1890sto the 1950s, ”society” became the way to imagine the nati<strong>on</strong> state. Theoppositi<strong>on</strong> of urban to rural displaced city and country. A newc<strong>on</strong>ceptualizati<strong>on</strong> of ”urban society” was understood as the loss of ”ruralcommunity.” To address the problems of an urban society, educati<strong>on</strong>discourses campaigned for mass schooling. Mapping of social differencewent into the explicit producti<strong>on</strong> of citizens for an urban society.The C<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of UrbanSociety as the Loss of Rural CommunityThe shift to ”society” can be read in early discourses of sociology thatclaimed ”society” as its domain of study. Sociological reas<strong>on</strong>ing at thetime c<strong>on</strong>flated ”the general c<strong>on</strong>cept of ’society’ with the empiricalphenomen<strong>on</strong> of territorially bounded social practices” of nati<strong>on</strong> states200


(Wagner 1994, p. 30). While c<strong>on</strong>flating ”society” and ”territory” Americansociology from the 1890s to the 1930s c<strong>on</strong>cerned itself with thenature and problems of city life. In 1915, the American Journal ofSociology published an exhaustive research agenda in an article entitled”The City: Suggesti<strong>on</strong>s for the Investigati<strong>on</strong> of Human Behavior in theCity Envir<strong>on</strong>ment.” Sociologists, it was argued, should view the city asa ”laboratory or clinic” for the study of ”society” (Lindner 1996, p. 61.)A reprint in 1925 changed the title from ”City Envir<strong>on</strong>ment” to ”UrbanEnvir<strong>on</strong>ment” in an attempt to give ”urban society” an empiricalgrounding.The idea of ”grounding” enfolded the metaphor of ”land” into a”higher” empirical form. If <strong>on</strong>e wanted to study the distinct ways ofliving in ”society,” <strong>on</strong>e went to the ”city.” When reformers accepted thecity as the ”laboratory or clinic” of society, their investigati<strong>on</strong>s were groundedin geographic locati<strong>on</strong>s that excluded the rural from c<strong>on</strong>ceptualizati<strong>on</strong>s ofsociety. Again, the attempt was to ”see” nati<strong>on</strong>al space in its entirety(including/excluding its ”rural-ness”) through the ”urban.”Even as the oppositi<strong>on</strong> between urban and rural was articulated, bythe late 1880s, new chains of interacti<strong>on</strong> were established through theinventi<strong>on</strong>s of global ”time z<strong>on</strong>es,” coordinated interc<strong>on</strong>tinental railroadtimetables, and the telegraph and teleph<strong>on</strong>e. The percepti<strong>on</strong> held bysociologists, borrowing from the German theorist Georg Simmel, wasthat the influence of cities ”spread” throughout society. Rural areas wereheld in oppositi<strong>on</strong> to the urban but were ultimately subsumed underthe rubric of ”urban society” (Lindner 1996).An urban-rural dichotomy produced and ordered the oppositi<strong>on</strong> of”society” to ”community.” ”Community” came to represent the ”natural”or rural way in which dispositi<strong>on</strong>s for collective cooperati<strong>on</strong> andsocial harm<strong>on</strong>y were instilled in the individual. In c<strong>on</strong>trast, an ”urbansociety” represented a complex way of life in which a ”heterogeneity” ofcivic, occupati<strong>on</strong>al, ethnic, and professi<strong>on</strong>al relati<strong>on</strong>s lead tospecializati<strong>on</strong>, separati<strong>on</strong> and c<strong>on</strong>flict (Savage & Warde 1993; Franklin1986). 3 Social problems (i.e. in cities) were understood as the irretrievable”loss” of a means for ”social c<strong>on</strong>trol” found previously in rural existence.The shift to an urban society as an all-encompassing spatial understandingcan be read as a dis-embedding/re-embedding of social c<strong>on</strong>-201


texts of identity and locati<strong>on</strong>. The urban-rural binary c<strong>on</strong>structed newcategories of inclusi<strong>on</strong>/ exclusi<strong>on</strong>.The pastoral/cosmopolitan image shifted to the ecological. Cosmopolitanand pastoral images of the city-country were enfolded into the metaphorof nati<strong>on</strong> as society. Biological c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s of the ”city” as analogous tothe human body became taken as a model for society as a whole. Ahealthy social body was compared to a healthy city. That is, a healthysocial body had the anatomical structure of the city—its organizati<strong>on</strong>,relati<strong>on</strong>s, and pathological locati<strong>on</strong>s. For instance, Jane Addams (1912)argued that the ”city street” was an unhealthy place for the ”spirit ofyouth” because it provided unregulated intercourse with pleasures foundin dance halls, vulgar theaters, alcohol and cocaine. The pastoral ”veinsand arteries” of cities became sites of social pathology. Social-biologicaldiscourses initiated ”ecological” public health reforms in urban designand city planning by locating deviance and abnormality (Glazer 1984).Social science ”laws” began to be cast in statistical form and reshapedreas<strong>on</strong>ing about reform. ”New kinds of people came to be counted”(Hacking 1991 p. 183). Demographics of ethnicity, occupati<strong>on</strong>, marriage,or age became standardized and differentiated collective c<strong>on</strong>textsfor the individual. The creati<strong>on</strong> of statistical regularities as populati<strong>on</strong>al”groups” cleared social space of ambiguities and related the governingof society to newly defined social identities (Wagner 1994). It becamepossible to map cities (and society), to correlate ”groups” to other socialmeasures (such as ”intelligence” or birth rates), and to make predicti<strong>on</strong>s.A statistics of social difference relocated the citizen in new administrativeidentities that could be policed within the same system of policingcity streets.Just as bodily pathologies were associated with ”alien” organisms andpoor hygiene, social pathologies were associated with the immigrant”slum” or ”settlement district.” New immigrants—from Ireland, Italy,Slovakia, Poland, Turkey, Russia or China—fared the poorestec<strong>on</strong>omically, had to compete for the lowest paying jobs, and werecrowded into housing located next to the foundry, dock, railroad andfactory. They were classified as unskilled or as ”peasant stock” similar tothe itinerant farm wage-laborer and southern ”negro” sharecropper.Eugenics and psychometrics discourses calculated the dangers that new202


immigrants posed to the American ”social body” because the groupsdiluted the ”gene pool” and degenerated intelligence and morality (Kamin1974; Gould 1981). The c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of ”urban-ness” took <strong>on</strong>new and ominous nati<strong>on</strong>al overt<strong>on</strong>es because American ”society” wasbelieved to be most threatened by the unregulated growth andmismanagement of populati<strong>on</strong>s in cities.The ”Burgess Ecological Model” of urban growth emerged as a wayto correlate the biological pathologies of a ”social body” to its”laboratory,” the ”city” (Glazer 1984). The model c<strong>on</strong>ceived of cities asfollowing a general and statistically regular (and therefore ”natural”)pattern of outward growth through c<strong>on</strong>centric z<strong>on</strong>es. The ”wave pattern”of segregati<strong>on</strong>, invasi<strong>on</strong>, c<strong>on</strong>flict, and successi<strong>on</strong> was believed to be a ”natural”process of Americanizati<strong>on</strong>. The model’s narrative went like this:first, groups sorted themselves into segregated neighborhoods; as <strong>on</strong>egroup gained ec<strong>on</strong>omically and invaded another area, it came intoc<strong>on</strong>flict with the group already there; after a certain populati<strong>on</strong>al ”tippoint,” the new group would replace or succeed the old. Until an immigrantgroup had been properly assimilated—researchers found it usuallytook two or three generati<strong>on</strong>s—formal means of social c<strong>on</strong>trol wereneeded.The ecological image of the city explained and justified the immigrant”slum” as an inclusi<strong>on</strong>ary/exclusi<strong>on</strong>ary strategy of internment.The immigrant represented a ”viral” threat: the social body needed tobe protected from invading and virulent organisms by quarantining itsinfected areas, treating the disease, and then waiting for the healthyparts of the social body to absorb them.Technologies of social c<strong>on</strong>trol were legitimated by the ecological model.One method of ”social c<strong>on</strong>trol” enfolded the metaphor of land intomarket discourses. ”Real estate” bankers and developers used an implicit”filter-down” housing model that assumed the poor wouldeventually be able to move up and out of the slum into the betterhousing left behind by the more affluent. Another means of socialc<strong>on</strong>trol regulated movement. ”Restrictive covenants” and z<strong>on</strong>ing lawslisted who could or could not live in an area and were recognized asthe legal use of the police power of a municipality. 4 Although theecological model became a c<strong>on</strong>tested argument about the nature of cities,203


it c<strong>on</strong>tinues to be used to predict real estate value and to decide whogets home-mortgage loans (Palen 1995).At the time, nothing could be discursively further from the ”city”than the ”rural community.” Urbanism c<strong>on</strong>tributed to the developmentof policies for social c<strong>on</strong>trol because it helped to differentiate am<strong>on</strong>gnew immigrant groups. At the turn of the century, a large porti<strong>on</strong> of”rural” populati<strong>on</strong>s were immigrants, but the enclosures of ”ruralcommunities” were believed to give them the ”natural” dispositi<strong>on</strong>s forself-government. ”Young Citizens” leagues were established in rural areasto help the process al<strong>on</strong>g, but educators directed as much c<strong>on</strong>cern tolinking ”lagging” rural school practices to an industrial world. It wasthe presence of immigrants in the cities and urbanizati<strong>on</strong>, however, thatprompted reform movements for mass educati<strong>on</strong> (Gulliford 1984).The problematic of inclusi<strong>on</strong> situated schooling as a means to ”treat”the ”disease” at the ”local” level. The formalizati<strong>on</strong> of the ”comprehensive”high school can be read as a feature of the z<strong>on</strong>ed landscape. During asec<strong>on</strong>d round of ”comm<strong>on</strong>” school reforms, the scaffolding of discoursesof urbanism, professi<strong>on</strong>alism, and human development redefined ”comm<strong>on</strong>”into ”comprehensive” in which individuals were grouped accordingto statistical norms. Stages of ”childhood,” special needs of ”adolescence,”and the ”truant,” ”delinquent,” or ”incorrigible” mapped a new terrain forcurriculum (Baker 1988; Kett 1977). The ”mentally defective” werec<strong>on</strong>fined to the home or county asylum because they were believed to beunfit for an urban society.In relati<strong>on</strong> to the comprehensive high school, the ”local” becamedifferentiated according to degrees of pathology and was brought underprofessi<strong>on</strong>al regulati<strong>on</strong>. The shift occurred by identifying ”healthy” z<strong>on</strong>esof the social body as the top of ”civilized society” (e.g. the occupati<strong>on</strong>aland residential z<strong>on</strong>es of civic leaders, businessmen and professi<strong>on</strong>als)(Tyack 1974). Through a revised spatial reas<strong>on</strong>ing, residents of slumsand segregated neighborhoods were no l<strong>on</strong>ger trusted to exercise theirpolitical privilege to elect school officials. The advent of city-wideelecti<strong>on</strong>s of professi<strong>on</strong>al superintendents displaced previous forms ofcity politics based up<strong>on</strong> neighborhood and ward systems. Defining the”municipality” (legally and administratively) as the indivisible politicalunit was like the American Civil War writ small. The new enclosure of204


the ”municipality” relocalized self-government, over which theprofessi<strong>on</strong>al school superintendent presided.The rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of nati<strong>on</strong>al space into an urban society issignificant to an understanding of schooling as an instrument ofinclusi<strong>on</strong>. The shift to discourses of society redefined problems ofparticular city locati<strong>on</strong>s into nati<strong>on</strong>al terms. The image of an ”urbansociety” represented a nati<strong>on</strong>al developmental trend in which the ”rural”became read as ”backward” and ”out of step” in thought about socialproblems having nati<strong>on</strong>al proporti<strong>on</strong>s (see also Gulliford 1984). Themethods invented to solve problems in cities were extended to the entireterritory of society. Social and educati<strong>on</strong>al policies that ”worked” forthe city school were believed to be equally efficacious when applied tothe rural school (e.g. intelligence testing and the producti<strong>on</strong> of expertknowledges).The larger point is that historical narratives ”forget” that particularcities, such as Chicago, were the testing grounds for generalizedapplicati<strong>on</strong>s of social c<strong>on</strong>trol. An empirically defined and vivisectedAmerican ”society” was born out of an amalgamati<strong>on</strong> of discursivepractices, statistical operati<strong>on</strong>s, and the inventi<strong>on</strong> of new administrativec<strong>on</strong>texts that arose in particular pathologized locati<strong>on</strong>s. The shiftcan be read as a dis-embedding of identity and locati<strong>on</strong> which werethen re-embedded in the space of ”urban society.”Inclusi<strong>on</strong>s/Exclusi<strong>on</strong>s of Social Identity as CitizenshipC<strong>on</strong>cern for citizenship was reflected in the Cardinal Principles ofSec<strong>on</strong>dary Educati<strong>on</strong> (1918). We can read the report as remapping thecitizen into an explicit figure to be p<strong>on</strong>dered and produced. The statedpurpose was to coordinate the sec<strong>on</strong>dary school and the performanceof citizenship with new social instituti<strong>on</strong>s by preparing the individualto take up pre-existing identities.In the report, the curriculum for the ”adolescent” was organized anddifferentiated around ”adult life performances.” A good citizen took <strong>on</strong>”adult” resp<strong>on</strong>sibilities for his family’s health, aspired to a vocati<strong>on</strong>,cooperated with others, engaged in appropriate leisure pursuits, anddeveloped character by assuming pers<strong>on</strong>al initiative and service to hisnati<strong>on</strong>. Good citizenship meant recognizing <strong>on</strong>e’s literal place in so-205


