General Information - Florida State University College of Law

General Information - Florida State University College of Law General Information - Florida State University College of Law

03.12.2012 Views

FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW VOLUME 37 SUMMER 2010 NUMBER 4 TABLE OF CONTENTS DISTINGUISHED SCHOLAR SERIES FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD: AN ECONOMIC AND TAX ANALYSIS.................................... David Hasen 789 ARTICLES METHADEMIC:DRUG PANIC IN AN AGE OF AMBIVALENCE ......................................................... Deborah Ahrens 841 PEARSON, IQBAL, AND PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM.......................................................Goutam U. Jois 901 KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET ................................. Erik S. Knutsen 945 NOTES AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET: THE NEXT REVOLUTION .................................................... Alvan Balent 981 BUSINESS INSURANCE:FIRST-PARTY COMMERCIAL PROPERTY INSURANCE AND THE PHYSICAL DAMAGE REQUIREMENT IN A COMPUTER-DOMINATED WORLD ...................................... Amy R. Willis 1003

FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

VOLUME 37 SUMMER 2010 NUMBER 4<br />

TABLE OF CONTENTS<br />

DISTINGUISHED SCHOLAR SERIES<br />

FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD:<br />

AN ECONOMIC AND TAX ANALYSIS.................................... David Hasen 789<br />

ARTICLES<br />

METHADEMIC:DRUG PANIC IN AN AGE<br />

OF AMBIVALENCE ......................................................... Deborah Ahrens 841<br />

PEARSON, IQBAL, AND PROCEDURAL<br />

JUDICIAL ACTIVISM.......................................................Goutam U. Jois 901<br />

KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET ................................. Erik S. Knutsen 945<br />

NOTES<br />

AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET:<br />

THE NEXT REVOLUTION .................................................... Alvan Balent 981<br />

BUSINESS INSURANCE:FIRST-PARTY<br />

COMMERCIAL PROPERTY INSURANCE AND THE<br />

PHYSICAL DAMAGE REQUIREMENT IN A<br />

COMPUTER-DOMINATED WORLD ...................................... Amy R. Willis 1003


The Ausley House: Home <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>Law</strong> Review<br />

<strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong><br />

<strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong><br />

The <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> is fully approved by<br />

the American Bar Association and is a member <strong>of</strong> the Association <strong>of</strong><br />

American <strong>Law</strong> Schools. The <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong>fers a three-year course <strong>of</strong> study<br />

leading to the Juris Doctor degree with certificate programs in international<br />

and environmental law. Furthermore, a Master <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong>s degree<br />

(LL.M.) in American <strong>Law</strong> for Foreign <strong>Law</strong>yers is available for foreign<br />

graduate students who have legal training.<br />

The <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> has approximately 700 students. Its research<br />

center contains nearly 518,000 volumes and 3,600 current subscriptions.<br />

Educational opportunities are plentiful. The location <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>College</strong>—only blocks from the Capitol, the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> <strong>Florida</strong>, a<br />

number <strong>of</strong> federal and state courts, and various administrative<br />

agencies—makes extensive externship programs possible. Students<br />

publish the <strong>Law</strong> Review, the Journal <strong>of</strong> Land Use & Environmental<br />

<strong>Law</strong>, and the Journal <strong>of</strong> Transnational <strong>Law</strong> & Policy. Moot Court and<br />

Mock Trial teams have won national honors. Each summer, the <strong>College</strong><br />

conducts a nationally recognized program at Oxford <strong>University</strong>, England.<br />

These resources support the goal Dean Mason Ladd identified<br />

when the <strong>College</strong> was founded in 1966: “Its one aim is excellence in the<br />

preparation and education <strong>of</strong> students so that they will acquire the<br />

knowledge, comprehension, and judgment essential to the performance<br />

<strong>of</strong> legal services in a complex and rapidly changing society.”<br />

ii


FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF LAW<br />

ADMINISTRATION<br />

ERIC J. BARRON, B.S., M.S., PH.D., President <strong>of</strong> the <strong>University</strong><br />

LAWRENCE G. ABELE, B.S., M.S., PH.D., Provost and Vice President for Academic Affairs<br />

DONALD J. WEIDNER, B.S., J.D., Dean and Alumni Centennial Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

WAYNE A. LOGAN, B.A., M.A., J.D., Gary & Sallyn Pajcic Pr<strong>of</strong>essor and Associate Dean for<br />

Academic Affairs<br />

DONNA R. CHRISTIE, B.S., J.D., Elizabeth C. & Clyde W. Atkinson Pr<strong>of</strong>essor and Associate Dean<br />

for International Programs<br />

JIM ROSSI, B.S., J.D., LL.M., Harry M. Walborsky Pr<strong>of</strong>essor and Associate Dean for Research<br />

ROBIN KUNDIS CRAIG, B.A., M.A., PH.D., J.D., Attorneys’ Title Pr<strong>of</strong>essor and Associate Dean for<br />

Environmental Programs<br />

NANCY L. BENAVIDES, B.S., J.D., Associate Dean for Student Affairs<br />

ROSANNA CATALANO, B.S. J.D., Assistant Dean for Administration<br />

MARK PANKEY, B.B.A., M.S., Associate Vice President for Development<br />

JANEIA DANIELS, B.S., J.D., Assistant Dean for Student Affairs<br />

FACULTY<br />

FREDERICK M. ABBOTT, B.A., J.D., LL.M., Edward Ball Eminent Scholar<br />

KELLI A. ALCES, B.A., J.D., Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

PAOLO ANNINO, B.A., M.A., J.D., PH.D., Clinical Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

ROBERT E. ATKINSON, B.A., J.D., Ruden, McClosky, Smith, Schuster & Russell Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

BARBARA ANN BANOFF, B.A., J.D., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

SHAWN J. BAYERN, B.S., J.D., Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

TAMARA G. BLENKHORN, B.A., J.D., Legal Writing Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

CURTIS BRIDGEMAN, B.A., M.A., PH.D., J.D., James Edmund & Margaret Elizabeth Hennessey<br />

Corry Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

ELIZABETH CHAMBLEE BURCH, B.A., J.D., Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

THOMAS V. BURCH, B.B.A., B.A., J.D., Legal Writing Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

DONNA R. CHRISTIE, B.S., J.D., Elizabeth C. & Clyde W. Atkinson Pr<strong>of</strong>essor and Associate Dean<br />

for International Programs<br />

NEIL P. COHEN, B.A., J.D., LL.M., Visiting Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

ROBIN KUNDIS CRAIG, B.A., M.A., PH.D., J.D., Attorneys’ Title Pr<strong>of</strong>essor and Associate Dean for<br />

Environmental Programs<br />

JEANNE B. CURTIN, B.S., M.B.A., J.D., Legal Writing Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

TALBOT D’ALEMBERTE, B.A., J.D., President Emeritus and Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

JOSEPH M. DODGE, B.A., LL.B., LL.M., Stearns Weaver Miller Weissler Alhadeff &<br />

Sitterson Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

DINO FALASCHETTI, B.S., M.B.A., A.M., PH.D., Associate Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> and Economics<br />

BRIAN D. GALLE, A.B., J.D., LL.M., Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

SALLY C. GERTZ, B.A., J.D., Clinical Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

STEVEN G. GEY, B.A., J.D., David & Deborah Fonvielle and Donald & Janet Hinkle Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

ELWIN J. GRIFFITH, B.A., J.D., LL.M., Tallahassee Alumni Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

TARA LEIGH GROVE, B.A., J.D., Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

ADAM J. HIRSCH, A.B., M.A., M.PHIL., J.D., PH.D., William & Catherine VanDercreek Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

FAYE E. JONES, B.A., M.S., J.D., Director <strong>of</strong> Research Center and Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

LAWRENCE S. KRIEGER, A.B., J.D., Clinical Pr<strong>of</strong>essor and Director <strong>of</strong> Clinical Externship Programs<br />

JENNIFER P. LAVIA, A.B., J.D., Legal Writing Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

TAHIRIH V. LEE, A.B., A.M., M.A., M.PHIL., J.D., PH.D., Associate Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

WAYNE A. LOGAN, B.A., M.A., J.D., Gary & Sallyn Pajcic Pr<strong>of</strong>essor and Associate Dean for<br />

Academic Affairs<br />

SCOTT D. MAKAR, B.S., M.B.A., J.D., PH.D., Richard W. Ervin Visiting Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

DAN MARKEL, A.B., M.PHIL., J.D., D’Alemberte Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

DAVID L. MARKELL, B.A., J.D., Steven M. Goldstein Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

TRICIA ANN MATTHEWS, B.A., M.A., J.D., Legal Writing Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

UMA OUTKA, B.A., M.A., J.D., Visiting Scholar<br />

GREGG D. POLSKY, B.A., J.D., LL.M., Sheila M. McDevitt Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

AMELIA RINEHART, B.S.E., M.S.E., J.D., Visiting Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

iii


JIM ROSSI, B.S., J.D., LL.M., Harry M. Walborsky Pr<strong>of</strong>essor and Associate Dean for Research<br />

J. B. RUHL, B.A., PH.D., J.D., LL.M., Matthews & Hawkins Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Property<br />

MARK B. SEIDENFELD, B.A., M.A., J.D., Patricia A. Dore Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Administrative <strong>Law</strong><br />

NAT S. STERN, A.B., J.D., John W. & Ashley E. Frost Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

RUTH E. STONE, B.S., J.D., Clinical Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

CHARLEE MORGAN TAYLOR, B.A., J.D., Legal Writing Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

FERNANDO R. TESÓN, J.D., LL.M., S.J.D., Tobias Simon Eminent Scholar<br />

FRANITA TOLSON, B.A./B.S., J.D., Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

MANUEL ANTONIO UTSET,JR., B.S., J.D., Charles W. Ehrhardt Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

DONALD J. WEIDNER, B.S., J.D., Dean and Alumni Centennial Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

LESLEY WEXLER, B.A., J.D., Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

JOLEN RAWLS WOLF, B.A., J.D., Legal Writing Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

RESEARCH CENTER STAFF<br />

FAYE E. JONES, B.A., M.S., J.D., Director <strong>of</strong> Research Center and Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

ROBIN R. GAULT, B.A., M.S., PH.D., J.D., Associate Director<br />

MARY M. MCCORMICK, B.A., M.L.I.S., J.D., Assistant Director for Public Services<br />

MARGARET C. CLARK, B.A., M.A., Research Librarian<br />

MARIN DELL, B.S., J.D., M.S., Research Librarian<br />

ELIZABETH FARRELL, B.S., J.D., M.S., Research/Instructional Technology Librarian<br />

ANNE D. BARDOLPH, B.A., M.S., Assistant Director for Acquisitions<br />

PATRICIA BINGHAM-HARPER, B.A., B.M., M.S., M.M., Assistant Director for Cataloging<br />

PATRICIA K. SIMONDS, B.S., M.S., Assistant Director for Interlibrary Loan/Serials<br />

JON R. LUTZ, B.A., M.A., M.S., Assistant Director for Electronic Services<br />

EMERITUS FACULTY<br />

DAVID F. DICKSON, A.B., LL.B., M.S., PH.D., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

CHARLES W. EHRHARDT, B.S., J.D., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

ROBERT H. KENNEDY, B.A., LL.B., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

JOHN W. LARSON, A.B., J.D., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

JOSHUA M. MORSE, III, J.D., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

JARRET C. OELTJEN, B.A., J.D., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

DAVID F. POWELL, B.B.A., J.D., LL.M., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

EDWIN M. SCHROEDER,PH.B., M.S., J.D., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

HAROLD P. SOUTHERLAND, B.S., J.D., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

JOHN W. VAN DOREN, A.B., LL.B., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

WILLIAM VANDERCREEK, B.S., J.D., LL.M., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

JOHN K. VINSON, B.A., J.D., LL.M., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

JOHN F. YETTER, B.S., J.D., LL.M., Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Emeritus<br />

iv


FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY<br />

LAW REVIEW ALUMNI ASSOCIATION<br />

EDITOR’S COUNSEL<br />

DUBOSE AUSLEY<br />

JOANN BLACKWELL<br />

ENRICO GONZALEZ<br />

ED SCHROEDER<br />

LOU WRIGHT<br />

BENEFACTORS<br />

JOHN S. FAGAN<br />

SPONSORS<br />

ILEANA A. CRUZ-BONGINI JASON B. DUBOW<br />

KAREN L. ASHER COHEN<br />

MICHAEL P. BRUYERE<br />

THOMAS V. BURCH<br />

ROBERT S. COHEN<br />

AMY L. COMER<br />

DAVID M. JEFFRIES<br />

ERIC J. KAIDANOW<br />

MATTHEW R. BERNIER<br />

CHRISTOPHER F. BUSCH<br />

MICHAEL A. CAMPBELL<br />

JASON S. FEDER<br />

GARRETT J. HARPER<br />

ALVAN BALENT<br />

TERIN M. BARBAS<br />

ROBERT F. KOHLMAN<br />

PATRONS<br />

CHET KAUFMAN<br />

ALYSSA S. LATHROP<br />

BRUCE A. LEINBACK<br />

REBECCA J. MERCIER-<br />

VARGAS<br />

JEANNE M. MILLER<br />

TRAVIS L. MILLER<br />

DANIEL L. MONROE<br />

MEMBERS<br />

MALINDA L. HAYES<br />

BRETT J. HOROWITZ<br />

CHRISTOPHER S. LINDE<br />

PETER R. MARKSTEINER<br />

DEBORAH J. MEYER<br />

STEVEN D. MUSCATELLO<br />

ASSOCIATE MEMBERS<br />

MATTHEW L. BEVILLE<br />

NORMAN A. BURKETT<br />

v<br />

PATRICK J. RENGSTL<br />

MARVIN P. PASTEL<br />

LINDA SCHMIDT<br />

STEPHEN R. SENN<br />

JENNIFER L. SHELFER<br />

MICHAEL A. SJUGGERUD<br />

LESLEI G. STREET<br />

ROBERTO M. VARGAS<br />

NOAH H. NADLER<br />

RACHEL E. NORDBY<br />

DANIEL C. NORRIS<br />

SARAH E. SPECTOR<br />

MICHAEL L. WENGER<br />

JACOB T. CREMER


The <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>Law</strong> Review is produced four times<br />

per year at the <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong>, Tallahassee, FL 32306-1601. Periodicals<br />

postage paid at Tallahassee, <strong>Florida</strong>, and at additional mailing<br />

<strong>of</strong>fices. United <strong>State</strong>s Postal Service Publication Number 991780.<br />

ISSN 0096-3070. POSTMASTER: Send address corrections to <strong>Florida</strong><br />

<strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong>, <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong>, <strong>Law</strong> Review, Tallahassee, FL<br />

32306-1601.<br />

Student activity fees allocated by the <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong><br />

Student Government Association and Congress <strong>of</strong> Graduate<br />

Students provide a portion <strong>of</strong> the funding for the <strong>Law</strong> Review.<br />

The views expressed in published material are those <strong>of</strong> the authors<br />

and do not necessarily reflect the policies or opinions <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Law</strong> Review,<br />

its editors and staff, or the <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong>. We welcome<br />

and will consider for publication letters to the Editor about<br />

work appearing in the <strong>Law</strong> Review.<br />

Copyright © 2010 by the <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>Law</strong> Review<br />

Member, National Conference <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> Reviews<br />

The <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>Law</strong> Review hereby grants permission<br />

for copies <strong>of</strong> all articles on which it holds the copyright to be<br />

made and used by nonpr<strong>of</strong>it educational institutions, provided that<br />

copies are distributed at or below cost, the author and journal are<br />

identified, and proper notice is affixed to each copy. All other rights<br />

are reserved.<br />

The <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>Law</strong> Review thanks Reed Elsevier<br />

for the donation <strong>of</strong> LEXIS research services and West Group for the<br />

donation <strong>of</strong> WESTLAW research services.<br />

vi


FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

VOLUME 37 SUMMER 2010 NUMBER 4<br />

ANDREW GROGAN<br />

Executive Editor<br />

NANCY A. PINZINO<br />

Executive Editor<br />

BRANDON W. WHITE<br />

Managing Editor<br />

HOLLY GRIFFIN<br />

NATHAN HILL<br />

LAURA MCDONALD<br />

TIFFANY RODDENBERRY<br />

Notes & Comments Editors<br />

MATTHEW J. ALLMAN<br />

ALVAN BALENT JR.<br />

TERIN M. BARBAS<br />

BRIAN BOHM<br />

DAVID BOYER<br />

CHRISTOPHER BUSCH<br />

T. BROOKS COLLINS<br />

JACOB T. CREMER<br />

JACQUELINE DAVISON<br />

MATTHEW DEVINE<br />

PATRICK FLEMMING<br />

KEVIN FORSTHOEFEL<br />

JESSICA GALLEGOS<br />

JOHN "EVAN"GIBBS<br />

CHRISTIN F. GONZALEZ<br />

LAWTON GRAVES<br />

EDITORIAL BOARD<br />

AMANDA L. SWINDLE<br />

Editor in Chief<br />

MATTHEW LEE EVANS<br />

TRUMON PHILLIPS<br />

JONATHAN PICARD<br />

MIRIAM SOWINSKI<br />

Associate Editors<br />

MEMBERS<br />

JUSTIN R. INFURNA<br />

REBECCA LEEAN JOHNS<br />

BENJAMIN R. KELLEY<br />

MELANIE R. LEITMAN<br />

FERRELL MAGUIRE<br />

SARA MASON<br />

JON HARRIS MAURER<br />

DONALD MCGRAW<br />

HANNAH MONROE<br />

STEVEN D. MUSCATELLO<br />

YORDANKA NEDYALKOVA<br />

STEFANI CARINA NORRBIN<br />

GLADYS ANDREA ORTEGA<br />

ZACHARY OSWALD<br />

NATHAN PAULICH<br />

HILLARY COPELAND POWELL<br />

ALEX QUIMBY<br />

ROBERT E. ATKINSON<br />

CURTIS BRIDGEMAN<br />

STEVEN G. GEY<br />

Faculty Advisors<br />

BRENDA ELLIS<br />

Office Manager<br />

vii<br />

CHRISTA PLETCHER<br />

Executive Editor<br />

MOLLIE SMITH<br />

Writing &Research Editor<br />

STEVEN M. HOGAN<br />

Senior Articles Editor<br />

JOEL LEPPARD<br />

WILLIAM OURAND<br />

ALEXANDER PYRROS<br />

LUKE WATERS<br />

Article Selection Editors<br />

MICHAEL REDONDO<br />

JASON RUDDERMAN<br />

DAVID RUSSELL<br />

RYAN SAWYER<br />

SAMUEL STARKEY<br />

MATTHEW STEFANY<br />

JUSTIN S. SWARTZ<br />

BRANDI Y. THOMPSON<br />

TRAVIS R. THOMPSON<br />

MICHAEL TITUS<br />

PHILIP S. TRAYNOR<br />

JESSE UNRUH<br />

LAUREN VICKROY<br />

SETH WELNER<br />

CHARLES WHITTINGTON<br />

LAYNE ZHAO


<strong>General</strong> <strong>Information</strong><br />

Cite As. Cite this journal as FLA.ST.U.L.REV.<br />

Submissions. The <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>Law</strong> Review welcomes<br />

unsolicited manuscripts on topics <strong>of</strong> interest to the legal pr<strong>of</strong>ession.<br />

The <strong>Law</strong> Review acknowledges that unsolicited manuscripts<br />

may be submitted to other journals. All pieces will be evaluated as<br />

expeditiously as possible, but the <strong>Law</strong> Review assumes no responsibility<br />

for the return <strong>of</strong> unsolicited manuscripts. Manuscripts should<br />

be typewritten and double-spaced, with notes in footnote form. Citations<br />

should conform to The Bluebook: A Uniform System <strong>of</strong> Citation<br />

(18th ed.). Citations to <strong>Florida</strong> sources should conform to the <strong>Florida</strong><br />

<strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>Law</strong> Review <strong>Florida</strong> Style Manual (6th ed.), a copy <strong>of</strong><br />

which may be obtained for $5 from the <strong>Law</strong> Review. The <strong>Law</strong> Review<br />

accords great deference to an author’s work but reserves the right to<br />

determine the final form in which articles will be published.<br />

Advertising. The <strong>Law</strong> Review accepts advertisements that may<br />

be <strong>of</strong> use to its readers. Rates for full- and half-page advertisements<br />

are available from the Editor in Chief at the mailing address and telephone<br />

number below.<br />

Subscriptions. The subscription price is $30 for one year’s four<br />

issues or $10 for a single issue. <strong>Florida</strong> firms and individuals should<br />

add the appropriate sales tax. Foreign subscribers should add 50<br />

cents per issue or $2 per year for postage. Subscriptions are renewed<br />

automatically unless the subscriber sends a timely notice <strong>of</strong> termination.<br />

All notifications <strong>of</strong> address changes should include old and new addresses<br />

with ZIP+4 codes. Article reprints are available for 15 cents per<br />

page by contacting the Office Manager. Back issues more than one year<br />

old may be purchased from William S. Hein & Co., 1285 Main St., Buffalo,<br />

NY 14209 and are also available in electronic format for all your research<br />

needs on HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org).<br />

Correspondence. Address all correspondence to the <strong>Florida</strong><br />

<strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>Law</strong> Review, <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong>, <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong>,<br />

Tallahassee, FL 32306-1601. Direct manuscripts and manuscript<br />

inquiries to “Submissions.” Direct all other advertising and<br />

business matters to the Editor in Chief. Contact the editorial and<br />

business staff at (850) 644-2045.<br />

Errata. Bring errors in this volume to the attention <strong>of</strong> the Editor<br />

in Chief. The <strong>Law</strong> Review will publish corrections when necessary.<br />

Access. This document is available upon request in other formats<br />

for individuals with print-related disabilities. Contact the ADA Office,<br />

301 Westcott Administration Building, <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong>,<br />

Tallahassee, FL 32306-1470, (850) 644-5283 (Voice) or (850) 644-<br />

6693 (TDD).<br />

The <strong>Law</strong> Review is also available on the World Wide Web at<br />

http://www.law.fsu.edu/journals/lawreview.<br />

viii


THE MISSION OF THE<br />

FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW<br />

To provide a forum for contemporary legal discourse, we must:<br />

Adhere to the highest standards <strong>of</strong> analysis, accuracy, and<br />

timeliness in publishing the <strong>Law</strong> Review;<br />

Distinguish the <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> as a leading institution, known for<br />

its support <strong>of</strong> scholarship and academic pursuit;<br />

Attract the <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong>’s finest legal communicators<br />

by encouraging independent legal thought, <strong>of</strong>fering positions<br />

<strong>of</strong> responsibility, and maintaining a tradition <strong>of</strong> service to<br />

our <strong>College</strong>;<br />

Inform our pr<strong>of</strong>ession about the compelling issues <strong>of</strong> our time<br />

by providing a forum for student scholars, practitioners, and<br />

legal educators;<br />

Offer our pr<strong>of</strong>ession a selection <strong>of</strong> articles balanced between the<br />

theoretical and the practical;<br />

Uphold the honor and decorum <strong>of</strong> our pr<strong>of</strong>ession by championing<br />

the highest standards <strong>of</strong> conduct;<br />

Stand together as advocates <strong>of</strong> quality legal education and strive<br />

to improve the reputation <strong>of</strong> our <strong>Law</strong> Review and <strong>of</strong> our school;<br />

Inspire cooperation, commitment, and camaraderie among our<br />

membership and the <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> at large; and<br />

Safeguard an institutional memory and tradition so that those<br />

who follow will benefit from our experience.<br />

ix


FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD: AN<br />

ECONOMIC AND TAX ANALYSIS<br />

DAVID HASEN *<br />

ABSTRACT<br />

Many <strong>of</strong> the consequences <strong>of</strong> issuing and purchasing options on publicly traded property<br />

have been well understood since Black and Scholes developed a model for option pricing. No<br />

model <strong>of</strong> options, however, provides an accurate economic analysis <strong>of</strong> the actual transactions<br />

that issuers and purchasers engage in when options are bought and sold. One consequence<br />

<strong>of</strong> this gap in understanding is that the rules for taxing options remain poorly developed.<br />

This Article provides a transactional analysis <strong>of</strong> option sales for the first time. The focus<br />

is on covered options, but the analysis also has implications for options in which the underlying<br />

property serves merely as a reference obligation and is owned by neither party to the<br />

transaction. The analysis demonstrates that while all options have as one component a<br />

swap <strong>of</strong> variable risks or returns on the underlying property for a fixed payment, “in the<br />

money” options involve, in addition, a forward transfer <strong>of</strong> the benefits and correlative burdens<br />

<strong>of</strong> a part <strong>of</strong> the underlying property that is equivalent to a forward sale <strong>of</strong> that part.<br />

Commentators have not identified this embedded forward sale because the payment arrangement<br />

between the parties to the option transaction obscures it; however, a comparison<br />

<strong>of</strong> option prices derived under the Black-Scholes model with the theoretical prices <strong>of</strong> such<br />

forwards demonstrates that the transactions are identical. The analysis also illuminates the<br />

relationships between options and other common financial transactions, such as collars,<br />

and it permits a clear assessment <strong>of</strong> the advantages and disadvantages <strong>of</strong> possible tax rules<br />

for financial options.<br />

I. INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................. 790<br />

II. OPTION BASICS.................................................................................................. 795<br />

A. Options <strong>General</strong>ly ...................................................................................... 795<br />

B. Tax Rules.................................................................................................... 797<br />

1. Options Not Subject to Special Rules .................................................. 797<br />

2. Special Situations ................................................................................ 800<br />

C. Problems in Option Taxation ..................................................................... 801<br />

1. Basic Call Option ................................................................................. 802<br />

2. Basic Put Option .................................................................................. 804<br />

3. Special Situations ................................................................................ 805<br />

III. SUGGESTED CONCEPTUAL APPROACH ............................................................... 805<br />

A. <strong>State</strong>ment <strong>of</strong> the Theory ............................................................................. 806<br />

B. Demonstration ............................................................................................ 811<br />

1. Risk Neutrality and Zero Risk-Free Rate ............................................ 811<br />

a. Neutral Disposition <strong>of</strong> Upside Potential and Downside Risk ....... 812<br />

b. Neutral Disposition Plus OTM Put Option ................................... 813<br />

c. Extension to Call Option ............................................................... 816<br />

2. Positive Risk-Free Rate ........................................................................ 817<br />

a. Neutral Disposition <strong>of</strong> Upside Potential and Downside Risk ....... 817<br />

b. Neutral Disposition Plus OTM Put Option ................................... 818<br />

c. Accounting for the Time Value <strong>of</strong> Money ....................................... 819<br />

3. Risk Premium ...................................................................................... 822<br />

C. Conclusion .................................................................................................. 824<br />

IV. TAX ANALYSIS ................................................................................................... 825<br />

* Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Penn <strong>State</strong> <strong>Law</strong> School, Penn <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong>. I thank Joshua Coval,<br />

Arturo Estrada, David Gamage, Rebecca Harrigal, Andrew Kleit, Pamela Lew, Robert<br />

Martin, John Rogers, Reed Shuldiner, Lon Smith, Patrick White and participants at the<br />

Northern California Tax Roundtable for comments and suggestions. I remain solely responsible<br />

for any errors.


790 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

A. Underlier Owned ........................................................................................ 826<br />

1. Ownership Throughout the Option Term ............................................ 828<br />

a. Non-ITM Option ............................................................................ 828<br />

b. ITM Option .................................................................................... 830<br />

2. Ownership Acquired After Option Sale ............................................... 832<br />

B. Underlier as Reference Obligation ............................................................. 834<br />

C. Possible Tax Approaches ............................................................................ 835<br />

1. Basic Problems Under Current <strong>Law</strong> .................................................... 835<br />

2. Proposals .............................................................................................. 837<br />

a. Option Sale Date ........................................................................... 837<br />

b. Option Exercise .............................................................................. 838<br />

c. Option Lapse or Cancellation ........................................................ 839<br />

V. CONCLUSION ..................................................................................................... 839<br />

I. INTRODUCTION<br />

The treatment <strong>of</strong> options is a vexed area in the tax law. At its<br />

most basic, an option is a contract between two parties under which<br />

one <strong>of</strong> them purchases from the other the right, but not the obligation,<br />

to purchase or sell property (an “underlier”) at a fixed price (the<br />

“strike price”) on a particular date in the future (the “exercise date”<br />

or “strike date”). 1 Long subject to “open-transaction” treatment, the<br />

sale <strong>of</strong> an option represents one <strong>of</strong> the few cases in which money can<br />

change hands in a commercial setting without triggering any immediate<br />

income tax consequences. 2 Instead, the grantor <strong>of</strong> an option typically<br />

includes nothing in income on receipt <strong>of</strong> payment for the option<br />

(the “option premium”), while the option purchaser is entitled neither<br />

to an immediate deduction <strong>of</strong> the option premium 3 nor to amortize<br />

the premium prior to the exercise date. 4 Further, unless it is highly<br />

likely on the option sale date that the option will be exercised, 5 no<br />

sale <strong>of</strong> the underlier is deemed to have occurred for tax purposes on<br />

sale <strong>of</strong> the option, even though, in economic terms, the option sale is<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten similar to a partial sale <strong>of</strong> the underlier. Instead, tax consequences<br />

first arise when something further happens in respect <strong>of</strong> the<br />

option, such as its exercise, 6 lapse, cancellation, or disposition. 7<br />

1. JOHN C. HULL, OPTIONS, FUTURES, AND OTHER DERIVATIVES 179-184 (7th ed.<br />

2009).<br />

2. See Va. Iron Coal & Coke Co. v. Comm’r, 99 F.2d 919, 921-22 (4th Cir. 1938); see<br />

also Rev. Rul. 78-182, 1978-1 C. B. 265; 26 U.S.C. § 1234 (2006). The other major exception<br />

to the taxation <strong>of</strong> cash on receipt rule is the nontaxation <strong>of</strong> loan proceeds. Cases in which a<br />

non-cash exchange <strong>of</strong> property for property goes untaxed are more common. They include<br />

exchanges <strong>of</strong> certain like-kind properties, 26 U.S.C. § 1031, and the contribution <strong>of</strong> property<br />

to a controlled corporation in exchange for the corporation’s stock, 26 U.S.C. § 351(a), or<br />

to a partnership in exchange for an interest in the partnership. 26 U.S.C. § 721.<br />

3. Rev. Rul. 78-182, 1978-1 C.B. 265.<br />

4. See 26 C.F.R. § 1.263(a)-(4)(c)(1)(iii)(E).<br />

5. Rev. Rul. 80-238, 1980-2 C.B. 96.<br />

6. Rev. Rul. 78-182, 1978-1 C.B.265 .<br />

7. 26 U.S.C. § 1234A.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 791<br />

Most commentators view this regime as incorrect, 8 but beyond<br />

that partial consensus little agreement exists on how the tax law<br />

should apply to options. Options have been variously described as, or<br />

as analogous to, services transactions, 9 carved-out property interests,<br />

10 partnerships, 11 amounts received under a claim <strong>of</strong> right, 12 instances<br />

<strong>of</strong> “dynamic hedging,” 13 and wagers. 14 Each <strong>of</strong> these characterizations<br />

would theoretically support a different set <strong>of</strong> rules for option<br />

taxation. Each has virtues, but none is fully satisfactory. For example,<br />

under the carved-out interest approach, the option sale would<br />

be viewed as its own complete disposition <strong>of</strong> a contingent property interest,<br />

regardless <strong>of</strong> whether the option was exercised. This approach<br />

has intuitive appeal for call options, which give the option purchaser<br />

the right to buy property, but in the case <strong>of</strong> a put option, where the<br />

option purchaser acquires the right to dispose <strong>of</strong> the underlier, it is<br />

difficult to see how the disposition on the option sale date <strong>of</strong> what appears<br />

to be a potential liability counts as a property transaction. Similarly,<br />

under a claim <strong>of</strong> right analysis, the option premium might be<br />

viewed not as part <strong>of</strong> a property transaction, but as a separate transaction<br />

creating income for the option grantor because the premium is<br />

not subject to limitation on its use by the recipient. 15 Under such an<br />

analysis, the premium would be immediately includible in income,<br />

though possibly subject to adjustment later on. Immediate inclusion<br />

seems to be a sensible result, except that amounts received on condition<br />

<strong>of</strong> providing a service or subject to a future obligation generally<br />

are not treated as received under a claim <strong>of</strong> right, 16 though they<br />

might be taxable on other grounds. 17 Further, where the option is<br />

“deep in the money” and so highly likely to be exercised, the option<br />

sale appears to be more analogous to a forward sale <strong>of</strong> the underlier<br />

8. See, e.g., Eric D. Chason, Naked and Covered in Monte Carlo: A Reappraisal <strong>of</strong> Option<br />

Taxation, 27 VA. TAX REV. 135, 138-39 (2007); Noël B. Cunningham & Deborah H.<br />

Schenk, Taxation Without Realization: A “Revolutionary” Approach to Ownership, 47 TAX<br />

L. REV. 725, 775-76 (1992); Calvin H. Johnson, Taxing the Income from Writing Options, 96<br />

TAX NOTES TODAY 201-54 (1996); Yoram Keinan, United <strong>State</strong>s Federal Taxation <strong>of</strong> Derivatives:<br />

One Way or Many?, 61 TAX LAW. 81, 146-57 (2007). But see Kevin J. Liss, Rationalizing<br />

the Taxation <strong>of</strong> Options in the Age <strong>of</strong> Derivatives, 61 TAX LAW. 855, 856 (2008) (arguing<br />

that holding option transactions open for tax purposes until exercise, lapse, disposition or<br />

cancellation is correct).<br />

9. Johnson, supra note 8, at 6.<br />

10. Cunningham & Schenk, supra note 8, at 780-81.<br />

11. Bruce Kayle, Realization Without Taxation? The Not-So-Clear Reflection <strong>of</strong> Income<br />

From an Option to Acquire Property, 48 TAX L. REV. 233, 277 (1993).<br />

12. Id. at 248-54.<br />

13. David M. Hasen, A Realization-Based Approach to the Taxation <strong>of</strong> Financial Instruments,<br />

57 TAX L. REV. 397, 429-49 (2004).<br />

14. Liss, supra note 8, at 856-57.<br />

15. N. Am. Oil Consol. v. Burnet, 286 U.S. 417, 424 (1932).<br />

16. See, e.g., Rev. Rul. 58-234, 1958-1 C.B. 279.<br />

17. See, e.g., Schlude v. Comm’r, 372 U.S. 128, 133-37 (1962) (requiring an accrualmethod<br />

taxpayer to include sums paid for dance lessons to be provided in the future).


