JeanPaul_Sartre_JeanPaul_Sartre_Basic_Writing

JeanPaul_Sartre_JeanPaul_Sartre_Basic_Writing JeanPaul_Sartre_JeanPaul_Sartre_Basic_Writing

13.07.2015 Views

Phenomenology59consciousness. That there is an objective world available to us is argued tobe an achievement of consciousness. It is the positing and constitution ofthe world that makes knowledge of it possible. If we ask how consciousnessitself is possible, then Husserl’s answer, increasingly from 1913, is thatconsciousness is grounded in the pure ego (reine Ich). The term‘transcendental ego’ (transzendentale Ich) is first used in the ErstePhilosophie and Phanomenologische Psychologie and appears in thesecond volume of Ideas (which Husserl worked on from 1912–28).There are three aspects of this Husserlian picture which Sartre cruciallyrejects: the transcendental ego, the essentialism and the epoché. In TheTranscendence of the Ego (1937) Sartre argues that the existence of thetranscendental ego is inconsistent with the unity of consciousness. Thereis the unity of consciousness, so there is no transcendental ego. The verypostulation of the transcendental ego is phenomenologically illegitimatebecause phenomenology describes only what appears to consciousnessand, as subject of consciousness, no transcendental ego appears toconsciousness.Sartre’s existentialism, including Roquentin’s meditations in Nausea onthe contingency of things being and being what they are, is an implicitrepudiation of Husserl’s essentialism. Husserl grounds what is in necessity,Sartre in contingency.Sartre rejects the phenomenological epoché because it entails thatconscious states may be coherently studied in abstraction from their realobjects in the world. To understand this we need to turn to the phenomenologyof Martin Heidegger (1889–1976).Heidegger’s massive and influential Sein und Zeit (Being and Time)(1927) is an attempt to clarify the question of being (Seinsfrage). The questionof being is not What exists? but What is it for anything to be rather than notbe?, What exactly does it consist in for there to be something rather thannothing?. Heidegger thinks the question of being has been forgotten orrepressed since Plato and Aristotle. It was thought in a pure form, whichshould be recovered, by the pre-socratic philosophers, notably Parmenidesand Heraclitus. However, Heidegger thinks a pre-requisite for the inquiryinto being is an inquiry into the being of the inquirer: the being who iscapable of raising the question of being. Heidegger’s name for one’s ownbeing, or the kind of existence exhibited by human being, is Dasein.

60Jean-Paul Sartre: Basic WritingsThe being of Dasein is being-in-the-world. The hyphenation of thisexpression signals Heidegger’s insistence that being, in and world are notontologically separable. Much of Being and Time is taken up with thedescription of the structures of being-in-the-world. Dasein is the site, orclearing in the forest (Lichtung), where being is disclosed to itself. TheSeinsfrage is not answered in Being and Time, which remained unfinished,but in its closing chapters Heidegger suggests there is a kind of timeprimordial with regard to being: a transition between future and past thatbeing itself presupposes and is constitutive of Dasein.Sartre’s own existential phenomenology is a synthesis of Husserl’s andHeidegger’s thought. Sartre substitutes the Heideggerian structure beingin-the-worldfor the Husserlian epoché. Although Heidegger eschews apsychologistic vocabulary to engage in fundamental ontology, Sartre revivesthe Husserlian emphasis on consciousness but insists that consciousnessis necessarily embedded in the world. It cannot be usefully or coherentlyabstracted from its objects.Two extracts are reproduced below, one from Sketch For a Theory ofEmotions that is accessible, the other from Being and Nothingness which ismore demanding. In the first, Sartre distinguishes phenomenology frompsychology, especially from scientific psychology, which, he feels, cannot inprinciple explain the distinctively human. In his critique of positivism hefreely appropriates the phenomenology of Husserl and the fundamentalontology of Heidegger. Heidegger was uncomfortable with Sartre’s use ofhis thought, and in Sketch For a Theory of Emotions we can see why.Heidegger is called a ‘psychologist’ by Sartre and ‘Dasein’ is rendered‘human reality’. (The standard French translation of Sein und Zeit, L’Etre etle temps, renders ‘Dasein’ as ‘realité humaine’.)Heidegger is at pains to distance himself from the psychologism andepistemology of the Western intellectual tradition and ‘Dasein’ denotes amanner of being that is not captured by the empirical connotations of ‘humanreality’. Nevertheless, Sartre is not concerned with Heideggerian exegesisbut with developing a phenomenology through the particular case of emotion.In the first part of the extract from Being and Nothingness, called ‘ThePhenomenon’, Sartre claims phenomenology’s reduction of what exists tothe appearance of what exists is progress, because it overcomes somedualisms (or binary oppositions) constitutive of philosophical problems:

60Jean-Paul <strong>Sartre</strong>: <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Writing</strong>sThe being of Dasein is being-in-the-world. The hyphenation of thisexpression signals Heidegger’s insistence that being, in and world are notontologically separable. Much of Being and Time is taken up with thedescription of the structures of being-in-the-world. Dasein is the site, orclearing in the forest (Lichtung), where being is disclosed to itself. TheSeinsfrage is not answered in Being and Time, which remained unfinished,but in its closing chapters Heidegger suggests there is a kind of timeprimordial with regard to being: a transition between future and past thatbeing itself presupposes and is constitutive of Dasein.<strong>Sartre</strong>’s own existential phenomenology is a synthesis of Husserl’s andHeidegger’s thought. <strong>Sartre</strong> substitutes the Heideggerian structure beingin-the-worldfor the Husserlian epoché. Although Heidegger eschews apsychologistic vocabulary to engage in fundamental ontology, <strong>Sartre</strong> revivesthe Husserlian emphasis on consciousness but insists that consciousnessis necessarily embedded in the world. It cannot be usefully or coherentlyabstracted from its objects.Two extracts are reproduced below, one from Sketch For a Theory ofEmotions that is accessible, the other from Being and Nothingness which ismore demanding. In the first, <strong>Sartre</strong> distinguishes phenomenology frompsychology, especially from scientific psychology, which, he feels, cannot inprinciple explain the distinctively human. In his critique of positivism hefreely appropriates the phenomenology of Husserl and the fundamentalontology of Heidegger. Heidegger was uncomfortable with <strong>Sartre</strong>’s use ofhis thought, and in Sketch For a Theory of Emotions we can see why.Heidegger is called a ‘psychologist’ by <strong>Sartre</strong> and ‘Dasein’ is rendered‘human reality’. (The standard French translation of Sein und Zeit, L’Etre etle temps, renders ‘Dasein’ as ‘realité humaine’.)Heidegger is at pains to distance himself from the psychologism andepistemology of the Western intellectual tradition and ‘Dasein’ denotes amanner of being that is not captured by the empirical connotations of ‘humanreality’. Nevertheless, <strong>Sartre</strong> is not concerned with Heideggerian exegesisbut with developing a phenomenology through the particular case of emotion.In the first part of the extract from Being and Nothingness, called ‘ThePhenomenon’, <strong>Sartre</strong> claims phenomenology’s reduction of what exists tothe appearance of what exists is progress, because it overcomes somedualisms (or binary oppositions) constitutive of philosophical problems:

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!