ciety by fulfilling ec<strong>on</strong>omic and moral resp<strong>on</strong>sibilities as a ”member ofneighborhood, town, or city, State, and Nati<strong>on</strong>” (p. 14). A differentiatedand unequal landscape became a legitimate and inviolable order.A curriculum for citizenship had a distinct pedagogy. Taking <strong>on</strong> therole of citizen entailed the acquisiti<strong>on</strong> of ””habits in cooperati<strong>on</strong>,””collective thinking,” and ”collective resp<strong>on</strong>sibility” as ”attitudes andhabits important in a democracy” (p. 15). The citizen not <strong>on</strong>ly has torecognize his social locati<strong>on</strong> but perform it in a prescribed manner.The idea of ”collective” is a discursive strategy of enclosure thatworks to include/exclude. The inclusi<strong>on</strong>ary rhetoric positi<strong>on</strong>s theyoung as ”outside” the space of the reas<strong>on</strong>able citizen. Although youngpeople participated in strikes, boycotts, and disseminati<strong>on</strong> of dissidentliterature in various challenges to the social order, the curricularand pedagogical reorganizati<strong>on</strong> rec<strong>on</strong>structs the young to serve thenati<strong>on</strong> through a circumscribed role as active performers in the”neighborhood” (see Kett 1977; Murphy 1990). Young people’s politicalparticipati<strong>on</strong> was reclassified as ”truant” or ”delinquent” if it wasseen as ”immature” identificati<strong>on</strong> with the wr<strong>on</strong>g people and places.Not <strong>on</strong>ly were the young regarded as too ”immature” to participate,the performance of citizenship, itself, became something to be craftedand schooled into the citizen. Since ”society” could no l<strong>on</strong>ger dependup<strong>on</strong> ”rural communities” to instill the dispositi<strong>on</strong>s for selfgovernment,pedagogical strategies and psychological identities wereinvented to regulate citizenship. The vectors of citizenship were realignedwith the z<strong>on</strong>ing of physical and social inclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong> ofsocietal identities.As the report remapped deficiencies according to the demands ofan urban society, it also remapped the <strong>teacher</strong>. Previously the pastoral<strong>teacher</strong> functi<strong>on</strong>ed to guide moral development through evangelicalaffecti<strong>on</strong> and disciplinary regimens of comportment and recitati<strong>on</strong>.The new c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong> of psychology, professi<strong>on</strong>alism, and administrati<strong>on</strong>laid out a different terrain for the ”<strong>teacher</strong>.” The figure of the”professi<strong>on</strong>al <strong>teacher</strong>” began to redistribute pastoral nurturing intopedagogical specialties that addressed ”needs” of psychologicaldevelopment whereas the professi<strong>on</strong>al <strong>teacher</strong> herself was expected tomaintain a proper ”social distance.”206


No doubt, reformers perceived a change away from a rural to an urbanway of life and sought to harness change to the engines of progress. Itwas an attempt to maintain and z<strong>on</strong>e a nati<strong>on</strong>al landscape by orderingnati<strong>on</strong> as society. As Nikolas Rose (1996a) writes, ”[p]lanned and sociallyorganized mechanisms were to weave a complex web that would bindthe inhabitants of a territory into a single polity, a space of regulatedfreedom” (p. 164). We should not regard the shift in reform discoursesas a reacti<strong>on</strong> to social change as much as change itself: other forms ofpolitical participati<strong>on</strong> and cultural organizati<strong>on</strong> are taken off the mapof the citizen.To summarize, the further normalizati<strong>on</strong> of space combined withthe advent of twentieth century statistics produced new relati<strong>on</strong>sc<strong>on</strong>ceived of as society. Uprooted and displaced social identities werere-embedded in new administrative and psychological mappings.Identificati<strong>on</strong> with <strong>on</strong>e’s background was subsumed by ”American”identity in which standardized social locati<strong>on</strong>s became the collectivec<strong>on</strong>texts for identity and self-governing.Governing a Multicultural Society Through ”Community”:Redefining the Problematic of Inclusi<strong>on</strong>A new urbanism has emerged in current American educati<strong>on</strong>al reformdiscourses of multiculturalism and community. Multicultural discoursesaddress nati<strong>on</strong>al and global changes. Global populati<strong>on</strong>al migrati<strong>on</strong>shave created a racial and cultural diversity for which the schools arebelieved to be an instrument of inclusi<strong>on</strong> (see e.g. Istance 1997).The discursive rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of an ”urban society” into a”multicultural society” rec<strong>on</strong>figures meanings of ”difference,””heterogeneity,” and ”diversity.” Multicultural discourses associate thenew diversity with cities, particularly ”inner cities.” When multiculturaldiscourses use the labels ”urban” or ”inner city” without designatingrace, race is still implied. ”Urban” acts as a shorthand euphemism forpoor ”black” and people of color (see also Lemann 1991).In various studies of demographic shifts in school populati<strong>on</strong>s,c<strong>on</strong>cepts such as ”inner city” and ”isolated rural” have become part ofthe c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of ”urban” as opposed to ”suburban.” Schematically,multicultural, poor, and people of color are discursively located in207


”urban,” ”inner city,” or ”isolated rural” areas. In c<strong>on</strong>trast, m<strong>on</strong>ocultural,white, and middle or upper class populati<strong>on</strong>s are discursivelylocated in the ”suburb” (Haberman 1995; Goodlad 1990; Noordhoff& Kleinfeld 1990; and Weiner 1989).As multicultural discourses overlay the schema of urbanism, issues ofsocial justice and equality are redefined in terms of social class and race.For example, a nati<strong>on</strong>al report <strong>on</strong> diversity and a ”crisis” in educati<strong>on</strong>finds that in the largest school districts, up to seventy percent of publicschool enrollment are children of color. These children ”are more likelyto be poor, hungry, in poor health, and to drop out of school than theirwhite counterparts” (Zeichner 1992, p. 3). In an all-encompassing c<strong>on</strong>trast,<strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong> students are portrayed as ”overwhelmingly white,female, m<strong>on</strong>olingual, from a rural (small town) or suburban communityand . . . come to their <strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong> programs with very limitedinterracial and intercultural experience” (p. 4). The problematic ofinclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong> has shifted.Social discourses of ”society” and ”community” remapped the ”city.” Theshift in problematics is readable in the ways in which the overlay ofurbanism and multiculturalism draws in various discourses of ”society”and ”community.” In a recent overview of the upcoming c<strong>on</strong>ference forthe American Educati<strong>on</strong>al Research Associati<strong>on</strong> (AERA), the scaffoldingof multiple discourses maps a new landscape. The 1998 theme is”Diversity and Citizenship in Multicultural Societies” (Sleeter and Banks1997). I (re)present the overview to highlight the interweaving (andpanicking) discourses of urbanism, multiculturalism, society, andcommunity:Educators in multicultural societies face a new challenge as the gapbetween rich and poor widens. There is a crisis for people of color ininner city communities because jobs have moved to the suburbs.Joblessness and poverty impact the citizenship of the new urban poorby eroding social and cultural life and robbing young people ofdreams. The role of educati<strong>on</strong> is to develop citizens to be politicallyactive in restoring all communities.To think of an ”inner city” as a ”community” would have been impossibleat the beginning of the century. The idea of nati<strong>on</strong> as a multiculturalsociety incorporates and reformulates the previous noti<strong>on</strong> of an urban208


society. Previously, administrative identities were invented to understandan ”urban society” as ”heterogeneous” because the space of social relati<strong>on</strong>swas differentiated into hierarchies of occupati<strong>on</strong>al, civic, instituti<strong>on</strong>al,and demographic groups.The idea of the United States as a ”multicultural society” situates”heterogeneity” <strong>on</strong> a new map of the citizen. In multiple discourses thatrefer to a global c<strong>on</strong>text to address the role of schooling in nati<strong>on</strong> states,social space is redefined. Out of respect for cultural and racial identities,the idea of assimilati<strong>on</strong> is rejected; multiple communities, it is argued,make up a multicultural society rather than a heterogeneous but unitary”social body.” Differences of race, culture, and social class are recast asidentities which are understood as membership in multiple communities.The problematic for inclusi<strong>on</strong> in a multicultural society has become: howdo we reform schooling so that multiple (and c<strong>on</strong>flicting) communitiescan achieve social justice and equality, particularly the inner city community?The Turn to Community:From Societal Identity to Identity as LifestyleA shift to discourses of ”community” engenders a new and salient vocabularyfor thinking about the ”urban” school. For instance, school professi<strong>on</strong>als areexpected to foster ”community” relati<strong>on</strong>s: <strong>teacher</strong>s are to work closely withthe geographic ”community” of the school as well as c<strong>on</strong>sider schools as”learning communities” and their classrooms as settings in which they workto instill a ”sense of community” in their students (see e.g. Annual UrbanC<strong>on</strong>ference 1997).The turn to discourses of ”community” requires a careful reading.Like the previous motifs of the ”local” and ”comm<strong>on</strong>” school, ”community”suggests a separate sphere of aut<strong>on</strong>omy protected from stateinterventi<strong>on</strong> in which individuals participate equally in determining theirlives. Discursively, however, a variety of particular senses of ”community”are used to problematize, analyze, and intervene. A ”sense of community”can c<strong>on</strong>vey Dewey’s sense of shared norms and values to create socialharm<strong>on</strong>y, whereas a sense of ”community activism” can c<strong>on</strong>note challengesto the social order, as in the American Civil Rights movements. The ideaof ”community c<strong>on</strong>trol” can also be used to argue against the patr<strong>on</strong>izingand disabling social instituti<strong>on</strong>s of the welfare state which the previous209


shift to society invented (Cohen 1985).In many ways, the idea of ”local” or ”community c<strong>on</strong>trol” sharessimilarities with the technologies of ”social c<strong>on</strong>trol” at the beginning ofthe century. In the 1960s, ”community activism” was a mobilizati<strong>on</strong> ofparticipati<strong>on</strong> to questi<strong>on</strong> political and social c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>s. Today, in placeof ”society,” ”community” takes <strong>on</strong> a normative functi<strong>on</strong>: citizens in amulticultural society, it is argued, inhabit multiple communities thatmake claims up<strong>on</strong> them, of which they need to be made aware. Theeffort to recuperate ”community” and ”local c<strong>on</strong>trol” from the stateemerges, ir<strong>on</strong>ically, from the expert discourses that c<strong>on</strong>struct communityas a means to govern.Social locati<strong>on</strong>s have become identity as lifestyle. We can think of appealsto the citizen’s participati<strong>on</strong> in ”communities” as a discursive shift thatrelocalizes self-government. The site of ”community,” as Nikolas Roseargues, is a discursive space of new moral relati<strong>on</strong>s in which individualshave obligati<strong>on</strong>s and allegiances to multiple and heterogeneous communities(1996a, 1996b). Community becomes a ”micro point of management” ofa variety of overlapping networks which are no l<strong>on</strong>ger anchored in physicalspace or the ordered space of society. The ”community” becomes a projectof political reflecti<strong>on</strong> which aligns the capacities and aspirati<strong>on</strong>s of thecitizen with the aims of government (Popkewitz 1996).The subject of government is transformed by attaching governmentalidentities directly to the life space and life course of the individual whomust actively reshape his or her social positi<strong>on</strong> in a c<strong>on</strong>stantly movingsocial c<strong>on</strong>text. A new citizenship in neo-liberal discourses implies a”lifestyle” related to individual c<strong>on</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong> patterns and practices ofleisure in which <strong>on</strong>e takes an active role in defining and creating a socialidentity (Wagner 1994). A liberal ethos of choice and self-promoti<strong>on</strong>transforms the qualified citizen into <strong>on</strong>e who takes pers<strong>on</strong>al resp<strong>on</strong>sibilityand initiative in managing <strong>on</strong>e’s social destiny and risks. To do so, thecitizen must be flexible in identifying with multiple communities and,therefore, must be taught the psychological dispositi<strong>on</strong>s and capacitiesfor making reas<strong>on</strong>able choices.210