792 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

than to a payment subject to a claim <strong>of</strong> right. Comparable difficulties<br />

arise under the remaining characterizations mentioned above.<br />

Prior to the advent <strong>of</strong> modern financial products, the failure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

tax law to tax options correctly (for those who so view the current<br />

rules) amounted to little more than an irritation. Options were relatively<br />

uncommon, tended to be short-lived, and typically were not entered<br />

into for tax avoidance purposes. 18 In short, even if options were<br />

wrongly taxed, not much hung in the balance. This relatively tolerable<br />

state <strong>of</strong> affairs no longer holds. Modern financial products have<br />

rendered options ubiquitous, 19 have made the choice to purchase or<br />

sell them depend in many cases solely upon tax considerations, and<br />

have extended the terms <strong>of</strong> many options to economically significant<br />

periods. 20 At least three significant problems in option taxation have<br />

emerged as a consequence. First, under the current regime, a large<br />

class <strong>of</strong> taxpayers is taxed incorrectly in ways that are economically<br />

significant, simply because the option premium goes untaxed for a<br />

significant period <strong>of</strong> time. Second, because the open transaction doctrine<br />

differs so dramatically from the accrual or accrual-type regimes<br />

commonly applied to other, similar financial instruments, 21 taxpayers<br />

can elect their tax treatment at little if any economic cost. For example,<br />

a taxpayer seeking an immediate deduction for an option-like<br />

premium can enter into an economically similar notional principal<br />

contract that permits deduction <strong>of</strong> the option premium-like payment<br />

over time, whereas the same taxpayer can purchase a conventional<br />

and economically similar option if deferral <strong>of</strong> the deduction is preferable.<br />

Third, and in a related vein, taxpayers can opt into tax arbitrage<br />

without much difficulty through the expedient <strong>of</strong> entering into<br />

arrangements that largely <strong>of</strong>fset for economic purposes but not for<br />

tax purposes. Amplifying on the previous example, a taxpayer might<br />

purchase an option-like notional principal contract that generates<br />

current deductions while selling an economically similar option in return<br />

for an option premium that is not taxed in the current period.<br />

Added to these difficulties is the fact that much <strong>of</strong> the justification<br />

for the wait-and-see regime under the open transaction doctrine does<br />

not carry over to financial options anyway. Formerly, option purchases<br />

tended to be associated with transactions in unique underlying<br />

18. See generally Tony Ware, Financial Derivatives—A Brief Introduction, MITACS<br />

6th Annual Conference, May 11, 2005, available at http://finance.math.ucalgary.ca/papers/<br />

MitacsShortCourse2005.pdf.<br />

19. See generally id.<br />

20. See, e.g., 26 C.F.R. § 1.446-3(f)(3) (addressing the tax consequences <strong>of</strong> options embedded<br />

in notional principal contracts having a multi-period life).<br />

21. In addition to CPDIs, the following instruments are subject to accrual or accrualtype<br />

taxation: notional principal contracts, 26 C.F.R. § 1.446-3, original issue debt instruments,<br />

26 U.S.C. § 1272, “dealer” property, 26 U.S.C. § 475, certain foreign currency contracts,<br />

26 U.S.C. § 988.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 793<br />

property, 22 and as a consequence the establishment <strong>of</strong> a financial<br />

equivalent for the option would be difficult if not impossible. In the<br />

typical case, the reason for the option purchase was that at or near<br />

the time <strong>of</strong> potential purchase <strong>of</strong> the underlier, some question existed<br />

about whether the purchaser wanted or would be able to acquire or<br />

retain it. 23 That decision may not have depended upon objective, readily<br />

observable financial information, but on imponderables such as<br />

whether the particular underlier in question best satisfied the purchaser’s<br />

personal or business needs or whether financing for the purchase<br />

<strong>of</strong> the underlier would be available. 24 An individual might be<br />

willing to buy an antique dresser as long as nothing better was <strong>of</strong>fered<br />

at the flea market; Blackacre might suit a farmer’s plans to expand<br />

operations, but the availability <strong>of</strong> a bank loan could be uncertain<br />

on the day the property is <strong>of</strong>fered for sale. The purchase <strong>of</strong> a call<br />

option in either case would enable the prospective buyer to resolve<br />

these contingencies in exchange for a fee. However, quantifying the<br />

economic effect <strong>of</strong> paying the fee—the premium paid for the option—<br />

to either party in such a situation is a difficult if not impossible task.<br />

In particular, it typically will not be possible to establish a readily<br />

observable value for an option <strong>of</strong> that kind.<br />

By contrast, modern financial options typically are written on<br />

fungible property, which means that information about the true value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the option is readily available. 25 Unlike Blackacre and Whiteacre,<br />

there is no material difference between an option on share A <strong>of</strong><br />

IBM stock and one with the same terms on share B because there is<br />

no difference in the shares. Consequently, the economic characteristics<br />

<strong>of</strong> the derivative financial option are readily ascertainable, and<br />

worries about mistaxation if valuation occurs on the option purchase<br />

date are largely absent.<br />

These two general phenomena—the failure <strong>of</strong> the tax law to reach<br />

appropriate rules for the taxation <strong>of</strong> financial options and the collapse<br />

<strong>of</strong> the practical justifications for applying the open transaction<br />

doctrine to such options—indicate that much is to be gained from an<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> financial options that can disclose their actual economics<br />

and explicate how a realization-based income tax should apply to<br />

them. This Article seeks to accomplish these goals through an application<br />

<strong>of</strong> standard and well-understood concepts in the tax law, informed<br />

by the Black-Scholes model <strong>of</strong> option pricing. The primary focus<br />

here is so-called “covered options,” or options in which one <strong>of</strong> the<br />

parties owns the property that is subject to the option. However, the<br />

22. See, e.g., E. ALLAN FARNSWORTH,CONTRACTS 175-79 (4th ed. 2004).<br />

23. See id.<br />

24. See generally ROBERT F. BRUNER,APPLIED MERGERS &ACQUISITIONS 425 (2004).<br />

25. Thomas A. Smith, The Efficient Norm for Corporate <strong>Law</strong>: A Neotraditional Interpretation<br />

<strong>of</strong> Fiduciary Duty, 98 MICH.L.REV. 214, 258-59 (1999).


794 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

analysis also has ramifications for the tax analysis <strong>of</strong> options that are<br />

mere bilateral contracts because the payout structure <strong>of</strong> such contracts<br />

is the same as that <strong>of</strong> a covered option. Consequently, the two<br />

types <strong>of</strong> transactions <strong>of</strong>ten are close substitutes for each other. To<br />

give a sense <strong>of</strong> the tax stakes involved, consider that millions <strong>of</strong> options<br />

contracts having a combined value <strong>of</strong> several billions <strong>of</strong> dollars<br />

are traded daily in the United <strong>State</strong>s alone. 26<br />

Under the analysis developed here, the purchase <strong>of</strong> an option is<br />

properly viewed as consisting <strong>of</strong> the cashing out <strong>of</strong> a possible gain or<br />

loss, together with (in the case <strong>of</strong> “in the money” options) a forward<br />

property transaction, where the term property is understood in its<br />

standard tax sense <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> the economic benefits and correlative<br />

burdens associated with an asset or part <strong>of</strong> an asset. 27 Critically,<br />

this analysis applies equally to put and call options, despite the apparent<br />

incongruity <strong>of</strong> treating the <strong>of</strong>f-loading <strong>of</strong> risk in the case <strong>of</strong> the<br />

purchase <strong>of</strong> a put option as a property disposition. The basic teaching<br />

is that true “option” arrangements arise only to the extent that options<br />

are exchanges <strong>of</strong> fixed for uncertain returns or risks. The balance<br />

<strong>of</strong> any option transaction—that is, the portion that is “in the<br />

money” on the option sale date—is a property transaction. In this<br />

transaction, the opportunity for gain and the risk <strong>of</strong> loss that straddle<br />

the expected value <strong>of</strong> the underlier on the exercise date are transferred<br />

to the party that would formally purchase the underlier (or its<br />

equivalent) on exercise. The fact that in the money options constitute<br />

transfers <strong>of</strong> risks and correlative burdens explains how options shade<br />

into simple forward contracts as they move deeper into the money on<br />

the option sale date.<br />

So understood, it becomes possible to formulate rules for the taxation<br />

<strong>of</strong> options that respect the lines that exist between the types <strong>of</strong><br />

returns options generate. On one hand, out-<strong>of</strong>-the-money options are<br />

closely akin to the purchase <strong>of</strong> a service that should be taxed as ordinary<br />

income to the option writer, but on the other hand, certain options<br />

have property disposition-like characteristics. Without an understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> how the risk-shifting part <strong>of</strong> any option shades into<br />

the property-shifting part <strong>of</strong> some options, it has not been possible to<br />

formulate tax rules that are consistent with both <strong>of</strong> these aspects <strong>of</strong><br />

options. Further, the understanding <strong>of</strong> options developed in this Article<br />

makes it possible to devise rules that are consistent with principles<br />

that have long operated in the tax system, particularly the following<br />

two: 1) that the taxpayer does not realize the gain or loss as-<br />

26. In 2008, nearly 1.2 billion options having a total cash value <strong>of</strong> nearly $1 trillion<br />

were traded on the Chicago Board Options Exchange. See Chicago Board Options Exchange,<br />

CBOE 2008 Market Statistics, at 1, available at http://www.cboe.com/Data/<br />

marketstats-2008.pdf (last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

27. See Grodt & McKay Realty, Inc. v. Comm’r, 77 T.C. 1221, 1243-45 (1981).


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 795<br />

sociated with an asset until the asset is disposed <strong>of</strong> (known as the<br />

“realization rule”), and 2) that capital income is taxed differently<br />

from ordinary income. 28 While the analysis here does not decisively<br />

point to any particular tax regime for options, it suggests that certain<br />

approaches will be more effective and appropriate than others, and it<br />

illustrates the extent to which differing approaches involve, and do<br />

not involve, legitimate trade-<strong>of</strong>fs. The analysis also helps to explain<br />

the flaws in the current law as well as the strengths and weaknesses<br />

<strong>of</strong> others’ suggestions for the taxation <strong>of</strong> options.<br />

The approach developed here has eluded commentators because<br />

they typically have not focused on the entire stream <strong>of</strong> payments in<br />

an option transaction. Instead, commentators have tended to separate<br />

the option purchase from the option payout (or lapse), focusing<br />

on the rights delivered on exercise <strong>of</strong> the option separately from those<br />

involved in the payment <strong>of</strong> the option premium itself. <strong>State</strong>d otherwise,<br />

they have let the optics <strong>of</strong> option transactions drive their analyses.<br />

However, once the total sequence <strong>of</strong> payments in an option<br />

transaction is taken into account, the property transaction inherent<br />

in any in the money option becomes manifest. The portion, if any, <strong>of</strong><br />

the option premium that is economically attributable to the in the<br />

money aspect <strong>of</strong> the option is nothing more than a shift in the timing<br />

<strong>of</strong> the payouts from ownership <strong>of</strong> a part <strong>of</strong> the underlier.<br />

Part II reviews the basic law for the taxation <strong>of</strong> options. Part III<br />

<strong>of</strong>fers a novel analysis that aspires both to explain the economics <strong>of</strong><br />

an option transaction and to clarify the ways in which options are<br />

similar to, but distinct from, the various instruments and arrangements<br />

to which others have compared them. The analysis in Part III<br />

relies heavily on the Black-Scholes option pricing model, but it elaborates<br />

significantly on the model in its explanation <strong>of</strong> the on-theground<br />

facts that correspond to the results produced under the model.<br />

Part IV sets forth possible tax rules for options in light <strong>of</strong> the economic<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> options developed in Part III.<br />

II. OPTION BASICS<br />

A. Options <strong>General</strong>ly<br />

Options come in two basic forms. 29 A call option, or “call,” gives the<br />

owner <strong>of</strong> the option the right but not the obligation to purchase a given<br />

item <strong>of</strong> property at a given price on one or more dates in the future.<br />

A put option, or “put,” gives the owner the right but not the obligation<br />

to sell a given item <strong>of</strong> property at a given price on one or<br />

28. See 26 U.S.C. § 1(h) (2006) (discussing favorable rates for long-term capital gain <strong>of</strong> individuals);<br />

26 U.S.C. § 1001 (discussing gain or loss on property generally taxed when realized).<br />

29. See generally HULL, supra note 1, at 179-84.


796 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

more dates in the future. In standard parlance, a call option is said to<br />

be “in the money” (“ITM”) at any time that the fair market value <strong>of</strong><br />

the underlier exceeds the option exercise price; “at the money”<br />

(“ATM”) if the fair market value equals the exercise price; and “out <strong>of</strong><br />

the money” (“OTM”) at any time that the fair market value is less<br />

than the exercise price. Similarly, a put is ITM if the value <strong>of</strong> the underlier<br />

is less than the exercise price, ATM if the values are equal,<br />

and OTM otherwise. Thus, an option will not be exercised if it is<br />

OTM on the exercise date.<br />

The following example demonstrates these concepts.<br />

Simple call option: On Day 1, A pays $Y to B in exchange<br />

for an option to purchase 100 shares <strong>of</strong> XYZ Company stock<br />

from B at $X on Day 2, one year later.<br />

If the fair market value <strong>of</strong> 100 shares <strong>of</strong> XYZ stock on Day 2 exceeds<br />

$X, the option will be ITM, and A will exercise the option; otherwise,<br />

the option will lapse unexercised. 30 If the option provided A the right<br />

to sell, rather than to buy, 100 shares <strong>of</strong> XYZ stock, the option would<br />

be a put and A would exercise only if the fair market value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

XYZ stock were not greater than $X on Day 2.<br />

Options that may be exercised on just one date are referred to as<br />

European options, while options exercisable on more than one date<br />

are referred to as American options. 31 Options also may be either<br />

physically settled or cash settled. A physically settled option requires<br />

the purchase or sale <strong>of</strong> the underlier to occur if the option is exercised,<br />

while a cash settled option is exercised through the option<br />

writer’s transfer <strong>of</strong> the net option value to the option holder on the<br />

exercise date. In the previous examples, a physical settlement <strong>of</strong> either<br />

option would require the option holder to tender, in the case <strong>of</strong><br />

the call, $X to the option writer on Day 2 in order to receive the stock,<br />

or in the case <strong>of</strong> the put, the underlying XYZ stock in order to receive<br />

$X. If, by contrast, the options were cash-settled, then the holder <strong>of</strong><br />

the option would be entitled to a cash payment equal to the difference<br />

between the fair market value <strong>of</strong> the stock and $X in the case <strong>of</strong> the<br />

call, or between $X and the fair market value <strong>of</strong> the stock in the case<br />

<strong>of</strong> the put. Thus, as contrasted with a physically settled option, neither<br />

party to a cash settled option need own the underlier at any<br />

time. Where the underliers are fungible, publicly traded property<br />

30. For ease <strong>of</strong> exposition. I disregard the case where the option is ATM on the exercise<br />

date. In that case, it is a matter <strong>of</strong> indifference whether the option is exercised or not.<br />

31. HULL, supra note 1, at 179-81.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 797<br />

such as publicly traded stock, commodities, or futures, the difference<br />

between cash and physical settlement <strong>of</strong>ten approaches nil. 32<br />

Lastly, options may be contingent in the sense that some condition<br />

beyond the option’s being ITM on the exercise date must be satisfied<br />

in order for the option to be exercisable. In a now common product<br />

known as a credit default swap (a “CDS”), the writer <strong>of</strong> the swap may<br />

promise to pay for the decline in value <strong>of</strong> an underlier on one or more<br />

dates, but only when the decline is due to some factor other than<br />

changes to general market conditions. 33 In economic terms, a CDS <strong>of</strong><br />

this type is economically equivalent to a contingent put option. Most<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> insurance also are economically equivalent to contingent put<br />

options, as long as the purchaser <strong>of</strong> the insurance has an insurable<br />

interest in the underlier. 34<br />

B. Tax Rules<br />

A welter <strong>of</strong> rules governs the taxation <strong>of</strong> options. Some <strong>of</strong> the<br />

rules are statutory, some are administrative, and some derive from<br />

decisional law.<br />

1. Options Not Subject to Special Rules<br />

The open transaction doctrine applies to options not subject to a<br />

special statutory regime. 35 The doctrine itself dates from the 1931<br />

Supreme Court case Burnet v. Logan, 36 which did not deal with options<br />

but with contingent payment rights. In Logan, the taxpayer<br />

sold an interest in a mining company and received payment in the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> cash plus rights to a percentage <strong>of</strong> future mine earnings over<br />

an indefinite period. The Court held that the taxpayer was entitled to<br />

recover her basis in the property sold before reporting any <strong>of</strong> the<br />

payment for her mining stock as gain from the transaction because<br />

the uncertainty inherent in the timing and amount <strong>of</strong> future payouts<br />

32. Even where the option is on a commodity such as wheat, physical settlement<br />

commonly occurs in connection with the separate transfer <strong>of</strong> the underlier to a person in<br />

the trade or business <strong>of</strong> selling the underlier. Id. at 10.<br />

33. As its name implies, the associated trigger is generally a default <strong>of</strong> some kind by<br />

the issuer on the reference obligation, or else some similar event such as a downgrade in<br />

the creditworthiness <strong>of</strong> the issuer <strong>of</strong> the underlier. See Roberto Blanco et al., An Empirical<br />

Analysis <strong>of</strong> the Dynamic Relation Between Investment-Grade Bonds and Credit Default<br />

Swaps, 60 J. FIN. 2255, 2256 (2005).<br />

34. As a simple example, homeowner’s insurance is equivalent to a put option on the<br />

home with a strike price equal to the fair market value <strong>of</strong> the home (or its insured amount,<br />

whichever is less) where the decline in value is due to certain events, such as a fire or a<br />

flood. True insurance relationships also generally require the option holder to have an insurable<br />

interest in the underlier. Bertram Harnett & John V. Thornton, Insurable Interest<br />

in Property: A Socio-Economic Reevaluation <strong>of</strong> a Legal Concept, 48 COLUM. L.REV. 1162,<br />

1162-63 (1948).<br />

35. See Va. Iron Coal & Coke Co. v. Comm’r, 99 F.2d 919, 921-22 (4th Cir. 1938).<br />

36. Burnet v. Logan, 283 U.S. 404, 413-14 (1931).


798 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

made taxation inappropriate, given that the consequences <strong>of</strong> the sale<br />

would be determined with certainty in subsequent periods.<br />

In Virginia Iron Coal & Coke Co. v. Commissioner, 37 the open<br />

transaction rule was extended to options at the behest <strong>of</strong> the government.<br />

The taxpayer received payments over a three-year period<br />

for an option it had sold to a third party that provided the third party<br />

the right to purchase stock or mineral lands. When the option holder<br />

let the option lapse in 1934, the taxpayer filed amended returns for<br />

the years in which it had received payments, treating the amounts<br />

received as ordinary income in those years. 38 The government argued,<br />

and the court agreed, that the open transaction doctrine applied because<br />

at the time the payments were received “it was impossible to<br />

determine whether they were taxable or not” and, because the nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> option payments received in a particular year might first become<br />

ascertainable after the statute <strong>of</strong> limitations had closed for that year,<br />

only a rule that the taxable event occurred in the year <strong>of</strong> lapse or exercise<br />

would be administrable. 39<br />

Although the problem <strong>of</strong> uncertainty lingering beyond the statute<br />

<strong>of</strong> limitations motivated the decision in Virginia Iron, the kind <strong>of</strong> uncertainty<br />

that commonly has been considered to justify application <strong>of</strong><br />

the open transaction doctrine is that <strong>of</strong> character <strong>of</strong> the option premium.<br />

40 If the option purchaser exercises its right to buy or sell under<br />

the option, a transfer <strong>of</strong> property will occur, and it would seem that<br />

the tax consequences attending a property disposition should also<br />

apply to the option sale. That is, the two transactions together appear<br />

to constitute a single property disposition and should be so<br />

treated for tax purposes. 41 If, however, the option goes unexercised,<br />

then at least in a formal sense no property changes hands, and the<br />

tax consequences <strong>of</strong> the option sale would seem to differ too, assuming<br />

that the tax consequences <strong>of</strong> nonproperty transactions generally<br />

differ from those <strong>of</strong> property transactions. Accordingly, because it is<br />

not possible to get the “right” answer with any certainty on the option<br />

sale date, it is better to hold the transaction open – that is, to<br />

wait and see. 42<br />

Although subsequent developments, both administrative and legislative,<br />

have substantially narrowed the scope <strong>of</strong> application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

open transaction doctrine, 43 the doctrine’s basic rationale—<br />

37. 99 F.2d at 921.<br />

38. Id. at 919-21.<br />

39. Id. at 921-22.<br />

40. See Rev. Rul. 78-182, 1978-1 C.B. 265.<br />

41. Id.<br />

42. See Burnet, 283 U.S. at 413, (articulating the justification for the open transaction<br />

doctrine, albeit in a nonoption setting);Va. Iron Coal & Coke Co., 99 F.2d at 919 (extending<br />

the rationale to options).<br />

43. See, e.g., Temp. Reg. § 15A.453-1(d)(2)(iii).


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 799<br />

uncertainty in the tax consequences <strong>of</strong> a transaction in the taxable<br />

period—continues to serve as the basis for the tax treatment <strong>of</strong> most<br />

options. 44 Accordingly, under current practice for options not subject<br />

to special rules, receipt <strong>of</strong> the option premium is a nontaxable<br />

event. 45 If the option is exercised, the option writer treats the premium<br />

as part <strong>of</strong> the amount realized in the case <strong>of</strong> a call and as a reduction<br />

in the purchase price in the case <strong>of</strong> a put. The holder treats<br />

the premium symmetrically, adding the premium to basis in the case<br />

<strong>of</strong> a call and subtracting the premium from the amount realized in<br />

the case <strong>of</strong> a put. 46 Under the sample transaction above, on exercise<br />

<strong>of</strong> the call, B would treat $X + $Y as the amount received as payment<br />

for the XYZ stock, and A’s basis in the stock would be the same<br />

amount. If the option were a put, then A’s amount realized and B’s<br />

amount paid would be $X - $Y. The character <strong>of</strong> any gain or loss recognized<br />

is generally the same as that <strong>of</strong> the underlier in the hands <strong>of</strong><br />

the seller <strong>of</strong> the property. 47<br />

When an option is not exercised, or is disposed <strong>of</strong> in some way prior<br />

to its possible exercise, different rules apply to holders and writers <strong>of</strong><br />

options. Holders are generally subject to the rules <strong>of</strong> § 1234(a), which<br />

provide that gain or loss to the option holder on disposition (including<br />

lapse) 48 <strong>of</strong> the option has the character as short- or long-term capital<br />

that the underlier does or would have in the holder’s hands. If, however,<br />

the underlier is or would be inventory or not otherwise a capital asset<br />

in the holder’s hands, gain or loss generally will be ordinary. 49 The<br />

same rules apply where the option is cancelled by mutual agreement <strong>of</strong><br />

the parties (with or without a cancellation payment). 50<br />

Writers <strong>of</strong> options are generally subject to the rules <strong>of</strong> § 1234(b) when<br />

the option is not (or not yet) exercised. In the case <strong>of</strong> an option on stock,<br />

securities, or commodities, the disposition, lapse, or cancellation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

option generally will produce short-term capital gain or loss, unless the<br />

underlier is not a capital asset in the holder’s hands or the option is<br />

granted in the ordinary course <strong>of</strong> the taxpayer’s trade or business <strong>of</strong><br />

granting options, in either <strong>of</strong> which cases gain or loss is ordinary. 51<br />

44. Rev. Rul. 78-182, 1978-1 C.B. 265.<br />

45. Id.<br />

46. Id.<br />

47. Id.<br />

48. 26 U.S.C. § 1234(a)(2) (2006).<br />

49. See 26 U.S.C. § 1222 (defining capital gain or loss as gain or loss from the sale or<br />

exchange <strong>of</strong> a capital asset).<br />

50. 26 U.S.C. § 1234A.<br />

51. See Rev. Rul. 78-182, 1978-1 C.B. 265; 26 U.S.C. § 1234A.


800 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

2. Special Situations<br />

The rules described above do not apply to a variety <strong>of</strong> options and<br />

persons. Most importantly, under § 475, mark-to-market rules apply<br />

to taxpayers who are either (1) dealers in options, 52 or (2) traders in<br />

options who elect to have mark-to-market rules apply to income and<br />

loss from their option transactions, regardless <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

underlier. 53 Under the mark-to-market rules, dealers and electing<br />

traders value, or mark to market, their inventory annually and either<br />

pay tax on the net increase in value <strong>of</strong> the inventory or take a deduction<br />

for the net decrease over the previous year. Gain or loss is ordinary<br />

in character. 54 In the case <strong>of</strong> a dealer in options, the mark-tomarket<br />

regime means that while open transaction treatment still applies<br />

when the option is entered into, the tax system will take into<br />

account the appreciation or decline in value <strong>of</strong> the option during the<br />

year. Persons in the trade or business <strong>of</strong> writing options generally<br />

treat option premiums as ordinary income, but again subject to deferral<br />

under the open transaction doctrine. 55<br />

The rules described in Section II.B.1 also do not apply in a number<br />

<strong>of</strong> special situations. First, they do not govern options on “section<br />

1256 contracts.” 56 Section 1256 contracts comprise a variety <strong>of</strong> publicly<br />

traded financial contracts, most <strong>of</strong> which are valued on a daily basis<br />

by the exchanges on which they are traded. 57 Like options held as<br />

inventory or by dealers in securities, section 1256 contracts (some <strong>of</strong><br />

which are themselves options), and options on them are subject to a<br />

mark-to-market regime, 58 but unlike inventory or dealer property, §<br />

1256 mandates that gain and loss on section 1256 contracts be 40%<br />

short-term capital and 60% long-term capital in character. 59<br />

Second, holders <strong>of</strong> nonexercised put options entered into in connection<br />

with certain short sales are subject to § 1233. 60 In a short<br />

sale, one party borrows property that it then sells to a purchaser. The<br />

seller later “closes out” the short sale by delivering to the lender<br />

52. Taxpayers who are dealers in securities may hold securities, including options, as<br />

inventory or not. Subject to limited exceptions, if held as inventory, the option is generally<br />

subject to inventory accounting. See 26 U.S.C. § 475(b) (2006); see also 26 U.S.C. § 475(a)(1)<br />

(requiring annual fair market valuation <strong>of</strong> the option). If the option is not held as inventory,<br />

essentially the same MTM rules apply. See 26 U.S.C. § 475(a)(2).<br />

53. 26 U.S.C. § 475(f).<br />

54. See 26 U.S.C. § 1221(a)(1) (excluding inventory from the definition <strong>of</strong> “capital asset”<br />

and therefore from capital treatment on sale or exchange).<br />

55. See, e.g., I.R.S. Priv. Ltr. Rul. 78-46-059 (Aug. 18, 1978) (treating income from option<br />

premiums in the case <strong>of</strong> a person in the trade or business <strong>of</strong> granting options).<br />

56. 26 U.S.C. § 1234(c)(1). Certain options are themselves “section 1256 contracts.” See<br />

26 U.S.C. § 1256(b)(3)-(4). These too, <strong>of</strong> course, are subject to the general rules <strong>of</strong> § 1256.<br />

57. 26 U.S.C. § 1256(g)(4)-(6).<br />

58. 26 U.S.C. § 1256(a)(1).<br />

59. 26 U.S.C. § 1256(a)(3).<br />

60. 26 U.S.C. § 1234(a)(3)(c).


