JeanPaul_Sartre_JeanPaul_Sartre_Basic_Writing

JeanPaul_Sartre_JeanPaul_Sartre_Basic_Writing JeanPaul_Sartre_JeanPaul_Sartre_Basic_Writing

13.07.2015 Views

Others237my being. This primitive language is not necessarily seduction; we shall see otherforms of it. Moreover we have noted that there is another primitive attitude confrontingthe Other and that the two succeed each other in a circle, each implying the other. Butconversely seduction does not presuppose any earlier form of language; it is thecomplete realization of language. This means that language can be revealed entirely andat one stroke by seduction as a primitive mode of being of expression. Of course bylanguage we mean all the phenomena of expression and not the articulated word, whichis a derived and secondary mode whose appearance can be made the object of anhistorical study. Especially in seduction language does not aim at giving to be knownbut at causing to experience.But in this first attempt to find a fascinating language I proceed blindly since I amguided only by the abstract and empty form of my object-state for the Other. I can noteven conceive what effect my gestures and attitudes will have since they will alwaysbe taken up and founded by a freedom which will surpass them and since they canhave a meaning only if this freedom confers one on them. Thus the “meaning” of myexpressions always escapes me. I never know exactly if I signify what I wish tosignify nor even if I am signifying anything. It would be necessary that at the preciseinstant I should read in the Other what on principle is inconceivable. For lack ofknowing what I actually express for the Other, I constitute my language as an incompletephenomenon of flight outside myself. As soon as I express myself, I can only guess atthe meaning of what I express—i.e., the meaning of what I am—since in this perspectiveto express and to be are one. The Other is always there, present and experienced as theone who gives to language its meaning. Each expression, each gesture, each word is onmy side a concrete proof of the alienating reality of the Other. It is only the psychopathwho can say, someone has stolen my thought”—as in cases of psychoses of influence,for example. 3 The very fact of expression is a stealing of thought since thought needsthe cooperation of an alienating freedom in order to be constituted as an object. Thatis why this first aspect of language—in so far as it is I who employ it for the Other—is sacred. The sacred object is an object which is in the world and which points to atranscendence beyond the world. Language reveals to me the freedom (the transcendence)of the one who listens to me in silence.But at the same moment I remain for the Other a meaningful object— that which Ihave always been. There is no path which departing from my object-state can lead theOther to my transcendence. Attitudes, expressions, and words can only indicate tohim other attitudes, other expressions, and other words. Thus language remains forhim a simple property of a magical object—and this magical object itself. It is an actionat a distance whose effect the Other exactly knows. Thus the word is sacred when I

238Jean-Paul Sartre: Basic Writingsemploy it and magic when the Other hears it. Thus I do not know my language anymore than I know my body for the Other. I can not hear myself speak nor see myselfsmile. The problem of language is exactly parallel to the problem of bodies, and thedescription which is valid in one case is valid in the other.Fascination, however, even if it were to produce a state of being-fascinated in theOther could not by itself succeed in producing love. We can be fascinated by an orator,by an actor, by a tightrope-walker, but this does not mean that we love him. To be surewe can not take our eyes off him, but he is still raised on the ground of the world, andfascination does not posit the fascinating object as the ultimate term of thetranscendence. Quite the contrary, fascination is transcendence. When then will thebeloved become in turn the lover?The answer is easy: when the beloved projects being loved. By himself the Otheras-objectnever has enough strength to produce love. If love has for its ideal theappropriation of the Other qua Other (i.e., as a subjectivity which is looking at anobject) this ideal can be projected only in terms of my encounter with the Other-assubject,not with the Otheras-object. If the Other tries to seduce me by means of hisobject-state, then seduction can bestow upon the Other only the character of a preciousobject “to be possessed.” Seduction will perhaps determine me to risk much toconquer the Other-as-object, but this desire to appropriate an object in the midst ofthe world should not be confused with love. Love therefore can be born in the belovedonly from the proof which he makes of his alienation and his flight toward the Other.Still the beloved, if such is the case, will be transformed into a lover only if he projectsbeing loved; that is, if what he wishes to overcome is not a body but the Other’ssubjectivity as such. In fact the only way that he could conceive to realize thisappropriation is to make himself be loved. Thus it seems that to love is in essence theproject of making oneself be loved. Hence this new contradiction and this new conflict:each of the lovers is entirely the captive of the Other inasmuch as each wishes to makehimself loved by the Other to the exclusion of anyone else; but at the same time eachone demands from the other a love which is not reducible to the “project of beingloved.”What he demands in fact is that the Other without originally seeking to makehimself be loved should have at once a contemplative and affective intuition of hisbeloved as the objective limit of his freedom, as the ineluctable and chosen foundationof his transcendence, as the totality of being and the supreme value. Love thus exactedfrom the other could not ask for anything; it is a pure engagement without reciprocity.Yet this love can not exist except in the form of a demand on the part of the lover.The lover is held captive in a wholly different way. He is the captive of his verydemand since love is the demand to be loved; he is a freedom which wills itself a body

238Jean-Paul <strong>Sartre</strong>: <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Writing</strong>semploy it and magic when the Other hears it. Thus I do not know my language anymore than I know my body for the Other. I can not hear myself speak nor see myselfsmile. The problem of language is exactly parallel to the problem of bodies, and thedescription which is valid in one case is valid in the other.Fascination, however, even if it were to produce a state of being-fascinated in theOther could not by itself succeed in producing love. We can be fascinated by an orator,by an actor, by a tightrope-walker, but this does not mean that we love him. To be surewe can not take our eyes off him, but he is still raised on the ground of the world, andfascination does not posit the fascinating object as the ultimate term of thetranscendence. Quite the contrary, fascination is transcendence. When then will thebeloved become in turn the lover?The answer is easy: when the beloved projects being loved. By himself the Otheras-objectnever has enough strength to produce love. If love has for its ideal theappropriation of the Other qua Other (i.e., as a subjectivity which is looking at anobject) this ideal can be projected only in terms of my encounter with the Other-assubject,not with the Otheras-object. If the Other tries to seduce me by means of hisobject-state, then seduction can bestow upon the Other only the character of a preciousobject “to be possessed.” Seduction will perhaps determine me to risk much toconquer the Other-as-object, but this desire to appropriate an object in the midst ofthe world should not be confused with love. Love therefore can be born in the belovedonly from the proof which he makes of his alienation and his flight toward the Other.Still the beloved, if such is the case, will be transformed into a lover only if he projectsbeing loved; that is, if what he wishes to overcome is not a body but the Other’ssubjectivity as such. In fact the only way that he could conceive to realize thisappropriation is to make himself be loved. Thus it seems that to love is in essence theproject of making oneself be loved. Hence this new contradiction and this new conflict:each of the lovers is entirely the captive of the Other inasmuch as each wishes to makehimself loved by the Other to the exclusion of anyone else; but at the same time eachone demands from the other a love which is not reducible to the “project of beingloved.”What he demands in fact is that the Other without originally seeking to makehimself be loved should have at once a contemplative and affective intuition of hisbeloved as the objective limit of his freedom, as the ineluctable and chosen foundationof his transcendence, as the totality of being and the supreme value. Love thus exactedfrom the other could not ask for anything; it is a pure engagement without reciprocity.Yet this love can not exist except in the form of a demand on the part of the lover.The lover is held captive in a wholly different way. He is the captive of his verydemand since love is the demand to be loved; he is a freedom which wills itself a body

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!