Urbanism and Lifestyle: Neo-liberalDiscourses of Markets and MulticulturalismEven though discourses of markets and multiculturalism pursue differentideological agendas, they both c<strong>on</strong>tribute to the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> ofcitizenship as lifestyle. In each, the oppositi<strong>on</strong>al space of urbanism servesto distinguish communities and to organize interpretati<strong>on</strong>s and practices.Market discourses mobilize implicit meanings of community as”lifestyle.” The self-governing citizen does not bel<strong>on</strong>g to a cohesivelydefined ”community” but is n<strong>on</strong>etheless empowered through an identityas c<strong>on</strong>sumer to act within a ”local” and private sector. Market discoursesemphasize ”local” school decisi<strong>on</strong>-making and parental involvementin schools (see e.g Powell, et al. 1985). But political choices are redefinedas choices of where to live, to shop, what to eat, where to enroll childrenin schools, or how to manage <strong>on</strong>e’s health (as in a ”healthy lifestyle”).Redefining issues of justice and equality as differences in lifestyleoccludes social inequalities embedded in the American landscape andreinscribes patterns of inclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong> by making normativedistincti<strong>on</strong>s. The ”suburban” lifestyle is an implicit norm that subordinatesthe ”inner city.” For example, Chubb and Moe (1990) argue that”heterogeneous” urban schools have ”troublesome clientele” who areoverburdened by a bureaucracy that doesn’t allow them to choose. Theauthors claim that a more fair and just system of schooling would takeas its model the ”homogeneous” and ”suburban” school in which parentscan act as discerning ”c<strong>on</strong>sumers.” Market discourses assume that eachand all are situated equally to make reas<strong>on</strong>able choices. But, the failureor refusal to choose appropriately or to live <strong>on</strong>e’s life in a way thatdem<strong>on</strong>strates pers<strong>on</strong>al resp<strong>on</strong>sibility and initiative demarcate the newlyincluded/excluded. The excluded are no l<strong>on</strong>ger understood as membersof social groups; they are dispersed into a variety of expert pedagogicalspecialties or are subjected to more invasive strategies of surveillance(see e.g. Murray 1995). The ”new urban poor,” the ”jobless,” and those<strong>on</strong> ”public assistance,” are recast as ”troublesome clients” who need to betaught to live a better lifestyle, to make better use of leisure time, and tomake better c<strong>on</strong>sumer decisi<strong>on</strong>s. Markets, and schools designed to providec<strong>on</strong>sumer products, offer expertise in the neighborhood by renderingpsychological services in job seeking, health educati<strong>on</strong>, or parenting.211


Multicultural discourses make normative distincti<strong>on</strong>s am<strong>on</strong>gcommunities by referring implicitly to lifestyle. We can read the liberalethos in the AERA overview as c<strong>on</strong>structing a citizen who has dreamsand aspirati<strong>on</strong>s. The role of educati<strong>on</strong> is to develop active, involved,goal-oriented citizens whose missi<strong>on</strong>s are to strengthen and c<strong>on</strong>struct”community” collective c<strong>on</strong>texts in which a variety of lifestyles maycoexist.The ”crisis” of ”urban” or ”inner city” schools is understood in termsof demographic predicti<strong>on</strong>s which identify a gap between the ”urban”child and <strong>teacher</strong>. The ”gaps” that positi<strong>on</strong> the ”urban” child and <strong>teacher</strong>are translated into descripti<strong>on</strong>s of their different life courses, life spaces,and lifestyles. A shift occurs from discourses of demographic differenceto a psychological register (Popkewitz, in press). Issues of racism, gender,and social inequalities are transformed into psychological issues ofself-awareness, individual attitudes, and beliefs. The ”urban” child and<strong>teacher</strong> are understood as members of geographical, social and racialgroups, but their group identity is then transformed into oppositi<strong>on</strong>alpsychological biographies.Lifestyle as Psychological Biography: Inclusi<strong>on</strong>s/Exclusi<strong>on</strong>s in the New Pedagogies of CommunityA variety of proposals attempt to locate the ”crisis” throughgeographical metaphors. For example, proposals focus up<strong>on</strong> theprospective <strong>teacher</strong> in efforts to reform <strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong> to addressurban settings rather than the ”suburban or relatively mildly urbanschool” (Goodlad 1990, p. 254). Others argue that if <strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong>is to effectively resp<strong>on</strong>d to the crisis, then orienting the curriculum tothe inner city also applies to the suburbs and rural areas, but not viseversa(see e.g. Weiner 1989). Still others express doubt that <strong>teacher</strong>educati<strong>on</strong> can transform the ”culturally incompetent <strong>teacher</strong> who mightsurvive in a small town or suburb [but] will not last a day in an urbansituati<strong>on</strong> except as a failure or burnout” (Haberman 1995, p. 92, myemphasis). Implicit in the remapping of individual competencies intogeographical ”settings,” ”areas,” or ”situati<strong>on</strong>s” is a binary of differentand oppositi<strong>on</strong>al lifestyle communities.212


To understand the ”urban” child, administrative categories of race andsocial class are remapped by psychological discourses of pers<strong>on</strong>ality,dispositi<strong>on</strong>s, affect, and learning style. The ”urban” child is viewed ashaving ”street-wise intelligence,” ”potential,” and qualities of ”resilience,”but as lacking c<strong>on</strong>fidence, aspirati<strong>on</strong>s, and self-esteem (see the analysisby Popkewitz, in press). An implicit ”suburban” norm is used todistinguish the ”urban” child—not as an individual—but as a memberof a populati<strong>on</strong>al group. Psychological discourses c<strong>on</strong>struct a separateset of curricular and pedagogical guidelines for different racial andcultural rates of development and learning styles (see e.g. Murrell 1993).Moreover, in new ”c<strong>on</strong>structivist” pedagogies—in which learning is moresecurely tied to the goal-oriented, active, and choosing individual—theblame for school failure is shifted even further <strong>on</strong>to the ”urban” child(Popkewitz, in press).Since ”urban” children need a <strong>teacher</strong> who ”cares” and who cannurture the very qualities that disqualify them, the <strong>teacher</strong> isrec<strong>on</strong>structed in discourses of socializati<strong>on</strong> and psychological attitudesand beliefs. Issues of poverty, poor self-esteem, and a lack of aspirati<strong>on</strong>sof the abnormal child are held in oppositi<strong>on</strong> to—if not explained by—the <strong>teacher</strong>’s cultural incompetence and limited experience. Theprospective <strong>teacher</strong> is cast as an unwitting captive of her ”suburban”locati<strong>on</strong>. Her <strong>teacher</strong> training must make her aware that she is ”culturallyinsular,” ”parochial,” ”provincial” and that she has ”limited geographicaspirati<strong>on</strong>s” (Zimpher 1989; Wisneiwski & Ducharme 1989). To remedyher inner deficiencies, she is immersed in the community of the urbanor rural school (Noordhoff & Kleinfeld 1990; Lads<strong>on</strong>-Billings 1994;and Zeichner 1992). The overlay of urbanism with the discursive figureof the professi<strong>on</strong>al <strong>teacher</strong> creates the need for a kind of moral ”baptism”after which she can assume a mobile and professi<strong>on</strong>al identitythat crosses over into internments of pathological communities.The discursive space of urbanism has shifted in which the field ofsymbolic values are reversed. What used to be believed as necessary anduseful has become the problem. For example, the shedding of <strong>on</strong>e’sbackground identity to be an ”American” is now the afflicti<strong>on</strong> (exceptthe <strong>teacher</strong> must still sever her ties to an inadequate background). Also,to have ”street wise intelligence” is a good attribute since the ”urban”213


child cannot be recognized as having a ”normal” intelligence. The reversalof values is significant because they appear to be effecting importantchanges that open the school and make it more democratic for ”urban”children, families and communities. But the structure of the discursivefield has not changed; it reinscribes a pattern by which new categoriesof exclusi<strong>on</strong> can be invented.C<strong>on</strong>cluding CommentsThe analysis of urbanism allows us to ask what effects are particular tothe U.S. and more general questi<strong>on</strong>s about comparative studies andtheir implicati<strong>on</strong>s for social exclusi<strong>on</strong>. In the U.S. the revised field ofsymbolic values in a new urbanism seems to draw a more inclusive mapof the American Citizen. I have argued that inclusi<strong>on</strong>ary reformsstructured by the discursive space of urbanism have drawn differentmaps that historically worked to exclude. The act of locating ”problemplaces” encloses people in the panic of our discourses to save them fromcrisis. We ought to problematize this reas<strong>on</strong>ing, not because the labelsare inaccurate or because implementati<strong>on</strong> has failed. The ways in whichurbanism structures educati<strong>on</strong>al reform re-establishes categories ofexclusi<strong>on</strong> that the discourses supposedly are arguing against.We can note several important reinscripti<strong>on</strong>s in efforts to envisi<strong>on</strong> thespace of the nati<strong>on</strong>. First, inclusi<strong>on</strong>ary rhetoric depends up<strong>on</strong> invoking acollectivity such as ”America” or ”community” as an enclosure that supersedesother identities. Deficiencies are then identified for which the role ofschooling is to invent strategies to include. But the inclusi<strong>on</strong> simultaneouslyworks to exclude in revised normative distincti<strong>on</strong>s. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, the ”city”or ”urban” <strong>teacher</strong> has always been a figure to transform. The new c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong>—ofplacing the ”rural,” ”inner city,” and ”urban” outside thespace of reas<strong>on</strong>—has repositi<strong>on</strong>ed the <strong>teacher</strong>. Multiple discourses weremobilized in the recurrent transformati<strong>on</strong>s of the m<strong>on</strong>itorial, pastoral, andprofessi<strong>on</strong>al <strong>teacher</strong>. The rec<strong>on</strong>structed professi<strong>on</strong>al <strong>teacher</strong> has beenreinserted into an ”inner city community” with new technical knowledgesand competencies to instruct the child in dispositi<strong>on</strong>s, attitudes, and beliefsbelieved to be necessary for social inclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong>.And finally, the oppositi<strong>on</strong>al space of urbanism re-establishes a needto police, investigate, and subject to further rigor the space of the ”ur-214


an” and bring it under new strategies of discipline. The overlay of anew urbanism with discourses of multiculturalism, society, markets,community, and lifestyle reproduces unrecognized exclusi<strong>on</strong>s at the verymoment they seek to include; new exclusi<strong>on</strong>s are inscribed in the Americanlandscape.Urbanism as an oppositi<strong>on</strong>al space relates to comparative studies ofglobalizati<strong>on</strong> and regi<strong>on</strong>alizati<strong>on</strong> that invoke a dichotomy between ”global”and ”local” or ”nati<strong>on</strong>al” and ”local.” An implicit assumpti<strong>on</strong> hasbeen that geographic scale helps us to understand issues of social justiceand equality. The embedding of geographic scale into populati<strong>on</strong>al reas<strong>on</strong>inginvests the state with a sovereign noti<strong>on</strong> of power in which groupsof people wield their power to dominate others. The bigger thegeographic scale over which privileged groups exert c<strong>on</strong>trol, it is assumed,the more power is used and abused.But in the problematic of governmentality, the dichotomy of globallocalobscures the productive side of power in which power is localizable.I draw up<strong>on</strong> an argument by the geographer, Nigel Thrift (1995) toelaborate. To subsume the particular or local under the nati<strong>on</strong>al or globalis a way to exclude. In the case of urbanism, the early metaphor ofnati<strong>on</strong> as land helped c<strong>on</strong>struct both the ”local” and ”nati<strong>on</strong>al” to makegovernment ”at a distance” possible. Images of the city were used tolocate ”nati<strong>on</strong>al” problems by dis-embedding meanings from particularc<strong>on</strong>texts and re-embedding them ”locally” as universal principles.Moreover, the ”nati<strong>on</strong>al” or ”global” mobilizes large scale, theoreticallyencompassing questi<strong>on</strong>s and answers that gloss over the historically singularand particular effects of power that c<strong>on</strong>struct patterns of inclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong>. When discourses shifted to nati<strong>on</strong> as society, the theoreticallyencompassing rubric of ”urban society” mobilized multiple social reformsthat subordinated ”rural” and ”local” issues and excluded socially definedgroups under ”American” identity. The merging of urbanism with currentdiscourses of community relocalizes power but does not destroy it ormake it more equitable.The discursive localizati<strong>on</strong> of power is important to discussi<strong>on</strong>s thatuse oppositi<strong>on</strong>al categories such as the dichotomy of global-local. Global-localdistincti<strong>on</strong>s, such as centralizati<strong>on</strong> versus decentralizati<strong>on</strong>, stateversus civil society, or social ec<strong>on</strong>omies versus markets, are used to frame215


arguments for social reform and can work to reinscribe new forms ofinjustice and inequality. The point is that we can understand issues thatare of ”nati<strong>on</strong>al” or ”global” importance while at the same time recognizethat the dichotomy of global-local does not make all issues of democraticfreedom intelligible. The dichotomy can work, instead, to obscure therecogniti<strong>on</strong> that locally identified governance can be just as effective(and exclusi<strong>on</strong>ary) as nati<strong>on</strong>ally identified governance.The reinscripti<strong>on</strong> of patterns of inclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong> relates to a largerissue in comparative studies of educati<strong>on</strong> that make assumpti<strong>on</strong>s aboutthe relati<strong>on</strong>s of the present to its past and future. Historical relati<strong>on</strong>sare c<strong>on</strong>junctural rather than linear. Past formulati<strong>on</strong>s form a trajectorythat can join at any present moment with newer formulati<strong>on</strong>s. Whetherthe oppositi<strong>on</strong>al space of urbanism will produce similar discursive effectsin the future cannot be predicted and cannot serve, therefore, as a guidefor educati<strong>on</strong>al reform. The analysis of urbanism can serve, however,to reopen the terms of the debate. Recovering unrecognized patterns ofinclusi<strong>on</strong>/exclusi<strong>on</strong> opens up ways of thinking and allows otherpossibilities to be thought.ReferencesAddams, Jane. 1912. The spirit of youth and the city streets. New York: MacmillanCompanyAnders<strong>on</strong>, Benedict. 1991. Imagined communities: reflecti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the origin and spreadof nati<strong>on</strong>alism. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> & New York: Verso.Baker, Bernadette. 1998. Childhood-as-rescue in the emergence and spread of the U.S.public school. In T. Popkewitz & M. Brennan (Eds.), Foucault’s challenge:discourse, knowledge and power in educati<strong>on</strong>, New York: Teachers College Press.Banfield, Edward C. 1970. The unheavenly city: The nature and future of our urbancrisis. Bost<strong>on</strong>, Little, Brown.Becker, Carl. 1932. The Heavenly city of the eighteenth-century philosophers.New Haven: Yale University Press.Cardinal Principles of Sec<strong>on</strong>dary Educati<strong>on</strong>: A report of the commissi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> thereorganizati<strong>on</strong> of sec<strong>on</strong>dary educati<strong>on</strong>, appointed by the Nati<strong>on</strong>al Educati<strong>on</strong>Associati<strong>on</strong>. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Educati<strong>on</strong>, Bulletin, 1918,No. 35. United States Government Printing Office. Washingt<strong>on</strong>: 1937.de Certeau, Michel. 1984. The practice of everyday life. S. Rendall (Trans.). Berkeley,Los Angeles, & L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: University of California Press.Chartier, Roger. 1988. Cultural history: Between practices and representati<strong>on</strong>s. LydiaCochrane (Trans.) Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.216