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 801<br />

property identical to the property borrowed. Section 1234(a)(3) provides<br />

that the rules <strong>of</strong> § 1233(c) apply to losses resulting from the<br />

nonexercise <strong>of</strong> put options described in that section. Section 1233(c)<br />

in turn states that if the taxpayer acquires a put option to sell property<br />

on the same date it acquires the property to which the option, if<br />

exercised, will apply, then any loss on the nonexercise <strong>of</strong> the option is<br />

added to the basis <strong>of</strong> the property so acquired.<br />

Lastly, the general rules may not apply to situations in which the<br />

option is embedded in another instrument or is treated as part <strong>of</strong><br />

another arrangement. Examples <strong>of</strong> the first situation include the<br />

previously discussed case <strong>of</strong> an option embedded in an NPC as well<br />

as options embedded in contingent payment debt instruments. For<br />

these instruments, the option premium is generally accounted for<br />

over the term <strong>of</strong> the instrument on the basis <strong>of</strong> assumptions about<br />

the returns the option will generate. Any disparity between the projections<br />

and the actual returns is accounted for either periodically or<br />

at term. Examples <strong>of</strong> explicit integration or quasi-integration regimes<br />

include options entered into as hedges, 61 as parts <strong>of</strong> a straddle, 62 or in<br />

connection with a wash sale. 63 In these cases, the tax treatment <strong>of</strong><br />

the option depends in some way on the treatment <strong>of</strong> the asset or instrument<br />

with which it is associated.<br />

C. Problems in Option Taxation<br />

This Subpart identifies some <strong>of</strong> the difficulties that options pose to<br />

the tax system. The discussion involves variations on the following<br />

basic fact pattern:<br />

Suppose A is the owner <strong>of</strong> 100 shares <strong>of</strong> XYZ stock, which<br />

does not pay dividends. On Day 1, A and B enter into an option<br />

transaction pursuant to which the option, if exercised,<br />

will result in the transfer <strong>of</strong> the XYZ stock to B on Day 2,<br />

one year later. The stock is worth $100 on Day 1, and A’s adjusted<br />

basis in the stock is $10. As <strong>of</strong> Day 1, A has held the<br />

XYZ stock for more than one year. XYZ stock has moderate<br />

volatility <strong>of</strong> 30%. In the case <strong>of</strong> a call option, A will be the<br />

seller <strong>of</strong> the option and B the buyer, while in the case <strong>of</strong> a<br />

put, these roles will be reversed. At all times, the risk-free<br />

rate <strong>of</strong> return is 10%. Neither A nor B is a trader or dealer<br />

in stock or options.<br />

Throughout this discussion, the terms ATM, ITM and OTM are<br />

defined relative to the forward price <strong>of</strong> the underlier on the exercise<br />

61. See 26 C.F.R. § 1.446-4.<br />

62. See § 1092.<br />

63. See § 1091.


802 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

date, as determined on the option sale date. This usage differs from<br />

standard usage, which defines the terms relative to the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

underlier on the date the determination (as ATM, ITM or OTM) is<br />

made. Further, interest is assumed to accrue on a continuously compounded<br />

basis rather than periodically. For example, under an assumed<br />

rate <strong>of</strong> 10% compounded continuously, property worth $100 on<br />

Day 1 would have a forward price <strong>of</strong> $110.52 on Day 2, one year later.<br />

64 The assumption <strong>of</strong> continuous compounding is made to simplify<br />

the analysis because the Black-Scholes model <strong>of</strong> option pricing on<br />

which the analysis rests assumes continuous compounding. The<br />

analysis here would hold if Black-Scholes were modified to assume<br />

periodic compounding, but it is easier to hold Black-Scholes constant<br />

and to assume continuous compounding rather than to hold constant<br />

the assumption that interest compounds periodically and modify<br />

Black-Scholes. Under these parameters, a call option sold on the<br />

property on Day 1 having an exercise date <strong>of</strong> Day 2 would be ATM if<br />

the strike price is $110.52, OTM if it is above $110.52, and ITM if it<br />

is less than $110.52. For a put option, the ITM and OTM designations<br />

would be reversed.<br />

1. Basic Call Option<br />

Consider first an ATM call option that A sells to B. Since the riskfree<br />

rate is 10%, an ATM option will have a strike price <strong>of</strong> $110.52. It<br />

would sell for $11.92. 65 Under the open transaction doctrine, A does<br />

not take the $11.92 into income on Day 1 but instead waits until<br />

something further happens. In the meantime, A can invest the premium.<br />

While investment earnings would be subject to tax, the exemption<br />

<strong>of</strong> the principal from tax is equivalent to taxing the premium<br />

but exempting the yield on it. 66 In other words, it is equivalent to<br />

consumption taxation <strong>of</strong> the premium. 67 The nondeductibility <strong>of</strong> the<br />

premium to B may provide some comfort from a tax revenue perspective,<br />

but the fact remains that on an individual basis, the parties are<br />

not properly taxed. 68 And if the parties are not subject to the same<br />

marginal rates, revenue neutrality also is not preserved. This last<br />

64. The general formula for continuous compounding is: A = Pe rt , where A is the<br />

amount, P is the initial principal, r is the rate expressed as a decimal, and t is the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> years.<br />

65. The pricing is based on the Black-Scholes theorem and can be derived using a<br />

Black-Scholes pricing calculator, many <strong>of</strong> which are available online. See, e.g., The Derivatives<br />

‘Zine, http://www.margrabe.com/OptionPricing.html (last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

66. Cary Brown, Business-Income Taxation and Investment Incentives, in INCOME,<br />

EMPLOYMENT, AND PUBLIC POLICY:ESSAYS IN HONOR OF ALVIN H. HANSEN 300, 301 (1948).<br />

67. Joseph Bankman & David A. Weisbach, The Superiority <strong>of</strong> an Ideal Consumption<br />

Tax Over an Ideal Income Tax, 58 STAN.L.REV. 1413 (2006).<br />

68. One can view the overall arrangement as a kind <strong>of</strong> surrogate taxation.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 803<br />

problem may be particularly acute where B is a non-U.S. person not<br />

subject to U.S. tax generally.<br />

The fact that A acquires an investment opportunity suggests that<br />

there is an exchange in the transaction because parties dealing at<br />

arm’s length do not exchange value for nothing. The fact that no<br />

payment occurs on the option sale date suggests further that the<br />

transaction contains a loan <strong>of</strong> some sort. In short, if parties dealing<br />

at arm’s length do not provide something for nothing, the investment<br />

opportunity that A acquires will have been paid for. 69 Therefore, the<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> explicit interest indicates that the price <strong>of</strong> the option is<br />

discounted. 70 B pays an amount for the option that reflects the forgone<br />

opportunity to earn a return on the premium during the year<br />

prior to exercise. <strong>State</strong>d otherwise, $11.92 represents the discounted<br />

present value <strong>of</strong> the option premium on Day 2. Under the assumed<br />

10% risk-free rate <strong>of</strong> return, if the option premium were due on that<br />

day (regardless <strong>of</strong> exercise), B would pay $13.17. This analysis suggests<br />

that interest should be deemed to accrue on the premium for<br />

tax purposes, with a corresponding deduction to A.<br />

The failure to tax the interest on the premium is not the only<br />

troubling feature <strong>of</strong> the option sale. 71 Considering the possible outcomes<br />

<strong>of</strong> the transaction, it seems clear that on Day 1, A has locked<br />

in gain no matter what happens. On that day, A receives $11.92. If<br />

the option is exercised, A will receive an additional $110.52 on Day 2,<br />

for a total <strong>of</strong> $122.44, in exchange for the stock. A’s taxable gain will<br />

be $112.44. If the option is not exercised, A gets to keep the $11.92,<br />

again fully taxable, without parting with the stock. It is therefore unclear<br />

why A should not be taxed in some fashion on the $11.92 on receipt<br />

(with, under current law, a corresponding basis adjustment).<br />

The justification for open transaction treatment would not seem to<br />

apply in this instance, since it is known on Day 1 that there will be<br />

income and that under current law it is capital in nature. Although,<br />

under current law, it is not known on Day 1 whether the gain will be<br />

short-term or long-term, 72 the justification for short-term gain to option<br />

writers in the nonexercise case is not that such gain is “inherently”<br />

short-term, but that grantors will manipulate the timing <strong>of</strong><br />

capital gains if the character <strong>of</strong> the gain depends on the holding pe-<br />

69. William A. Klein, Tailor to the Emperor With No Clothes: The Supreme Court's<br />

Tax Rules for Deposits and Advance Payments, 41 UCLA L. REV. 1685, 1695 (1994) (“From<br />

an economic perspective there are no interest-free loans, only hidden, or imputed, interest.<br />

The hidden interest . . . is always there.”).<br />

70. See id.<br />

71. See Johnson, supra note 8, at 4-8 (criticizing the failure to tax interest on the premium).<br />

72. If the option lapses, the premium is considered short-term capital gain under<br />

§1234(b). If the option is exercised, it is considered long-term capital gain under §1234(a),<br />

given the facts <strong>of</strong> the discussion example.


804 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

riod <strong>of</strong> the underlier. 73 Accordingly, it is unclear why the granting <strong>of</strong><br />

an option on appreciated property is not taxable on the grant date to<br />

the extent <strong>of</strong> at least the lesser <strong>of</strong> the appreciation or the option premium,<br />

with the character <strong>of</strong> the gain determined by up-front rule,<br />

possibly with adjustment down the road.<br />

2. Basic Put Option<br />

Under the facts <strong>of</strong> the discussion example, the mirror put option<br />

would have A transferring the $11.92 to B on Day 1 in exchange for<br />

the right, but not the obligation, to sell B the 100 shares <strong>of</strong> XYZ stock<br />

at $110.52 on Day 2. 74 As the grantor <strong>of</strong> a put, B does not own the<br />

property subject to the option, so the worry that the receipt <strong>of</strong> the option<br />

premium represents partial payment for the underlier would<br />

seem to be misplaced. Again, however, the grantor receives the option<br />

premium with no tax consequences, raising questions about whether<br />

interest should be imputed to the transaction or the grantor should<br />

include the full premium on receipt under a claim <strong>of</strong> right or prepayment<br />

analysis. Claim <strong>of</strong> right generally requires a taxpayer to include,<br />

in income, an amount received that may be subject to a future<br />

return, as long as the taxpayer is not subject to restriction. 75 However,<br />

if later return is required, the taxpayer typically may take a deduction.<br />

76 Similarly, amounts received as prepayments for future services<br />

generally are includible, 77 subject to limited exceptions. 78<br />

The transaction also has sale elements that would seem to point to<br />

possible recognition <strong>of</strong> gain for A. Although A does not receive cash, A<br />

does obtain protection against downside loss because A can cash out<br />

the stock at any time prior to Day 2 for at least the present discounted<br />

value <strong>of</strong> $110.52 on Day 2. A thereby has disposed <strong>of</strong> risk <strong>of</strong> loss, one <strong>of</strong><br />

the primary indicia <strong>of</strong> ownership. 79 Whether that disposition ought to<br />

be sufficient to trigger recognition <strong>of</strong> gain or loss is less certain. Numerous<br />

provisions in the tax law treat the disposition solely <strong>of</strong> risk <strong>of</strong><br />

loss as something short <strong>of</strong> a sale but different from simple ownership,<br />

73. 26 U.S.C. §1234.<br />

74. As in the case <strong>of</strong> the call option, the put price is derived using the Black-Scholes<br />

option pricing formula. See supra note 64-65. Where an option is ATM, the put and call<br />

prices are the same on the option sale date.<br />

75. N. Am. Oil Consol. v. Burnet, 286 U.S. 417, 424 (1932).<br />

76. Id.; see also 26 U.S.C. § 1341 (providing deduction or credit choice to taxpayer for<br />

certain amounts returned).<br />

77. 26 C.F.R. § 1.451-1(a) (cash-method taxpayers); Schlude v. Comm’r, 372 U.S. 128<br />

(1963) (discussing accrual-method taxpayers).<br />

78. See, e.g., Artnell Co. v. Comm’r, 400 F.2d 981 (1968) (holding that deferral for accrual-method<br />

taxpayer was allowed where amount and timing <strong>of</strong> future associated expenses<br />

clearly ascertainable at time <strong>of</strong> receipt); Rev. Proc. 2004-342004-22 IRB 991 (describing<br />

one-year deferral for certain prepayments).<br />

79. See Grodt & McKay Realty Inc. v. Comm’r, 77 T.C. 1221, 1237-38 (1981) (identifying<br />

risk <strong>of</strong> economic loss as a primary aspect <strong>of</strong> tax ownership).


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 805<br />

typically by tolling applicable holding periods. 80 By the same token, no<br />

provision treats a transfer solely <strong>of</strong> risk <strong>of</strong> loss as sufficient to trigger<br />

recognition <strong>of</strong> income. 81 Again, however, the idea that nothing <strong>of</strong> significance<br />

for tax purposes has occurred seems questionable.<br />

3. Special Situations<br />

When an option is subject to a special regime, additional problems<br />

arise. These problems are not unique to the option setting but instead<br />

result from the inconsistent tax treatment <strong>of</strong> parties to the same<br />

transaction. As an example, a dealer in options may purchase a call<br />

from a non-dealer grantor. The dealer does not amortize the premium,<br />

but the option is marked to market annually. 82 Consequently, income<br />

or loss is registered by just one side <strong>of</strong> the transaction while it is open.<br />

Similarly, and as discussed in the Introduction, taxpayers may take<br />

advantage <strong>of</strong> the different rules that apply to options embedded in notional<br />

principal contracts or to options entered into as hedges 83 to obtain<br />

a timing or character benefit or to arbitrage a return.<br />

III. SUGGESTED CONCEPTUAL APPROACH<br />

This Part develops an economic analysis <strong>of</strong> options that explains<br />

them in terms <strong>of</strong> the actual transactions that the parties to an option<br />

sale enter into. For purposes <strong>of</strong> this basic analysis, it is assumed that<br />

either the put purchaser or the call writer owns the underlier—that<br />

is, the analysis here applies to “covered” options. Subpart A states<br />

the theory and Subpart B provides a demonstration. The object is to<br />

provide an account <strong>of</strong> the economic consequences <strong>of</strong> option sales that<br />

illuminates the basic tax issues they raise. These issues are explored<br />

in Part IV.<br />

The approach developed here relies on the Black-Scholes model for<br />

option pricing, but it does not assume that the model describes what<br />

80. See, e.g., 26 U.S.C. § 246(c)(4) (holding period for purposes <strong>of</strong> dividend received<br />

deduction is not met during periods in which the taxpayer does not bear the risk <strong>of</strong> loss <strong>of</strong><br />

ownership); 26 U.S.C. § 1058(b)(3) (requiring that the owner <strong>of</strong> securities in a securities<br />

lending transaction transfer to the borrower neither the risk <strong>of</strong> loss nor the opportunity for<br />

gain in the securities for the purpose <strong>of</strong> qualifying for nonrecognition treatment under 26<br />

U.S.C. § 1058(a); 26 U.S.C. § 1059(d)(3) (relying on § 246 rules to toll the holding period for<br />

purposes <strong>of</strong> satisfying the holding period exception to the application <strong>of</strong> the extraordinary<br />

dividend basis and gain rules).<br />

81. For example, § 1259, which applies to “constructive sales” <strong>of</strong> “appreciated financial<br />

positions,” deems a disposition <strong>of</strong> such a position to occur where, among other things, a<br />

transaction has the effect <strong>of</strong> disposing <strong>of</strong> the benefits and burdens <strong>of</strong> ownership. See 26<br />

U.S.C. § 1259(c) (listing transactions). In Woodsam Associates, Inc. v. Commissioner, 16<br />

T.C. 649, 655 (1951), the court refused to treat the taxpayer’s nonrecourse borrowing, in<br />

excess <strong>of</strong> its basis in the property securing the debt, as a disposition <strong>of</strong> the property.<br />

82. 26 U.S.C. § 475(a)(2).<br />

83. 26 C.F.R. § 1.446-4(b) (2010) (requiring taxpayers to match the timing <strong>of</strong> a hedging<br />

transaction with the item hedged in a manner that clearly reflects income).


806 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

the parties to an option transaction actually do. Rather, it treats<br />

Black-Scholes as providing the correct mechanism for the pricing <strong>of</strong><br />

financial options, recognizing that Black-Scholes itself is an idealized<br />

model that has great relevance but not direct application to the real<br />

world. 84 Black and Scholes demonstrated how to model the purchase<br />

<strong>of</strong> an option as a combination <strong>of</strong> borrowing and purchasing or lending<br />

and selling fractional parts <strong>of</strong> the underlier, with continuous adjustment<br />

<strong>of</strong> the initial loan and equity amounts as the determinants <strong>of</strong><br />

the option price varied over time. The equivalence they established<br />

makes possible the accurate valuation <strong>of</strong> any financial option under<br />

idealized terms, and this valuation in turn is instrumental in explaining<br />

the actual transactions that parties to an option engage in.<br />

The equivalence does not imply, however, that the parties to the<br />

transaction should be treated as having engaged in the hypothetical<br />

debt and equity transactions that the model posits. 85<br />

A. <strong>State</strong>ment <strong>of</strong> the Theory<br />

A covered option is properly viewed as a division <strong>of</strong> the benefits<br />

and burdens <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier. To the extent the division<br />

is asymmetrical, so that one party assumes risks or acquires benefits<br />

<strong>of</strong> the underlier not associated with correlative benefits or risks <strong>of</strong> it,<br />

the option represents a transfer solely <strong>of</strong> either risk <strong>of</strong> loss or opportunity<br />

for gain in exchange for payment, typically cash. 86 This feature<br />

<strong>of</strong> options has long been well understood. To the extent the division is<br />

symmetrical, so that one party acquires both benefits and correlative<br />

burdens <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier, the option represents an onmarket<br />

forward property disposition. This feature <strong>of</strong> options has not<br />

been well understood. Assuming as a first approximation that there<br />

is no premium associated with the assumption <strong>of</strong> risk, the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the symmetrical transfer equals the value <strong>of</strong> a riskless instrument<br />

generating the associated interest during the option term.<br />

84. The Black-Scholes model makes a number <strong>of</strong> idealizing assumptions about options,<br />

including that volatility <strong>of</strong> the underlier can be known and that it is constant. The<br />

model also applies to simple options on nondividend paying securities, though it has been<br />

elaborated in various ways. For a general criticism <strong>of</strong> Black-Scholes as a model for understanding<br />

the pricing <strong>of</strong> actual options, see Adam H. Rosenzweig, Imperfect Financial Markets<br />

and the Hidden Costs <strong>of</strong> a Modern Income Tax, 62 SMU L. REV. 239, 288 (2009) (describing<br />

as an “open secret” the fact that Black-Scholes is wrong in assuming constant volatility<br />

<strong>of</strong> the underlier).<br />

85. In an earlier article, the author suggested rules for the taxation <strong>of</strong> financial options<br />

based on treating the parties as having engaged in the hypothetical transactions that<br />

Black and Scholes posit. David Hasen, A Realization-Based Approach to the Taxation <strong>of</strong><br />

Financial instruments, 57 TAX L. REV. 397, 439-40. Eric Chason later provided a similar,<br />

though more developed, approach. Chason, supra note 8. The present discussion focuses instead<br />

on the transactions in which the parties to an option actually engage.<br />

86. I thank Patrick White for clarification on this point.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 807<br />

As will be seen, under this theory, the point at which what I call<br />

the true “optionality” <strong>of</strong> an option—either the purchase <strong>of</strong> a fluctuating<br />

return or the <strong>of</strong>floading <strong>of</strong> a fluctuating risk, in either case in exchange<br />

for a fixed fee—reaches its maximum is where the asymmetry<br />

between risk-bearing and benefit-reaping is complete. This point occurs<br />

for options sold at a strike price that equals the forward price <strong>of</strong><br />

the underlier on the strike date, in other words, for options sold (in<br />

present value terms) at the money. Beyond this point—that is, for options<br />

issued in the money—there is simply no more possible <strong>of</strong>floading<br />

solely <strong>of</strong> risk (put option) or purchase solely <strong>of</strong> potential benefit<br />

(call option) with respect to the underlier. Rather, any additional<br />

component <strong>of</strong> the option sale is simply the forward transfer <strong>of</strong> a portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the risk correlative to the potential benefit transferred (call<br />

option) or potential benefit correlative to the risk transferred (put option)<br />

by the owner <strong>of</strong> the underlier that would have remained with<br />

the owner had the option not been ITM. Because this transfer <strong>of</strong> correlative<br />

risk and potential benefit is a transfer <strong>of</strong> both opportunity for<br />

gain and risk <strong>of</strong> loss, it is, if not a property transaction, closely akin<br />

to one. Further, because the slice is a symmetrical transfer <strong>of</strong> potential<br />

risk and potential benefit, its value on the option sale date is<br />

simply the value <strong>of</strong> a debt instrument that would earn the corresponding<br />

time value return during the option period (disregarding, for<br />

the moment, the possibility that risk preferences are asymmetrically<br />

distributed among market participants). 87<br />

Viewed along a spectrum running from options sold out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

money, to options sold at the money, to options sold in the money, the<br />

following then can be said to occur on the option sale date:<br />

� In the OTM case, a portion <strong>of</strong> either the risk <strong>of</strong> loss (put<br />

option) or the opportunity for benefit (call option) associated<br />

with ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier is transferred in exchange<br />

for a cash payment;<br />

� In the ATM case, the entirety <strong>of</strong> either the risk <strong>of</strong> loss or<br />

the opportunity for benefit associated with ownership <strong>of</strong> the<br />

underlier is transferred in return for a cash payment; and<br />

� In the ITM case, a portion <strong>of</strong> either the risk <strong>of</strong> loss or the<br />

opportunity for benefit associated with ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier<br />

is transferred in return for a cash payment, just as in<br />

the OTM case, together with a forward disposition <strong>of</strong> symmetrical<br />

portions <strong>of</strong> the benefits and burdens <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong><br />

the underlier. Because possession <strong>of</strong> the opportunity for<br />

benefit together with the correlative risk <strong>of</strong> loss is typically<br />

87. See infra Part II.B.2.


808 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

paradigmatic <strong>of</strong> tax ownership, 88 this associated transfer can<br />

be considered a forward property transfer.<br />

In short, an ITM option differs from the corresponding OTM option<br />

not by having more “optionality,” but in that the ITM option has an<br />

associated property transfer that actually reduces the optionality as<br />

compared with an ATM option. This analysis explains how options<br />

shade into forward contracts—the greater the extent to which the option<br />

is ITM on the option sale date, the more the option sale constitutes<br />

a symmetrical transfer <strong>of</strong> benefits and burdens. At the limit,<br />

where the strike price is zero, all benefits and burdens have been<br />

transferred on the option sale date. An option with a zero strike price<br />

is a forward sale <strong>of</strong> the underlier. 89<br />

Diagram 1 illustrates these ideas. It contains four pictograms. In<br />

each, the horizontal axis represents the fair market value <strong>of</strong> the underlier<br />

on the exercise date, and the vertical axis represents the extent <strong>of</strong><br />

risk and benefit retained or disposed <strong>of</strong> on that date; A and B are the<br />

parties to the option transaction, except in the first pictogram. For<br />

ease <strong>of</strong> exposition, the risk-free rate at all times is assumed to be zero<br />

and the risk preferences <strong>of</strong> market participants are disregarded.<br />

The first pictogram represents A’s simple ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier.<br />

A retains, by definition, all risk <strong>of</strong> loss and all opportunity for<br />

gain, represented by the arrows going down to zero and up infinitely.<br />

The second pictogram illustrates the effect <strong>of</strong> A’s sale <strong>of</strong> a call option<br />

to B having a strike price <strong>of</strong> S1. B has acquired the upside potential<br />

in excess <strong>of</strong> S1, while A has retained upside potential to that point<br />

as well as all the downside risk <strong>of</strong> underlier. Since S1 exceeds the FMV<br />

on the exercise date, the option is OTM. Note that the option purchaser<br />

bears no risk <strong>of</strong> loss as measured on the option sale date.<br />

The third pictogram represents A’s sale <strong>of</strong> an ATM call option having<br />

a strike price, S2, equal to the underlier’s FMV. Here the optionality—the<br />

separation <strong>of</strong> the opportunity for gain from the risk <strong>of</strong><br />

loss—reaches its maximum. B is entitled to all opportunity for benefit<br />

and bears no risk <strong>of</strong> loss, all <strong>of</strong> which A retains. Under the theory<br />

described above, the option premium paid is at its maximum for this<br />

option, even though ITM options would have higher nominal premiums.<br />

Therefore, although an ITM option, as represented in the<br />

fourth pictogram showing an option with a strike price equal to S3,<br />

88. Grodt & McKay Realty, Inc. v. Comm’r, 77 T.C. 1221,1243-44 (1981).<br />

89. See David F. Levy, Disparities in Tax Treatment Among Prepaid Forward Contracts,<br />

Deep in the Money Options, Prepaid Swaps, and Contingent Debt Instruments, in<br />

TAX STRATEGIES FOR CORPORATE ACQUISITIONS, DISPOSITIONS, SPIN-OFFS, JOINT<br />

VENTURES, FINANCINGS, REORGANIZATIONS &RESTRUCTURINGS, 432 PLI/Tax 729, 745<br />

n.24 (1998) (“Indeed, as the option premium increases and the strike price <strong>of</strong> the option decreases,<br />

the economic differences between a deep in the money purchase option and a standard<br />

prepaid forward contract begin to disappear.”).


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 809<br />

will have a higher nominal option premium than the premium for the<br />

option having the ATM strike price <strong>of</strong> S2, the higher premium will be<br />

made up for in the stream <strong>of</strong> future payments under the option. That<br />

is, the timing <strong>of</strong> payouts under the S3 option hides the fact that the<br />

true swap <strong>of</strong> fluctuating for nonfluctuating payments is the same as<br />

it is under the S1 option and therefore lower than it is under the S2<br />

option. The optionality pieces <strong>of</strong> the S1 and S3 transactions—that is,<br />

the portions that represent the transfer <strong>of</strong> fluctuating benefits for<br />

cash—are the same and are smaller than the optionality piece under<br />

the ATM option (S2).<br />

The fact that the optionality pieces are the same for the depicted<br />

OTM and ITM options does not mean that the two options are the<br />

same. It means only that the way in which they differ has to do with<br />

what else is transferred in the ITM case. In an OTM option, all that<br />

occurs is an exchange <strong>of</strong> a fixed payment for either the right to a portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> fluctuating upside returns (in a call) or the <strong>of</strong>f-loading <strong>of</strong> a<br />

portion <strong>of</strong> fluctuating downside risk (in a put). In the corresponding<br />

ITM option, that same exchange occurs, but there is, in addition, an<br />

on-market forward transfer <strong>of</strong> a symmetrical portion <strong>of</strong> the opportunity<br />

for gain and the risk <strong>of</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> the underlier. This portion is<br />

represented in the fourth pictogram by the dual-pointing arrow that<br />

crosses the FMV line. As contrasted with the swap <strong>of</strong> benefit (or risk<br />

in the case <strong>of</strong> a put) for cash that characterizes the optionality piece,<br />

the only net consideration that travels in the other direction is the interest<br />

that would be earned on the transfer because the owner <strong>of</strong> the<br />

underlier transfers a risk that exactly <strong>of</strong>fsets, in expected value, the<br />

benefit that is also transferred. Diagram 2 summarizes these points.<br />

Diagram 1: Simple Ownership and Three Types <strong>of</strong> Option Transfers


810 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

Diagram 2: Extent <strong>of</strong> Optionality<br />

The obvious objection to this view is that if the option writer in an<br />

ITM option is considered to be absorbing less risk for cash (in the<br />

case <strong>of</strong> a put) or parting with less potential benefit for cash (in the<br />

case <strong>of</strong> a call) than is the writer <strong>of</strong> an ATM option, and if the related<br />

property transaction under an ITM option is not cashed out until the<br />

exercise date (whether or not exercise occurs), then the price for an<br />

ATM option should exceed the price <strong>of</strong> both an OTM option and an<br />

ITM option, other things being equal. In fact, <strong>of</strong> course, the option<br />

price continues to rise as the negotiated terms <strong>of</strong> the option go farther<br />

into the money on the option sale date. For instance, if an OTM<br />

option costs $X on the option sale date, an ATM option having otherwise<br />

identical terms will cost more than $X on that date and an ITM<br />

option will cost still more. The price structure <strong>of</strong> options seems to<br />

suggest that the true optionality increases continuously from deep<br />

OTM, through ATM, to deep ITM.<br />

In fact, the price structure is misleading. The higher price for ITM<br />

options reflects nothing more than a payment scheduling arrangement.<br />

The price increase for the option premium attributable to the<br />

option’s having an ITM strike price is precisely made up for in the<br />

payout structure under the option. Viewed as a whole, the portion <strong>of</strong><br />

the overall ITM option sale that represents an asymmetrical exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> risky returns for nonrisky returns, or what I call the true<br />

option piece <strong>of</strong> an ITM option, is smaller and therefore costs less than<br />

an ATM option by precisely the amount <strong>of</strong> the associated property<br />

disposition. The pure option piece <strong>of</strong> an ITM option, that is, the portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the option premium received in exchange for absorbing risk<br />

(put) or providing opportunity for gain (call), has the same cost as the<br />

identical OTM option.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 811<br />

These considerations indicate that the property disposition portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> an ITM option is actually the mirror image <strong>of</strong> another common<br />

transaction, known as a “collar.” In a collar, the owner <strong>of</strong> property<br />

disposes <strong>of</strong> the potential upside benefit above a certain price as well<br />

as the risk <strong>of</strong> loss below a certain price, retaining opportunity for<br />

gain and risk <strong>of</strong> loss in-between. 90 For example, A may own XYZ<br />

stock having a current fair market value <strong>of</strong> $100. If A sells a call at<br />

$110 and buys a put at $90, A retains the opportunity for gain and<br />

risk <strong>of</strong> loss within the $90 to $110 band but has disposed <strong>of</strong> the remaining<br />

opportunity and risk. In the property disposition portion <strong>of</strong> a<br />

mirror ITM option, the property owner would retain the opportunity<br />

for gain above $110 and the risk <strong>of</strong> loss below $90 but dispose <strong>of</strong> the<br />

opportunity and risk in-between. The only difference between this retention<br />

and an actual ITM option is that the on-market property disposition<br />

in the ITM option is married to an OTM option, so that either<br />

the remaining downside risk (in the case <strong>of</strong> a put) or the remaining<br />

upside potential (in the case <strong>of</strong> a call) accompanies the symmetrical<br />

disposition <strong>of</strong> opportunity and risk. This additional transfer also<br />

serves to obscure the forward property disposition that occurs in<br />

the ITM portion <strong>of</strong> an ITM option.<br />

B. Demonstration<br />

The following illustrations convey these ideas in a series <strong>of</strong> steps. In<br />

Section 1, the assumed risk-free rate is zero and parties’ risk preferences<br />

are disregarded. These assumptions are made to illustrate the<br />

basic nature <strong>of</strong> option transactions, and they are relaxed in Section 2.<br />

In addition, the discussion does not begin with an option, but with the<br />

type <strong>of</strong> nonoption property disposition that occurs in an ITM option.<br />

True option arrangements are then added (i.e., exchanges, for cash, <strong>of</strong><br />

risk <strong>of</strong> loss or opportunity for benefit), showing that the resulting<br />

transactions are identical to options observed in the marketplace.<br />

Throughout this Subpart: (1) Owner is the owner <strong>of</strong> Underlier, a<br />

piece <strong>of</strong> fungible property worth $100 on the option sale date; and<br />

(2) Purchaser agrees on the option sale date to purchase some or all<br />

<strong>of</strong> the property from Owner, to engage in related transactions on the<br />

exercise date, or both.<br />

1. Risk Neutrality and Zero Risk-Free Rate<br />

In this Section, the risk-free rate <strong>of</strong> return is assumed to be 0%<br />

and risk preferences are assumed to be neutrally distributed among<br />

90. See, e.g., 26 C.F.R. § 1.446-3(f)(2)(v) (2010) (prescribing the tax treatment <strong>of</strong> collars<br />

embedded in a notional principal contract).


812 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

market participants, meaning that no one pays a premium to assume<br />

risk or to shed it.<br />

a. Neutral Disposition <strong>of</strong> Upside Potential and Downside Risk<br />

Consider first a basic forward transfer <strong>of</strong> the opportunity for gain<br />

and the risk <strong>of</strong> loss on a portion <strong>of</strong> Underlier.<br />

Transaction 1: On-market division. On Day 1, Owner<br />

sells Purchaser the first 25% <strong>of</strong> the upside potential and<br />

Purchaser agrees to assume the first 25% <strong>of</strong> the downside<br />

risk in the price <strong>of</strong> Underlier as measured on Day 2, one<br />

year later.<br />

In Transaction 1, the only transfer that occurs on Day 1 is <strong>of</strong> the<br />

risks and benefits associated with the 25% disposition. Because the<br />

interest rate is zero, Purchaser will pay nothing to Owner on Day 1.<br />

(If on Day 1 Purchaser wished to acquire the 25% interest on Day 2,<br />

Purchaser could also promise on Day 1 to pay, on Day 2, 25% <strong>of</strong> the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> Underlier as measured on Day 1. Of course, in the financial<br />

instruments context, either party is indifferent between ownership <strong>of</strong><br />

the market value <strong>of</strong> a property right and the property right itself.)<br />

The parties could effect Transaction 1 by entering into (1) a forward<br />

sale <strong>of</strong> Underlier on Day 1 for $100 with a settlement date <strong>of</strong> Day 2,<br />

(2) Purchaser’s sale to Owner <strong>of</strong> a call on Underlier with a strike<br />

price equal to $100 plus the appreciation up to the first 25% <strong>of</strong> expected<br />

upside benefit as measured on Day 2 and a strike date <strong>of</strong> Day<br />

2, and (3) Owner’s sale to Purchaser <strong>of</strong> a put with a strike price equal<br />

to $100 less the decline up to the first 25% <strong>of</strong> expected downside risk<br />

as measured on Day 2 and a strike date <strong>of</strong> Day 2. The values <strong>of</strong> (2)<br />

and (3), by hypothesis, are equal and <strong>of</strong>fsetting. Further, since the<br />

parties are willing to cash-settle Transaction 1, they could do so<br />

simply by agreeing, instead <strong>of</strong> to transactions (1) through (3), that on<br />

Day 2 Owner would pay Purchaser the actual appreciation, if any, up<br />

to the amount representing the first 25% <strong>of</strong> the potential upside benefit<br />

in Underlier as measured on Day 1. Purchaser would then pay<br />

Owner the actual decline in value, if any, up to the amount<br />

representing the first 25% <strong>of</strong> the potential downside risk, also as<br />

measured on Day 1.<br />

The range <strong>of</strong> values that corresponds to the first 25% <strong>of</strong> the opportunity<br />

for benefit and risk <strong>of</strong> loss in Underlier can be computed using<br />

the familiar Black-Scholes option pricing theorem. This is done by<br />

setting the put and call option premiums equal to 75% <strong>of</strong> the price <strong>of</strong><br />

an ATM option (put or call) as measured on Day 2 and deriving the<br />

associated option strike prices. In dollar terms, this range will be<br />

asymmetrical around the Day 2 forward price (as measured on Day<br />

1), or $100, because on Day 2 Underlier can assume any positive val-


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 813<br />

ue but no negative value. 91 Assuming moderate volatility <strong>of</strong> 10%, the<br />

range is $102.27 to $97.94. 92 Thus, Owner will pay Purchaser the<br />

excess, if any, <strong>of</strong> the value on Day 2 <strong>of</strong> Underlier over $100, up to<br />

$102.27, and Purchaser will pay Owner the excess, if any, <strong>of</strong> $100<br />

over the value on Day 2 <strong>of</strong> Underlier, down to $97.94.<br />

b. Neutral Disposition Plus OTM Put Option<br />

Now suppose that in addition to Transaction 1, Purchaser agrees<br />

on Day 1 to pay the drop in value, if any, <strong>of</strong> Underlier below $97.94,<br />

as measured on Day 2.<br />

Transaction 2: Division plus put option. The facts are<br />

the same as in Transaction 1, but Purchaser also agrees to<br />

pay the excess, if any, <strong>of</strong> $97.94 over the FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier<br />

on Day 2. Owner transfers $3.00 to Purchaser on Day 1. The<br />

parties agree to cash-settle on Day 2.<br />

Note that Transaction 2 differs from Transaction 1 solely in that it<br />

adds Purchaser’s sale <strong>of</strong> an OTM put to Owner with a strike price <strong>of</strong><br />

$97.94. The put option part <strong>of</strong> Transaction 2 is the transfer <strong>of</strong> risk<br />

with respect to possible declines below $97.49. Under the same assumptions<br />

about Underlier as apply in Transaction 1, the put value<br />

under the Black-Scholes formula is $3.00.<br />

On Day 2, the following outcomes are possible in Transaction 2:<br />

1. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier equals or exceeds $102.27: Owner<br />

pays Purchaser $2.27.<br />

2. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier is between $100 and $102.27: Owner<br />

pays Purchaser the excess <strong>of</strong> the FMV over $100.<br />

3. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier is less than $100: Purchaser pays<br />

Owner the difference between $100 and the FMV. 93<br />

The critical point to recognize is that the precise economic arrangement<br />

that Transaction 2 effects can be replicated under a number<br />

<strong>of</strong> different payment schedules. Owner can pay less or more up<br />

front in exchange for more or less payment on Day 2, as long as interest<br />

is appropriately accounted for. (And since, under the simplified<br />

91. The Black-Scholes theorem accounts for this asymmetry through the assumption<br />

that returns are log-normally rather than normally distributed about the forward price.<br />

See HULL, supra note 1, at 277-79.<br />

92. These figures represent the strike prices <strong>of</strong> a call priced at $3 and a put priced at<br />

$3 when an ATM (whether put or call) is priced at $4. The analysis would not change if the<br />

volatility were different, though the range <strong>of</strong> prices would change.<br />

93. That is, Purchaser pays up to $2.06 under the piece <strong>of</strong> Transaction 2 that Transaction<br />

1 represents, and Purchaser pays the excess, if any, <strong>of</strong> $97.94 over the FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier<br />

on Day 2, which is Purchaser’s obligation under the put part <strong>of</strong> Transaction 2. This<br />

sum is the same as what is stated in the text.


814 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

assumptions here, the interest rate is zero, there is no discounting effect<br />

from prepayment.) In particular, suppose the parties wanted to<br />

ensure that Owner’s only payment to Purchaser occurs on Day 1.<br />

They could agree to the following:<br />

Transaction 3: Division plus option plus prepayment.<br />

Same as Transaction 2, but Owner pays an additional $2.27<br />

to Purchaser on Day 1, for a total <strong>of</strong> $5.27, and receives an<br />

additional $2.27 under each payout scenario. The parties<br />

agree to cash-settle on Day 2.<br />

The payouts <strong>of</strong> Transaction 3 on Day 2 are as follows:<br />

1. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier equals or exceeds $102.27: No payments.<br />

2. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier is less than $102.27: Purchaser pays<br />

Owner difference between $102.27 and FMV.<br />

The net value <strong>of</strong> Transaction 3 is exactly the same as that <strong>of</strong><br />

Transaction 2 because all that has happened is that $2.27 more has<br />

been paid to Purchaser up front and, in each case, the same $2.27 has<br />

been subtracted from Purchaser’s payout or added to Purchaser’s<br />

payment obligation on Day 2. Because the discount rate is assumed<br />

to be 0% in this pattern, the present value on Day 1 <strong>of</strong> $2.27 on Day 2<br />

is $2.27.<br />

Note, however, that Transaction 3 has exactly the same payout<br />

structure as an ITM put option.<br />

Transaction 4: ITM put option. Owner pays Purchaser<br />

$5.27 on Day 1 in exchange for the right to sell Underlier to<br />

Purchaser on Day 2 for $102.27. The parties cash-settle the<br />

obligation on Day 2.<br />

It is in fact the case that under the same Black-Scholes pricing<br />

model that produced the price <strong>of</strong> $3.00 for an OTM put with a strike<br />

price <strong>of</strong> $97.94, the price <strong>of</strong> a $102.27 put option for Underlier on<br />

these terms is $5.27. In other words, this ITM put is the same as an<br />

OTM put plus the associated property transfer described in Transaction<br />

1. As explained above, this result should not be surprising because<br />

it is not possible for the option writer to provide more price<br />

protection with respect to the underlier than is available under an<br />

ATM option. 94<br />

94. The statement should be qualified because the parties could enter into an arrangement<br />

in which the option writer agrees to overcompensate the option holder for a<br />

drop in price (or, for that matter, to supplement an increase in price). For example, the<br />

parties to a put option could provide that the option writer would pay the option holder 1.5<br />

times the drop in price, if any, prior to exercise. Such a transaction would in effect mimic<br />

the option holder’s purchase <strong>of</strong> an additional interest in the underlier, together with more


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 815<br />

The preceding discussion suggests the following points:<br />

� An ATM option represents nothing more than the complete<br />

separation <strong>of</strong> the benefits and burdens <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong><br />

the underlier between the parties to the option transaction.<br />

� An OTM option is the same as an ATM option, except<br />

that it is a separation <strong>of</strong> a smaller percentage <strong>of</strong> the total<br />

benefits and burdens.<br />

� An ITM option is the same as an OTM option plus the onmarket<br />

forward sale <strong>of</strong> a portion <strong>of</strong> the benefits and correlative<br />

burdens <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier. That is, in an<br />

ITM option, some <strong>of</strong> the exchange <strong>of</strong> fluctuating returns<br />

(call) or risks (put) for fixed consideration that would otherwise<br />

be supplied in an ATM option is replaced by a correlative<br />

transfer <strong>of</strong> the risks (call) or fluctuating returns (put) <strong>of</strong><br />

some <strong>of</strong> the underlier, and the balance is an OTM option<br />

transaction. The transfer <strong>of</strong> fluctuating returns and correlative<br />

risks is a transfer <strong>of</strong> ownership. On the facts above, the<br />

swap <strong>of</strong> variable risk for cash in the ITM put option—that is,<br />

the true option piece—is the same as the swap provided under<br />

the OTM put having a strike price <strong>of</strong> $97.94.<br />

o To the extent the ITM option involves the symmetrical<br />

transfer <strong>of</strong> risks and benefits about the FMV expected<br />

on the strike date, it is the mirror image <strong>of</strong> a collar.<br />

In a collar, one party retains the risks and benefits<br />

over a range <strong>of</strong> values straddling the FMV and disposes<br />

<strong>of</strong> the benefits above that range and the risks below it.<br />

A party creates a collar by writing a call at the abovemarket<br />

price and purchasing a put at the below-market<br />

price. In general, the put and call prices are the same if<br />

the percentages <strong>of</strong> risk and benefit disposed <strong>of</strong> are the<br />

same.<br />

The ITM portion <strong>of</strong> an ITM option is the mirror image<br />

<strong>of</strong> a collar in that the purchaser <strong>of</strong> the collar retains the<br />

value straddling the FMV on the strike date and disposes<br />

<strong>of</strong> the tails <strong>of</strong> the distribution, while the call seller<br />

or put purchaser sells the straddling portion and retains<br />

the tails.<br />

� The fact that an ITM option costs more than an OTM or<br />

ATM option reflects nothing more than a payment arrange-<br />

price protection. I omit consideration <strong>of</strong> such arrangements here, as they are not observed<br />

in the market (as far as I am aware). Further, the same basic analysis would apply, though<br />

with more complexity.


816 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

ment between the parties; no additional consideration is exchanged<br />

for the ITM portion apart from interest or a risk<br />

premium.<br />

c. Extension to Call Option<br />

A call option differs from a put in that the writer disposes <strong>of</strong> upside<br />

potential instead <strong>of</strong> assuming downside risk. The net effect,<br />

however, is the same: the option sale effects an asymmetrical distribution<br />

<strong>of</strong> risks and benefits in the underlier so that the writer possesses<br />

risks not associated with <strong>of</strong>fsetting benefits. As in the case <strong>of</strong> a<br />

put, the maximum optionality occurs when the option writer ends up<br />

with all downside risk and the option holder has all the upside potential—namely,<br />

an ATM call. When the option is OTM on the option<br />

sale date, there is less potential benefit transferred and, correspondingly,<br />

a lower option price. Where the option is ITM on the option<br />

sale date, there is a greater option price than in the ATM case, but<br />

only because a part <strong>of</strong> the price represents the same type <strong>of</strong> forward<br />

transfer that arises in the case <strong>of</strong> a put—that is, a disposition <strong>of</strong> a<br />

symmetrical portion <strong>of</strong> the burdens and benefits <strong>of</strong> the underlier.<br />

The following examples, which use the same assumptions as in<br />

the case <strong>of</strong> the put, illustrate these points. First, recall Transaction 1:<br />

On-market division. On Day 1, Owner sells Purchaser the first 25%<br />

<strong>of</strong> the upside potential and Purchaser agrees to assume the first 25%<br />

<strong>of</strong> the downside potential in Underlier between Day 1 and Day 2, one<br />

year thereafter.<br />

It was shown that the price range corresponding to the first 25%<br />

<strong>of</strong> the benefits and burdens is $102.27 to $97.94. Thus, if the parties<br />

cash-settle, then on Day 2, Owner pays Purchaser the excess, if any,<br />

<strong>of</strong> the difference between Underlier’s FMV and $100, up to $2.27. At<br />

the same time, Purchaser pays the excess, if any, <strong>of</strong> the difference between<br />

$100 and Underlier’s FMV, up to $2.06.<br />

Additionally, the parties could effect Transaction 1 with a different<br />

schedule <strong>of</strong> payments. In the case <strong>of</strong> a call option, Owner writes<br />

the option, so the parties can arrange for a single payment by having<br />

Purchaser rather than Owner prepay.<br />

Transaction 1a: On-market division with prepayment.<br />

Same as Transaction 1, except that on Day 1, Purchaser<br />

pays Owner $2.06, and on Day 2 Owner will net a<br />

$2.06 payment to Purchaser with whatever other payment is<br />

required on that day to effect the transfer <strong>of</strong> the first 25% <strong>of</strong><br />

upside potential and downside risk.<br />

The only difference between Transactions 1 and 1a is that the parties<br />

have rearranged the timing <strong>of</strong> their payments. In Transaction 1a,


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 817<br />

on Day 2, Owner pays Purchaser the excess, if any, <strong>of</strong> the difference<br />

between Underlier’s FMV and $97.94, up to $102.27.<br />

Finally, suppose that the parties engage in the following transaction,<br />

in addition to Transaction 1a.<br />

Transaction 5: OTM call. On Day 1, Owner separately<br />

sells an OTM call to Purchaser with a strike price <strong>of</strong><br />

$102.27, exercisable on Day 2, in one year.<br />

The price <strong>of</strong> the call is $3.00. Assume again that all transactions<br />

are cash-settled. As in the put option case, the payouts under the<br />

combination <strong>of</strong> Transaction 1a and Transaction 5 are the same as<br />

under Owner’s simple sale <strong>of</strong> an ITM call to Purchaser with a strike<br />

price <strong>of</strong> $97.94. Moreover, Purchaser’s combined payment on Day 1 <strong>of</strong><br />

$5.06 is the same as the Black-Scholes price for this ITM call. 95<br />

2. Positive Risk-Free Rate<br />

This Section extends the analysis <strong>of</strong> Section 1 to the more realistic<br />

setting in which the risk-free rate <strong>of</strong> return is positive. In this context,<br />

the transfer <strong>of</strong> funds gives rise to an interest payment for the<br />

use <strong>of</strong> money, whether or not the interest payment is expressly broken<br />

out. Consequently, in addition to the exchange <strong>of</strong> risky returns<br />

for a fixed payment and, in the case <strong>of</strong> an ITM option, the transfer <strong>of</strong><br />

beneficial ownership <strong>of</strong> a portion <strong>of</strong> the underlier, there also will be<br />

interest paid in the transaction. If the analysis under the zero riskfree<br />

rate holds, the same results should follow as before, except that<br />

this interest piece should be present as well.<br />

All assumptions in this Section are the same as in Section 1,<br />

except that the hypothetical risk-free rate is 10% and it is compounded<br />

continuously.<br />

a. Neutral Disposition <strong>of</strong> Upside Potential and Downside Risk<br />

Consider again a basic forward transfer <strong>of</strong> equal and <strong>of</strong>fsetting<br />

opportunity for gain and risk <strong>of</strong> loss on Underlier.<br />

Transaction 6: On-market division. On Day 1, Owner<br />

sells Purchaser the first 25% <strong>of</strong> the upside potential and<br />

Purchaser agrees to assume the first 25% <strong>of</strong> the downside<br />

risk in the price <strong>of</strong> Underlier as measured on and Day 2, one<br />

year thereafter.<br />

95. The cost <strong>of</strong> the option is $5.06, rather than $5.27 in the case <strong>of</strong> a put, because the<br />

cost <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>floading the first 25% <strong>of</strong> the downside potential is $2.06, while the cost <strong>of</strong> purchasing<br />

the first 25% <strong>of</strong> upside is $2.27. This difference reflects the fact that in an option, the<br />

minimum value the underlier can take on the exercise date is 0, while there is in principle<br />

no maximum value, and in the call case the payment goes in the other direction. See generally<br />

HULL, supra note 1, at 277-79.


818 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

At a continuously compounded rate <strong>of</strong> 10%, the expected value <strong>of</strong><br />

Underlier on Day 2 is $110.52, 96 and the price <strong>of</strong> either a call or a put<br />

with that strike price would, as in the case <strong>of</strong> a zero risk-free rate, be<br />

$4. Analogously, an on-market disposition <strong>of</strong> the first 25% <strong>of</strong> potential<br />

upside gain and the first 25% <strong>of</strong> downside risk would correspond<br />

to a range <strong>of</strong> values for Underlier on Day 2 bounded by the strike<br />

prices for a call and a put each having a cost <strong>of</strong> $3.00. This range is<br />

$108.24 as the strike price for the put to $113.02 as the strike price<br />

for the call. The only difference between this case and the zero riskfree<br />

rate case is that the range over which payments will be made on<br />

Day 2 has shifted up and expanded by the amount <strong>of</strong> interest expected.<br />

97 If on Day 2 Underlier has appreciated, Owner pays Purchaser<br />

the lesser <strong>of</strong> $2.50 (equal to $113.02 less $110.52) or the difference<br />

between Underlier’s FMV on Day 2 and $110.52. If on Day 2<br />

Underlier has declined in value, Purchaser pays Owner the lesser <strong>of</strong><br />

$2.28 (equal to $110.52 less $108.24) or the difference between<br />

$110.52 and Underlier’s FMV on Day 2.<br />

b. Neutral Disposition Plus OTM Put Option<br />

The same ITM put option that was replicated through the combination<br />

<strong>of</strong> an OTM put and a neutral on-market division when the riskfree<br />

rate was assumed to be zero looks as follows under a 10% rate:<br />

Transaction 7: Division plus OTM put option. Same as<br />

Transaction 6, but Purchaser also agrees to pay the excess,<br />

if any, <strong>of</strong> $108.24 over the FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier on Day 2. Owner<br />

transfers $3.00 to Purchaser on Day 1. The parties agree<br />

to cash-settle on Day 2.<br />

The payout structure under this combination is as follows:<br />

1. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier equals or exceeds $113.02: Owner<br />

pays Purchaser $2.50.<br />

2. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier is between $113.02 and $110.52:<br />

Owner pays Purchaser the excess <strong>of</strong> the FMV over $110.52.<br />

3. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier is less than $110.52: Purchaser pays<br />

Owner the difference between $110.52 and the FMV. 98<br />

96. The formula for continuous compounding is FV = Pe Yr , where FV is future value, e<br />

is the base <strong>of</strong> the natural logarithm, Y is the number <strong>of</strong> years to maturity and r is the interest<br />

rate expressed as a decimal.<br />

97. Thus, the spread between $97.96 and $102.27 is $4.33. The $4.33 invested at 10%<br />

with continuous compounding for one year is $4.78, which is the difference between<br />

$113.02 and $108.24, the spread on Day 2 in Transaction 6.<br />

98. That is, Purchaser pays up to $2.28 under the piece <strong>of</strong> Transaction 7 that Transaction<br />

6 represents, and Purchaser pays the excess, if any, <strong>of</strong> $108.24 over the FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier<br />

on Day 2, which is Purchaser’s obligation under the OTM put portion <strong>of</strong> Transaction 7.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 819<br />

As before, this transaction can be replicated under a payment<br />

schedule that is front-loaded so that Owner pays Purchaser just once,<br />

on Day 1, with no change to the underlying economics. As in the zero<br />

risk-free rate case, this adjustment requires that the maximum<br />

amount Owner may be required to pay on Day 2 under Transaction 7<br />

be incorporated into the payments on Day 1. The difference, however,<br />

is that because the risk-free rate is non-zero, the Day 1 additional<br />

payment must be appropriately discounted. In Transaction 7, Owner’s<br />

maximum payout on Day 2 is $2.50. Owner can be guaranteed<br />

not to have to make that payout on Day 2 if on Day 1 Owner pays, in<br />

addition to the $3.00 for the OTM put option, the present value <strong>of</strong><br />

$2.50 as measured on Day 2 and, in exchange, receives $2.50 more on<br />

Day 2 than Owner would have received in Transaction 7. The value<br />

on Day 1 <strong>of</strong> $2.50 as measured on Day 2 is $2.26. 99 Therefore, the<br />

parties can replicate Transaction 7 as follows:<br />

Transaction 8: Division plus option plus prepayment.<br />

Same as Transaction 7, but Owner pays an additional $2.26<br />

to Purchaser on Day 1, for a total <strong>of</strong> $5.26, and receives an<br />

additional $2.50 under each payout scenario. The parties<br />

agree to cash-settle on Day 2.<br />

The payouts <strong>of</strong> Transaction 8 on Day 2 are as follows:<br />

1. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier equals or exceeds $113.02: No payments.<br />

2. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier is between $110.52 and $113.02: Purchaser<br />

pays Owner difference between $113.02 and FMV.<br />

3. FMV <strong>of</strong> Underlier is less than $110.52: Purchaser pays<br />

Owner $2.50 plus difference between $110.52 and FMV, or<br />

difference between $113.02 and FMV.<br />

This payout structure is the same as that for an ITM put having a<br />

strike price <strong>of</strong> $113.02, and, again, the Black-Scholes price for this<br />

option is $5.26.<br />

c. Accounting for the Time Value <strong>of</strong> Money<br />

The discussion above indicates that the analysis when the riskfree<br />

rate is positive does not differ from the analysis when the riskfree<br />

rate is zero, except that the time value <strong>of</strong> money plays a role. Its<br />

presence in the ITM option is easiest to see because the price structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> the portion <strong>of</strong> the ITM option that represents a disposition <strong>of</strong><br />

economic ownership (risk and correlative benefit) incorporates a discount<br />

rate on the prepayment. Discounting, however, is no less<br />

99. That is, $2.26 invested at 10% continuously compounded yields $2.50 in one year.


820 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

present in the true option piece. If the portion <strong>of</strong> the option premium<br />

that represents an exchange <strong>of</strong> fluctuating returns for a fixed payment<br />

were unconditionally due on the exercise date rather than payable<br />

on the option sale date, the premium would be more expensive<br />

by an amount equal to the accrued interest on the premium between<br />

the date <strong>of</strong> entry into the option and the exercise date. 100<br />

However, the fact that one can impute an interest rate to establish<br />

economic equivalents between payments made on Day 1 and on Day<br />

2 does not settle the question <strong>of</strong> whether an interest or discounting<br />

element is present in the standard option transaction, where the option<br />

premium is paid on Day 1. In particular, it does not demonstrate<br />

that the option purchaser gets the benefit <strong>of</strong> a discounted price for<br />

the option. That benefit arises only if the option premium is economically<br />

prepaid—that is, if the benefit that the option purchaser obtains<br />

is received later than the payment date. If so, then there has been an<br />

extension <strong>of</strong> the use <strong>of</strong> money for a period <strong>of</strong> time, which is to say a<br />

loan, rather than a simultaneous exchange <strong>of</strong> consideration for goods<br />

or services. 101 To illustrate, if on Day 1 A and B agree that A will pay<br />

B today for services to be rendered in one year, interest should be<br />

imputed to A (and deemed paid by B) on the implicit loan that runs<br />

from A to B: the price to A would be higher if A paid for the services<br />

when rendered in one year. 102 The difference between the price A actually<br />

pays and what the services would cost if paid for when rendered<br />

is an interest charge. Analogously, if on Day 1 A and B agree<br />

that B will provide the service to A immediately and A will pay for<br />

them in one year and performance actually occurs in one year, then<br />

the loan runs in the other direction—from B to A.<br />

In the option context, the question is whether the option purchaser<br />

receives an immediate or ongoing benefit from the time the option<br />

is entered into, in which case the premium is at most partially discounted<br />

and therefore partially a loan, or instead the purchaser receives<br />

a benefit only on the exercise date (or dates, for American options).<br />

In the latter case, the loan element is clear: the option writer<br />

is paid now for benefits delivered only later. The considerations developed<br />

in Part II suggest that all benefits <strong>of</strong> the option transaction<br />

materialize economically on the exercise date (or dates); therefore,<br />

that interest does economically arise on all parts <strong>of</strong> the premium<br />

prior to that time. Consider first a simple European option, under<br />

which the option purchaser acquires a right that may be exercised on<br />

100. See Daniel I. Halperin, Interest in Disguise: Taxing the “Time Value <strong>of</strong> Money”, 95<br />

YALE L.J. 506, 512-15 (1986).<br />

101. Klein, supra note 69, at 1709-10.<br />

102. See generally Halperin, supra note 100, at 512-15.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 821<br />

only one exercise date. Although, as one commentator observes, 103 the<br />

option purchaser acquires a valuable right on the option purchase<br />

date, that fact merely establishes that future rights have a present<br />

value, not that benefits are conferred when the future right is acquired.<br />

The purchaser <strong>of</strong> a remainder interest in property also acquires<br />

valuable rights on purchase, but it does not appear that the<br />

rights are used prior to the ripening <strong>of</strong> the interest. The question,<br />

therefore, is not whether the option purchaser acquires a valuable<br />

right on the option purchase date. Rather, it is whether any <strong>of</strong> the<br />

rights so acquired are immediately cashed out, and it seems clear<br />

that they are not. If they were, one would expect a systematic decline<br />

in the value <strong>of</strong> rights during the period between the option purchase<br />

date and the exercise date. No such decline takes place. Indeed, one<br />

does not imagine that if, after the option sale, the option writer signaled<br />

that it would default on the exercise date, the option holder’s<br />

damages would be discounted by the portion <strong>of</strong> the pre-exercise period<br />

that had elapsed. Further, on the writer side, nothing is required<br />

until the exercise date. Prior to that time, the writer merely stands<br />

ready to perform.<br />

The question is more difficult for an American option. The analysis<br />

runs the same for the period prior to the first exercise date, but it<br />

is less clear how to analyze the period during which exercise is possible.<br />

In purely legal terms, during the exercise period, the option writer<br />

has an ongoing obligation to do something until the earlier <strong>of</strong> exercise<br />

or lapse, suggesting that benefits may be provided continuously<br />

during the exercise period. Even so, the fact <strong>of</strong> an on-going obligation<br />

does not seem to give rise to the transfer <strong>of</strong> an on-going benefit or<br />

service. Unlike a person who contracts to provide services as needed<br />

over a fixed period <strong>of</strong> time, the obligation under an option contract is<br />

singular. The option writer has only one obligation; prior to fulfilling<br />

it, the writer need do nothing, just as during the pre-exercise period.<br />

Conversely, once exercise occurs, the duty is fully discharged. The only<br />

difference between the writer’s obligations before the exercise period<br />

and during the period prior to exercise is that the writer may be<br />

more constrained in its use <strong>of</strong> resources because it must have the resources<br />

on hand at all times from the first exercise date until exercise<br />

or lapse. This heightened obligation appears to be relatively trivial.<br />

Further, the case for treating the service as provided on exercise is<br />

even stronger in economic, as opposed to legal, terms. As a matter <strong>of</strong><br />

economic theory, any call option should be exercised on the last day<br />

<strong>of</strong> the exercise period because <strong>of</strong> the benefit in ex ante terms that the<br />

103. Kevin J. Liss, Options as Disguised Financings: The Demise <strong>of</strong> an Urban Tax Legend,<br />

27 VA.TAX REV. 907, 927-30 (2008).


822 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

passage <strong>of</strong> time has on its value. 104 Under the reasonable assumption<br />

that holders <strong>of</strong> financial options act solely on the basis <strong>of</strong> the economic<br />

dictates <strong>of</strong> their positions, an American call option should be<br />

viewed as equivalent to a European call option whose strike date is<br />

the last day <strong>of</strong> the American option’s strike period. This general rule<br />

must be qualified for put options because the value <strong>of</strong> the right to invest<br />

the proceeds <strong>of</strong> sale on exercise <strong>of</strong> the put may exceed the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the potential fluctuations in the underlier price, depending on the<br />

extent to which the put is ITM during the exercise period, the volatility<br />

<strong>of</strong> the underlier, and the risk-free rate. 105 Nonetheless, the fact<br />

that all <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the put, like that <strong>of</strong> a call, is realized on exercise<br />

suggests again that all benefits, if any, are realized on exercise.<br />

3. Risk Premium<br />

The discussion to this point has disregarded the market in risk;<br />

instead, it has proceeded on the assumption that market participants<br />

are as apt to take on risk as to lay it <strong>of</strong>f, with the consequence that no<br />

party to the option transaction receives a fee to engage in the transaction.<br />

In practice, however, risk-bearing is costly because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

marginal utility <strong>of</strong> wealth, which means there is a systematic bias<br />

against risk assumption. 106 Individuals with low wealth will suffer a<br />

greater subjective cost from the loss <strong>of</strong> a dollar than they will enjoy a<br />

benefit from the gain <strong>of</strong> a dollar, while individuals with greater<br />

wealth are less subject to these costs. Thus, wealthier individuals<br />

tend to assume more risk than poorer ones. For example, individuals<br />

increase the proportion <strong>of</strong> fixed to variable returns in their portfolios<br />

as they age because 107 time is an inchoate form <strong>of</strong> wealth that investors<br />

transform into material wealth by investing in riskier returns<br />

earlier in their lives. Earlier generations pay later ones to do this.<br />

Similarly, more skilled individuals such as dealers or traders bear<br />

risk as a service to others and receive compensation for doing so. The<br />

compensation is typically observed in such items as the spreads that<br />

dealers charge, insurance fees, and the systematic difference between<br />

fixed and floating rates <strong>of</strong> interest observed in swap transactions. 108<br />

The phenomenon <strong>of</strong> fixed-for-floating-exchange that lies at the<br />

core <strong>of</strong> any option transaction might suggest that put writers and call<br />

purchasers systematically charge a premium to take on downside<br />

risk or to cash out upside benefit in any option arrangement. The in-<br />

104. HULL, supra note 1, at 211-12.<br />

105. Id. at 212-14.<br />

106. See generally Sergio Pastorello et al., Statistical Inference for Random-Variance<br />

Option Pricing, 18 J. BUS.&ECON.STAT. 358 (2000).<br />

107. Nancy Ammon Jianakoplos & Alexandra Bernasek, Financial Risk Taking by Age<br />

and Birth Cohort, 72 S. ECON. J. 981, 983 (2006).<br />

108. See generally id.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 823<br />

tuition is clear in the case <strong>of</strong> put writers, who enable the option purchaser<br />

to cash out all downside risk for a fixed price while retaining<br />

the opportunity to benefit from market appreciation. The extension to<br />

call purchasers, however, does not hold. The reason for this is that<br />

risk premiums are present because <strong>of</strong> the unpredictability <strong>of</strong> losses,<br />

not <strong>of</strong> returns generally whether losses or gains. 109 It is the prospect<br />

<strong>of</strong> a loss, which is more costly for persons <strong>of</strong> relatively lower wealth,<br />

that generates a risk premium. Bearing in mind that the owner <strong>of</strong><br />

any underlier can eliminate all risk simply by selling the underlier<br />

and investing in a riskless instrument, the owner <strong>of</strong> the underlier<br />

will not sell a call to lock in a fixed upside while continuing to bear<br />

downside risk unless the owner is paid a fee. That fee is a risk premium.<br />

Thus, in general, option holders pay option writers a risk<br />

premium. This premium should be observable as a higher option<br />

premium for both puts and calls, to the extent in either case the<br />

holder acquires a floating benefit or disposes <strong>of</strong> a floating loss.<br />

This analysis suggests a testable hypothesis. The theory developed<br />

in this paper is that all options contain an asymmetric exchange <strong>of</strong> a<br />

fixed payment either to receive a variable benefit (call option), or to<br />

shed an unknown risk (put option), and that ITM options contain a<br />

shift <strong>of</strong> a portion <strong>of</strong> the symmetric benefits and burdens <strong>of</strong> ownership<br />

<strong>of</strong> the underlier. The discussion <strong>of</strong> risk in this Section indicates that<br />

to the extent options are asymmetric exchanges <strong>of</strong> fluctuating for<br />

known returns (that is, not ITM), the writer <strong>of</strong> the option will charge<br />

a fee. However, to the extent an option is ITM, a portion <strong>of</strong> the benefits<br />

and burdens <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier are shifted to the party<br />

that would own the underlier (or an equivalent cash value) should<br />

the option be exercised. Therefore, in the case <strong>of</strong> an ITM call, one<br />

would expect the risk premium a call writer receives respecting the<br />

non-ITM portion <strong>of</strong> the option to be <strong>of</strong>fset by the risk premium the<br />

option holder receives respecting the ITM portion, since the ITM portion<br />

involves an assumption <strong>of</strong> both opportunity and risk. In other<br />

words, observed risk premiums for calls should reach a maximum<br />

when the strike price is ATM on the option sale date and then decline<br />

rapidly for strike prices on the option sale date that are deeper ITM.<br />

Indeed, the net risk premium should shift in the direction <strong>of</strong> the call<br />

purchaser once the purchaser is bearing more than half the risk <strong>of</strong><br />

ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier–in other words, well before the strike<br />

price reaches zero, which is simply a prepaid forward contract.<br />

A similar though less dramatic phenomenon should be observable<br />

in the case <strong>of</strong> a put option. The risk premium reaches its maximum<br />

when the option is sold ATM. For put options sold ITM, no additional<br />

risk premium is collected. Consequently, the portion <strong>of</strong> the option<br />

109. Id.


824 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

premium attributable to the ITM portion should not reflect any additional<br />

charge to assume risk.<br />

C. Conclusion<br />

Any covered option represents a separation <strong>of</strong> at least some <strong>of</strong> the<br />

risks <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier from some <strong>of</strong> the benefits <strong>of</strong> ownership.<br />

The extent <strong>of</strong> separation reaches a maximum when the strike<br />

price <strong>of</strong> the option is equal to the forward price <strong>of</strong> the underlier on<br />

the exercise date—that is, when it is ATM as measured on the exercise<br />

date. For options sold out <strong>of</strong> the money on the option purchase<br />

date, less separation occurs. For options sold in the money on the option<br />

purchase date, less separation also occurs than in an ATM option,<br />

but there is an additional forward property disposition. The<br />

payment arrangement obscures the forward property disposition because<br />

the arrangement makes the ITM portion <strong>of</strong> the option premium<br />

appear as consideration for additional “optionality,” when in fact the<br />

arrangement is merely a timing mechanism.<br />

Once the forward element <strong>of</strong> an ITM option becomes manifest, it<br />

becomes clear that the most apt analogy <strong>of</strong> an option to an existing<br />

instrument is to a partnership. Partnerships commonly exhibit the<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> sequential ownership involved in an ITM option. Indeed,<br />

Bruce Kayle has noted the substantial affinity between a call option<br />

and certain partnership arrangements, though he does not develop<br />

the point. 110 Rather, he illustrates the idea through a simple comparison.<br />

He notes that the owner <strong>of</strong> income-producing property<br />

(Partner 1) can contribute it to a newly formed partnership in exchange<br />

for cash and a partnership interest that entitles the partner<br />

to X% <strong>of</strong> the income from the property over time and to Y% <strong>of</strong> the appreciation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the property, if any, after five years, at which time the<br />

partnership will sell the property. Another person (Partner 2) would<br />

then contribute cash to the partnership in exchange for a partnership<br />

interest that entitles the partner to the remaining 100%-X% <strong>of</strong> the<br />

income and to 100%-Y% <strong>of</strong> the appreciation on sale. 111 Kayle observes<br />

that the partnership arrangement just described is not very different<br />

from Partner 1’s sale to Partner 2 <strong>of</strong> an income interest and a separate<br />

option to purchase a portion <strong>of</strong> the property in five years. 112<br />

Kayle’s point is that the sequential nature <strong>of</strong> ownership characteristic<br />

<strong>of</strong> certain option transactions is just the sort <strong>of</strong> sharing arrangement<br />

commonly found in partnerships. That point is corroborated by<br />

the analysis above, which demonstrates that ITM options involve a<br />

110. Kayle, supra note 11, at 270-75 (Example 10).<br />

111. Id.<br />

112. The cash flows are different in the option and partnership cases, but their present<br />

values should be the same.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 825<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> sequential sharing <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier. One party<br />

bears the first X% <strong>of</strong> risk and benefit, and the other party the remainder,<br />

though there is additionally an OTM option that then separates<br />

risk from benefit.<br />

Finally, the discussion in this Part explains the essential similarity<br />

between the forward sale portion <strong>of</strong> an ITM option and a collar.<br />

The only difference is in the identities <strong>of</strong> the persons holding the various<br />

interests in the underlier. In a collar, the original owner parts<br />

with risks and benefits at a remove from the forward price and retains<br />

the risks and benefits immediately surrounding the forward<br />

price, while in the forward sale portion <strong>of</strong> an ITM option the opposite<br />

occurs: the original owner parts with the risks and benefits immediately<br />

surrounding the forward price and retains the risks and benefits<br />

at a remove. As a consequence, the parties end up in the opposite<br />

posture, but the nature <strong>of</strong> the division <strong>of</strong> ownership is identical. This<br />

identity is obscured not only by the payment arrangement in an ITM<br />

option but by the fact that the ITM property disposition is married to<br />

a genuine option purchase in which one <strong>of</strong> the tails is also sold—<br />

through either an <strong>of</strong>floading <strong>of</strong> downside risk or the purchase <strong>of</strong> floating<br />

benefit, in either case in exchange for a fixed payment.<br />

IV. TAX ANALYSIS<br />

This Part evaluates the tax rules that ought to apply to options in<br />

light <strong>of</strong> the analysis in Part III. Because <strong>of</strong> the realization rule and<br />

the special treatment that the tax law affords to capital assets, 113 two<br />

basic cases arise: where the party selling upside potential (call writer)<br />

or purchasing downside protection (put purchaser) owns the underlier<br />

(a covered option), and where the underlier serves merely as a<br />

reference obligation for the option writer and holder. The first case<br />

divides into two subcases: where the underlier is held by the relevant<br />

party at all times between the option sale date and the exercise date,<br />

and where it is not, which is akin to a short sale. Subpart A deals<br />

with the cases involving ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier, and Subpart B<br />

deals with those in which the underlier serves as a reference obligation.<br />

Finally, Subpart C explores some <strong>of</strong> the approaches that might<br />

be adopted under current law, or with some variation to current law,<br />

in light <strong>of</strong> the tax analysis that would apply under basic tax principles<br />

as developed in Subparts A and B.<br />

113. See, e.g., 26 U.S.C. § 1(h) (2006) (discussing preferential rates for certain longterm<br />

capital gains); 26 U.S.C. § 1211 (discussing limitations on capital loss deductions); 26<br />

U.S.C. § 1212 (discussing carryover <strong>of</strong> excess capital losses).