Chubb, John and Terry Moe. 1990. Politics, markets and America’s schools. Washingt<strong>on</strong>,D.C.: The Brookings Instituti<strong>on</strong>.Davies, Wayne and David Herbert. 1993. Community studies: The societal c<strong>on</strong>text.In Communities within cities: An urban social geography. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: BelhavenPress; New York: Halsted Press, pp. 8-32.Dewey, John. 1916. Democracy and Educati<strong>on</strong>. New York: The Free press.Dumm, Thomas L. 1996. Freedom and space. In Michel Foucault and the politicsof freedom. New York: Sage Publicati<strong>on</strong>s, pp. 29-68.Foucault, Michel. 1984. Space, knowledge, and power. In P. Rabinow (Ed.) The FoucaultReader. New York: Panthe<strong>on</strong> Books, pp. 239-256.——1980. Power/knowledge: Selected interviews and other writings, 1972-1977.C. Gord<strong>on</strong> (Ed.). New York: Panthe<strong>on</strong> Books.Franklin, Barry. 1986. Building the American community: The school curriculumand the search for social c<strong>on</strong>trol. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> & Philadelphia: Falmer Press.Giddens, Anth<strong>on</strong>y. 1990. The c<strong>on</strong>sequences of modernity. Stanford, California:Stanford University Press.Gitlin, Jay. 1992. On the boundaries of empire: c<strong>on</strong>necting the west to its imperial past.In W. Cr<strong>on</strong><strong>on</strong>, G. Miles, and J. Gitlin (Eds.) Under an open sky: RethinkingAmerica’s western past. New York & L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: W.W. Nort<strong>on</strong> & Co., pp. 71-89.Glazer, Nathan. 1984. Note <strong>on</strong> Sociological images of the city. In L. Rodwin & R.Hollister (Eds.). Cities of the mind: Images and themes of the city in the socialsciences. New York & L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Plenum Press, pp. 337-344.Goodlad, John I. 1990. Teachers for our nati<strong>on</strong>’s schools. San Francisco, California:Jossey-Bass Publishers.Gord<strong>on</strong>, Colin. 1991. Governmental rati<strong>on</strong>ality: an introducti<strong>on</strong>. The Foucault effect:Studies in governmentality with two lectures by and an interview with MichelFoucault. University of Chicago Press, pp. 1-52.Gould, Stephen J. 1981. The mismeasure of man. New York & L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: W.W. Nort<strong>on</strong>& Company.Gulliford, Andrew. 1984. America’s Country Schools. Nati<strong>on</strong>al Trust for HistoricPreservati<strong>on</strong>: The Preservati<strong>on</strong> Press.Haberman, Martin. 1995. Star <strong>teacher</strong>s of children in poverty. West Lafayette, Indiana:Kappa Delta Pi.Hacking, Ian. 1991. How should we do the history of statistics? In G. Burchell, C.Gord<strong>on</strong> & P. Miller (Eds.) The Foucault effect: studies in governmentality:with two lectures by and an interview with Michel Foucault. Chicago:University of Chicago Press, pp. 181-196.Istance, David. 1997. Educati<strong>on</strong> and social exclusi<strong>on</strong>. The OECD observer. No. 208,pp. 27-30.J<strong>on</strong>es, Dave. 1990. The genealogy of the urban school<strong>teacher</strong>. In S.J. Ball (Ed.) Foucaultand Educati<strong>on</strong>: Disciplines and Knowledge. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> & New York: Routledge.Kaestle, Carl. 1983. Pillars of the republic: Comm<strong>on</strong> schools and American society,1780-1860. New York: Hill and Wang.Kamin, Le<strong>on</strong>. 1974. The science and politics of IQ. New York: Halsted Press.Kett, Joseph. 1977. Rites of passage: Adolescence in America, 1790 to the present.New York: Basic Books.Kliebard, Herbert. [1986] 1992. The struggle for the American curriculum, 1893-1958.New York and L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge.217


Lads<strong>on</strong>-Billings, Gloria. 1994. The dreamkeepers: successful <strong>teacher</strong>s of African Americanchildren. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass Publishers.Lemann, Nicholas. 1991. The promised land: The great Black migrati<strong>on</strong> and how itchanged America. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Lindner, Rolf. [1990] 1996. Adrian Morris (Trans.) The reportage of urban culture:Robert Park and the Chicago school. Cambridge University Press.Marx, Leo. 1964. Machine in the garden: Technology and the pastoral ideal in America.New York: Oxford University Press.Meinig, D<strong>on</strong>ald W. 1986. The Shaping of America: A geographical perspective <strong>on</strong> 500years of history. Volume 1, Atlantic America, 1492-1800. New Haven andL<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Yale University Press.———1993. The Shaping of America: A geographical perspective <strong>on</strong> 500 years of history.Volume 2, C<strong>on</strong>tinental America, 1800-1867. New Haven and L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: YaleUniversity Press.Mitchell, W. J. Thomas (Ed.) (1994). Landscape and Power. University of Chicago Press.Murphy, Marjorie. 1990. Blackboard uni<strong>on</strong>s: The AFT and the NEA, 1900-1980. Ithaca& L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Cornell University Press.Murray, Matthew. 1995. Correcti<strong>on</strong> at Cabrini-Green: a sociospatial exercise of power.Envir<strong>on</strong>ment and Planning D: Society and Space, Vol. 13, pp. 311-327.Murrell, Peter. 1993. Afrocentric immersi<strong>on</strong>: Academic and pers<strong>on</strong>al development ofAfrican American males in public schools. In T. Perry and J. Fraser (Eds.)Freedom’s plow: Teaching in the multicultural classroom. New York: Routledge.Noordhoff, Karen and Judith Kleinfeld. 1990. Shaping the rhetoric of reflecti<strong>on</strong> formulticultural settings. In R. Clift, W. R. Houst<strong>on</strong>, and M.C. Pugach (Eds.).Encouraging reflective practice in educati<strong>on</strong>: an analysis of issues and programs.New York and L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Teachers College, Columbia University, pp. 163-185.Palen, J. John. 1995. The Suburbs. New York: McGraw-Hill, Inc.Popkewitz, Thomas. S. 1996. The Administrati<strong>on</strong> of freedom: The redemptive culture ofthe educati<strong>on</strong>al sciences. Paper prepared for an internati<strong>on</strong>al seminar <strong>on</strong>educati<strong>on</strong>al policy at The Catholic University, Sao Paulo, Brazil, September 2-3.——(in press). The Struggle for the Soul: [ethnographic analysis of spatial politics in TFA]———(in press). Pedagogical ideas in historical spaces: ”C<strong>on</strong>structivism,” and thegoverning the ”self.”Powell, A. G., E. Farrar and D. Cohen. 1985. The shopping mall highschool: Winnersand losers in the educati<strong>on</strong>al marketplace. Bost<strong>on</strong>: Hought<strong>on</strong> Mifflin.Rose, Nikolas. 1996a. Governing ”advanced” liberal democracies. In A. Barry, T. Osborneand N. Rose (Eds.) Foucault and political reas<strong>on</strong>: liberalism, neo-liberalism andrati<strong>on</strong>alities of government. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 37-64.——1996b. Governing enterprising individuals. Inventing our selves: Psychology, power,and pers<strong>on</strong>hood. New York and Melbourne: Cambridge University Press, pp.150-168.Savage, Mike and Alan Warde. 1993. Urban sociology, capitalism and modernity. NewYork: C<strong>on</strong>tinuum Publishing Company.Sennett, Richard. 1994. Flesh and st<strong>on</strong>e: The body and the city in western civilizati<strong>on</strong>.New York & L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: W.W. Nort<strong>on</strong> & Co.Shefter, Martin. 1984. Images of the city in political science: Communities, administrativeentities, competitive markets, and seats of chaos. In L. Rodwin & R. Hollister(Eds.). Cities of the mind: Images and themes of the city in the social sciences.New York & L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Plenum Press, pp. 337-344.218


Silver, Hilary. 1994/5-6. Social exclusi<strong>on</strong> and social solidarity: Three paradigms.Internati<strong>on</strong>al labour review. Vol. 133, pp. 531-578.Sleeter, Chritine E. and Banks, James A. Annual Meeting 1998. Educati<strong>on</strong>al Researcher.Vol. 26, No. 8, November 1997, p. 37.Thrift, Nigel. 1995. A Hyperactive world. In R.J. Johns<strong>on</strong> (Ed.) Geography and globalchange. Cambridge: Blackwell, pp. 18-35.Toulmin, Stephen. 1990. Cosmopolis: The hidden agenda of modernity. ChicagoUniversity Press.Tyack, David B. 1974. The <strong>on</strong>e best system: a history of American urban educati<strong>on</strong>.Cambridge & L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Harvard University Press.Wagner, Peter. 1994. A sociology of modernity. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> & New York: Routledge.Weiner, Lois. 1989. Asking the right questi<strong>on</strong>s: an analytic framework for reform of urban<strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong>. The urban review. Vol. 21, No. 3, pp. 151-161.Williams, Raym<strong>on</strong>d. 1973. The city and the country. New York: Oxford University Press.Wills, Gary. 1997. The American Adam. New York Review of Books, March 6, pp. 30-34.Wisniewski, Richard, and Edward Ducharme (Eds.) 1989. The professors of teaching:an inquiry. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press.Young, Robert J. 1995. Col<strong>on</strong>ial Desire: hybridity in theory, culture, and race. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> &New York: Routledge.Zeichner, Kenneth. 1992. Educating <strong>teacher</strong>s for cultural diversity. Nati<strong>on</strong>al center forresearch <strong>on</strong> <strong>teacher</strong> learning, NCRTL. Special report, September. Michigan:Michigan State University.Zimpher, Nancy. 1989. The RATE project: A profile of <strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong> students.Journal of <strong>teacher</strong> educati<strong>on</strong>. November-December, pp. 27- 30.Notes1 From de Certeau (1984), pp. 95-96.2 Throughout, the terms ”image” or ”landscape” can be thought of as a ”process by whichsocial and subjective identities are formed” (Mitchell 1994, p. 1). Representati<strong>on</strong>s arediscursive practices that scaffold images and landscapes into systems of ideas and acti<strong>on</strong>s.The imagery imposes itself <strong>on</strong> social and physical reality, and it shapes expectati<strong>on</strong>s andorientati<strong>on</strong>s. The scaffolding c<strong>on</strong>structs and rec<strong>on</strong>structs collective c<strong>on</strong>texts in whichsocial identities are formed.3 The noti<strong>on</strong> of an ”urban society” as heterogeneous is different from late twentieth centuryusages that signify cultural and racial differences in a ”multicultural society.” This pointis taken up in the next secti<strong>on</strong>.4 Restrictive covenants and z<strong>on</strong>ing laws began in New York City in 1916 and weresubsequently adopted by city planners around the country (Palen 1995). As new policies,they exemplify how meanings are dis-embedded and then re-embedded as generalizableprinciples219


220


THEODORA LIGHTFOOTMetaphor, Imagery and theImmigrant as ”Other.”[In recent years we have developed] a new professi<strong>on</strong>al vocabularywhich speaks of the process of exclusi<strong>on</strong>, of marginal populati<strong>on</strong>s,communities and individuals [which] is significant in that it indicatesa revised problematizati<strong>on</strong>... of those who cannot fulfill theirresp<strong>on</strong>sibilities as qualified citizens. They are unable to enterprise theirlives or manage their own risk; the risk they pose, <strong>on</strong> this account, tothemselves and to others, must be managed by experts. Of course thisclassificati<strong>on</strong> can be articulated in very different ways and with differentc<strong>on</strong>sequences, depending up<strong>on</strong> whether it is couched in the language of‘welfare dependency’ from the right, [or] in the language of social injusticefrom the left. But these different articulati<strong>on</strong>s operate with a surprisinglyc<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant picture of the subjects of exclusi<strong>on</strong>. (Nicholas Rose, 1995)In tune with the quote from Nicholas Rose, above, I will be using thispaper to explore the topic of “excluded” groups, or as “others” inc<strong>on</strong>temporary public discourse in the United States. In this case, I willprimarily be looking at the c<strong>on</strong>cept of excluded others in the discourseof educati<strong>on</strong>al reform, by examining the imagery of marginality, andcultural deficit which has accrued to immigrants and other speakers ofEnglish as a sec<strong>on</strong>d language through the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of special languageinstructi<strong>on</strong> programs to serve these groups. In making this argument, Iwill be exploring and undermining a myth comm<strong>on</strong> to educati<strong>on</strong>alreformers— which is that educati<strong>on</strong>al policy makers and advocates canstand apart from the injustices and prejudices of society at large in orderto ”fix” social injustice through the educati<strong>on</strong>al system.Within this mythology, reformers and policy makers can proposestraightforward soluti<strong>on</strong>s to social, ec<strong>on</strong>omic and educati<strong>on</strong>al problems,liberating society’s unfortunates and empowering them to become welleducated,productive citizens.221