826 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

A. Underlier Owned<br />

In this Subpart, assume that the put purchaser or the call seller<br />

owns the underlier on the exercise date. In Section 1, ownership<br />

commences no later than the option sale date, while in Section 2, the<br />

consequences <strong>of</strong> the holder’s acquisition <strong>of</strong> the underlier after the option<br />

sale but prior to the exercise date are briefly considered.<br />

Throughout, basic income tax principles are applied without regard<br />

to either special statutory and regulatory rules that provide for contrary<br />

treatment or questions <strong>of</strong> tax administration. Thus, dispositions<br />

<strong>of</strong> equity are taxable as realization events; 114 services income is<br />

taxed on receipt, 115 subject to certain limited exceptions; 116 and time<br />

value <strong>of</strong> money income accrues on a constant yield-to-maturity basis<br />

with continuous compounding. 117<br />

The principal tax question raised for any covered option is whether<br />

the option sale is in whole or part a capital transaction, and that<br />

question depends in turn on whether and to what extent the transaction<br />

is a property transaction. 118 In the financial instruments context,<br />

if it is a property transaction, it is likely to be capital, 119 unless the<br />

option is stock in trade or inventory <strong>of</strong> the taxpayer 120 or is a hedge<br />

with respect to stock in trade or inventory. 121 Capital transactions<br />

generally are treated much differently from noncapital transactions<br />

under the Code. Capital gains and losses are netted, 122 capital losses<br />

generally may not be deducted against ordinary income except to a<br />

limited extent, 123 and long-term capital gains <strong>of</strong> individual taxpayers<br />

are taxed at favorable rates. 124 Further, income from capital transactions<br />

generally is not registered by the tax system until realized. 125<br />

By contrast, ordinary income is subject to graduated rates; 126 may be<br />

114. 26 U.S.C. § 1001.<br />

115. 26 C.F.R. § 1.451-1 (2010) (discussing cash-method taxpayers); Schlude v. Comm’r,<br />

372 U.S. 128, 138-39 (1963) (Stewart, J., dissenting) (discussing the accrual-method).<br />

116. See, e.g., Boise Cascade Corp. v. United <strong>State</strong>s, 530 F.2d 1367, 1378 (Ct. Cl. 1976)<br />

(accrual-method taxpayer permitted to defer, until performance <strong>of</strong> related services, inclusion<br />

<strong>of</strong> prepaid services income for which the associated future expenses were certain in<br />

time and relatively certain in amount).<br />

117. See note 52, supra, for a discussion <strong>of</strong> the discrepancies between continuous and<br />

periodic compounding. Tax law generally assumes periodic compounding for interest-like<br />

returns, while the Black-Scholes model applies continuous compounding.<br />

118. § 1221(a) defines a capital asset as all property other than certain property excluded<br />

from the definition. 26 U.S.C. § 1221(a).<br />

119. 26 U.S.C. § 1221(a)(1) (2006).<br />

120. 26 U.S.C. § 1221(a).<br />

121. 26 U.S.C. § 1221.<br />

122. 26 U.S.C. § 1222.<br />

123. 26 U.S.C. § 1211 (limitation on capital loss deductions); 26 U.S.C. § 1212 (carryover<br />

<strong>of</strong> excess capital losses).<br />

124. 26 U.S.C. § 1(h).<br />

125. 26 U.S.C. § 1001(a).<br />

126. 26 U.S.C. § 1(a)-(d).


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 827<br />

subject to an accrual or other regime that accounts for income on an<br />

on-going basis, regardless <strong>of</strong> when it is realized; 127 and may, in the<br />

case <strong>of</strong> losses, <strong>of</strong>fset capital and ordinary income. 128<br />

Yet, although the concepts <strong>of</strong> “capital income” and “ordinary income”<br />

are deeply rooted in the income tax, most commentators agree<br />

that there is no pure concept <strong>of</strong> either that permits a ready or cogent<br />

argument for characterizing any particular item as intrinsically one<br />

or the other. 129 Modern finance theory has long recognized that any<br />

“ordinary” payment stream can be discounted into a present fixed<br />

“capital” sum. Given the economic equivalence between the two, efforts<br />

to identify a principled basis for determining which side <strong>of</strong> the<br />

line a transaction should fall on when the transaction shares some<br />

characteristics <strong>of</strong> both seems largely pointless. 130 Rather, a better approach<br />

is probably functional: Which characterization best serves the<br />

goals <strong>of</strong> the income tax? In light <strong>of</strong> the favorable treatment <strong>of</strong> capital<br />

income and the general preference to limit that treatment rather<br />

than to make it widely available, the better approach inclines toward<br />

ordinary characterization in ambiguous cases, unless a reason for a<br />

different result is manifest. Accordingly, in this discussion, capital<br />

treatment is reserved for gain or loss realized from the disposition <strong>of</strong><br />

property, where property ownership is understood in its standard tax<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> possessing the opportunity for gain and the correlative risk<br />

<strong>of</strong> loss with respect to some item. Transactions involving the disposition<br />

<strong>of</strong> either just the opportunity for gain or just the risk <strong>of</strong> loss are<br />

not property transactions but are, instead, “legs” <strong>of</strong> a property transaction.<br />

Sale <strong>of</strong> an OTM option is one such leg, and if the option is exercised,<br />

transfer <strong>of</strong> the other leg occurs as well, meaning that a property<br />

transaction has occurred. If the OTM option is not exercised,<br />

then the initial leg is undone and no property disposition occurs.<br />

Consequently, capital treatment for the disposition that occurs on the<br />

option sale date <strong>of</strong> an OTM option (or more accurately to the extent<br />

the option is OTM) seems inapposite.<br />

In an ITM option, by contrast, there is, in addition to an OTM option<br />

a property disposition <strong>of</strong> a portion <strong>of</strong> the underlier. This occurs<br />

because the transfer <strong>of</strong> benefits and correlative burdens in the ITM<br />

portion <strong>of</strong> the option is paradigmatic <strong>of</strong> a property disposition. Therefore,<br />

a tax system that reaches the “right” answer in the sense that it<br />

127. See 26 U.S.C. § 475 (mark-to-market <strong>of</strong> dealer inventory); 26 U.S.C. § 1272 (current<br />

accrual <strong>of</strong> OID); 26 C.F.R. § 1.1275-4 (2010) (current accrual <strong>of</strong> OID on contingent<br />

payment debt instruments).<br />

128. See, e.g., 26 U.S.C. §§ 62-63 (2006).<br />

129. See, e.g., David A. Weisbach, Line Drawing, Doctrine, and Efficiency in the Tax<br />

<strong>Law</strong>, 84 CORNELL L. REV. 1627 (1999).<br />

130. See, e.g., Calvin H. Johnson, Seventeen Culls from Capital Gains, 48 TAX NOTES<br />

623 (1990).


828 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

reserves capital treatment for disposition <strong>of</strong> all and only capital assets<br />

in any option transaction would tax the ITM portion, if any, as a<br />

capital transaction, assuming the underlier was a capital asset in the<br />

relevant party’s hands.<br />

1. Ownership Throughout the Option Term<br />

Under the analysis in Part III, every option involves an asymmetric<br />

division <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> the benefits and burdens <strong>of</strong> the underlier<br />

to the extent it is non-ITM. This asymmetric division seems to bear<br />

some attributes <strong>of</strong> a property transfer and some attributes <strong>of</strong> a nonproperty<br />

transfer. Separately, ITM options involve a symmetrical<br />

transfer <strong>of</strong> benefits and burdens that more closely resembles a forward<br />

property disposition. The following Subsections address these<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> option transactions.<br />

a. Non-ITM Option<br />

Part III established that a non-ITM option in effect divides ownership<br />

<strong>of</strong> the underlier between the option holder and the option writer.<br />

The transaction is not capital in the traditional sense because it is<br />

not a transfer <strong>of</strong> property, but a peculiar sort <strong>of</strong> sharing arrangement<br />

in which the option holder retains or acquires certain benefits but not<br />

detriments, while the writer acquires or retains certain detriments<br />

but not benefits. Together, the two parties have all the indicia <strong>of</strong><br />

ownership but separately neither does for any range <strong>of</strong> values covered<br />

by the option. The full consequences <strong>of</strong> a disposition <strong>of</strong> the underlier<br />

to a third party would be borne just as they are borne by an<br />

owner, but these consequences would be divided unequally between<br />

the writer and the holder.<br />

Viewed from this perspective, the non-ITM option premium is a<br />

fee that the holder pays for the writer to accept the adverse consequences<br />

<strong>of</strong> ownership. It is a prepayment for the service <strong>of</strong> bearing<br />

the risk <strong>of</strong> property ownership without the associated benefit on the<br />

exercise date. In general, prepayments not for a capital asset are subject<br />

to immediate taxation, unless an exception applies. 131 Apart from<br />

narrow statutory exceptions for certain types <strong>of</strong> subscription income<br />

132 and club dues, 133 the only exceptions to immediate inclusion<br />

<strong>of</strong> prepaid services income are for an accrual-method taxpayer that<br />

either satisfies the requirements for administratively granted safe<br />

harbor relief (not here applicable) 134 or can reliably associate the pre-<br />

131. See 26 C.F.R. § 1.451-1 (cash-method taxpayers); Schlude v. Comm’r, 372 U.S. 128<br />

(1963); Am. Auto Ass’n v. United <strong>State</strong>s, 367 U.S. 687 (1961) (accrual-method taxpayers).<br />

132. 26 U.S.C. § 455 (2006).<br />

133. 26 U.S.C. § 456.<br />

134. Rev. Proc. 04-34, 2004-22 I.R.B. 991.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 829<br />

paid item with an obligation to be discharged for a relatively certain<br />

amount in a readily identifiable subsequent tax period. 135 Because <strong>of</strong><br />

the contingency <strong>of</strong> the obligation that an option writer assumes, the<br />

latter exception does not apply either, leading to immediate inclusion.<br />

Although a better theoretical result would be to defer inclusion<br />

(and any associated deduction) until the period <strong>of</strong> exercise or lapse<br />

and to treat the option premium as a loan, requiring immediate inclusion<br />

instead without any deemed interest or expense on the loan<br />

may not be a bad proxy for taxation <strong>of</strong> the holder’s interest and the<br />

writer’s associated deduction on a deemed loan. 136<br />

The holder should enjoy mirror treatment. Assuming the option is<br />

entered into in connection with the taxpayer’s trade or business or<br />

other income-producing activity, the premium should be deductible<br />

as, respectively, a business expense 137 or an expense incurred in connection<br />

with the production <strong>of</strong> income. 138 The deduction should be allowed<br />

in the period in which the exercise date (or, for the reasons<br />

stated previously, the last date <strong>of</strong> the exercise period) occurs. 139<br />

If the non-ITM option is exercised, the second “leg” <strong>of</strong> the property<br />

disposition occurs, and at this point it is appropriate to treat the total<br />

transaction (option sale plus exercise) as a property disposition. This<br />

treatment is correct because the original owner <strong>of</strong> the property has<br />

now parted with the benefits and the associated burdens <strong>of</strong> ownership.<br />

Consider the simple OTM put option described as part <strong>of</strong> Transaction<br />

2, under which Owner paid Purchaser $3.00 on Day 1 for the right to<br />

put Underlier to Purchaser on Day 2 for $97.94. 140 Suppose Owner exercises;<br />

i.e., Underlier is not worth more than $97.94 on Day 2. Solely<br />

with respect to the OTM portion <strong>of</strong> Transaction 2 (and assuming here<br />

that the associated ITM portion <strong>of</strong> the option had not been entered into),<br />

on Day 1, Owner transferred the risk <strong>of</strong> loss below $97.94 to Purchaser.<br />

Owner retained the risk <strong>of</strong> loss down to $97.94 as well as the<br />

potential for upside gain. On Day 2, Owner bears the loss from $100 to<br />

$97.94 and transfers all potential for upside gain to Purchaser. Although<br />

the property transfer appears to be <strong>of</strong>f-market (in that the<br />

135. See, e.g., Artnell Co. v. Comm’r, 400 F.2d 981 (7th Cir. 1968); Rev. Proc. 2004-34.<br />

136. See David Hasen, The Tax Treatment <strong>of</strong> Advance Receipts, 61 TAX L. REV. 395<br />

(2008).<br />

137. 26 U.S.C. § 162.<br />

138. 26 U.S.C. § 212.<br />

139. If the deduction is under § 212, it may be subject to the 2% floor applicable to certain<br />

taxpayers’ itemized deductions. See 26 U.S.C. § 67. Prior to the 2003 adoption <strong>of</strong> regulations<br />

under § 263, a cash-method taxpayer arguably was able to deduct the premium in<br />

the period paid, even if the exercise date occured in a subsequent period. See 26 C.F.R.<br />

§ 1.461-1(a)(1) (providing that cash-method taxpayers deduct expenses in the year paid unless<br />

a long-lived asset is created). Under current regulations, however, most premiums<br />

paid for options exercisable in a subsequent year must be capitalized. 26 C.F.R. § 1.263(a)-<br />

4(c)(1)(iii)(E) .<br />

140. See 26 C.F.R. § 1.263(a)-4(c)(1)(iii)(B) (2004).


830 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

property appears to change hands on Day 2 at a price that differs from<br />

its FMV on that day), this is merely an appearance. The transfer <strong>of</strong><br />

possession is a formality. The actual transfer <strong>of</strong> benefits and burdens<br />

took place in two steps—on Day 1 when some <strong>of</strong> the risk <strong>of</strong> loss shifted,<br />

and on Day 2 when the opportunity for gain went over as well. The two<br />

transfers, together, are on-market.<br />

If the option lapses, the originally transferred leg is transferred<br />

back and no property disposition occurs. For instance, if Underlier in<br />

the example above is worth any amount greater than $97.94 on Day<br />

2, the loss below $97.94 on Day 2 is zero.<br />

b. ITM Option<br />

For an ITM option, the analysis is more complicated. On the option<br />

sale date there is, in addition to a separation <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> the benefits<br />

<strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier from some <strong>of</strong> the associated burdens,<br />

an on-market forward disposition <strong>of</strong> a portion <strong>of</strong> the underlier.<br />

This portion <strong>of</strong> the option sale, therefore, should be treated as a forward<br />

<strong>of</strong> a certain sort. Perhaps unfortunately, under current law,<br />

forwards are generally held open, 141 subject to certain exceptions, 142<br />

until the actual transfer <strong>of</strong> the property takes place. Open transaction<br />

treatment for forwards when the seller owns the underlier seems<br />

even less justifiable than open transaction treatment for options. In a<br />

forward, all the seller retains is a wasting present interest—the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> which is known on the sale date. With respect to the portion<br />

sold, full transfer <strong>of</strong> benefits and burdens has occurred. Consequently,<br />

and as a number <strong>of</strong> commentators have observed, 143 a current<br />

sale <strong>of</strong> future rights should be accounted for currently even under<br />

our realization-based income tax. If forwards were currently<br />

taxed, then the ITM portion <strong>of</strong> an ITM option should be treated as a<br />

taxable transaction when the option is sold.<br />

Naturally, the introduction <strong>of</strong> separate treatment for the property<br />

disposition portion <strong>of</strong> an ITM option introduces complexity into the<br />

tax rules for options. Moreover, the complexity is compounded by the<br />

fact that the property disposition in an ITM option is <strong>of</strong> a peculiar<br />

sort. It is not the disposition <strong>of</strong> a physical portion, a ratable portion,<br />

or a temporal portion <strong>of</strong> the underlier, but rather <strong>of</strong> a risk portion.<br />

For each <strong>of</strong> the first three types <strong>of</strong> division, the tax rules are relatively<br />

straightforward, at least in conceptual terms. If, for example, the<br />

141. 26 U.S.C. § 1233.<br />

142. 26 U.S.C. § 1256 (certain regulated futures contracts subject to mark-to-market<br />

taxation); 26 U.S.C. § 1259 (constructive sale <strong>of</strong> appreciated financial positions).<br />

143. See, e.g., Cunningham & Schenk, supra note 8; Hasen, supra note 13; Levy, supra note<br />

89. In addition, certain provisions <strong>of</strong> the Code already require present accounting for forward<br />

dispositions. See, e.g., 26 U.S.C. § 305(e) (present accounting <strong>of</strong> certain preferred dividendstripping<br />

transactions); 26 U.S.C. § 1286 (present accounting <strong>of</strong> bond-stripping transactions).


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 831<br />

owner <strong>of</strong> a share <strong>of</strong> stock sells a fraction <strong>of</strong> the share, the extent <strong>of</strong><br />

the risk and benefit in the underlier that the purchaser acquires is<br />

proportional to the fraction purchased. Thus, the purchaser <strong>of</strong> onehalf<br />

the share would assume a risk <strong>of</strong> loss equal to 50% <strong>of</strong> the risk<br />

associated with the full underlier and acquire the correlative potential<br />

benefit. 144 The same result applies to cotenants that share an undivided<br />

interest in real property. 145 Similarly, a temporal division <strong>of</strong><br />

the underlier results, in conceptual terms, in the creation <strong>of</strong> a wasting<br />

present interest and a growing future interest. The tax rules for<br />

such property dispositions can be complicated, but the underlying<br />

conceptual analysis is well understood. 146<br />

By contrast, in an ITM option, the transfer <strong>of</strong> partial ownership in<br />

the underlier is sequential, or “horizontal.” The parties do not share<br />

risk and reward ratably or in temporal succession but rather in<br />

risk/benefit sequence. If the ITM portion <strong>of</strong> the option represents a<br />

forward sale <strong>of</strong> X% <strong>of</strong> the underlier, then the transferee assumes the<br />

first X% <strong>of</strong> risk and reward, while the transferor retains the remaining<br />

(100 – X)%, which is distributed about the transferred portion.<br />

This division suggests that the transferor should be viewed as disposing<br />

<strong>of</strong> property “<strong>of</strong>f the top,” in that the portion disposed <strong>of</strong> is the portion<br />

that is first and exclusively affected by price fluctuations in the<br />

underlier. Once the division occurs, post-option sale fluctuations in<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> the underlier that do not exceed the range <strong>of</strong> risk and<br />

benefit transferred have no economic effect on the transferor. This<br />

means that the transferor has no economic stake in those fluctuations.<br />

At the same time, price fluctuations that do exceed the range<br />

have no (additional) effect on the transferee, meaning that the transferee<br />

has no stake in them.<br />

These considerations indicate that the transferor’s tax basis in the<br />

portion <strong>of</strong> the underlier sold forward should be allocated only to the extent<br />

that it falls within the actual price range <strong>of</strong> that portion on the option<br />

sale date. If the transferor’s basis does not fall within that range,<br />

the transferor has no tax cost associated with the disposition at all,<br />

and therefore no basis should be allocated to <strong>of</strong>fset the proceeds. This<br />

approach tends to result in a more certain but smaller recognition <strong>of</strong><br />

gain or loss on disposition than would a ratable allocation rule.<br />

Transaction 4, discussed previously, illustrates the basic analysis:<br />

Transaction 4: ITM put option. Owner pays Purchaser<br />

$5.27 on Day 1 in exchange for the right to sell Underlier to<br />

144. See 26 C.F.R. § 1.616 (2009) (providing basis rules for partial dispositions <strong>of</strong> property).<br />

145. Id.<br />

146. See, e.g., Kenneth F. Joyce & Louis A. Del Cotto, The AB (ABC) and BA Transactions:<br />

An Economic and Tax Analysis <strong>of</strong> Reserved and Carved Out Income Interests, 31 TAX<br />

L. REV. 121 (1976).


832 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

Purchaser on Day 2 for $102.27. The parties cash-settle the<br />

obligation on Day 2.<br />

Transaction 4 consists <strong>of</strong> an OTM put having a strike price <strong>of</strong> $97.94<br />

and a prepaid, on-market disposition <strong>of</strong> the first 25% <strong>of</strong> opportunity<br />

for gain and risk <strong>of</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> Underlier, corresponding to the range <strong>of</strong><br />

values on Day 2 between $97.94 and $102.27. In the transaction, the<br />

risk-free rate was assumed to be zero, no risk premium was paid, and<br />

Underlier’s FMV on Day 1 was $100.<br />

If we suppose that Owner’s basis is anything less than $97.94,<br />

then under the theory that basis should be allocated to the disposition<br />

only to the extent Owner has basis over the disposed <strong>of</strong> range,<br />

Owner should be treated as recognizing $100 - $97.94, or $2.06, <strong>of</strong><br />

gain. Thus, if Owner’s basis is $80, Owner has $2.06 <strong>of</strong> gain. By contrast,<br />

if Owner’s basis is $98, Owner has $2 <strong>of</strong> gain.<br />

One might object that if Owner has basis in excess <strong>of</strong> 75% <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Underlier’s FMV, Owner should get a partial basis <strong>of</strong>fset on the option<br />

sale date because only 25% <strong>of</strong> Underlier is sold. Thus, if Owner’s<br />

basis is $80, it might seem Owner should recognize four-fifths<br />

($80/$100) <strong>of</strong> $2.06, rather than the full $2.06. However, because the<br />

sale is not <strong>of</strong> a ratable portion but <strong>of</strong> an identifiable horizontal slice,<br />

and because the risk and benefit disposed <strong>of</strong> is associated only with<br />

that slice, a ratable basis allocation rule would seem to be incorrect;<br />

it does not associate “paid-for” basis with a “paid-for” portion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

underlier sold. Note further that although less basis <strong>of</strong>fset occurs<br />

than in a ratable disposition, the amount <strong>of</strong> gain recognized on the<br />

option sale date is smaller. Although Owner has disposed <strong>of</strong> 25% <strong>of</strong><br />

the opportunity for gain and risk <strong>of</strong> loss and Owner allocates no basis<br />

to the portion sold, Owner’s gain is $2.06 rather than 25% <strong>of</strong> the entire<br />

$25 <strong>of</strong> built-in gain, or $6.25.<br />

Analogous treatment occurs where Owner is in a loss position.<br />

Owner may take a loss equal to the lesser <strong>of</strong> $102.27 - $100 or Owner’s<br />

basis in Underlier - $100. This treatment reflects the fact that,<br />

solely with respect to the ITM portion <strong>of</strong> the option, Owner has disposed<br />

<strong>of</strong> tax ownership through that range but not above or below it.<br />

If the option is exercised, the retained portion <strong>of</strong> Underlier is simply<br />

transferred pursuant to the exercise, as described above in the OTM<br />

case. If the option is not exercised, the sold portion is deemed repurchased<br />

at its FMV and Owner’s basis in that portion simply reflects<br />

the part <strong>of</strong> the option premium paid on Day 1 that is allocable to it.<br />

2. Ownership Acquired After Option Sale<br />

Under the analysis developed in Part III, only ITM options involve<br />

a property transfer prior to the exercise date. All options, however,<br />

involve a risk-benefit disaggregation transaction on the option sale


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 833<br />

date, together with a reunification on the exercise date <strong>of</strong> the parts<br />

previously separated. If the option is exercised, the “trailing” leg that<br />

the initial owner (the put seller or call writer) retained goes over to<br />

the property purchaser, while if the option is not exercised, the “leading”<br />

leg that the initial owner transferred is returned to that owner.<br />

Since the non-ITM portion does not involve a property disposition,<br />

the ownership <strong>of</strong> the underlier prior to the exercise date is irrelevant.<br />

Gain or loss on exercise <strong>of</strong> the option will continue to be determined<br />

by the difference between exercise price and basis <strong>of</strong> the underlier<br />

and its basis in the owner’s hands, whether that basis was determined<br />

after the option sale date (because the underlier was purchased<br />

after that date) or not.<br />

A similar approach should apply to the ITM portion, if any, <strong>of</strong> an<br />

option where the underlier is acquired after the option sale date.<br />

There are two cases in which acquisition <strong>of</strong> the underlier during the<br />

pendency <strong>of</strong> the option may have an effect on the tax treatment <strong>of</strong> the<br />

transaction prior to exercise: where the purchaser <strong>of</strong> an ITM put and<br />

the seller <strong>of</strong> an ITM call acquire the underlier. Recall that for both<br />

types <strong>of</strong> ITM options, on the option sale date the underlier seller<br />

promises to deliver a portion <strong>of</strong> the underlier (or its equivalent) to the<br />

counter-party on the exercise date. Prior to the seller’s purchase <strong>of</strong><br />

the underlier, there should be no tax consequence to the disposition.<br />

Under a realization-based income tax, the tax consequences <strong>of</strong> entering<br />

into the option transaction should first be reckoned on the option<br />

sale date when the forward transfer occurs. On that date, the expected<br />

cost <strong>of</strong> satisfying the transfer is zero: the seller conceptually<br />

exchanges a portion <strong>of</strong> the underlier for a bond <strong>of</strong> equal value paying<br />

the risk-free rate. The expected cost to the seller on the option sale<br />

date <strong>of</strong> satisfying that obligation is just the FMV <strong>of</strong> the portion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

underlier sold forward, since that is what the seller would have to<br />

pay on the option sale date to procure the portion sold forward.<br />

Once the seller acquires the underlier, additional tax consequences<br />

<strong>of</strong> the sale may be reckoned. At that time, the seller’s cost <strong>of</strong><br />

satisfying its obligation under the forward sale portion <strong>of</strong> the option<br />

is established. For example, consider the ITM put option in Transaction<br />

4, but assume that Owner does not own Underlier on the option<br />

sale date. If Owner purchases Underlier at $90 six months after the<br />

option sale date, then Owner’s cost <strong>of</strong> delivering 25% <strong>of</strong> Underlier on<br />

Day 2 is $0 because the portion <strong>of</strong> the underlier disposed <strong>of</strong> in the<br />

ITM piece <strong>of</strong> the option is entirely in excess <strong>of</strong> the cost to Owner <strong>of</strong><br />

acquiring the property.


834 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

B. Underlier as Reference Obligation<br />

If the parties to the option transaction use the underlier merely as<br />

a reference obligation, the transaction becomes a simple bet. It is a<br />

zero-sum game in which one party’s gain is precisely <strong>of</strong>fset by the<br />

counter-party’s loss. 147 In recent years, the tax law has tended to<br />

treat such bets as generating capital income and loss because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

risky nature <strong>of</strong> the returns they generate, 148 but there appears to be<br />

no deep reason why the returns should not be characterized as ordinary<br />

and subject to an economic accrual or similar regime, such as<br />

mark-to-market taxation. 149 There is no particular historical<br />

precedent for according capital treatment to returns just because<br />

they are risk-based, and the policy rationales for deferral and favorable<br />

rates on capital income do not seem to apply to bets. In general,<br />

these rationales center on encouraging the formation <strong>of</strong> real capital<br />

and avoiding the bunching <strong>of</strong> income in a single tax year that arises<br />

under the realization rule. Wagers do not involve the formation <strong>of</strong><br />

physical capital, and bunching becomes a problem only where an accrual<br />

regime is assumed not to be in place.<br />

If, however, capital treatment <strong>of</strong> traditional capital assets (such as<br />

where the option involves a physical underlier) is taken as a given,<br />

then the tax rules for wagering-type options should take account <strong>of</strong><br />

the avoidance possibilities that dissimilar rules for physical and notional<br />

options would create. 150 The avoidance possibilities derive from<br />

two main problems: discontinuity and inconsistency. Discontinuity<br />

arises when instruments that generate similar returns are subject to<br />

dissimilar tax rules; 151 the general solution is to tax similar instruments<br />

like their close substitutes. 152 Inconsistency arises when the<br />

same return is taxed differently, depending upon the form in which it<br />

is received; 153 the general solution is to adopt a robust method for<br />

147. See Edward D. Kleinbard, Risky and Riskless Positions in Securities, 71 TAXES<br />

783, 784 (1993).<br />

148. See, e.g., 26 U.S.C. § 1234A (2006) (treating certain “closing transactions” as generating<br />

short-term capital gain and loss); 26 C.F.R. § 1.446-3(c) (2010) (bullet swap not<br />

treated as subject to NPC rules).<br />

149. See Keinan, supra note 8, at 146 (arguing that all returns from financial instruments<br />

should be treated as ordinary and subject to taxation on an accrual or mark-tomarket<br />

basis); Hasen, supra note 13, at 403-07 (arguing that a better basis for distinguishing<br />

between returns entitled to capital treatment, including deferral under the realization<br />

rule, and ordinary returns accounted for under an economic accrual regime is whether the<br />

taxpayer owns a physical underlier); see also Kleinbard, supra note 147, at 784 (noting that<br />

financial products differ from traditional capital assets in that the former are simple bets<br />

that can be replicated in principle indefinitely).<br />

150. David A. Weisbach, Line Drawing in the Tax <strong>Law</strong>, 84 CORNELL L. REV. 1627 (1999).<br />

151. Jeff Strnad, Taxing New Financial Products: A Conceptual Framework, 46 Stan.<br />

L. Rev. 569, 573 (1994).<br />

152. Weisbach, supra note 150, at 1661.<br />

153. Id. at 1645.


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 835<br />

identifying the overall economic return the taxpayer locks in ex ante,<br />

but the problems with developing such methods are notorious. 154 The<br />

problem in the present context is that from the standpoint <strong>of</strong> either<br />

the writer or the holder <strong>of</strong> the option, the returns from the bet may<br />

be similar to the returns from a physically settled option. Accordingly,<br />

the rules ought to be similar for the two types <strong>of</strong> transactions.<br />

Further, the rules need to require taxpayers to associate <strong>of</strong>fsetting<br />

positions, such as where the taxpayer buys an option in one form and<br />

sells a similar or identical one in another. How the rules might accomplish<br />

these goals falls outside the scope <strong>of</strong> this discussion; I merely<br />

identify the issues here.<br />

C. Possible Tax Approaches<br />

The rules described in the preceding Subparts suffer from<br />

both complexity and the fact that they diverge considerably from current<br />

law. The question therefore arises how one might simplify<br />

the rules suggested without either sacrificing the basic ideas or introducing<br />

major complexity into current law. The following <strong>of</strong>fers<br />

some general suggestions.<br />

1. Basic Problems Under Current <strong>Law</strong><br />

The principal authorities that govern the taxation <strong>of</strong> options are<br />

Revenue Ruling 78-182 155 and, for options on financial assets (other<br />

than those taxed under § 1256, or held as inventory or by dealers), §§<br />

1234 and 1234A. In general, these authorities provide for open transaction<br />

treatment on the writing <strong>of</strong> an option and for capital treatment<br />

on sale, exchange, lapse, termination, or exercise <strong>of</strong> the option<br />

if the underlier is or would be a capital asset in the taxpayer’s hands.<br />

When the option is exercised, in the case <strong>of</strong> a call the cost <strong>of</strong> the option<br />

is added to the purchaser’s basis and treated as part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

amount realized by the seller, and the cost <strong>of</strong> a put is treated as a reduction<br />

in the amount realized by the seller and as reducing the purchaser’s<br />

basis in the property. There is some question whether any <strong>of</strong><br />

these authorities apply to options that by their terms are or may be<br />

cash-settled.<br />

The main differences between these rules and the rules set forth<br />

in Subparts III.A and III.B are as follows:<br />

1. Existing law places most options on open-transaction accounting;<br />

154. Id. at 1663.<br />

155. Rev. Rul. 78-182, 1978-1 C.B. 265.


836 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

2. Existing law treats all portions <strong>of</strong> the option premium as<br />

capital (assuming the underlier is a capital asset in the<br />

hands <strong>of</strong> the relevant party), whereas the preceding discussion<br />

suggests that the option premium, to the extent it is for<br />

an OTM option, is ordinary income to the option writer (and<br />

creates an ordinary expense to the option purchaser);<br />

3. No interest income or deduction is imputed to the parties<br />

to an option under present law, whereas economically all<br />

parts <strong>of</strong> the option premium are discounted to the present<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the premium payment on the exercise date; and<br />

4. The nonproperty portion <strong>of</strong> an option transaction is not<br />

separately treated from the property portion.<br />

The first <strong>of</strong> these differences is the most significant because it<br />

represents a significant deferral opportunity in light <strong>of</strong> the fact that<br />

many parties to option transactions may be tax-indifferent, or at<br />

least relatively tax-indifferent. 156 The simple solution is to treat option<br />

premiums as generating ordinary income to the writer and as<br />

providing a deduction to the purchaser in the period in which the<br />

strike date (or the last strike date for American options) occurs. Regarding<br />

timing, this change to the law could be accomplished administratively<br />

through the revocation <strong>of</strong> Revenue Ruling 78-182, except<br />

that it is unclear whether the Service would or should revoke 78-182<br />

in light <strong>of</strong> Congress’s evident intent to affirm open transaction<br />

treatment through adoption <strong>of</strong> §§ 1234 and 1234A. Further, character<br />

changes would need to be addressed through amendment <strong>of</strong> §§<br />

1234 and 1234A directly.<br />

If one wanted to rectify the problem <strong>of</strong> mixed ordinary and capital<br />

treatment <strong>of</strong> the premium, it would be necessary for Congress to remove<br />

the statutory obstacles to bifurcation (again, §§ 1234 and<br />

1234A). Having done that, the Treasury likely would have authority<br />

to require bifurcation <strong>of</strong> the option into capital and noncapital portions<br />

on the option sale date and to require separate accounting <strong>of</strong><br />

the various pieces <strong>of</strong> the option payout on the date <strong>of</strong> exercise, lapse,<br />

or disposition. 157 This might or might not prove burdensome, but the<br />

fact that parties dealing in financial options tend to be sophisticated<br />

weighs in favor <strong>of</strong> a relatively robust accounting regime, possibly<br />

156. See David M. Schizer, Balance in the Taxation <strong>of</strong> Derivative Securities: An Agenda<br />

for Reform, 104 COLUM.L.REV. 1886, 1893-94 (2004).<br />

157. See 26 U.S.C. § 446 (2006) (requiring taxpayer’s method <strong>of</strong> accounting to “clearly<br />

reflect income”); 26 U.S.C. § 7805 (providing Treasury general authority to prescribe regulations<br />

under Title 26).


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 837<br />

augmented by a simplified accounting method that taxpayers could<br />

elect to have apply. 158<br />

As regards the problem <strong>of</strong> failing to account for interest, one could<br />

impute interest income and deduction to the parties on the option<br />

premium. It is not clear that any provision <strong>of</strong> current law prevents<br />

such an imputation. A somewhat less accurate but administratively<br />

easier approach would be to treat payment <strong>of</strong> the option premium as<br />

a closed transaction on the option sale date, as indicated above.<br />

Finally, the failure to tax the ITM portion <strong>of</strong> an option on the option<br />

sale date mainly becomes an issue only if forwards become subject<br />

to current taxation, as a number <strong>of</strong> commentators have argued<br />

they should. 159 If forwards were taxed on a current basis, it would be<br />

appropriate if not necessary given the similarity <strong>of</strong> the ITM portion <strong>of</strong><br />

ITM options to forwards to alter the rules for options to require identification<br />

<strong>of</strong> the ITM portion, if any, with associated treatment under<br />

the forward contract rules. By the same token, it is unclear how<br />

much would be sacrificed on the option side in preserving open<br />

transaction treatment for both standard forwards and the ITM portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> an option. If the distortion is small, the gain in simplicity may<br />

be worth the cost <strong>of</strong> incorrect taxation. Of course, that result would<br />

preserve whatever distortions persist as a result <strong>of</strong> the system’s failure<br />

to tax forwards correctly.<br />

A further, less significant, problem resulting from the failure to<br />

tax the ITM portion <strong>of</strong> an option as a forward on the option sale date<br />

is that the current rules do not treat any portion <strong>of</strong> the option sale as<br />

taxable if the option is not exercised. The analysis here has demonstrated,<br />

however, that economically the owner <strong>of</strong> the underlier should<br />

be taxed on the forward portion <strong>of</strong> the ITM option regardless <strong>of</strong><br />

whether the option is exercised. Nonexercise should be treated as a<br />

sale back to the option writer, resulting in appropriate basis adjustment,<br />

not as though no sale had occurred.<br />

2. Proposals<br />

The discussion above suggests the following rules as a possible regime<br />

for taxing financial options.<br />

a. Option Sale Date<br />

� To the extent the option is OTM, the writer includes the<br />

premium in income. The holder takes a deduction under §<br />

162 or 212 for the premium in the period in which or with<br />

158. See, e.g., Prop. 26 C.F.R. § 1.446-3(e) (proposing a variety <strong>of</strong> methods to account<br />

for nonperiodic contingent payments made on certain NPCs).<br />

159. See supra Part III.A.


838 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

which ends the last day that the option may be exercised,<br />

subject to any limitations that may apply. 160<br />

� To the extent, if any, the option is ITM, the parties treat<br />

the premium as a loan or a prepayment. The reason for differing<br />

treatment from the OTM piece is that this portion <strong>of</strong><br />

the premium is nothing more than a payment arrangement<br />

for the fluctuation in the part <strong>of</strong> the underlier sold forward.<br />

Interest is imputed to the option holder at the risk-free rate,<br />

with a corresponding deduction to the option writer. Alternatively,<br />

the premium could be included and deducted on receipt,<br />

with corresponding adjustments on exercise.<br />

� For an ITM option, the portion <strong>of</strong> the option that<br />

represents a forward sale is treated as such on the option<br />

sale date, with gain or loss recognized on that date. This<br />

rule presupposes that the rules for forwards are changed to<br />

provide for taxation on the sale date rather than on the date<br />

<strong>of</strong> delivery.<br />

o As an alternative, the forward may be held open until<br />

the exercise date, in which case the deemed purchase<br />

price must include an interest factor. Further, on lapse,<br />

the portion sold forward is treated as immediately<br />

sold back.<br />

b. Option Exercise<br />

� For non-ITM options, the transaction is a sale at the exercise<br />

price, with gain or loss recognized. Character depends on<br />

whether the seller <strong>of</strong> the property holds it as a capital asset.<br />

o A policy question arises regarding the measuring period<br />

for the underlier owner. Where the seller’s holding<br />

period on the option sale date is one year or less and on<br />

the exercise date is more than one year, it is unclear<br />

whether gain or loss on exercise should be short-term or<br />

long-term. 161 As explained above, the sale in effect occurs<br />

in two stages. Administrability considerations suggest<br />

that a bifurcation regime should not apply, while<br />

the general policy <strong>of</strong> limiting the preferential treatment<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital transactions suggests that the gain or loss<br />

should be short-term. On the other hand, there may be<br />

160. See, e.g., §§ 68 (phase-out <strong>of</strong> itemized deductions), 161 (denying double deduction<br />

for any item), 261 (disallowance <strong>of</strong> deductions for expenditures that must be capitalized).<br />

161. See 26 U.S.C. § 1(h) (2006) (providing for preferential treatment <strong>of</strong> long-term capital<br />

gains for individuals); 26 U.S.C. § 1222 (defining long-term capital gains as gains on<br />

capital assets held more than one year); 26 U.S.C. § 1223 (defining holding period).


2010] FINANCIAL OPTIONS IN THE REAL WORLD 839<br />

greater deadweight loss from denying long-term capital<br />

treatment in this setting than from permitting it. The<br />

correct answer is not clear.<br />

� For ITM options, exercise represents a sale <strong>of</strong> the balance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the underlier, but taking account <strong>of</strong> basis already assigned<br />

to the portion sold forward on the option sale date.<br />

c. Option Lapse or Cancellation<br />

� On a non-ITM option, there are no consequences on lapse<br />

other than deduction for the premium, if it has not already<br />

been deducted.<br />

� On an ITM option, the property previously treated as sold<br />

forward is treated as sold back; if it was held open on the option<br />

sale date, a sale and sale-back occur.<br />

V. CONCLUSION<br />

Options represent nothing more than a particular type <strong>of</strong> property<br />

division. They are not spatial, as when a party sells a physical piece<br />

<strong>of</strong> a larger asset, temporal, as when a party sells a leasehold or a remainder<br />

interest in an asset, or “vertical,” as when a party sells a<br />

ratable share <strong>of</strong> property so that the two owners share risk and reward<br />

as tenants in common. In their pure form, options are a division<br />

<strong>of</strong> risk and reward for which the party bearing the risk without the<br />

reward is appropriately compensated. In addition, ITM options become,<br />

in part, a horizontal or sequential transfer <strong>of</strong> ownership, much<br />

as may occur in a partnership. This horizontal form <strong>of</strong> ownership divides<br />

the incidents <strong>of</strong> ownership according to who bears the first risk<br />

and benefit, and who bears the rest. As previously explained, the<br />

ITM portion is identical to a collar transaction, except that in a collar<br />

the original property owner retains the first risk and benefit while<br />

selling the last; while in the ITM portion <strong>of</strong> an ITM option, the original<br />

owner retains the last and sells the first.<br />

The forward transfer <strong>of</strong> property that takes place in the ITM portion,<br />

if any, <strong>of</strong> an option has not been identified previously because the<br />

payment arrangement between the parties to an option transaction<br />

obscures it. This payment arrangement ensures that the option purchaser<br />

makes only one payment to the option seller (apart from a<br />

payment in connection with the exercise <strong>of</strong> a call), and it reflects appropriate<br />

discounting at the risk-free rate because the payment occurs<br />

on the option sale date, not the exercise date. But the payout structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> any actual ITM option is identical to the payout structure associated<br />

with a forward transfer <strong>of</strong> a portion <strong>of</strong> the underlier coupled with a<br />

garden-variety OTM option. This structure explains why, even though


840 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:789<br />

non-ITM options are fundamentally different from forward sales as regards<br />

the portion <strong>of</strong> property disposed <strong>of</strong>, ITM options become partial<br />

forwards and shade into full forwards at the limit.<br />

Our realization-based income tax recognizes a difference between<br />

“ordinary” and “capital” income—however tenuous or unstable the underlying<br />

concepts may be. In light <strong>of</strong> the difference, and assuming it<br />

persists, the tax system ought to attempt to identify the portions <strong>of</strong> option<br />

transactions that qualify as ordinary or capital and tax them accordingly,<br />

assuming that administrative costs resulting from complexity<br />

and gamesmanship do not swamp the benefits that might arise from<br />

a more accurate taxation <strong>of</strong> options. Part III <strong>of</strong>fers one set <strong>of</strong> possible<br />

solutions in light <strong>of</strong> these concerns, but it is by no means the only possible<br />

set. It also illustrates some <strong>of</strong> the trade<strong>of</strong>fs that arise in any effort<br />

to develop a workable system that taxes options in approximately the<br />

“correct” manner, where “correct” is understood against a baseline <strong>of</strong><br />

realization-based taxation for risky returns generated by capital and<br />

special rates and basketing rules for capital income.


METHADEMIC: DRUG PANIC IN AN AGE OF<br />

AMBIVALENCE<br />

DEBORAH AHRENS *<br />

ABSTRACT<br />

The story <strong>of</strong> criminal sanctions in modern America is a familiar—and depressing—<br />

narrative. According to the narrative, we live in an era where the dynamics <strong>of</strong> popular politics,<br />

the practices <strong>of</strong> the media, and the (<strong>of</strong>ten racialized) anxieties <strong>of</strong> modern life combine to<br />

create a one-way ratchet, in which we identify perceived new threats to public order and respond<br />

unthinkingly with harsh new criminal sanctions. On the surface, the wave <strong>of</strong> concern<br />

over methamphetamine that swept the nation in the middle part <strong>of</strong> this decade followed this<br />

script, as a media panic led to substantial popular concern and significant new legislation.<br />

When one digs a little deeper, however, the story is more complicated: Instead <strong>of</strong> a singular<br />

focus on increased criminal penalties and mass incarceration, we see a multifaceted strategy<br />

focused on educating the public, limiting access to ingredients, and remediating environmental<br />

concerns raised by the manufacture <strong>of</strong> the drug.<br />

Why has public and legislative concern about a drug described in terms <strong>of</strong> natural disasters<br />

and communicable deadly diseases generated cold medication restrictions and educational<br />

programs rather than extensive new criminal law? This Article—the first comprehensive<br />

examination <strong>of</strong> our legal and cultural response to methamphetamine—asks and attempts<br />

to answer that question. After providing a succinct history <strong>of</strong> modern American drug<br />

policy, the Article narrates the wave <strong>of</strong> coverage that sparked concern about a possible “Methademic”<br />

and then catalogs state and local responses to the alleged threat. It concludes by<br />

<strong>of</strong>fering some informed speculation about the possible reasons for this surprisingly tepid response.<br />

After considering and rejecting or partially crediting a number <strong>of</strong> explanations—<br />

most notably that the popular identification <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine as a “white drug” muted<br />

the expected hostility to its users—the Article concludes that the public response to methamphetamine<br />

was, in fact, the first chapter in a new era <strong>of</strong> drug policy: the age <strong>of</strong> ambivalence.<br />

I. INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................. 842<br />

II. A (RELATIVELY)BRIEF HISTORY OF AMERICAN DRUG POLICY .......................... 846<br />

A. The Twentieth Century and Drug Policy Development .............................. 847<br />

1. The Temperance Movement ................................................................. 848<br />

2. The Racialization <strong>of</strong> Opiates and Narcotics ........................................ 849<br />

3. Marijuana (and LSD) .......................................................................... 851<br />

B. Crackademic: The 1980s and Beyond ........................................................ 852<br />

III. METHADEMIC! ................................................................................................... 859<br />

A. Methamphetamine Use as an “Epidemic” .................................................. 860<br />

B. Legislative Responses to Methamphetamine .............................................. 865<br />

1. Precursor Regulations .......................................................................... 867<br />

2. Methamphetamine Registries .............................................................. 872<br />

3. Property Regulations ........................................................................... 873<br />

4. Child-Protective Measures ................................................................... 875<br />

5. Methamphetamine Prisons .................................................................. 876<br />

6. Drug Treatment Courts ....................................................................... 876<br />

7. Educational Programs ......................................................................... 878<br />

IV. MAKE NEW DRUG LAWS, BUT KEEP THE OLD.................................................... 879<br />

A. Familiar Fourth Amendment Developments ............................................. 880<br />

* Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Seattle <strong>University</strong> School <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong>. JD, New York <strong>University</strong>;<br />

MPP, Harvard <strong>University</strong>; BA, Brown <strong>University</strong>. I would like to thank the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

South Carolina School <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> and Seattle <strong>University</strong> School <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong> for their generous research<br />

support; fellow panelists at the 2008 <strong>Law</strong> and Society Conference for their helpful<br />

comments; Andrew Tsoming and James Arsenault for their research assistance; and my<br />

husband, Andrew Siegel, for all <strong>of</strong> his advice and assistance.


842 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

B. “But What About the Children?” ................................................................ 882<br />

V. WHY IS THIS PANIC DIFFERENT FROM ALL OTHER PANICS? .............................. 884<br />

A. Some Preliminary Theories ........................................................................ 884<br />

1. Race ...................................................................................................... 884<br />

2. Media Coverage.................................................................................... 888<br />

3. Alternative Panics ................................................................................ 890<br />

4. Personal Responsibility as Political Focus .......................................... 892<br />

5. Privatizing/Outsourcing ..................................................................... 894<br />

B. An Age <strong>of</strong> Ambivalence ............................................................................... 895<br />

VI. CONCLUSION ..................................................................................................... 898<br />

I. INTRODUCTION<br />

The mainstream scholarly read <strong>of</strong> criminal law and sentencing in<br />

the United <strong>State</strong>s is that the nation has in modern times moved only<br />

in one direction, towards increased criminalization <strong>of</strong> behavior and<br />

lengthier sentences for crimes. 1 This expansion <strong>of</strong> law and creation <strong>of</strong><br />

prison cells occurs regardless <strong>of</strong> whether crime is increasing and<br />

whether empirical studies support its need—either the public demands<br />

that the criminal law extend to cover additional conduct and<br />

legislators are only too happy to oblige, or legislators perceive political<br />

gains to be possible if they persuade the public that a given behavior<br />

is particularly socially dangerous and merits criminalization<br />

or increased punishment. In particular, in the area <strong>of</strong> illicit drugs,<br />

legislators have expanded codes and increased penalties over the<br />

course <strong>of</strong> the twentieth century—most strikingly, since the mid-<br />

1970s—in ways that have dramatically increased our prison population.<br />

At this point, the United <strong>State</strong>s imprisons both the largest<br />

number <strong>of</strong> people and the highest percentage <strong>of</strong> its citizenry <strong>of</strong> any<br />

1. This phenomenon is sometimes referred to as a “one-way ratchet”: for political<br />

reasons, legislatures can only move in the direction <strong>of</strong> criminalization and imprisonment.<br />

See, e.g., Lynn Adelman & Jon Deitrich, Rita, District Court Discretion, and Fairness in<br />

Federal Sentencing, 85 DENV. U.L.REV. 51, 54 (2007) (describing the United <strong>State</strong>s Sentencing<br />

Guidelines Commission’s process <strong>of</strong> creating guidelines as a “one-way ratchet” increasing<br />

sentences); Nancy J. King, Judicial Oversight <strong>of</strong> Negotiated Sentences in a World<br />

<strong>of</strong> Bargained Punishment, 58 STAN. L.REV. 293, 301 (2005) (describing Congressional adjustments<br />

to federal sentencing rules as a “one-way ratchet”); Erik Luna, The Overcriminalization<br />

Phenomenon, 54 AM.U.L.REV. 703, 719 (2005) (positing that the criminal code expands<br />

because politicians have a political incentive to criminalize but not to decriminalize);<br />

Alice Ristroph, Desert, Democracy, and Sentencing Reform, 96 J. CRIM. L.&CRIMINOLOGY<br />

1293, 1349 (2006) (describing majority rule as a “one-way ratchet” that expands the penal<br />

state); William J. Stuntz, The Pathological Politics <strong>of</strong> Criminal <strong>Law</strong>, 100 MICH. L.REV.<br />

505, 507 (2001) (arguing that “all change in criminal law seems to push in the same direction—toward<br />

more liability”); Ian Weinstein, The Revenge <strong>of</strong> Mullaney v. Wilbur: United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s v. Booker and the Reassertion <strong>of</strong> Judicial Limits on Legislative Power to Define<br />

Crimes, 84 OR. L.REV. 393, 399 (2005) (describing a “one-way ratchet” in which legislation<br />

“only begets more penal law and imposes even harsher sentences”). But see Darryl K.<br />

Brown, Democracy and Decriminalization, 86 TEX. L.REV. 223, 225 (2007) (arguing that<br />

“[t]he ratchet <strong>of</strong> crime legislation turns both ways” and describing ongoing legislative efforts<br />

to decriminalize behavior).


2010] METHADEMIC 843<br />

nation in the world. 2 Scholars and lay commentators, seeking to explain<br />

the striking incarceration increase in modern America, <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

point to the widespread criminalization <strong>of</strong> drug use and, in particular,<br />

to the increased attention to and enforcement <strong>of</strong> antidrug laws as<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the “War on Drugs.” 3<br />

After the rash <strong>of</strong> media articles about methamphetamine in 2005<br />

and 2006, 4 an observant student <strong>of</strong> American criminal sanctions<br />

might have expected to find, ensconced in new methamphetaminerelated<br />

legislation, exponentially increased penalties, new mandatory<br />

minimum sentences, life imprisonment for multiple <strong>of</strong>fenses—the<br />

sorts <strong>of</strong> changes in the law that occurred in response to a perceived<br />

epidemic <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine during the late 1980s and early 1990s. 5 The<br />

one-way ratchet <strong>of</strong> criminal sanctions would have turned in the direction<br />

<strong>of</strong> code expansion and punishment increase, and sellers, producers,<br />

and users <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine would have expected to find<br />

themselves incarcerated.<br />

Those sorts <strong>of</strong> changes, however, have not broadly characterized<br />

new methamphetamine legislation. Rather, the bulk <strong>of</strong> changes have<br />

either restricted the ability <strong>of</strong> potential methamphetamine manufacturers<br />

to access the materials used to generate methamphetamine or<br />

sought to contain the effects <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine use and production<br />

on innocent bystanders who might be exposed to environmental<br />

toxins and laboratory explosions. 6 Certainly, some themes that we<br />

have seen with past waves <strong>of</strong> drug legislation and litigation have<br />

been repeated—in particular, the insulation <strong>of</strong> children from the effects<br />

<strong>of</strong> drug use and the expansion <strong>of</strong> Fourth Amendment exceptions<br />

2. The United <strong>State</strong>s has increased its incarcerated population fivefold since the early<br />

1970s. According to the Bureau <strong>of</strong> Justice Statistics, by the middle <strong>of</strong> 2007, 1,595,034<br />

persons were incarcerated in state and federal prisons, and an additional 766,010 persons<br />

were either serving sentences in local jails or held in jail pretrial. See WILLIAM J. SABOL &<br />

HEATHER COUTURE, U.S.DEP’T OF JUSTICE, PRISON INMATES AT MIDYEAR 2007, (Jun. 2008)<br />

1, 6, available at http://bjs.ojp.usdoj.gov/index.cfm?ty=pbdetail&iid=840; see also PEW CTR.<br />

ON THE STATES, ONE IN 100: BEHIND BARS IN AMERICA 2008 3, 5 (2008), available at<br />

http://www.pewcenteronthestates.org/uploadedFiles/8015PCTS_Prison08_FINAL_2-1-<br />

1_FORWEB.pdf (finding that one in 100 adult Americans currently are incarcerated in jail or<br />

prison, and providing breakdowns <strong>of</strong> incarceration rates by race and gender). In addition, a<br />

substantial number <strong>of</strong> Americans, while not incarcerated, are under probation and parole supervision.<br />

See generally PEW CTR. ON THE STATES, ONE IN 31: THE LONG REACH OF AMERICAN<br />

CORRECTIONS (2009), available at http://www.pewcenteronthestates.org/uploadedFiles/<br />

One%20in%20100.pdf.<br />

3. See, e.g., MICHAEL TONRY, MALIGN NEGLECT—RACE, CRIME, AND PUNISHMENT IN<br />

AMERICA 4 (1995) (discussing the degree to which the “War on Drugs” is responsible for the<br />

mass incarceration <strong>of</strong> African Americans); Kenneth B. Nunn, Race, Crime and the Pool <strong>of</strong><br />

Surplus Criminality: Or Why the “War on Drugs” was a “War on Blacks,” 6 J. GENDER RACE<br />

&JUST. 381, 393 (2002) (arguing that “[t]he mass incarceration <strong>of</strong> African Americans is a<br />

direct consequence <strong>of</strong> the War on Drugs” and <strong>of</strong>fering data to demonstrate more generally<br />

the connection between drug policy and increased incarceration rates).<br />

4. See infra Part III.A.<br />

5. See infra Part II.B.<br />

6. See infra Part III.B.


844 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

to accommodate law enforcement needs. 7 Methamphetamine users,<br />

producers, and traffickers have been prosecuted and incarcerated, 8<br />

while some states have increased the penalties for methamphetamine<br />

<strong>of</strong>fenses. 9 However, in general, the law’s response to the methamphetamine<br />

pandemic has been more tempered than recent history<br />

might project. 10<br />

What explains the difference in legislative response? Perhaps<br />

some <strong>of</strong> it has to do with race. According to some scholarship on drug<br />

control in the United <strong>State</strong>s, drug prohibition tends to dovetail with<br />

cultural attitudes towards particular groups (generally defined by<br />

race, ethnicity, class, or national origin), and anxiety about particular<br />

subgroups manifests itself through draconian new criminal sanc-<br />

7. See infra Part IV.<br />

8. See, e.g., BUREAU JUST. STAT., FEDERAL JUSTICE STATISTICS 2005, BUREAU JUS<br />

STATISTICS BULLETIN 2 (September 2008), available at http://bjs.ojp.usdoj.gov/<br />

index.cfm?ty=pbdetail&iid=1104 (noting that twenty-two percent <strong>of</strong> Drug Enforcement<br />

Agency arrests in 2005 were for methamphetamine <strong>of</strong>fenses).<br />

9. See, e.g., Act <strong>of</strong> May 21, 2004, ch. 845, §§2-3, 2004 Tenn. Pub. Acts 1922, 1923 (codified<br />

at Tenn. Code. Ann. §39-17-417 (Supp. 2005)) (lowering the triggering quantity <strong>of</strong><br />

methamphetamine for certain sentences from 100 and 1000 grams to 26 and 300 grams).<br />

10. For recent works that note this surprising trend, see DORIS MARIE PROVINE, UNEQUAL<br />

UNDER LAW: RACE IN THE WAR ON DRUGS 165-66 (2007) (citing evidence about methamphetamine<br />

policy and concluding that, when it comes to drug policy, there seem to be “signs that<br />

something may have been learned from past experience”); Michael B. Cassidy, Examining Crack<br />

Cocaine Sentencing in a Post-Kimbrough World, 42 AKRON L. REV. 105, 133-34 (2009) (“Perhaps<br />

a better indicator <strong>of</strong> Congress’ willingness to change is its handling <strong>of</strong> the dramatic rise <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine,<br />

which some have termed the ‘new crack.’ In 2006, Congress enacted the first<br />

comprehensive methamphetamine law, which, surprisingly, focuses less on tougher penalties<br />

and more on cutting <strong>of</strong>f access to the ingredients used to manufacture the drug.”); see also Maureen<br />

P. Smith, Comment, America’s Methamphetamine Crisis: Solving One <strong>of</strong> America’s Leading<br />

Drug Problems Through Child Abuse and Nuisance <strong>Law</strong>s, 57 CATH.U.L.REV. 605, 612 (2008)<br />

(advocating the use <strong>of</strong> nuisance and, to a lesser extent, child abuse laws as primary tools for<br />

fighting methamphetamine despite <strong>of</strong>fering a hyperbolic account <strong>of</strong> current problems caused by<br />

the drug).<br />

The academic literature on our cultural and legal response to methamphetamine is still in<br />

its infancy. The leading sociologists and criminologists who study drug policy have thus far been<br />

surprisingly silent about methamphetamine. A few law journals have published scattered pieces—<strong>of</strong>ten<br />

student works—cataloging and critiquing some meth-related legislations. See, e.g.,<br />

Maureen P. Smith, Note, Cooking Up Solutions to a Cooked Up Menace: Responses to Methamphetamine<br />

in a Federal System, 119 HARV. L.REV. 2508 (2006); see also Elizabeth E. Joh, Imagining<br />

the Addict: Evaluating Social and Legal Responses to Addiction, 2009 UTAH L. REV. 175<br />

(comparing media coverage <strong>of</strong> and legal response to methamphetamine addiction with the very<br />

different response to tobacco addiction). The Sentencing Project, an academically-inclined advocacy<br />

organization, has published one significant study: RYAN S. KING, THE SENTENCING<br />

PROJECT, THE NEXT BIG THING?METHAMPHETAMINE IN THE UNITED STATES (2006), available at<br />

http://www.sentencingproject.org/doc/publications/dp_nextbigthing_meth.pdf. Popular commentators<br />

have shown a bit more interest. See, e.g., DIRK JOHNSON, METH: THE HOME-COOKED<br />

MENACE: HOW A LETHAL DRUG IS DEVASTATING OUR COMMUNITIES AND WHAT’S BEING DONE<br />

ABOUT IT (2005) (<strong>of</strong>fering a hyperbolic account <strong>of</strong> meth use and its consequences); NICK REDING,<br />

METHLAND: THE DEATH AND LIFE OF AN AMERICAN SMALL TOWN (2009) (<strong>of</strong>fering a more<br />

nuanced portrait <strong>of</strong> meth use and its consequences, one that largely portrays meth use as an effect—rather<br />

than a cause—<strong>of</strong> the decline <strong>of</strong> rural America).