In this paper, I will be undermining the myth of the reformer or policymaker as liberator, and replacing it with a more complex and nuanced, butalso darker view of educati<strong>on</strong>al reform, in which policies always representa trade-off. In this view, educati<strong>on</strong>al change always has unexpected andpotentially risky c<strong>on</strong>sequences. While any given reform may potentiallybenefit a certain group in a certain way, it must also be suspected of thepotential to exacerbate power differentials in other ways, perhaps furthermarginalizing a different group, or perhaps by granting certain benefits tothe targeted group, while increasing their difficulties in other ways.This view of reform will not argue against educati<strong>on</strong>al change. As aneducator who has worked for many years with speakers of English as asec<strong>on</strong>d language, I would str<strong>on</strong>gly agree that the educati<strong>on</strong>al system hasnot treated members of this group fairly, and that steps should be takento make their educati<strong>on</strong>al experience less difficult and aversive than ittoo frequently is, at present.However, I do wish to present an argument for undertakingeducati<strong>on</strong>al reforms carefully, and with full awareness of the fact thatany educati<strong>on</strong>al system is embedded in a complex network of powerrelati<strong>on</strong>s, which encompasses not <strong>on</strong>ly students, <strong>teacher</strong>s and citizens,but also educati<strong>on</strong>al researchers, policy makers and reformers, no matterhow c<strong>on</strong>cerned they are with doing good. Knowing that <strong>on</strong>e isworking with complex power networks will not take all of the risk outof educati<strong>on</strong>al reform. However, an awareness of the fact that <strong>on</strong>e isinevitably dealing with risk, and with trade-offs may at least make itpossible to mitigate these dangers while making a desired change.I will be making this argument, then, by examining the languagesurrounding immigrati<strong>on</strong>, educati<strong>on</strong>al reform, and compensatoryeducati<strong>on</strong> in the United States since World War II.I will be arguing that language, and imagery, are integral to the workings ofpower, of inequality and of injustice in society. While some sort of ”reality”undoubtedly exists outside of human experience, as culture-driven beings whoseminds are structured through language, we are unable to experience that realitydirectly. All members of any given society share a number of discursive, orrhetorical devices which bring them together as a cultural and linguistic group.In other words, all members of a society share a number of underlying tropes, orsymbolic c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s expressed through language, which they use, both to make222


sense out of the mass of sensory input which humans are receiving every instant,and to affirm their identity as part of a cohesive social group. These tropes arelargely unc<strong>on</strong>scious, forming an apparently ”neutral” background against whichwe weave the stories of our everyday experience. The color of this ”neutral”background <strong>on</strong>ly becomes evident when compared to the backgrounds framingother cultures and other time periods. (Foucault, 1972)However, since our current society also seems to heavily hierarchical,these underlying tropes which frame our c<strong>on</strong>sciousness also form atightly woven mesh of power relati<strong>on</strong>s. In this outlook, then, languageis inextricably linked to power, and power, at least in a c<strong>on</strong>temporaryWestern c<strong>on</strong>text, is inextricably linked to inequality. Power, andinjustice then, are part of the fabric of our every day experience—ofthe way we speak, that we form our thoughts, that we live our dailylives, and that we understand our own identities and those of theother beings who surround us. In the words of the philosopher SusanBordo:...certain groups and ideologies ...have dominance...[but this dominanceis sustained] not by decree of design from above...but through regulating themost intimate and minute elements of the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of space, time, andembodiment..(Bordo,1993, 26-27)Because language is so important to power relati<strong>on</strong>s, then, not <strong>on</strong>lyficti<strong>on</strong> and poetry, but any text from everyday life can be read as literature.As the literary scholar Edward Said points out, there is no realdistincti<strong>on</strong> between ”objective” writing and literature.We cannot speak of history today, without, for instance, making room in ourstatements about it for [the c<strong>on</strong>cept that] all historical writing is writing anddelivers figural language and representati<strong>on</strong>al tropes, be they in the codes ofmet<strong>on</strong>ymy, metaphor, allegory, or ir<strong>on</strong>y. (Said, 1993, 304)Furthermore, it is crucial to undertake a close reading of the texts of everydaylife, if we wish to begin the process 1 of understanding the power-loadeddiscursive structures, or tropes, which structure our reality. Once we understandthat this level of reality exists we will still not be totally ”free” of it. Infact, it may not be possible to be ”free” of discourse, and to be fully human.However, we can begin to work with, and manipulate this level of reality.In this case, I will be looking at literary imagery, or tropes whichstructure three types of discourse—that of the anti-immigrant right,223


that of the early years of elite oriented post-war bilingual educati<strong>on</strong>,and that of the mass-programs in English as a sec<strong>on</strong>d language andbilingual educati<strong>on</strong> which are directed towards ordinary immigrantfamilies, and which have characterized immigrant educati<strong>on</strong> since themid-1960s. These three discourses have been regarded as radically differentfrom each other. What I wish to show, is that in fact, all threediscourses share the focus and limitati<strong>on</strong>s of a comm<strong>on</strong> discursivestructure, or comm<strong>on</strong> root metaphors. N<strong>on</strong>e of the reforms havemanaged to step out of these discursive structures to do anything radically”different” either for or to immigrant students. Without challengingthese structures, it is unlikely that anything will change radically in thelives of immigrant students or their <strong>teacher</strong>s.Anti-immigrant imageryThe most extreme discourse c<strong>on</strong>cerning immigrants and immigrantstudents is, obviously, that of the anti-immigrant right-wing. As can beexpected in a country which has traditi<strong>on</strong>ally had a high rate of immigrati<strong>on</strong>,there has been a l<strong>on</strong>g history of anti-immigrant voices in theUnited States. In recent years, a number of these anti-immigrant voiceshas coalesced in a relatively coherent discourse, which has framed manypeople’s fears of immigrati<strong>on</strong> in a post-World War II c<strong>on</strong>text. This understandingis framed in a number of salient tropes, or images.A central, unifying theme running through many anti-immigrantstatements, is the idea that immigrants pose an urgent threat to thiscountry because immigrati<strong>on</strong> is ”out of c<strong>on</strong>trol.” This idea, with itspotency increased by a metaphor representing Mexico’s populati<strong>on</strong>increase as a ”hemorrhage” (underscoring the sense of an emergency, ofvital interests at stake, and of life threatening “leakage”) can be seen inthe following quote from the Washingt<strong>on</strong> Times:On the border, with Mexico in various stages of collapse and itspopulati<strong>on</strong> hemorrhaging, things are totally out of c<strong>on</strong>trol. Wholebusinesses have sprung up, producing every type of Social Security card,voting card, green card, driver’s license, and passport.(Geyer, 1986, in Dudley, 199, 163)Also implied in the ”loss of c<strong>on</strong>trol,” seen in the quote above, is a threat tothe sovereignty of the United States, as ”foreigners” take over regulatory224


powers which used to be functi<strong>on</strong>s of the U.S. government. In the citati<strong>on</strong>from the Washingt<strong>on</strong> Times, these powers involve the rights of citizenship,or residency, embodied in official papers such as ”green cards” or passports.In other related strands of discourse, such as Pat Buchanan’s campaignspeeches, the lost powers also include regulati<strong>on</strong>s over trade, or tariffs.Under the overarching image of immigrati<strong>on</strong> as “out of c<strong>on</strong>trol,”which is frequently represented, as above, by tropes referring to thespillage of liquid, (similar verbal imagery abounds, represented in phrasessuch as a “flood of illegal aliens” a “surging tide” of immigrants, or theclaim that irresp<strong>on</strong>sible policymakers have opened the “floodgates” toimmigrati<strong>on</strong>) come a number of sub-images, or sub-themes, referringominously to more specific “dangers,” “risks,” or “losses,” resulting fromthe “out of c<strong>on</strong>trol” immigrati<strong>on</strong> process.One ”danger” often presented in discussi<strong>on</strong>s of immigrati<strong>on</strong> is thatimmigrants will bring crime and social ”pathology” into this country.Immigrants are often rhetorically linked with images of crime anddeviance. This link is dem<strong>on</strong>strated in the following series of excerptsfrom the Immigrati<strong>on</strong> Time Bomb by Palmer Stacy and Wayne Lutt<strong>on</strong>.One of the c<strong>on</strong>sequences of ceasing to enforce sensible immigrati<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>trolshas been the wave of alien-related crime that has struck this country fromcoast to coast. [Despite laws denying entry to criminals] politicians haveallowed thousands of dangerous criminals and perverts to enter ourcountry...As many as 40,000 hardcore [Cuban] criminals and sex deviateswere welcomed by Jimmy Carter with ”an open heart and open arms.”Bullets and knives were so<strong>on</strong> entering the hearts of other Americans.(In Dudley, 1990 91)One important theme, often presented in terminology which explicitlylinks immigrants with other “underclass” groups such as African Americans,and “welfare mothers,” is the idea that this group lacks skills,and thus has a negative impact <strong>on</strong> the ec<strong>on</strong>omy. This negative impacttakes place <strong>on</strong> three levels.First of all, tied in with the idea of immigrati<strong>on</strong> as a toxic andunc<strong>on</strong>trolled “liquid” implied in terms such as “flood,” “leakage,” or“hemorrhage,” is the idea that unskilled immigrants are a predatorygroup which causes a “drain” of ec<strong>on</strong>omic resources, by coming to thiscountry and demanding welfare and expensive social services, which225


they do not “earn” through their tax dollars. This prevalent metaphorcan be seen in the following quote:The news media portray all the “Josés” in our country as hard-working,scared refugees from oppressi<strong>on</strong>. In reality, most of these people are simplyec<strong>on</strong>omic refugees who <strong>on</strong>ly serve to take jobs from American citizens anddrain our welfare and other benefit programs. (Stacy and Lutt<strong>on</strong>, 1988 inDudley, 1990, 149)A similar sentiment, lacking <strong>on</strong>ly the image of a drain, is expressed inthe following quote from a fund-raising letter distributed in 1986 bythe organizati<strong>on</strong> English First.Tragically many immigrants these days...never become productivemembers of society. They remain stuck in a linguistic and ec<strong>on</strong>omicghetto, many living off welfare and costing working Americans milli<strong>on</strong>sof tax dollars every year. [If we d<strong>on</strong>’t take legal steps] we’ll create apermanent underclass of unemployed citizens. And you and your childrenwill have to pick up the tab. (Pratt, 1986 in Crawford, 1996)Sec<strong>on</strong>d, in a strand of rhetoric already familiar from the campaignspeeches of Pat Buchanan, comes the image of immigrants as peoplewho ”steal jobs” from disadvantaged sectors of the U.S. populati<strong>on</strong>.This point was made recently by Jack Miles in the Atlantic M<strong>on</strong>thly.What difference is there between exporting jobs and importing workers?...If there were no Latinos —and no other immigrants— around to doall the work that there is to be d<strong>on</strong>e in Los Angeles, would blacks not behired to do it? I think they would be. Wages might have to be raised. Fricti<strong>on</strong>might be acute for a while. But in the end the work would go looking foravailable workers... The influx of immigrants willing to work l<strong>on</strong>g hoursfor low wages has depressed wages and increased competiti<strong>on</strong> bey<strong>on</strong>d anythingthat [this country has] ever faced. (Miles, 1992, 57)Finally, using imagery tied into the idea of “human capital,” antiimmigrantgroups imply that the presence of immigrant groups,which are presumed to be uneducated and uneducable, in the U.S.ec<strong>on</strong>omy, holds this country back from the type of ec<strong>on</strong>omic”development” which can <strong>on</strong>ly result from an ”educated workforce.”In this picture of development, even educated and professi<strong>on</strong>allyemployed Americans are negatively affected by the presence of ”unskilledimmigrants”, because the collective educati<strong>on</strong>al level of the226


workforce provides the human ”capital” which propels a nati<strong>on</strong>’sec<strong>on</strong>omy forward.In this type of argument, then the educati<strong>on</strong> and other skills of potentialworkers are explicitly compared to m<strong>on</strong>ey, or capital. Within theparameters of the metaphor of human capital, educati<strong>on</strong> is an”investment” or involves some sort of m<strong>on</strong>ey exchange, and the nati<strong>on</strong>is c<strong>on</strong>ceptualized as having a ”bank account” of human skills, whichcan be directly assessed and evaluated in terms of m<strong>on</strong>etary gains, andlosses. This type of imagery is exemplified by the arguments below:The United States is <strong>on</strong>e of several countries competing for thephysical and human capital of immigrants. As compared to two otherpotential host countries— Australia and Canada— the United Statesnow attracts the least skilled immigrants.... The fact that the newimmigrants are less skilled than the old is resp<strong>on</strong>sible for a significantreducti<strong>on</strong> in the potential nati<strong>on</strong>al income of the United States. If thepers<strong>on</strong>s who migrated between 1975 and 1979 had been as skilled asthose who came in the early 1960s, nati<strong>on</strong>al income would be at least$6 billi<strong>on</strong> higher in every single year of the immigrants’ working life.The accumulati<strong>on</strong> of these losses over time, combined with the c<strong>on</strong>tinuingentry of unskilled immigrant flows, implies that the l<strong>on</strong>g-run reducti<strong>on</strong> innati<strong>on</strong>al income and the corresp<strong>on</strong>ding losses in tax revenues may besubstantial. There are large ec<strong>on</strong>omic costs associated with American’s poorperformance in the immigrati<strong>on</strong> market....The fundamental questi<strong>on</strong> facingpolicy makers is whether these costs exceed the benefits of unskilled immigrati<strong>on</strong>.(Borjas, 1990, 20, 22)The next group of images involves the unifying trope of the”melting pot.” In this type of verbal imagery, traditi<strong>on</strong>al U.S, societyis portrayed in some way as being a ”melting pot” in which peopleenter to emerge transformed into a ”typical American. 2 ” This transformati<strong>on</strong>is often compared to a ”sacred trust” or a ”c<strong>on</strong>tract” inwhich people are expected to willingly exchange their old languages,cultures, and habits for the opportunities offered them by the UnitedStates. In c<strong>on</strong>temporary right-wing discourse, current immigrants areportrayed in various ways as ”unmeltable lumps” which cannot be”digested” or as ”tribes.” (Brimelow, 1995) This type of imagery isoften combined with allegati<strong>on</strong>s that the government has ”lost227


c<strong>on</strong>trol,” and that some sort of legal acti<strong>on</strong> is necessary to forceimmigrants to either c<strong>on</strong>form or to stay out.Many of the most visible debates about immigrati<strong>on</strong> and the ”meltingpot” involve language. This c<strong>on</strong>cern with the United States as a linguisticcauldr<strong>on</strong>, in which immigrant languages must be melted away at theborder in order for this country to preserve its unity is reflected in theproliferati<strong>on</strong> of English language amendments being proposed in thiscountry both in many states, and <strong>on</strong> the nati<strong>on</strong>al level through proposedlegislati<strong>on</strong> such as C<strong>on</strong>gressman Toby Roth’s (R-WI) H.R. 739 andPete King’s (R-NY) H.R. 1005, both of which would severely restrictthe rights of speakers of languages other than English to use those languagesin public arenas.Former Senator Warren Huddlest<strong>on</strong> explicitly c<strong>on</strong>trasts the idea ofthe United States as a linguistic ”melting pot” with the idea of thiscountry as a Tower of Babel.The United States is presently at a crucial juncture. We can either c<strong>on</strong>tinuedown the same path we have walked for the last two hundred years, usingthe melting pot philosophy to forge a str<strong>on</strong>g and unified nati<strong>on</strong>, or we cantake the new path that leads in the directi<strong>on</strong> of another Tower of Babel.(Huddlest<strong>on</strong>, 1983, in Crawford, 1992, 117)Some of the arguments for the United States as a linguistic ”meltingpot” ir<strong>on</strong>ically depict linguistic boundaries as a kind of symbolic nati<strong>on</strong>al”border” which must be made impermeable and defended againstalien invasi<strong>on</strong> in the same way that Pat Buchanan has pledged to ”defendthe borders of the United States.” (Buchanan in Welker, 1996)A nati<strong>on</strong> cannot survive if it fails to c<strong>on</strong>trol its borders and adapt auniversal language and culture. There is absolutely no future in Americaunless English language skills are mastered. Any tolerance of the polyglot isat cross-purposes with a harm<strong>on</strong>ious society and can <strong>on</strong>ly lead to a cesspoolof ethnic and social strife. (An<strong>on</strong>ymous letter to the editor, The CapitalTimes, May 23, 1991)Other arguments stress the ”melting” aspect of the ”melting pot”philosophy, and argue that English must be used ”inclusively” to breakimmigrants out of ”linguistic ghettos.” (Pratt in Crawford, 1996) Thissec<strong>on</strong>d argument is used a recent advertisement for the U.S. Englishorganizati<strong>on</strong>.228


I am proud of my heritage. Yet when I emigrated to the United States fromChile in 1965 to study architecture at Columbia University, I knew that tosucceed I had to adopt the language of my new home. As in the past, it iscritical today for new immigrants to learn English as quickly as possible.And that’s so they can benefit from the many ec<strong>on</strong>omic opportunities thatthis country has to offer. ...On the job and in the schools we’re supportingprojects that will ensure that all Americans have the chance to learn thelanguage of equal opportunity. (Mujica, U.S. English, 1994)However, arguments sung the image of the ”melting pot” go bey<strong>on</strong>dlanguage into the broader realm of culture. In these cases, the image ofa ”melting pot” represents the need for a ”core” of comm<strong>on</strong> culturalvalues to ”hold the country together.” Attached to this image is theassumpti<strong>on</strong> that without comm<strong>on</strong> traditi<strong>on</strong>s, comm<strong>on</strong> values, and acomm<strong>on</strong> view of history, the United States will be filled with c<strong>on</strong>flictand ethnic strife. In fact, some writers set the terms ”tribe” or ”tribalism”(with their associati<strong>on</strong>s with ”dark” ”Third World” people) as explicitopposites idea of the ”melting pot” or the ”unified nati<strong>on</strong>.” (Forexample, see Brimelow, 1995) Recent immigrants, then, are ”tribalists”or disruptive forces who bring previously unknown levels of c<strong>on</strong>flictinto a previously peaceful and unified country. These ”disruptive” or”bad” new immigrants are explicitly c<strong>on</strong>trasted with the ”good” oldimmigrants, who made good <strong>on</strong> the ”c<strong>on</strong>tract” they made when immigratingto this country, and subjected themselves to the forces of the”melting pot” or the ”Americanizati<strong>on</strong> process.”In the following quote, Robert Reinhold, a staff writer for the NewYork Times presents a public hearing to discuss the adopti<strong>on</strong> of a set ofhistory textbooks for the state of California as a vivid metaphor the role ofnew (disruptive) ethnic elements in destroying a nati<strong>on</strong>al unity <strong>on</strong>ce createdby a core of (primarily European) values. In this quote, the implicati<strong>on</strong>sthat a raucous and divided public burst suddenly into a ”shouting” matchafter quietly reciting the pledge of allegiance, aptly symbolizes the feelingof c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong> and betrayal felt by many c<strong>on</strong>servatives from ”old” Europeanimmigrant backgrounds when c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ted by demands for cultural pluralismmade by assertive coaliti<strong>on</strong>s of ”new” immigrants. 3As the packed meeting got underway, most people stood for the pledgeof allegiance. Indians, Chinese Americans, blacks, Hispanic Americans,229


Jews, Christians and Muslims all fell silent, placed hands over hearts andint<strong>on</strong>ed ”One nati<strong>on</strong>, under God, indivisible, with liberty and justice forall.” But the raucous hearing that followed was anything but indivisible. Infour and a half hours of shouting, a parade of speakers stepped before themicroph<strong>on</strong>e to denounce the[State of California’s selecti<strong>on</strong> of historybooks.]....If the c<strong>on</strong>cept of the melting pot is outdated, what is to replace it?History, some say, is a kind of property whose owner c<strong>on</strong>trols the future.From that perspective, the future...still bel<strong>on</strong>gs, however tenuously, to theprop<strong>on</strong>ents of traditi<strong>on</strong>al Western values. The current debate suggests,however, that an increasingly polyglot America has yet to come to terms withits diversity. (Reinhold, 1991,26, 27, 52)In c<strong>on</strong>trast, another New York Times staff writer, Richard Bernsteininvokes the image of an older Jewish immigrant from the wave of ”good”or ”assimilable” immigrants of the 1920s, who is puzzled anduncomprehending at the unwillingness of today’s ”new” immigrants tomake the commitment made by his generati<strong>on</strong> to their new country.In his autobiography, ”A Margin of Hope,” the critic Irving Howe,speaking about the ”ethnic” generati<strong>on</strong> of the 1920s and 1930s, recalls hishunger for school as a child of Jewish immigrants growing up in the Br<strong>on</strong>x;for Howe, mastering the English language was a badge of Americanness.”The educati<strong>on</strong>al instituti<strong>on</strong>s of the city were still under the sway of a unifiedculture, that dominant ’Americanism’ which some ethnic subcultures mayhave challenged a little, but which prudence and ambiti<strong>on</strong> persuaded themto submit to. (Bernstein, 1991, 52)Finally, some writers from the right imply that the ”newest wave” ofimmigrants is ”indigestible” or ”unmeltable” (Brimelow, 1995) becausethey different racially from the ”norm” which has traditi<strong>on</strong>ally dominatedthe United States and will thus will never be ”assimilated” into themainstream without altering the country to the point where it isunrecognizable. This idea draws <strong>on</strong> the image of the White, EuropeanAmerican as this country’s archetype, or norm. The writer PeterBrimelow, whose book Alien Nati<strong>on</strong> attracted a great deal of mediaattenti<strong>on</strong> in 1995, uses particularly striking imagery in his portrayal ofthe United States as a White, Anglo-Sax<strong>on</strong> nati<strong>on</strong> 4 . Interestingly, bothBrimelow and his wife are immigrants. Brimelow is from England, andhis wife from Canada. However, by painting a picture of the United230


States as a primarily White nati<strong>on</strong> based <strong>on</strong> Anglo-Sax<strong>on</strong> cultural values,Brimelow is able to portray himself as an insider, fighting to defend thiscountry from an inflow of threatening outsiders, or ”others.” Below hedescribes his infant s<strong>on</strong>, who, as a blue eyed bl<strong>on</strong>d, symbolizes the”traditi<strong>on</strong>al” White male ”American” whose interests are beingthreatened by the growth of the proporti<strong>on</strong> of people of color in thepopulati<strong>on</strong>, primarily through immigrati<strong>on</strong>.My s<strong>on</strong> Alexander, is a white male with blue eyes and bl<strong>on</strong>d hair. He hasnever discriminated against any<strong>on</strong>e in his little life (except, possibly youngwomen visitors whom he suspects of being baby-sitters). But public policynow discriminates against him. The sheer size of the so-called ”protectedclasses” that are now politically favored, such as Hispanics, will be a matterof vital importance as l<strong>on</strong>g as he lives. And their size is basically determinedby immigrati<strong>on</strong>. (Brimelow, 1995, 11)In other parts of his book, Brimelow makes even more explicit hisvisi<strong>on</strong> of a nati<strong>on</strong> as community of ”blood” links, implying that peoplehave comm<strong>on</strong> interests <strong>on</strong>ly when they share ”racial” or ”ethnic” traits.The word ”nati<strong>on</strong>” is derived from the Latin nescare, to be born. Itintrinsically implies a link by blood. A nati<strong>on</strong> in a real sense is an extendedfamily. The merging process by which all nati<strong>on</strong>s are created is not merelycultural, but to a c<strong>on</strong>siderable extent biological.(Brimelow, 1995, 203)In fact, using this type of logic, a White, Anglo Sax<strong>on</strong> immigrant likeBrimelow may see himself as more integrally a part of the UnitedStates than racial ”others” whose families have lived in this countryfor generati<strong>on</strong>s. Here Brimelow’s commentary <strong>on</strong> a story told by theAsian-American R<strong>on</strong>ald Takaki whose family has been in the UnitedStates for generati<strong>on</strong>s dem<strong>on</strong>strates the strength of the archetype ofWhites as ”typical” Americans.[Takaki relates a story in which a White taxi-driver who asks him howl<strong>on</strong>g he has been in this country because he speaks ”excellent English.].Onany reas<strong>on</strong>able scale [Takaki’s] complaint is trivial to the point of paranoia.He, after all is the famous author and tenured professor from theUniversity of California at Berkeley. The white Southerner is, perfectlypolitely, driving the cab. To the extent that there is any c<strong>on</strong>tent to Takaki’scomplaint, it is because he is Asian in a predominantly white society.And there is no cure for that except radically increasing the numbers of231