2010] METHADEMIC 845<br />

tions. 11 A common interpretation <strong>of</strong> the harsh response to crack cocaine,<br />

for example, is that the perceived epidemic coincided with anxiety<br />

about urban crime and racially-tinged animosity against what<br />

were perceived as mostly African-American users and sellers; the resulting<br />

expansive sanctions reflected racism against African Americans.<br />

12 Perhaps the comparatively sanguine reaction to methamphetamine<br />

results from the fact that the majority <strong>of</strong> users are white. 13<br />

Relatedly, perhaps the fact that the majority <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

users are white has changed the incentives for press, police, and politicians.<br />

If past drug hysteria was fueled by racialized bias and anxiety,<br />

and the press, public, and law enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficials have—due to<br />

the race <strong>of</strong> most methamphetamine users—tempered their responses<br />

and couched descriptions <strong>of</strong> the perceived methamphetamine epidemic<br />

in less florid language than they have used in the past, they may<br />

have produced a climate in which there is simply less demand for a<br />

draconian legal response. 14 Alternatively, the pressure for legislative<br />

change might flow from legislators and executives themselves: representatives<br />

and administrators might cynically perceive that they can<br />

increase personal or institutional power by persuading the public<br />

that there exists a serious problem with a particular substance or a<br />

group that might be linked to that substance. Perhaps <strong>of</strong>ficials believe<br />

that they have less to gain with harsh rhetoric and legislation<br />

where a drug-linked group is Caucasian.<br />

These theories go some distance, perhaps, in explaining the difference<br />

between past legislative responses to drug use and the current<br />

response to the use, sale, and manufacture <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine, but<br />

they are insufficient to provide a full account. To the contrary, there<br />

is increasing evidence that something bigger is going on: careful and<br />

contextual examination <strong>of</strong> our cultural and legislative response to<br />

methamphetamine suggests that public attitudes towards drug regulation<br />

more generally seem to be changing. There is increasing evidence<br />

that the current legislative climate seems generally hostile to<br />

ratcheting up criminal sanctions for drug crimes and that the public<br />

appetite for harsh sanctions has begun to wane. 15 The “one-way rat-<br />

11. See, e.g., JAMES B. BAKALAR &LESTER GRINSPOON, DRUG CONTROL IN A FREE<br />

SOCIETY 69 (1998) (“Attitudes toward minorities, work, worldly success and failure, or sex<br />

and family life sometimes turn out to be the real issues in a controversy about drugs.<br />

Drugs are symbols charged with cultural tensions.”).<br />

12. For discussion <strong>of</strong> the role that race played in fueling the legislative and cultural<br />

response to crack cocaine, see infra Part II.B and the works cited therein.<br />

13. For data on the racial composition <strong>of</strong> those using or selling methamphetamine, see<br />

infra notes 115-16 & 210 and accompanying text.<br />

14. See infra Part V.A.2.<br />

15. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this trend in the context <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine, see infra Part III.<br />

For some recent high-pr<strong>of</strong>ile incidents in which the trend has played out more broadly, see,<br />

for example, Theo Emery, Will Crack Cocaine Sentencing Reform Help Current Cons?, TIME ,<br />

Aug 7, 2009, available at http://www.time.com/time/nation/article/0,8599,1915131,00.html


846 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

chet” as applied to drug <strong>of</strong>fenses is beginning, in some high-pr<strong>of</strong>ile<br />

instances, to spin in the opposite direction.<br />

In Part II <strong>of</strong> this Article, I <strong>of</strong>fer a brief overview <strong>of</strong> drug policy in the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s, focusing on the link between sanctions for drug <strong>of</strong>fenses<br />

and the subgroups against which those sanctions have been targeted.<br />

In particular, I focus on the literature surrounding the crack cocaine<br />

pandemic <strong>of</strong> the late 1980s and the legislative response to concern expressed<br />

by the public and by the media. In Part III, I provide a synopsis<br />

<strong>of</strong> state and federal legislative responses to methamphetamine. In<br />

Part IV, I analyze ways in which these responses resemble and depart<br />

from past responses to perceived epidemics <strong>of</strong> drug use. Finally, in<br />

Part V, I provide explanations for why these responses are more tempered<br />

than what history might have predicted.<br />

President Barack Obama’s administration recently, and with little<br />

fanfare, declared that the “War on Drugs” has come to a close. 16<br />

While that announcement—and the policy shifts it represents—do<br />

not signal that we have entered an era <strong>of</strong> drug legalization, they do<br />

suggest that we have entered a new era in drug policy. As it turns<br />

out, the American appetite for criminalization and incarceration is<br />

not insatiable.<br />

II. A (RELATIVELY)BRIEF HISTORY OF AMERICAN DRUG POLICY<br />

The application <strong>of</strong> criminal sanctions to the use, sale, and manufacture<br />

<strong>of</strong> various drugs is a relatively modern phenomenon. Until<br />

the twentieth century, American criminal law did not encompass<br />

what we would now think <strong>of</strong> as illicit drugs; substances such as<br />

opium and cocaine were in fact commonly available in products manufactured<br />

legally and designed for mass consumption. 17 In Subpart A,<br />

(quoting President Obama, the Assistant Attorney <strong>General</strong> in charge <strong>of</strong> criminal law issues,<br />

and the Chair <strong>of</strong> Federal Sentencing Commission on the need to eliminate the infamous<br />

crack-powder cocaine sentencing disparity, citing legislative progress on such reform, and<br />

predicting that “this may be the year” that the disparity is eliminated); Gary Fields, White<br />

House Czar Calls for End to “War on Drugs,” WALL ST. J., May 14, 2009, at A3 (quoting new<br />

federal Drug Czar Gil Kerlikowske’s repudiation <strong>of</strong> the language, and some <strong>of</strong> the policies, <strong>of</strong><br />

the so-called “War on Drugs”); see also Kimbrough v. United <strong>State</strong>s, 552 U.S. 85 (2007) (allowing<br />

judges discretion to sentence individuals convicted <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine crimes to lesser terms<br />

based on judges’ personal disapproval <strong>of</strong> crack/powder disparity).<br />

16. See Fields, supra note 15.<br />

17. See LESTER GRINSPOON &JAMES B. BAKALAR, COCAINE: A DRUG AND ITS SOCIAL<br />

EVOLUTION 28 (1976) (noting that cocaine-containing Coca-Cola was essential in putting<br />

drugstore soda fountains at the center <strong>of</strong> 1890s culture); LESTER GRINSPOON &PETER<br />

HEDBLOM, THE SPEED CULTURE: AMPHETAMINE USE AND ABUSE IN AMERICA 185-86 (1975)<br />

(listing over-the-counter medications available at the end <strong>of</strong> the nineteenth century, such<br />

as the morphine-laced Dr. Grove’s Anodyne for Infants and Dr. M<strong>of</strong>fett’s Teething Compound);<br />

Craig Reinarman & Harry G. Levine, Punitive Prohibition in America, in CRACK IN<br />

AMERICA: DEMON DRUGS AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 323 (Craig Reinaman & Harry G. Levine,<br />

eds., 1997) (noting that Coca-Cola, advertised as a temperate “s<strong>of</strong>t drink” alternative to alcohol,<br />

contained cocaine, and groceries vended opium-based medications).


2010] METHADEMIC 847<br />

I <strong>of</strong>fer a short history <strong>of</strong> legislative decisions to criminalize and increase<br />

penalties attendant to trade and possession <strong>of</strong> various substances,<br />

viewed through the lens <strong>of</strong> the most common explanation for<br />

the growth <strong>of</strong> such policies, which sees them as an attempt to mark<br />

and constrain racial and other minorities who threaten the peace or<br />

self-image <strong>of</strong> traditional majorities. In Subpart B, I focus on the literature<br />

surrounding legislative responses to crack cocaine, the most<br />

high-pr<strong>of</strong>ile and thoroughly-dissected recent chapter in American<br />

drug policy.<br />

A. The Twentieth Century and Drug Policy Development<br />

What we now think <strong>of</strong> as illicit drugs were once widely available<br />

in the United <strong>State</strong>s and untouched by criminal law. 18 The various<br />

legislative developments attaching criminal sanctions to illicit drugs<br />

are creatures <strong>of</strong> the twentieth century, and those developments have<br />

corresponded, per many academic commentators, with periods <strong>of</strong> concern<br />

about population groups associated with those substances. 19 According<br />

to perhaps the most common critical narrative <strong>of</strong> United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s drug policy, changes in the criminal law as applied to illicit<br />

drugs come not at times <strong>of</strong> actual increases in drug use or drugrelated<br />

social problems; rather, at times <strong>of</strong> anxiety about particular<br />

disfavored social groups, the panicking public develops drug laws to<br />

regulate and punish the use and sale <strong>of</strong> drugs stereotypically associated<br />

with the disfavored group. 20 While the substances described<br />

18. See, e.g., DAVID F. MUSTO, THE AMERICAN DISEASE: ORIGINS OF NARCOTIC<br />

CONTROL, 1-2 (3d ed. 1999) (describing the popularity <strong>of</strong> opium use medically and recreationally<br />

during the nineteenth century and noting that opium use and trade was restricted<br />

only by tariff until 1909).<br />

19. For some <strong>of</strong> the academic works central to establishing this narrative, see generally<br />

MUSTO, supra note 18; TROY DUSTER, THE LEGISLATION OF MORALITY: LAW, DRUGS, AND<br />

MORAL JUDGMENT (1970); JOSEPH R. GUSFIELD, SYMBOLIC CRUSADE: STATUS POLITICS AND<br />

THE AMERICAN TEMPERANCE MOVEMENT (1963). For a more recent work that effectively<br />

summarizes and updates this narrative, see PROVINE, supra note 10; see also Erik Grant<br />

Luna, Our Vietnam: The Prohibition Apocalypse, 46 DEPAUL L. REV. 483, 486-512 (1997)<br />

(summarizing the history <strong>of</strong> American drug policy in terms largely consistent with these<br />

works and with this Article).<br />

20. This thesis has not gone unchallenged. For works that are at least skeptical <strong>of</strong> the<br />

idea that drug policy has primarily been about attacking disfavored social groups, see, for<br />

example, BAKALAR &GRINSPOON, supra note 11, at 68-72 (discussing forces that have contributed<br />

to modern drug control policies and emphasizing the fact that “drugs are not just<br />

symbols; they are substances with distinct chemical properties and physical and psychological<br />

effects”); GRINSPOON &BAKALAR, supra note 17, at 39-40 (“Naturally, then, many<br />

people think that racial prejudice inspired the hostility toward cocaine . . . . But we suspect<br />

that racial prejudice was ancillary.”); Randall Kennedy, The <strong>State</strong>, Criminal <strong>Law</strong>, and Racial<br />

Discrimination: A Comment, 107 HARV. L.REV. 1255, 1255-56 (1994) (critiquing scholarship<br />

and a then-recent court decision equating crack-powder cocaine disparity with racial targeting<br />

<strong>of</strong> African-Americans and arguing that police indifference to effects <strong>of</strong> crime on African-<br />

American communities is a bigger problem and a more virulent form <strong>of</strong> racism).


848 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

here doubtlessly can be dangerous for personal use and lead to negative<br />

social consequences for the communities in which users 21 live,<br />

the policy responses to those dangers and consequences are perhaps<br />

not those that rational legislatures would devise.<br />

1. The Temperance Movement<br />

While antidrug movements and legislation are twentieth-century<br />

developments, they were predated by a temperance movement against<br />

alcohol. Temperance advocates linked alcohol consumption to immigrant<br />

groups (particularly Irish and Italian immigrants) who were also<br />

at the time racialized as nonwhite. 22 Advocates blamed alcohol consumption<br />

among these groups for a host <strong>of</strong> social ills, including domestic<br />

abuse, thievery, and violent crime. 23 In examining the temperance<br />

movement’s reasons for drawing a connection between alcohol use and<br />

these social problems, Joseph Gusfield has argued that temperance<br />

“was one way in which a declining social elite tried to retain some <strong>of</strong> its<br />

social power and leadership.” 24 The politics <strong>of</strong> temperance was focused<br />

on reinforcing both the distinction between the rural, middle-class, native<br />

Protestant and the poor urban immigrant and the social dominance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the former. 25 Still, in terms <strong>of</strong> operationalizing its goals, the<br />

temperance movement sought “regulatory prohibition”—preventing<br />

persons from accessing alcohol through civil and administrative rules,<br />

rather than through the use <strong>of</strong> criminal law. While temperance advocates<br />

sought to eliminate the use <strong>of</strong> alcohol, individual use was never<br />

criminalized. 26 In other words, while the temperance movement<br />

wished to limit consumption <strong>of</strong> alcohol, and cast its arguments in moral<br />

terms, it did not seek to bring to bear the severe social stigma associated<br />

with criminal conviction and punishment. 27<br />

21. I refer throughout this Article to substance users, rather than substance addicts<br />

or abusers. As discussed below, not all persons who use drugs recreationally use them <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

or otherwise exhibit signs <strong>of</strong> addiction and abuse.<br />

22. The classic account <strong>of</strong> the racial and ethnic politics at the heart <strong>of</strong> the temperance<br />

debate is GUSFIELD, supra note 19; cf. MARY P. RYAN, CRADLE OF THE MIDDLE CLASS: THE<br />

FAMILY IN ONEIDA COUNTY, NEW YORK, 1790-1865 (1981) (examining the milieu in which<br />

the American temperance movement first emerged and locating its impulse in a complex<br />

web <strong>of</strong> ethnic, class, and religious animosities). For two provocatively titled accounts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ways in which American culture and politics once racialized particular European ethnic<br />

groups, see NOEL IGNATIEV, HOW THE IRISH BECAME WHITE (1996); DAVID ROEDIGER,<br />

WORKING TOWARD WHITENESS: HOW AMERICAN IMMIGRANTS BECAME WHITE: THE<br />

STRANGE JOURNEY FROM ELLIS ISLAND TO THE SUBURBS (2006).<br />

23. See, e.g., Reinarman & Levine, supra note 17, at 323.<br />

24. GUSFIELD, supra note 19, at 5-6 (arguing that temperance was essential to distinguishing<br />

the middle class, the hard worker, and the native American from the lower class,<br />

the layabout, and the immigrant).<br />

25. Id. at 6, 55-57.<br />

26. See Reinarman & Levine, supra note 17, at 323.<br />

27. The Temperance Movement did enjoy short-lived success in the form <strong>of</strong> the Volstead<br />

Act and the Twenty-First Amendment. See U.S. CONST. amend. XVIII (1919), repealed<br />

by U.S. CONST. amend. XXI (1933); National Prohibition Act (Volstead Act), 41 Stat.


2010] METHADEMIC 849<br />

2. The Racialization <strong>of</strong> Opiates and Narcotics<br />

Early efforts to restrict access to substances such as opium, cocaine,<br />

and marijuana similarly involved regulatory prohibition rather<br />

than the use <strong>of</strong> criminal law. Preliminary state laws required prescriptions<br />

for or otherwise limited the ability <strong>of</strong> consumers to purchase<br />

opium and cocaine. 28<br />

The linkage between concern about particular social groups and<br />

increased regulations <strong>of</strong> substances associated with that group, first<br />

noted with regard to the Temperance Movement, manifested itself in<br />

new ways during the early twentieth century. As David Musto argues,<br />

during that era, drug addiction became associated with “foreign<br />

groups and internal minorities who were already actively feared and<br />

the objects <strong>of</strong> elaborate and massive social and legal restraints.” 29 In<br />

particular, drug use was tied to Chinese immigrants and African<br />

Americans. Americans associated opium smoking, for example, with<br />

Chinese immigrants, against whom they were already mobilizing<br />

other restrictive legal tools (particularly immigration controls). 30<br />

Initially, the response to increased concern about drug use was<br />

once again regulatory. For example, the Harrison Narcotics Act, 31<br />

adopted by Congress in 1914, required producers and distributors to<br />

register with the government, track transactions, and pay special<br />

taxes for handling drugs; unregistered persons could purchase drugs<br />

only by prescription or for medical use. 32 Still, unlawful possession <strong>of</strong><br />

a drug was not criminalized; it might furnish evidence that the tax<br />

and regulatory schemes had been violated, but it did not subject the<br />

305 (1919), repealed by U.S. CONST. amend. XXI (1933). <strong>State</strong>s retain wide latitude to regulate<br />

alcohol under the Twenty-First Amendment, but the great bulk <strong>of</strong> jurisdictions<br />

permit the sale <strong>of</strong> alcohol and limit themselves to time, place, and manner restrictions<br />

(such as laws confining sales to particular days, hours, or locations, limiting the ability <strong>of</strong><br />

buyers to purchase small, inexpensive “minibottles,” prohibiting overservice, restricting<br />

drinking for persons under the age <strong>of</strong> twenty-one, preventing restaurants from serving alcohol<br />

on Sundays, or prohibiting public drunkenness). Even jurisdictions that prohibit the<br />

sale <strong>of</strong> intoxicating liquors do not criminalize “responsible” use <strong>of</strong> alcohol by persons over<br />

the age <strong>of</strong> twenty-one.<br />

For a new and interesting take on the relationship between alcohol and drug regulation,<br />

see GEORGE FISHER, MARRIED TO ALCOHOL: THE DRUG WAR’S MORAL ROOTS (forthcoming).<br />

28. See GRINSPOON &BAKALAR, supra note 17, at 40 (as <strong>of</strong> 1912, fourteen states had<br />

established school-based drug education to warn about cocaine and opium; as <strong>of</strong> 1914, forty-six<br />

states had some restrictions on cocaine purchases, and twenty-nine states had some<br />

restrictions for opium purchases).<br />

29. MUSTO, supra note 18, at 5.<br />

30. See id. at 3; GRINSPOON &HEDBLOM, supra note 17, at 185 (noting a shift in public attitudes<br />

about opiates from a sympathetic association with white, wounded, morphine-addicted<br />

Civil War soldiers to negative associations with opium-using Chinese laborers).<br />

31. Pub. L. No. 63-223, 38 Stat. 785 (1914).<br />

32. See GRINSPOON &BAKALAR, supra note 17, at 41 (describing the Act).


850 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

violator to criminal sanctions. And to the extent that states prohibited<br />

narcotics distribution, enforcement was lax. 33<br />

By 1931, the landscape had changed. As <strong>of</strong> 1931, thirty-six states<br />

made unauthorized possession <strong>of</strong> cocaine a criminal <strong>of</strong>fense, and in<br />

1951, federal law began to impose mandatory prison sentences for cocaine<br />

possession. 34 While this shift to criminal regulation has never been<br />

fully explained, it does correlate with an explosion <strong>of</strong> racialized imagery<br />

and a deepening <strong>of</strong> social anxiety about minority groups. During this<br />

era, concern about the large Chinese labor force in western states hit a<br />

fever pitch. Stories about Chinese immigrants using opium to lure white<br />

women into sexual slavery proliferated. Similar complaints about the<br />

use <strong>of</strong> opium by other “inferior” and “debased” people—Italian, Jewish,<br />

and central European immigrants—began to appear; such individuals<br />

were thought to be engaging in behaviors “contrary to white supremacy<br />

and white morality.” 35 By the end <strong>of</strong> World War II, heroin had largely<br />

supplanted opium as the opiate <strong>of</strong> choice, and “racial and social prejudices”<br />

against black and Hispanic users “helped solidify national attitudes”<br />

against heroin and opium use. 36<br />

After years <strong>of</strong> being considered a health tonic, American opinion <strong>of</strong><br />

cocaine turned to one <strong>of</strong> censure, as cocaine use became associated in<br />

the popular mind with various disfavored social groups, 37 in particular<br />

African Americans. 38 Fear <strong>of</strong> cocaine-using African Americans<br />

came at a time when lynching, disenfranchisement, and legallyenforced<br />

segregation were still central features <strong>of</strong> the American landscape.<br />

39 Some whites envisioned horrific encounters in which African<br />

Americas cocaine-users would develop violent, superhuman strength<br />

and would foil law enforcement attempts to subdue them; some stories<br />

went so far as to suggest that such cocaine users would act as if<br />

invulnerable to bullets. 40 Narratives abounded about cocaine-fueled<br />

33. See MUSTO, supra note 18, at 9 (explaining that states generally lacked sufficient<br />

manpower to enforce narcotics restrictions).<br />

34. See GRINSPOON &BAKALAR, supra note 17, at 42 (cataloging these changes).<br />

35. GRINSPOON &HEDBLOM, supra note 17, at 185.<br />

36. Id. at 188.<br />

37. See GRINSPOON &BAKALAR, supra note 17, at 39; see also Preface to the Expanded<br />

Edition <strong>of</strong> MUSTO, supra note 18, at x (noting that cocaine, once viewed as “an ideal tonic,”<br />

was reconstructed as “the most dangerous <strong>of</strong> all drugs” by 1900).<br />

38. See generally MUSTO, supra note 18, at 43-44 (noting the association between African<br />

Americans and cocaine in a variety <strong>of</strong> sources). Ironically, African Americans did not in<br />

fact use cocaine in numbers greater than, or even equal to whites. See GRINSPOON &<br />

BAKALAR, supra note 17, at 40 (arguing that African Americans probably had less access to<br />

cocaine because <strong>of</strong> their relative poverty, and noting that the best documented cocaine addiction<br />

cases were white pr<strong>of</strong>essional men, particularly doctors); see also MUSTO, supra<br />

note 18, at 8.<br />

39. See MUSTO, supra note 18, at 7.<br />

40. See GRINSPOON &BAKALAR, supra note 17, at 39.


2010] METHADEMIC 851<br />

men raping Caucasian women. 41 It is with regard to cocaine that the<br />

now-familiar narrative first became explicit: we must prohibit and<br />

criminalize drug possession to prevent dangerous people from accessing<br />

dangerous substances. 42<br />

3. Marijuana (and LSD)<br />

Marijuana legislation similarly dovetailed with prejudice. As marijuana<br />

use became linked with Mexican immigrants, government<br />

concern and expanded sanction followed apace. 43 During the 1930s,<br />

for example, the Federal Bureau <strong>of</strong> Narcotics conducted a raciallytinged<br />

educational campaign describing marijuana as such a potent<br />

criminological agent that a single use could transform an upstanding<br />

citizen into a violent criminal. 44<br />

The history <strong>of</strong> marijuana regulation nicely illustrates that the disfavored<br />

subgroup theory is not uniformly about race, ethnicity, or<br />

immigration. In the 1960s and early 1970s, a new round <strong>of</strong> drug<br />

regulation followed quickly 45 as some drugs—marijuana and LSD, in<br />

particular—became associated with a band <strong>of</strong> political and cultural<br />

dissenters. 46 Drug use became an axis on which dissenters explicitly<br />

set themselves apart and drug policy served as a mechanism through<br />

which the cultural majority reinforced its status as the embodiment<br />

<strong>of</strong> moral norms. 47 Through this lens, attention to drug use in the<br />

41. See id. at 38-39 (detailing how cocaine was linked in media articles to African-<br />

American convicts, lower economic classes, Jewish vendors, prostitutes, and poorlybehaved<br />

soldiers).<br />

42. See id. at 40. Like with marijuana, see infra notes 43-47 and accompanying text,<br />

the cultural anxieties that spawned the crackdown on cocaine transcended race. Grinspoon<br />

and Bakalar argue that racial prejudice was probably ancillary to a general desire to keep<br />

cocaine out <strong>of</strong> the hands <strong>of</strong> all potentially “dangerous” persons, including white women who<br />

might be seduced or corrupted by exposure to cocaine. See id.<br />

43. On the association <strong>of</strong> marijuana with Mexican immigrants, see, for example, H.<br />

WAYNE MORGAN, DRUGS IN AMERICA: ASOCIAL HISTORY, 1800-1980 93-94 (1981). For the<br />

story <strong>of</strong> the passage <strong>of</strong> the first significant federal law regulating marijuana and the climate<br />

<strong>of</strong> panic that facilitated that legislation, see HOWARD S. BECKER, OUTSIDERS:<br />

STUDIES IN THE SOCIOLOGY OF DEVIANCE 135-46 (1973).<br />

44. See BECKER, supra note 43, at 135-46; GRINSPOON &HEDBLOM, supra note 17, at 182.<br />

Grinspoon and Hedblom note that no data support or supported this assertion. Id. at 183.<br />

45. The most famous (and probably the most draconian) laws adopted during this era<br />

were New York’s so-called “Rockefeller Drug <strong>Law</strong>s,” which (until their recent amendment)<br />

imposed significant mandatory prison sentences for relatively minor drug infractions. See,<br />

e.g., Act <strong>of</strong> May 8, 1973, ch. 276 §§220.21, 220.43, 1973 N.Y. <strong>Law</strong>s 371, 380-81 (codified as<br />

amended in N.Y. Penal <strong>Law</strong>) (classifying criminal possession <strong>of</strong> two or more ounces <strong>of</strong> a<br />

controlled substance and criminal sale <strong>of</strong> one or more ounces <strong>of</strong> a controlled substance as<br />

Class A-I felonies).<br />

46. See Reinarman & Levine, Crack in Context, in CRACK IN AMERICA, supra note 17,<br />

at 7-8 (arguing that marijuana in the 1960s and 1970s became associated with youthful rebellion<br />

against achievement and opposition to the Vietnam War, creating a “dangerous”<br />

youth class and “a useful symbol in an essentially political conflict between cultures and<br />

generations.”). This analysis draws upon the earlier work <strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Becker. See generally<br />

BECKER, supra note, 43.<br />

47. See Reinarman & Levine supra note 46.


852 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

1960s and early 1970s was less about reducing the possible personal<br />

or social harm associated with drug use than it was about reinforcing<br />

the majority’s status; like in the periods preceding and following,<br />

drug legislation during this era was <strong>of</strong>ten a proxy for cultural contestation<br />

between competing social groups.<br />

B. Crackademic: The 1980s and Beyond<br />

The crack cocaine panic <strong>of</strong> the late 1980s probably has received<br />

the most attention, in the scholarly press and in the popular media,<br />

<strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> the various drug panics <strong>of</strong> the past century. Sociologists<br />

Craig Reinerman and Harry Levine have documented exhaustively<br />

and persuasively the press coverage <strong>of</strong> the crack cocaine “epidemic,”<br />

the timing <strong>of</strong> that coverage relative to documented trends in crack cocaine<br />

use, the extent to which press coverage reflected accurate information<br />

about crack cocaine effects, and the effects <strong>of</strong> press and<br />

public response on crack cocaine litigation and legislation. 48 During<br />

the late 1980s and early 1990s, the “one way ratchet” turned with a<br />

vengeance. The resulting system <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine laws persists into<br />

the present: lengthier terms <strong>of</strong> imprisonment, mandatory minimum<br />

sentences, parole and probation ineligibility, and penalties that escalate<br />

with increased numbers <strong>of</strong> convictions. 49<br />

Cocaine was not a new drug when coverage <strong>of</strong> a purported epidemic<br />

<strong>of</strong> crack cocaine use began. Cocaine, as discussed earlier, had been<br />

used throughout the twentieth century, and its use had long violated<br />

criminal law. 50 In surveying cocaine use in the United <strong>State</strong>s as <strong>of</strong><br />

1976, Lester Greenspoon and James Bakalar observed that cocaine “is<br />

rapidly attaining un<strong>of</strong>ficial respectability . . . . It is accepted as a relatively<br />

innocuous stimulant, casually used by those who can afford it to<br />

brighten the day or the evening . . . . Use <strong>of</strong> cocaine is gradually<br />

spreading in the upper middle class.” 51 Greenspoon and Bakalar noted<br />

that at the time that they were writing, “[w]ith a few minor exceptions,<br />

no one contends that coca causes any significant crime [or] violence.” 52<br />

Whatever Greenspoon and Bakalar might have predicted about<br />

the trajectory <strong>of</strong> social attitudes towards cocaine in the mid-1970s, by<br />

the mid-1980s, the trajectory clearly changed, at least with respect to<br />

48. See generally Craig Reinarman & Harry G. Levine, Crack in the Rearview Mirror:<br />

Deconstructing Drug War Mythology, 31 SOC. JUST. 182 (2004); CRACK IN AMERICA, supra<br />

note 17.<br />

49. See, e.g., Reinarman & Levine, supra note 17, at 321-22 (arguing that such escalating<br />

sanctions have typified the U.S. response to drugs and quoting government documents<br />

that demonstrate the intentionality <strong>of</strong> such a regime).<br />

50. See supra Part II.A.2.<br />

51. GRINSPOON &BAKALAR, supra note 17, at 64.<br />

52. Id. at 218.


2010] METHADEMIC 853<br />

one particular form <strong>of</strong> cocaine—crack. 53 Smoking cocaine to obtain a<br />

high was not new—cocaine users had for some time used cocaine by<br />

“freebasing.” 54 What was new was the attention to and panic about<br />

smokable cocaine.<br />

The media coverage <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine began in earnest in 1986, and<br />

was promptly distinguished by both its volume and its remarkable<br />

levels <strong>of</strong> hyperbole and disinformation. 55 Newsweek quoted an expert<br />

who described crack as a drug that produced an “instantaneous addiction”<br />

more severe than any other; 56 the New York Times and<br />

Newsweek compared crack cocaine to an epidemic or plague; 57 and<br />

media sources generally described the wildfire spread, epidemic use,<br />

plague proportions, and addictive properties <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine 58 in<br />

ways that their own later coverage found factually incorrect. 59 Crack<br />

cocaine was linked to violent crime. 60 As Reinarman and Levine ar-<br />

53. Crack cocaine is a smokeable form <strong>of</strong> cocaine produced by “cooking down” a mixture<br />

<strong>of</strong> powder cocaine, water, and baking powder. While cocaine has long been present in<br />

this country and has been smoked extensively since at least the early 1970s, the diluted,<br />

relatively inexpensive “cooked down” cocaine that came to be know as “crack” emerged in<br />

urban areas in 1984 and 1985. See Reinarman & Levine, supra note 46, at 1, 2 (explaining<br />

the emergence <strong>of</strong> “crack”). As Pr<strong>of</strong>essors Reinarman and Levine explain “Crack was not a<br />

new drug . . . . Crack was a marketing innovation.” Id.<br />

54. See Beverly Xaviera Watkins & Mindy Thompson Fullilove, The Crack Epidemic<br />

and the Failure <strong>of</strong> Epidemic Reponse, 10 TEMP. POL. &CIV. RTS. L.REV. 371, 377 (2001)<br />

(describing 1979 testimony before Congress warning <strong>of</strong> the dangers <strong>of</strong> “free-base cocaine”).<br />

55. Reinarman and Levine describe the press coverage <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine as a “media<br />

frenzy,” noting that in July <strong>of</strong> 1986, “the three major TV networks <strong>of</strong>fered seventy-four<br />

evening news segments on drugs, half <strong>of</strong> these about crack.” Reinarman & Levine, The<br />

Crack Attack: Politics and Media in the Crack Scare, in CRACK IN AMERICA, supra note 17,<br />

at 19-22. See generally JIMMIE L. REEVES &RICHARD CAMPBELL, CRACKED COVERAGE:<br />

TELEVISION NEWS, THE ANTI-COCAINE CRUSADE, AND THE REAGAN LEGACY (1994) (cataloging<br />

and critiquing television coverage <strong>of</strong> drugs during the 1980s and early 1990s); cf.<br />

MARTIN TORGOFF, CAN’T FIND MY WAY HOME: AMERICA IN THE GREAT STONED AGE,<br />

1945—2000, 350-57 (2004) (narrating the key mileposts <strong>of</strong> the press coverage and explaining<br />

how press portrayal played into themes <strong>of</strong> a larger culture war).<br />

56. See Reinarman & Levine, supra note 46, at 3 (citing Kids and Cocaine NEWSWEEK,<br />

Mar. 1, 1986, at 58-59).<br />

57. See id. at 3-4; see also Reinarman & Levine, supra note 55, at 24 (citing New York<br />

Times/CBS News polling data that indicated that in January <strong>of</strong> 1985, 1% <strong>of</strong> Americans<br />

considered drugs to be the most important problem facing the United <strong>State</strong>s; by September<br />

<strong>of</strong> 1989, that figure had risen to 64%).<br />

58. See Reinarman & Levine, supra note 55, at 20-22 (describing in depth the nature<br />

and timeline <strong>of</strong> mass media coverage <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine and noting that “plague,” “epidemic,”<br />

and “crisis” were descriptors commonly employed in press coverage).<br />

59. See Reinarman & Levine, supra note 46, at 4 (noting that, by 1989 or 1990, many major<br />

news outlets were running stories quietly critical <strong>of</strong> their own initial coverage <strong>of</strong> “crack”).<br />

60. See, e.g., Paul J. Goldstein, et al., Crack and Homicide in New York City: A Case<br />

Study in the Epidemiology <strong>of</strong> Violence, in CRACK IN AMERICA, supra note 17, at 113, 122-24<br />

(noting media coverage and political rhetoric about “crack-related murders” and finding,<br />

based on 1988 homicide data from New York City, that while a majority <strong>of</strong> drug-related homicides<br />

in New York City did involve cocaine or crack cocaine, most <strong>of</strong> the homicides had to do<br />

with the risks <strong>of</strong> the illicit drug market, as opposed to the psychopharmacological effects <strong>of</strong><br />

cocaine or crack cocaine); Watkins & Fullilove, supra note 54, at 375 (noting media coverage


854 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

gue, the overwhelming majority <strong>of</strong> young people in the United <strong>State</strong>s,<br />

during the time <strong>of</strong> hysterical coverage, were not using crack cocaine,<br />

and the overwhelming majority <strong>of</strong> people who had used crack cocaine<br />

had not continued to use it with any frequency. 61 By most measures,<br />

in the late 1980s, drug use generally—and cocaine use specifically—<br />

was in decline. 62 Despite the fact that fewer Americans were using<br />

drugs, by 1989, the majority <strong>of</strong> Americans polled identified the most<br />

important problem facing the United <strong>State</strong>s as “drugs.” 63<br />

Crack cocaine also produced headlines and prosecutions related to<br />

an alleged “crack baby” epidemic, where, per the media and other<br />

sources, crack cocaine caused large numbers <strong>of</strong> infants to suffer severe,<br />

irreversible health problems resulting from maternal use <strong>of</strong><br />

crack cocaine. In 1985 and 1986, major news outlets began reporting<br />

that crack cocaine-exposed babies might comprise a “biological underclass”<br />

suffering from, among other things, permanent mental retardation,<br />

deviance, and an inability to perform basic self-care<br />

tasks. 64 The idea <strong>of</strong> a permanent underclass <strong>of</strong> crack-cocaine-ruined<br />

children captured the public imagination. 65 Reports on the “crack baby”<br />

phenomenon proved medically unfounded—cocaine exposure affects<br />

newborns, but does not create a particular “crack baby” syndrome<br />

with the terrifying symptoms and developmental debilitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> crack cocaine in 1985 and 1986 that, focusing on violence, described crack cocaine addiction<br />

as “growing at alarming rates” and creating “an authentic national crisis.”).<br />

61. See Reinarman & Levine, supra note 48, at 186 (noting that during the period <strong>of</strong><br />

the crack cocaine scare into the early 2000s, fewer than five percent <strong>of</strong> eighteen to twentynine<br />

year olds ever tried crack, and <strong>of</strong> those who had tried it, 80% had not used crack cocaine<br />

within the past year and over 90% had not used it within the past month); id. at 188<br />

(noting that crack cocaine usage “did not spread far beyond the most marginalized and<br />

vulnerable segments <strong>of</strong> society”); id. at 189 (noting that per National Institute on Drug<br />

Abuse surveys, the use <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine among high school seniors declined every year from<br />

1986 through 1991, while media articles were writing about the “epidemic” spread <strong>of</strong> crack<br />

cocaine use).<br />

62. See Reinarman & Levine, supra note 55, at 18, 27-28 (surveying drug use data to<br />

conclude that by the time crack cocaine coverage began in earnest, drug use generally and<br />

cocaine and crack cocaine use specifically were in decline, and noting that 1982 was the<br />

high water mark for lifetime cocaine use among young Americans). Moreover, during the<br />

period in which media articles about crack cocaine proliferated, most cocaine users were<br />

“sniffing, rather than smoking,” the drug. Id. at 28.<br />

63. See id., supra note 55, at 24 (citing New York Times/CBS News polling data).<br />

64. See generally Reinarman & Levine, supra note 48, at 192 (describing the content <strong>of</strong><br />

articles and features in Newsweek, the Washington Post, and on CBS Evening News); Loren<br />

Siegel, The Pregnancy Police Fight the War on Drugs, in CRACK IN AMERICA at 249, 255, supra<br />

note 17, (summarizing late-1980s media articles about the “crack baby” phenomenon).<br />

65. Chapters <strong>of</strong> Children Requiring a Caring Kommunity (C.R.A.C.K.) can be found in<br />

several major cities; the program pays women who are addicted to drugs $200 to undergo<br />

sterilization or use long-term birth control such as IUDs. See generally Adam B. Wolf, Note,<br />

What Money Cannot Buy: A Legislative Response to C.R.A.C.K., 33 U. MICH. J.L.REFORM<br />

173 (1999) (arguing for legislation to prevent C.R.A.C.K. from <strong>of</strong>fering money in exchange<br />

for permanent sterilization or long-term birth control). The majority <strong>of</strong> women who have<br />

utilized the program are women <strong>of</strong> color. Id. at 178 (sixty-three percent <strong>of</strong> women who have<br />

participated in the C.R.A.C.K. program are African-American or Latina).