minorities and breaking down White America’s sense of identity.(Brimelow, 1996, 271-272)In other words, for many members of right-wing, anti-immigrant groups,immigrants are ”others” or ”outsiders” who represent various types of”threats” to the interests of ”insiders” who ”bel<strong>on</strong>g” in this country.These ”threats” are variously represented. They appear as populati<strong>on</strong>al,or demographic ”risks.” They may be portrayed as ec<strong>on</strong>omic problems,such as job loss, increases in the cost of social services, or in diluti<strong>on</strong> ofhuman capital They may be seen in terms of safety as a risk of increased”immigrant crime.” Finally, the threat of immigrati<strong>on</strong> emerges in the specterof a broken and betrayed nati<strong>on</strong>, marked by linguistic and cultural disunity.These examples cited above, of course, are drawn from what canpossibly be seen as a radical fringe discourse. Certainly figures like PatBuchanan, and, to a lesser extent, writers like Peter Brimelow go fartherthan many other Americans in painting a stark picture of a hypotheticalc<strong>on</strong>trast between a presumably unified and productive ”native” populati<strong>on</strong>,a small group of ”benign,” or ”harmless” immigrants like Brimelowhimself, and an unmanageably large group of disruptive, destabilizing,poorly educated, and unproductive immigrants who threaten the nati<strong>on</strong>’sborders, identity and ec<strong>on</strong>omy. What we will see in the followingsecti<strong>on</strong>s, however, is that the image of immigrants as what Rose, in theopening quote, would label as ”excluded others,” goes bey<strong>on</strong>d the radicalright, and, in fact, forms an important core metaphor for the way weform our images of, and plan programs for, immigrant and sec<strong>on</strong>dlanguage students. Like writers such as Brimelow, even many ”progressive”or ”liberal” educators and policy makers, are unable to break away fromthese core images of immigrants being divided into a small group of selfsufficientand benign immigrants who do not need special help, and alarger group of helpless and disenfranchized immigrants who need to bemanaged and transformed if they are not to cause social disrupti<strong>on</strong>, as theyare presumed to be incapable of taking care of themselves.The elite bilingual programs of the 1950sAfter a period of latency due to low rates of immigrati<strong>on</strong> during thedepressi<strong>on</strong> and the World War II years, the 1950s saw a resurgence ofimmigrati<strong>on</strong>. Language educati<strong>on</strong> programs for sec<strong>on</strong>d language speakers232


had been dormant during this period of low immigrati<strong>on</strong>, and thushad to be rec<strong>on</strong>structed new, when significant levels of immigrati<strong>on</strong>resumed after the war. These programs differed from previous languageeducati<strong>on</strong> programs because they were sparked by Federal funding, andmodeled their rati<strong>on</strong>ales <strong>on</strong> the discourse of the funding programsavailable to them.Am<strong>on</strong>g the earliest of these programs were the two-way bilingualeducati<strong>on</strong> programs provided in South Florida for Cuban refugeesfleeing Fidel Castro’s socialist society. As can be expected, many of therefugees coming out of Fidel’s Cuba were society’s elites. Since Cubahad been an ec<strong>on</strong>omically and racially stratified society, those peoplewho had the motivati<strong>on</strong> and the resources to leave Cuba were similarin crucial ways to elite groups in the United States— they were wealthy,highly educated, and largely ”White.” In other words, they were initiallyperceived 5 as fitting the image of Brimelow’s excepti<strong>on</strong>al immigrants,who could come into this country and take <strong>on</strong> its characteristics withoutthreatening either its identity, or its ec<strong>on</strong>omic structure.The early educati<strong>on</strong>al programs designed to serve the needs ofCuban students were drawn from the image of the excepti<strong>on</strong>al, orbenign immigrant. These programs were funded, al<strong>on</strong>g with a numberof other elite programs in math, science, and foreign languages bym<strong>on</strong>ey provided by the Nati<strong>on</strong>al Defense Educati<strong>on</strong> Act (NDEA)which was intended to train future intellectual elites, and operatedunder the slogan of ”Educati<strong>on</strong> for excellence.” (See Kaestle and Smith,1982.)These programs were initially developed then, within the frameworkof what Ruiz (1984) calls a ”language as resource” orientati<strong>on</strong>,based <strong>on</strong> the assumpti<strong>on</strong> that Cuban students could help teach Spanishto their English speaking peers through two-way bilingual educati<strong>on</strong>.Naturally, these programs were largely implemented in upper-incomeneighborhoods, such as Coral Gables, a wealthy Miami suburb.Discussi<strong>on</strong>s of such programs were framed in terms of the immigrantstudents providing valued skills and intellectual resources to their hostcommunities. For example, administrators in <strong>on</strong>e such program in theMiami area, proclaimed, describing the benefits of their bilingual programfor English and Spanish speakers alike, that their graduates would”have skills, abilities and understandings which will greatly extend [their]233


vocati<strong>on</strong>al potential and thus increase [their] usefulness to the community.”(Rojas in Mackey, 1977, 68)However, programs like the two way bilingual schools in South Floridawere to remain limited in scope, not <strong>on</strong>ly because of limited Federalfunding, but, perhaps more importantly, because the discourse beingused to frame the offspring of elite, White Cuban parents did not seemsapplicable to the masses of less educated and darker skinned immigrantscoming in from other countries. The trope of excpti<strong>on</strong>al educati<strong>on</strong> forexcepti<strong>on</strong>al immigrants had its limits, and these limits involved thediscursive exclusi<strong>on</strong> of the majority of low to moderate incomeimmigrants from ethnic backgrounds which were less easily describedas ’White” in mainstream U.S. discourse. This larger group of immigrantswas also pushing for educati<strong>on</strong>al inclusi<strong>on</strong>. However, in order to gainthis inclusi<strong>on</strong>, they had to be subsumed under the rubric of a radicallydifferent discourse—that of ”compensatory educati<strong>on</strong>” for social justice.While this latter discourse gave large numbers of immigrant studentsaccess to funding for special educati<strong>on</strong>al programs, it also drew theminto a discourse of deficit and disenfranchisement which, as we shall seein the next secti<strong>on</strong>, defined them as a populati<strong>on</strong> which was both ”atrisk” and threatening to the social and ec<strong>on</strong>omic stability of the nati<strong>on</strong>as a whole, if they were not ”managed” and ”transformed.” This type ofdiscourse, while more ”compassi<strong>on</strong>ate” than the language of Buchananand Brimelow, nevertheless, carries with it the stigma of immigrants as”excluded others” who need to managed for their own good.Immigrati<strong>on</strong> and educati<strong>on</strong> for social justiceIn the mid 1960s, mainstream discourse shifted rapidly and drasticallyin terms of what appeared to be ”legitimate” social spending foreducati<strong>on</strong>. Educati<strong>on</strong> was <strong>on</strong>e of the top priorities in President Johns<strong>on</strong>’sWar <strong>on</strong> Poverty. (Plunkett,1985, 534) Furthermore, educati<strong>on</strong>al spendingin the mid 1960s was heavily skewed towards language orientedprograms. At this point, even programs like Headstart, which includedlarge numbers of immigrant students but were primarily oriented towardsnative speakers of English had important language comp<strong>on</strong>ents gearedtowards remedying the linguistic ”deficits” of234


children whose mothers are harassed by many obligati<strong>on</strong>s, who spend12 or more hours working in the fields or in some<strong>on</strong>e else’s kitchen [andare not very likely to enjoy the maternal play and verbal interchangewhich children in more fortunate circumstances often know. [This affects]a child’s intelligence...[and c<strong>on</strong>stitutes] a verbal disability of a largepercentage of these children...(U.S. C<strong>on</strong>gress, Subcommittee <strong>on</strong>Employment, Manpower and Poverty, 1969, 52-53)However, the emergence of the word ”disability” in the above quoteshows the beginning of a new set of tropes infusing the language usedto legitimate educati<strong>on</strong>al programs which received the supplementalgovernmental funding (in additi<strong>on</strong> to the budgets provided to localschool boards from property taxes) <strong>on</strong> which many educati<strong>on</strong>al programsfor immigrants had come to defend. These tropes, like the language wesaw calling for anti-immigrant policies, focused <strong>on</strong> the idea of deservingstudents as ”disabled,” ”deficient,” or ”handicapped.”Bringing in another set of imagery, drawn largely from the languagesof human capital, and of social pathology, also seen in the last secti<strong>on</strong>,programs were also able to successfully market themselves, by stressingthe fact that their students were ”at risk” for poor educati<strong>on</strong>al attainment,unemployment or underemployment, and social pathology. Thefollowing quote from a prop<strong>on</strong>ent of increased federal spending for potentialdropouts in the mid-1960s reveals an abundance of this type of imagery.The unyielding persistence of large volume and high rate unemploymentin the face of increasing industrial producti<strong>on</strong> and general ec<strong>on</strong>omic expansi<strong>on</strong>c<strong>on</strong>tributed importantly to popular awareness of malutilizati<strong>on</strong> of humanresources... Even with a booming ec<strong>on</strong>omy and skill shortages, theunemployed, because of their various deficiencies, could not be absorbedinto jobs (233)... The growth of populati<strong>on</strong> and youth reaching labor forceage...c<strong>on</strong>stitutes a major problem for our ec<strong>on</strong>omy...The count of unemployedam<strong>on</strong>g our youth by definiti<strong>on</strong> excludes large numbers of youngsters who areout of school and, though able to work are not even looking for work. It isestimated that perhaps 300,000 or more are in this group. Many of theseyoungsters do not regard work as a desirable goal. Their social values differfrom those of ”respectable” society...Resentment against society and its instituti<strong>on</strong>sis comm<strong>on</strong>place and withdrawal and avoidance are not unusual.(235-236) (Levine, 1971, 233, 235-236)235


In other words, by the mid 1960s ”special” government funding overand above that provided by local school boards was abundant. However,programs billed as ”deserving” of this m<strong>on</strong>ey had to situate themselveswithin a particular discursive space. In other words, instead of educati<strong>on</strong>alprograms promising excellence for students who were perceived ascoming from the mainstream, funding was given preferentially tocompensatory programs, intended to bring ”outsiders” into the system,by changing them in order to make them socially acceptable and selfsufficient.This discourse implied, am<strong>on</strong>g other things, the frequent useof descriptors such as ”handicapped,” ”deficient,” and ”pathological”for participating students. It also brought with it a metaphor of ”humancapital” which made use of terminology from ec<strong>on</strong>omics to justifyeducati<strong>on</strong>al spending as an ”investment” intended to avoid future”problems” and ”expenditures.”Thus Title VII of the Elementary and Sec<strong>on</strong>dary Educati<strong>on</strong> Act passedin 1968 called for special educati<strong>on</strong>al programs for Limited EnglishProficiency students (a term which was first used in this period, andwhich exemplifies the language of deficit which had begun to dominatediscussi<strong>on</strong>s of immigrant students) provided they were both ”poor” and”educati<strong>on</strong>ally disadvantaged because of their inability to speak English.”(In Crawford, 1991, 32, emphasis mine) Title IV of the CivilRights Act stated that ”school districts must take affirmative steps torectify language deficiency in order to open its instructi<strong>on</strong>al programs tothese students.” (In Crawford, 1991, 34, emphasis mine) Finally, theLau decisi<strong>on</strong> of 1974, which represents an important landmark inestablishing the legal obligati<strong>on</strong> of school districts to provide specialinstructi<strong>on</strong> to students who did not speak English, refers to thehandicapping quality of the inability to speak English, and explicitlycompares immigrant children to children who have physical disabilities.Invidious discriminati<strong>on</strong> is not washed away because the able bodiedand the paraplegic are given the same state command to walk. (Hufstederin Crawford, 1991, 36)In the light of this shift in discourse, programs both in English as asec<strong>on</strong>d language and in bilingual educati<strong>on</strong> began to legitimatethemselves in terms of the individual pathologies, the disadvantages,and the ”risks” posed to society and to the ec<strong>on</strong>omy by their students.236


The following quote, from an article published in 1969 promoting anexpansi<strong>on</strong> of English as a sec<strong>on</strong>d language programs in Texas showshow thoroughly this language of pathology and risk had beenincorporated into descripti<strong>on</strong>s of immigrant students by this time.Unemployment and sub-employment in these slums are-much morethan in other areas- a matter of pers<strong>on</strong>al rather than ec<strong>on</strong>omic c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>.No c<strong>on</strong>ceivable increase in the gross nati<strong>on</strong>al product would stir thesebackwaters. The problem is less <strong>on</strong>e of inadequate opportunity than ofinability, under existing c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s, to use opportunity. Unemploymentin these areas is primarily a story of inferior educati<strong>on</strong>, no skills,discriminati<strong>on</strong>, fatherless children, unnecessarily rigid hiring practices andhopelessness. Fundamental to the problem seem to be the linguistic barriersMexican-Americans must fact when c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ting the educati<strong>on</strong>al system,the labor market, and society in general. ...[Lack of proficiency inEnglish is] as much of a handicap socially speaking as a cleft palate, deafness,etc. are in organic or physical terms. This type of handicap can be overcomeby intelligent diagnosis and special instructi<strong>on</strong> directed at the problemfacing the child-that is not understanding or speaking English.(Aparicio and Aparicio, 1969, 263-4, 272)A look at more recent discourse justifying educati<strong>on</strong>al programs forimmigrant or bilingual students shows that the discourse patterns referredto above have not substantially changed since the mid 1960s, except fora few minor shifts in terminology, such as the replacement of termssuch as ”culture of poverty” with other, more modern c<strong>on</strong>cepts such asthe ”underclass.”For example, an article from 1991, arguing for increased educati<strong>on</strong>alfunding for ”Hispanic” students is entitled Winners and LosersCircles....From the discussi<strong>on</strong> which has preceded this, it should beimmediately obvious who the ”losers” are.Being at risk means being diametrically opposed from obtainingacademic excellence...Students are at risk when they have the tendencyto disregard and ultimately drop out of school. Research c<strong>on</strong>ducted<strong>on</strong> students who drop out reveals c<strong>on</strong>sistency in the followingcharacteristics....a)They are frustrated with school; b) they have pooracademic records; they have discipline problems; they have adisadvantaged ec<strong>on</strong>omic and social level; e) they are often members237


of a minority group, particularly Native American, or Black; and f)they posses low aspirati<strong>on</strong>s and inferior self-c<strong>on</strong>cepts....(Cuellar andCuellar, 1991, 116)The authors stress the fact that ”Hispanics” because as a group, theyinclude a high proporti<strong>on</strong> of immigrants, and other ”limited Englishproficiency students are more ”at risk” and thus more pathological thanother racial minorities. Thus low achievement and social pathologyam<strong>on</strong>g immigrants has become racialized.Hispanics, and other groups with language barriers have shown aparticularly lower level of scholastic achievement, even when standardsare already low. Additi<strong>on</strong>ally, the dropout rates of Hispanic studentsare the highest in the nati<strong>on</strong>. (Cuellar and Cuellar, 1991, 116)At each stage in the circle that moves students away from academic excellence,language difficulties exacerbate the cycle. Not <strong>on</strong>ly is language adifficulty in academic tasks, but it also impairs students integrati<strong>on</strong> intothe social c<strong>on</strong>text of the schools....Academic excellence is virtuallyunattainable for language minority students who do not completely masterEnglish. ...(Cuellar and Cuellar, 1991, 129)Finally the authors make a str<strong>on</strong>g plea for funding priorities to be movedfrom other areas into special educati<strong>on</strong>al programs for ”Hispanics,” in orderto avoid the problems they have so vividly depicted.These findings suggest that soluti<strong>on</strong>s to advance students ... are best obtainedin the school itself. This is a relevant issue to c<strong>on</strong>sider in the debate related toeducati<strong>on</strong>al funding, particularly in view of the fiscal crisis overwhelmingeducati<strong>on</strong> in this decade. (Cuellar and Cuellar, 1991, 129)What we can see in the reading of the discourse of compensatoryeducati<strong>on</strong> for immigrants, motivated by a desire for social equality andinclusi<strong>on</strong>, which might initially appear c<strong>on</strong>siderably different from thelanguage of figures like Buchanan and Brimelow, who wish to keepimmigrants and ”racial minorities” outside of society. However, <strong>on</strong> closerexaminati<strong>on</strong> both discourses c<strong>on</strong>struct the majority of immigrants as not<strong>on</strong>ly disenfranchised but also incapable ”others” who must be ”managed,”in the <strong>on</strong>e case, by keeping them out of U.S. society, and in the other case,by managing and transforming, or in other words ”rescuing” them, toremedy their defects, and to mitigate the risk of their inclusi<strong>on</strong> inmainstream society.238


C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>sWhat I hope to have shown here, is that we all, as members ofc<strong>on</strong>temporary U.S. society, are inevitably drawn, by a kind of linguisticgravity, towards a fixed set of verbal or ”literary” tropes, which fix certainparameters <strong>on</strong> the way we perceive the problems of immigrati<strong>on</strong>,educati<strong>on</strong>, and sec<strong>on</strong>d language instructi<strong>on</strong>. All of us tend to divideimmigrants discursively into a very limited group of ”benign elites,”who pose relatively little ”threat” to social and ec<strong>on</strong>omic stability, but atthe same time need relatively few social services, and a much larger andmore ominous group of disenfranchised outsiders, who need to bemanaged, either by excluding them or transforming them, often at greatexpense, to make them ”like us.” It appears to be extremely difficult tobreak out of this paradigm, and envisi<strong>on</strong> immigrant students in a waywhich is free of this binary.However, educati<strong>on</strong>al reforms and educati<strong>on</strong>al programs whichattempt to bring about social inclusi<strong>on</strong> by buying into the ”good immigrant/badimmigrant” binary, also bring with them their own problemsand own risks. First of all, the portrayal of sec<strong>on</strong>d language speakers associally and culturally ”deficient” in order to obtain educati<strong>on</strong>al fundingrisks strengthening the discourse of the right wing, which would like tosee such individuals excluded both from the educati<strong>on</strong>al system, andfrom the nati<strong>on</strong> as a whole. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, the portrayal of a large majority ofsec<strong>on</strong>d language speakers as culturally and educati<strong>on</strong>ally deficient, isbound to have a chilling effect <strong>on</strong> the programs and the materials designedfor them, as well as <strong>on</strong> the expectati<strong>on</strong>s their <strong>teacher</strong>s hold forthem. Undoubtedly these discourses have numerous other effects, whichI, as a member of this culture, and thus of the same discourse communityI am ”reading” in this paper, am not easily capable of perceiving.This paper has, then, raised a problem, of how to plan and implementeducati<strong>on</strong>al policies, given the fact that policy makers, like all othercitizens, are members of a discursive community which entwines all ofus in webs of metaphorically based power inequities. Unlike many otherwriters, I will not propose an easy soluti<strong>on</strong> to this problem. It is myc<strong>on</strong>tenti<strong>on</strong> that this type of problem does not have a simple soluti<strong>on</strong>.In fact, the search for pure and simple answers has caused many of thedifficulties and frustrati<strong>on</strong>s experienced by educati<strong>on</strong>al reformers since239


World War II. I would like, however, to suggest that an understandingof the discursive basis of power inequities, while obviating the type ofblind optimism which characterized many of the reform efforts of the1960s and early 70s, might provide a better l<strong>on</strong>g term strategy forbeginning to unravel, little by little, the metaphorical spider web ofinequity in which we are all entwined.ReferencesBernstein, Richard. (1991, October 14). A War of Words, New York Times SundayMagazine, 34-52.Bordo, Susan. (1993), Unbearable Weight: Feminism, Culture and the Body. Berkeley:University of California Press.Borjas, George. (1990), Friends or Strangers: The Impact of Immigrants <strong>on</strong> the U.S.Ec<strong>on</strong>omu. New York: Basic Books.Bouvier, Le<strong>on</strong>. (1992), Peaceful Invasi<strong>on</strong>s: Immigrati<strong>on</strong> and the Changing America.Lanham, Maryland: University Press of America.Briggs, Vern<strong>on</strong>. (1992), Mass Immigrati<strong>on</strong> and the Nati<strong>on</strong>al Interest. New York: RandomHouse.Brimelow, Peter. (1995), Alien Nati<strong>on</strong>: Comm<strong>on</strong> Sense about America’s Immigrati<strong>on</strong> Disaster.New York: Random House.Crawford, James. (1991), Bilingual Educati<strong>on</strong>: History, Politics, Theory and Practice. LosAngeles: Bilingual Services, Inc.Cuellar, Alfredo and Cuellar, Mariano-Florentino. (1991, Fall), Winners’ and Losers’Circles: C<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s of Social and School Based Factors Affecting StudentAchievement, The Journal of Language Minority Issues, 9.Dudley, William (Ed.) (1990), Immigrati<strong>on</strong>:Opposing Viewpoints. San Diego: GreenhavenPress.Huddlest<strong>on</strong>, Walter. (1992), The Misdirected Policy of Bilingualism. In Crawford, James(Ed.),Language Loyalties: A Sourcebook for the Official EnglishC<strong>on</strong>troversy.Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Levine, Louis. (1971). Implicati<strong>on</strong>s of the Anti-Poverty Program for Educati<strong>on</strong> andEmployment. In Hallberg, Edm<strong>on</strong>d, (Ed,), Guidance for Urban DisadvantagedYouth. Washingt<strong>on</strong> D.C.: American Pers<strong>on</strong>nel and Guidance Associati<strong>on</strong>, 232-243.Reinhold, Robert. (1991, September 29th).Class Struggle, New York TImes SundayMagazine, 26-52.Rose, Nikolas. (1995). The Death of the Social? Re-figuring the TErritoriality ofGovernment, Unpublished Draft Manuscript.Ruiz, Richard. (1984). Orientati<strong>on</strong>s in Language Planning, NABE Journal, 8 (2), 15-34.Said, Edward. (1993). Culture and Imperialism. New York: Vintage Books.240


Notes1It is understood that this is a l<strong>on</strong>g and difficult process which will never be completed, aswe can never be totally c<strong>on</strong>sciously aware of the language which structures our reality.2By this, of course they mean typical of English speakers, of European origin who live inthe United States— not the rest of the Americas.3Ir<strong>on</strong>ically, many of the str<strong>on</strong>gest pleas for cultural and linguistic pluralism are made byAfrican-Americans and ”Hispanic” Americans, neither of which can be c<strong>on</strong>sidered inany sense of the word a ”new” immigrant of ethnic group. However, both groups arerelatively new players in the power game determining the discourse of both popularculture and the culture of schooling.4It would, however, be a mistake to portray Brimelow as an isolated extremist, or as out oftouch with the discourse of the right <strong>on</strong> race. In fact, Brimelow c<strong>on</strong>siders himself, withsome justificati<strong>on</strong> as a relative moderate <strong>on</strong> race compared to many other members of”right-wing” groups. His ideas are explored at length here mainly because his imagery isso vivid and articulately expressed that he provides a particularly striking example of atype of discourse which is, in fact, quite comm<strong>on</strong> in anti-immigrant rhetoric.5Later c<strong>on</strong>flicts over language and identity in South Florida have largely eroded this imageof Cubans as benign immigrants.(See Crawford, 1991.) However, the discourse we areexploring here comes from the learly 1960s, before these latter c<strong>on</strong>flicts had time toerupt.241


C<strong>on</strong>tributorsMary Baumann, University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin, Madis<strong>on</strong>, 225 N.Mills Sheet, Madis<strong>on</strong>, WI 537 06, US.mbaumann@students.wisc.eduLynn Fendler, University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin, Madis<strong>on</strong>, 225 N.Mills Sheet, Madis<strong>on</strong>, WI 537 06, US.lfender@students.wisc.eduDawnene Hammerberg, University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin, Madis<strong>on</strong>, 225 N.Mills Sheet, Madis<strong>on</strong>, WI 537 06, US. ddhammer@students.wisc.eduLisa Henn<strong>on</strong>, University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin, Madis<strong>on</strong>, 225 N.Mills Sheet, Madis<strong>on</strong>, WI 537 06, US.lnhenn<strong>on</strong>@students.wisc.eduSigurd Johanss<strong>on</strong>, Department of educati<strong>on</strong>, S-901 87 <strong>Umeå</strong>, Sweden.sigurd.johanss<strong>on</strong>@pedag.umu.seDory Lightfoot, University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin, Madis<strong>on</strong>, 225 N.Mills Sheet, Madis<strong>on</strong>, WI 537 06, US.tlightfo@students.wisc.eduKent Löfgren, Department of educati<strong>on</strong>, S-901 87 <strong>Umeå</strong>, Sweden.kent.lofgren@pedag.umu.seIngvar Rönnbäck, Department of educati<strong>on</strong>, S-901 87 <strong>Umeå</strong>, Sweden.ingvar.r<strong>on</strong>nback@pedag.umu.seHannah Tavares, University of Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin, Madis<strong>on</strong>, 225 N.Mills Sheet, Madis<strong>on</strong>, WI 537 06, US.htavares@students.wisc.eduEva Åström, Department of educati<strong>on</strong>, S-901 87 <strong>Umeå</strong>, Sweden.eva.astrom@pedag.umu.se242


C<strong>on</strong>tentsSociety - Technology - Educati<strong>on</strong>Dawnene D Hammarberg: Disrupted Assumpti<strong>on</strong>s: Social and HistoricalC<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s of Literacy, Illiteracy, and E-literacySigurd Johanss<strong>on</strong>: Chasm Between CodesKent Löfgren: Teacher Educati<strong>on</strong>, Statistical Methodologies and the C<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>of KnowledgeEva Åström: Computers as Panoptic<strong>on</strong> - The face of the market in an educati<strong>on</strong>alsettingResearch and the Researcher in SocietyLynn Fendler: Making Trouble: Predictability, Agency, and Critical Intellectuals:”All reificati<strong>on</strong> is a forgetting.“Ingvar Rönnbeck: Science and Evaluati<strong>on</strong>: Critical research or instrument fordestructiveness?Gender PerspectivesMary Baumann:Thinking the young woman’s bleeding: early discursiveinvestigati<strong>on</strong> of menarcheHannah Tavares: Poststructural Feminisms and Alter-pedagogical TalesThe C<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of "The Others"Lisa Henn<strong>on</strong>: Spatial Patterns of Inclusi<strong>on</strong>/Exclusi<strong>on</strong>: Governmentality andUrbanism in the USATheodora Lightfoot: Metaphor, Imagery and the Immigrant as ”Other.”C<strong>on</strong>tributorsOrder<str<strong>on</strong>g>M<strong>on</strong>ographs</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> Teacher Educati<strong>on</strong> and Research Vol 1, 2 & Vol 3from the Office for Teacher Educati<strong>on</strong> (lärarutbildningens kansli),<strong>Umeå</strong> University, S-901 87 <strong>Umeå</strong>, Sweden. Prize SEK 65, Vol 1 & 2,SEK 100 Vol 3, (incl. postage)Series editor: Ingrid Nilss<strong>on</strong>THE BOARD OF TEACHER EDUCATION AND RESEARCH, UMEÅ UNIVERSITYUTBILDNINGS- OCH FORSKNINGSNÄMNDEN FÖR LÄRARUTBILDNING I UMEÅPrinted in Sweden ISSN 1104-523X

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!