2010] METHADEMIC 855<br />

initially described. 66 Rather, many <strong>of</strong> the health problems found with<br />

babies born to mothers who had used crack were attributable to lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> prenatal care, poor nutrition and personal care, and co-existing<br />

substance use such as tobacco and alcohol. 67 The “crack baby” image<br />

has, however, endured, and has left in its wake legislative changes<br />

and creative prosecution strategies designed to apply criminal sanctions<br />

to women who expose developing fetuses to crack. 68<br />

66. See, e.g., Deborah A. Frank et. al., Growth, Development, and Behavior in Early<br />

Childhood Following Prenatal Cocaine Exposure: A Systematic Review, 285 JAMA 1613,<br />

1619 (2001) (effects <strong>of</strong> prenatal cocaine exposure are indiscernible once tobacco and alcohol<br />

exposure are controlled); L.C. Mayesm, et al., Commentary: The Problem <strong>of</strong> Prenatal Cocaine<br />

Exposure: A Rush to Judgment, 267 JAMA 406-08 (1992) (arguing, fairly soon after<br />

height <strong>of</strong> “crack baby” scare, that popular fears were likely overstated); Patrick Zickler,<br />

NIDA Studies Clarify Developmental Effects <strong>of</strong> Prenatal Cocaine Exposure, 14 NAT’L INST.<br />

ON DRUG ABUSE NOTES (Sept. 1999), available at<br />

http://archives.drugabuse.gov/NIDA_Notes/NNVol14N3/Prenatal.html (summarizing the<br />

position <strong>of</strong> the National Institute on Drug Abuse that cocaine delays motor skill and intellectual<br />

development, but that such effects are “not as pr<strong>of</strong>ound” as early reports indicated<br />

and that it is difficult for researches to isolate the effects <strong>of</strong> cocaine from those <strong>of</strong> poor prenatal<br />

care, poor self-care, coexisting drug use, and other factors known to negatively affect<br />

development); Cocaine Pharmacology, “Crack Babies,” Violence: Hearings Before the U.S.<br />

Sent’g Comm’n, (Feb. 25, 2002) (statement <strong>of</strong> Deborah Frank, M.D.), reprinted in 14 FED.<br />

SENT’G REP. 191, 196 (2002) (concluding, based on ten years <strong>of</strong> study at a National Institute<br />

on Drug Abuse project following developmental and behavioral outcomes for crack cocaine<br />

exposed babies, that crack cocaine does not affect babies differently than powder cocaine;<br />

that the effects <strong>of</strong> the drug are similar to those caused by tobacco; that there is no<br />

“crack baby” syndrome; and that early studies identifying such a syndrome were deeply<br />

flawed); see also 846 ANNALS OF N. Y. ACAD. SCI., John A. Harvey & Barry E. Kos<strong>of</strong>sky,<br />

eds., COCAINE: EFFECTS ON THE DEVELOPING BRAIN, at xi (1998) (making similar arguments).<br />

Dr. Ira Chasn<strong>of</strong>f, whose early anecdotal observations <strong>of</strong> babies born to crack-using<br />

mothers helped fuel the medial coverage, concluded after further research that he had<br />

“never seen a ‘crack kid.’ ” Ira J. Chasn<strong>of</strong>f, Missing Pieces <strong>of</strong> the Puzzle, 15<br />

NEUROTOXICOLOGY &TERATOLOGY 287, 288 (1993). Dr. Deborah Frank, a leading expert in<br />

children’s’ failure to thrive, concluded that the public outcry for the punishment <strong>of</strong> substance-using<br />

mothers and the disenfranchisement <strong>of</strong> their children as an unsalvageable,<br />

almost demonic “biological underclass . . . rest[s] not on scientific findings but upon media<br />

hysteria fueled by selected anecdotes.” Deborah A. Frank, Commentary: Children Exposed<br />

to Cocaine Prenatally: Pieces <strong>of</strong> the Puzzle, 15 NEUROTOXICOLOGY & TERATOLOGY 298, 299<br />

(1993).<br />

67. See Ira Glasser & Loren Siegel, When Constitutional Rights Seem Too Extravagant<br />

to Endure: The Crack Scare’s Impact on Civil Rights and Liberties, in CRACK IN<br />

AMERICA, supra note 17 at 229, 241-42.<br />

68. Prosecutors have employed existing child abuse statutes to prosecute women who<br />

test positive for drug use during pregnancy or whose newborn infants test positive for illicit<br />

drug use, particularly cocaine use. Prosecution strategies have ranged from coercive (designed<br />

to convince a drug-using pregnant women to seek treatment or face prosecution and<br />

incarceration) to directly punitive (criminally sanctioning women who use drugs while<br />

pregnant). See LAURA E. GÓMEZ, MISCONCEIVING MOTHERS: LEGISLATORS, PROSECUTORS,<br />

AND THE POLITICS OF PRENATAL DRUG EXPOSURE 78 (1997).<br />

These strategies generally have not survived scrutiny from reviewing courts. See, e.g.,<br />

Siegel, supra note 64, at 249 (describing cases in North Carolina, Virginia, and New York<br />

where prosecutors initially charged women who ingested cocaine while pregnant with assault<br />

with a deadly weapon with intent to kill, felony child neglect, and endangering the welfare <strong>of</strong><br />

a child; these indictments, as well as most similar indictments, were dismissed). In Ferguson<br />

v. City <strong>of</strong> Charleston, 532 U.S. 67 (2001), for example, the United <strong>State</strong>s Supreme Court re-


856 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

Crack cocaine was portrayed and perceived as something far more<br />

addictive and far more menacing than powder cocaine or any other<br />

drug. The legislative reaction to public and media concern about crack<br />

cocaine was swift and severe. 69 <strong>State</strong>s enacted new mandatory minimum<br />

sentences requiring <strong>of</strong>fenders to serve prison time; increased<br />

available statutory maximums; and in some cases, provided mandatory<br />

life without parole for crack-cocaine <strong>of</strong>fenses. 70 At the federal level,<br />

Congress included among its responses the now-infamous “100:1 ra-<br />

jected one such program, a cooperative effort between the Medical <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> South Carolina,<br />

the Charleston, South Carolina Solicitor’s Office, the Department <strong>of</strong> Social Services, the<br />

County Substance Abuse Commission, and the local police. 532 U.S. at 71, 81-82. Per this<br />

program, pregnant patients suspected <strong>of</strong> illicit drug use were subjected to urine drug screens.<br />

Id. at 71. Patients who tested positive for cocaine use prior to 28 weeks could be charged with<br />

simple possession <strong>of</strong> cocaine; after 28 weeks, to possession and distribution to a person under<br />

the age <strong>of</strong> 18; and at delivery, with the additional <strong>of</strong>fense <strong>of</strong> unlawful neglect <strong>of</strong> a child. Id. at<br />

71-72. The Supreme Court held that this program comprised a Fourth Amendment search<br />

that did not comport with the special needs exception from the generalized requirement <strong>of</strong> a<br />

warrant and probable cause. Id. at 81-82.<br />

<strong>State</strong> courts have similarly rejected prosecutions <strong>of</strong> women for child abuse based on<br />

drug use during pregnancy. See, e.g., <strong>State</strong> v. Martinez, 137 P.3d 1195, 1198 (N.M. Ct. App.<br />

2006) (refusing to extend state’s child abuse statute to cover fetuses). Though prosecutors<br />

have attempted to utilize a wide variety <strong>of</strong> statutes—including child abuse, child endangerment,<br />

and delivery <strong>of</strong> a controlled substance—most state courts similarly have declined<br />

to read existing statutes as holding drug-using pregnant women criminally responsible for<br />

the potential exposure <strong>of</strong> their fetuses. See, e.g., Reinesto v. Superior Court <strong>of</strong> Ariz., 894<br />

P.2d 733, 737 (AZ. Ct. App. 1995) (rejecting use <strong>of</strong> child abuse statute); People v. Hardy,<br />

469 N.W. 2d 50, 55 (Mich. Ct. App. 1991) (rejecting use <strong>of</strong> delivery <strong>of</strong> cocaine charge).; <strong>State</strong><br />

v. Gray, 584 N.E.2d 710, 713 (Ohio 1992) (rejecting child endangerment charge); <strong>State</strong> v.<br />

Dunn, 916 P.2d 952, 956 (Wash. App. 1996) (rejecting use <strong>of</strong> mistreatment <strong>of</strong> child statute);<br />

cf. <strong>State</strong> v. Deborah J.Z., 596 N.W.2d 490, 496 (Wis. Ct. App. 1999) (rejecting use <strong>of</strong> reckless<br />

homicide and related charges against mother who was drunk when she delivered a<br />

stillborn fetus). South Carolina, on the other hand, has permitted women to be prosecuted<br />

for <strong>of</strong>fenses based on fetal exposure to maternally ingested drugs. See <strong>State</strong> v. McKnight,<br />

576 S.E.2d 168, 174-75 (S.C. 2003) (permitting woman to be prosecuted for homicide by<br />

child abuse where woman had used cocaine during pregnancy and fetus was stillborn);<br />

Whitner v. <strong>State</strong>, 492 S.E. 2d 777, 782 (1997) (permitting child endangerment prosecution<br />

where pregnant woman ingested cocaine); see also Ellen Marrus, Crack Babies and the<br />

Constitution: Ruminations About Addicted Pregnant Women After Ferguson v. City <strong>of</strong><br />

Charleston, 47 VILL. L.REV. 299, 301-02 (2003) (describing various state strategies for<br />

prosecuting pregnant drug-using women and noting that courts generally have rejected<br />

such strategies). Women not charged specifically with <strong>of</strong>fenses related to ingesting drugs<br />

while pregnant may face stiffer sentences from judges who believe that jail or prison might<br />

ensure that pregnant women stop using drugs. See Siegel, supra note 64, at 250-51.<br />

Legislative efforts to create new statutes to permit specifically the prosecution <strong>of</strong><br />

drug-using pregnant women, while popular, never led to specific sanctions against drugusing<br />

pregnant women. See Lynn M. Paltrow et al. Governmental Responses to Pregnant<br />

Women Who Use Alcohol or Other Drugs, Part 1, WOMEN’S LAW PROJECT AND NAT’L<br />

ADVOCATES FOR PREGNANT WOMEN (Oct. 2000), available at http://www.drugpolicy.org/<br />

library/governmental_response_p1.cfm.<br />

69. See Reinarman & Levine, supra note 55, at 21 (noting that in 1986, “overwhelming<br />

majorities <strong>of</strong> both houses <strong>of</strong> Congress voted for new antidrug laws with long mandatory prison<br />

terms, death sentences, and large increases in funding for police and prisons”).<br />

70. See, e.g., Harmelin v. Michigan, 601 U.S. 957, 1028 (1991) (rejecting an Eighth<br />

Amendment challenge to a Michigan law providing for a mandatory life sentence for possession<br />

<strong>of</strong> a relatively minor amount <strong>of</strong> cocaine).


2010] METHADEMIC 857<br />

tio”—the United <strong>State</strong>s Sentencing Guidelines require 100 grams <strong>of</strong><br />

powder cocaine to trigger the same mandatory minimum sentence as<br />

one gram <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine, and this ratio is included in the Guidelines<br />

generally for cocaine and crack-cocaine <strong>of</strong>fenses. 71 These legislative<br />

responses to crack cocaine, which treated it as a new and more serious<br />

drug than powder cocaine, may explain some <strong>of</strong> the racial differences<br />

in incarceration rates. 72 What the legislative response to crack cocaine<br />

did not include was much by way <strong>of</strong> a public health response; government<br />

“focused less on standard public health practice and . . . more on<br />

the courts, the police, and the prisons.” 73<br />

If by the time legislation and media articles were appearing, however,<br />

crack cocaine use—never particularly widespread—was on the<br />

decline, how can we explain the dramatic legislative response, which<br />

suggested that crack cocaine abuse was both rampant and on the rise?<br />

Probably the most common explanation provided for the disconnect<br />

between the reaction to and the reality <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine has been<br />

that <strong>of</strong> race—white Americans were panicking about African Americans,<br />

particularly young urban African-American men. 74 Crack cocaine<br />

use and trade was linked through media articles and legislative<br />

debates to violent <strong>of</strong>fenses, degradation <strong>of</strong> urban centers, family<br />

breakdown, and a host <strong>of</strong> other social problems. 75 A lack <strong>of</strong> sympathetic<br />

identification on the part <strong>of</strong> Caucasian legislators and voters<br />

may have facilitated this linkage as well as the decision to deal with<br />

this constellation <strong>of</strong> perceived problems through incarceration and<br />

criminal control.<br />

Whether or not enforcement <strong>of</strong> drug laws is racist in design or intent,<br />

the argument goes, the War on Drugs has been in operation a<br />

war on African-Americans. 76 For many scholars and civil rights lead-<br />

71. Anti-Drug Abuse Act <strong>of</strong> 1986, Pub. L. No. 99-570, 100 Stat. 3207 (1986) (codified<br />

as amended at 21 U.S.C. § 841 (1994)).<br />

72. See, e.g., Troy Duster, Pattern, Purpose, and Race in the Drug War, in CRACK IN<br />

AMERICA, supra note 17, at 265-66 (describing differences in federal sentencing for powder<br />

and crack cocaine <strong>of</strong>fenses and noting that various federal sentencing laws related to crack<br />

cocaine contribute to a pattern <strong>of</strong> longer sentences for African-American defendants).<br />

73. Watkins & Fullilove, supra note 54, at 385-86.<br />

74. In addition to the works <strong>of</strong> Reinarman & Levine, collected in CRACK IN AMERICA,<br />

supra note 48, see the sources cited infra notes 76-77.<br />

75. See supra notes 55-60 and accompanying text.<br />

76. See, e.g., Alfred Blumstein, The Notorious 100:1 Crack: Powder Disparity—The<br />

Data Tell Us that It Is Time to Restore the Balance, 16 FED.SENT’G REP. 87, 87 (2003) (noting<br />

that the crack: powder sentencing differences are “particularly distressing because<br />

crack defendants are primarily black and powder defendants are primarily white and Hispanic,<br />

so the differential treatment can too easily be seen as a manifestation <strong>of</strong> racial discrimination”);<br />

Duster, supra note 72, at 264-65 (citing statistics to the effect that while in<br />

the early 1990s, African-Americans comprised 15-20% <strong>of</strong> drug users, in most urban areas,<br />

they comprised half to two-thirds <strong>of</strong> persons arrested for drug <strong>of</strong>fenses and attributing racial<br />

imbalances in arrest and prosecution rates to “the selective aim <strong>of</strong> the artillery in the<br />

drug war”); Glasser & Siegel, supra note 67, at 241 (arguing that “fears about crack merged<br />

easily with racial fears”); cf. David A. Sklansky, Cocaine, Race, and Equal Protection, 47


858 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

ers, late twentieth century drug policy was “[t]he [n]ew Jim Crow.” 77<br />

Civil rights activists particularly decried the differences in the federal<br />

sentencing guidelines for powder cocaine and crack cocaine, depicting<br />

this dual sentencing scheme as a transparent attempt to punish<br />

African-American criminality more harshly than its white counterpart.<br />

78 (Many scholars concur, arguing that the current racial imbalances<br />

in incarceration rates are substantially attributable to efforts<br />

to combat crack cocaine.) 79<br />

Some people who have looked at the responses <strong>of</strong> government bodies<br />

and the public in general to crack cocaine have theorized that part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the reaction was not only about race, but about the intersection between<br />

race and gender. Prosecutions <strong>of</strong> drug-using women have primarily<br />

been aimed at African-American women, 80 although drug use<br />

is fairly level among pregnant women <strong>of</strong> all races. 81 The gender/race<br />

linkage has perhaps reflected a desire to control African-American<br />

women who are considered undesirable mothers and to prevent them<br />

STAN. L.REV. 1283 (1995) (arguing that evidence is overwhelming that race is instrumental<br />

in explaining crack/powder cocaine disparity and faulting existing equal protection doctrine<br />

for not coming to same conclusion).<br />

Some go even further in assessing the relationship between race and the governmental<br />

response to crack cocaine. Nkechi Taifa, currently a Senior Policy Analyst at the Open<br />

Society Policy Center, argues that the federal approach to crack cocaine investigation,<br />

prosecution, and sentencing “is not only a direct reflection <strong>of</strong> the institutionalization <strong>of</strong> racism<br />

in the criminal justice system, but <strong>of</strong> systematic genocide, generally, against Black<br />

people as well.” Nkechi Taifa, Beyond Institutionalized Racism: The Genocidal Impact <strong>of</strong><br />

Executive, Legislative & Judicial Decision-Making in the Crack Cocaine Fiasco, NAT’L B.<br />

ASS’N MAG., Sept./Oct. 1996, at 13, 14-16 (arguing that crack cocaine sentences are not<br />

supported by empirical evidence and denote a “racially discriminatory drug enforcement<br />

policy,” and describing the federal crack: powder cocaine sentencing differences as “apartheid-type”).<br />

But see Kennedy, supra note 20, at 1267 (arguing that African Americans are<br />

harmed by under- rather than over-enforcement <strong>of</strong> drug laws); John P. Walters, Race and<br />

the War on Drugs, 1994 U. CHI. LEGAL F. 107, 144 (arguing that enforcement <strong>of</strong> drug laws<br />

has not reflected racism or produced racially disparate results).<br />

77. See, e.g., Symposium, U.S. Drug <strong>Law</strong>s: The New Jim Crow?, 10 TEMP.POL.&CIV.<br />

RTS. L.REV. 303 passim (2001); Ira Glasser, American Drug <strong>Law</strong>s: The New Jim Crow, 63<br />

ALB.L.REV. 703, 723 (2000).<br />

78. See, e.g., Powder Cocaine, Crack Cocaine, and Race, Hearing Before the U.S. Sent.<br />

Comm’n, (Feb. 25, 2002) (<strong>State</strong>ment <strong>of</strong> Wade Henderson, Executive Director <strong>of</strong> the Leadership<br />

Conference on Civil Rights) (arguing that federal drug policy disproportionately affects<br />

African Americans because <strong>of</strong> the heightened penalties for crack cocaine as compared<br />

to powder cocaine—as well as racism in criminal investigation and prosecution, and calling<br />

for Guidelines changes that would reduce disparities), reprinted in 14 FED. SENT’G REP.<br />

204, 205 (2002).<br />

79. See, e.g., Blumstein, supra note 76, at 87; Duster, supra note 72, at 265 (noting<br />

that in Virginia, in 1983, 63% <strong>of</strong> new prison admits for drug <strong>of</strong>fenses were white; by 1989,<br />

34% were white).<br />

80. See Glasser & Siegel, supra note 67, at 242.<br />

81. See Ira J. Chasn<strong>of</strong>f, Harvey J. Landress, & Mark E. Barrett, The Prevalence <strong>of</strong> Illicit<br />

Drug or Alcohol Use During Pregnancy and Discrepancies in Mandatory Reporting in Pinellas<br />

County, <strong>Florida</strong>, 322 NEW ENG. J. MED. 1202, 1204 (Apr. 26, 1990) (finding that in Pinellas<br />

County, <strong>Florida</strong>, while among pregnant women screened, 15.4% <strong>of</strong> white women and 14.1% <strong>of</strong><br />

African-American women tested positive for drugs, African-American women were ten times<br />

more likely to be reported for substance abuse); Siegel, supra note 64, at 251.


2010] METHADEMIC 859<br />

from continuing to reproduce. 82 For example, critiques <strong>of</strong> the “Children<br />

Requiring a Caring Kommunity” or “Project Prevention” program<br />

(“CRACK”), which <strong>of</strong>fers drug-addicted women two hundred dollars<br />

in exchange for sterilization, have argued that the program is an attempt<br />

to regulate “bad” mothers—largely poor, African-American<br />

women. 83<br />

Not all critiques <strong>of</strong> U.S. crack cocaine policy center on race. William<br />

Stuntz, for example, has described the response to crack cocaine<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> class. 84 Poor people are easier to spot using and trading<br />

drugs—they do so in public, on street corners, and in denselypopulated<br />

city centers where police may easily patrol, observe, and<br />

make arrests. More affluent citizens can conceal illicit activity with<br />

suburban remoteness, rolling lawns, and spacious homes. Poor people<br />

are reliant on appointed, indigent counsel, while affluent citizens can<br />

hire a choice <strong>of</strong> counsel and put up greater roadblocks to prosecution.<br />

The cost and effort <strong>of</strong> pursuing poor people, who are more likely to<br />

use and trade in crack cocaine, versus wealthier people, who might<br />

be more likely to use other drugs, makes the poor a more attractive<br />

target for law enforcement and prosecutors. 85<br />

The response to crack cocaine has thus been the subject <strong>of</strong> numerous<br />

academic critiques. At the center <strong>of</strong> most has been the thesis that<br />

the reaction to crack cocaine, publicly and legislatively, was overreaction<br />

fueled by panic and deeply embedded in volatile patterns <strong>of</strong> race,<br />

class, and gender.<br />

III. METHADEMIC!<br />

Methamphetamine is not a recent drug innovation; the substance<br />

has been around for ninety years and has been the subject <strong>of</strong> varying<br />

amounts <strong>of</strong> media coverage and legislative action for some time. Beginning<br />

in 2004 and 2005, however, legislators, media outlets, and<br />

private citizens began paying increased attention to methampheta-<br />

82. See, e.g., Deleso Alford Washington, “Every Shut Eye, Ain’t Sleep”: Exploring the<br />

Impact <strong>of</strong> Crack Cocaine Sentencing and the Illusion <strong>of</strong> Reproductive Rights for Black<br />

Women from a Critical Race Feminist Perspective, 13 AM. U.J.GENDER SOC. POL’Y &L.<br />

123, 133-36 (2005).<br />

83. See, e.g., Renee Chelian, Remarks on the “CRACK” Program: Coercing Women’s<br />

Reproductive Choices, 5 J.L. SOC’Y. 187, 193-94 (2003) (describing C.R.A.C.K.’s outreach to<br />

various social service providers and agencies and arguing that the program targets poor,<br />

minority women); Sheila C. Cummings, Foreword: Is CRACK the Cure? 5 J. L. SOC’Y 1, 5-6<br />

(2003) (describing the C.R.A.C.K program); Dana Hirschenbaum, Note, When CRACK Is<br />

the Only Choice: The Effect <strong>of</strong> a Negative Right <strong>of</strong> Privacy on Drug-Addicted Women, 15<br />

BERKELEY WOMEN’S L.J. 327, 327-28 (2000) (noting that advertisements for the C.R.A.C.K.<br />

program are, by design, placed primarily in poor urban neighborhoods).<br />

84. William J. Stuntz, Race, Class, and Drugs, 98 COLUM.L.REV. 1795, 1795 (1998).<br />

85. See id.; see also Glasser & Siegel, supra note 67, at 235 (noting that, during the<br />

1980s, large-scale, aggressive drug sweeps focused on poor, minority, urban neighborhoods,<br />

“where drug dealing tended to be open and easy to detect”).


860 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

mine as a social problem, and all fifty states adopted new legislation<br />

related to methamphetamine. It is this period which I refer to as a<br />

“methademic,” 86 a period <strong>of</strong> public and political panic about a perceived,<br />

raging new epidemic <strong>of</strong> drug abuse.<br />

In this Part, I provide an overview <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine’s history<br />

and a synopsis <strong>of</strong> recent legislative responses to this perceived epidemic<br />

<strong>of</strong> methamphetamine addiction. In Subpart A, I briefly explain<br />

the characteristics <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine, media coverage <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine,<br />

and trends in methamphetamine use and abuse. In Subpart<br />

B, I summarize the legislative response to methamphetamine<br />

from 2004 forward—particularly, the enactment <strong>of</strong> prevention-based<br />

laws designed to curtail methamphetamine use and production by<br />

discouraging people from experimenting with the drug and curtailing<br />

the availability <strong>of</strong> the drug’s ingredients.<br />

A. Methamphetamine Use as an “Epidemic”<br />

Methamphetamine, also referred to in its various forms as “ice,”<br />

“crystal,” “crank,” “speed,” and a variety <strong>of</strong> other slang terms, 87 is a<br />

stimulant drug that acts on the central nervous system to produce a<br />

chemical high by stimulating the release <strong>of</strong> dopamine. 88 Depending<br />

on its form, methamphetamine can be snorted, injected, ingested, or<br />

smoked, and the method <strong>of</strong> use affects the rapidity with which the<br />

body processes the drug and the onset <strong>of</strong> the user’s high. 89 Methamphetamine<br />

can be physiologically addictive according to medical definitions<br />

<strong>of</strong> addiction, 90 and repeated usage <strong>of</strong> the drug is associated<br />

with impaired dopamine production and other side effects. 91 Me-<br />

86. References to the purported methamphetamine epidemic as a “methademic” have<br />

been fairly frequent. See, e.g., Jim Lynch, County Combats Growing Meth Crisis: Authorities<br />

in Pierce County, Wash. Say the Easily Made Drug Poses Crime, Health and Environmental<br />

Threats, OREGONIAN, Aug. 20, 2000, at A21.<br />

87. Many articles catalog methamphetamine slang. For one particularly colorful list,<br />

see Douglas Morris, Methamphetamines: Types, Forms, Effects, and the Federal Sentencing<br />

Guidelines, 32 NAT’L ASS’N CRIM. DEF. LAW. CHAMPION MAG., Jan. 2009, at 20 (“Methamphetamine<br />

is known by a plethora <strong>of</strong> nicknames including, inter alia, meth, crank, speed,<br />

chicken feed, crystal, go-fast, shabu, glass, ice, strawberry quick, and methlies quick.”).<br />

88. U.S. DEP’T OF HEALTH &HUM. SERVS., Methamphetamine: Abuse and Addiction,<br />

2006 NAT’L INST. ON DRUG ABUSE RESEARCH REPORT SERIES 3-4.<br />

89. Methamphetamine is produced in two forms—powder and crystal (and is in this<br />

way similar to cocaine). Powdered methamphetamine is generally ingested, injected, or inhaled.<br />

Jane Carlisle Maxwell, Methamphetamine: Epidemiological and Research Implications<br />

for the Legal Field, 82 N.D. L. REV. 1121, 1121-22 (2006). Crystal forms <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

are generally either smoked or heated and inhaled. Id.<br />

90. See, e.g., Anna M. Johnson, A Perspective Regarding Treatment for Methamphetamine<br />

Addiction, 82 N.D. L. REV. 1435, 1435-36 (2006).<br />

91. For a thorough summary <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine’s major effects and side effects, see<br />

Avi Brisman, Meth Chic and the Tyranny <strong>of</strong> the Immediate: Reflections on the Culture-<br />

Drug/Drug-Crime Relationships, 82 N.D. L. REV. 1273, 1275-83 (2006).


2010] METHADEMIC 861<br />

thamphetamine is classified federally as a Schedule II drug, 92 but is<br />

available legally, by prescription, under the trade name Desoxyn or<br />

in generic form. 93<br />

Concern about methamphetamine use and addiction also is not<br />

new. Amphetamines, which are chemically similar to methamphetamine,<br />

94 historically received rounds <strong>of</strong> media and legislative attention.<br />

95 Domestic methamphetamine “home-cooking” probably had its<br />

origin in California in the 1950s, as Korean War veterans may have<br />

imported methamphetamine production methods when they returned<br />

from service. 96 Major media sources covered methamphetamine abuse<br />

by long-haul truckers and motorcycle gangs during the 1970s and<br />

1980s, when articles described the popularity <strong>of</strong> the drug’s use for<br />

maintaining alertness on overnight drives. 97 A smattering <strong>of</strong> news articles<br />

and academic works documented methamphetamine production<br />

and distribution, particularly in the western United <strong>State</strong>s, in the<br />

late 1980s 98 and into the 1990s. 99 In particular, between 1996 and<br />

1999, a handful <strong>of</strong> news articles either predicted that a methamphetamine<br />

“epidemic” was imminent or described such an epidemic as<br />

having already taken root. 100<br />

92. Controlled Substances Act, 21 U.S.C. §§801-971 (2006). Methamphetamine was<br />

added to the Act as a Schedule II drug under in 1971. See Schedules <strong>of</strong> Controlled Substances:<br />

Amphetamine, Methamphetamine and Optical Isomers, 36 FED. REG. 12,734 (July<br />

7, 1971).<br />

93. On the legal uses <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine, see JOHNSON, supra note 10, at 7; U.S.<br />

DEPT. OF HEALTH &HUM.SERVS., supra note 88, at 2.<br />

94. Methamphetamine is a “synthetic” drug that draws its active ingredient from its<br />

“parent drug” amphetamine. It is produced by chemically adding a second methyl-group<br />

molecule to an amphetamine compound. On the chemical relationship between methamphetamine<br />

and amphetamine, see, for example, Brisman, supra note 91, at 1275-77, 1276-<br />

77 n.5.<br />

95. The major academic work on the history <strong>of</strong> American use and regulation <strong>of</strong> amphetamine<br />

is GRINSPOON &HEDBLOM, supra note 17, passim.<br />

96. On the early history <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine production and use, including in particular<br />

its substantial use by military personnel during World War II and the Korean War, see,<br />

for example, DAVID T. COURTWRIGHT, FORCES OF HABIT: DRUGS AND THE MAKING OF THE<br />

MODERN WORLD 76-84 (2001); M. Douglas Anglin et al., History <strong>of</strong> the Methamphetamine<br />

Problem, 32 J. PSYCHOACTIVE DRUGS 137, 137-38 (2000); Brisman, supra note 91, at 1303-04;<br />

see also GRINSPOON &HEDBLOM, supra note 17, at 18-20, 24-25 (discussing amphetamine use<br />

among U.S. soldiers and veterans <strong>of</strong> World War II and the Korean War, albeit without distinguishing<br />

between methamphetamine and other amphetamines).<br />

97. See, e.g., JOHNSON, supra note 10, at 7 (describing use <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine by<br />

long-haul truckers and motorcycle gangs in the 1960, 1970s, and 1980s).<br />

98. See, e.g., Jonathan Beaty, Southern California Tales <strong>of</strong> the Crank, TIME, Apr. 24,<br />

1989, at 10 available at http://www.time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171,957521,00.html<br />

(describing use and manufacture in Southern California); Richard Lacayo, The Menace <strong>of</strong><br />

Ice, TIME, Sept. 18, 1989, at 28 (describing methamphetamine as Hawaii’s number one<br />

drug and noting that methamphetamine was making “serious inroads” in other states and<br />

that “speed kings” were planning “vast expansions in production”).<br />

99. See, e.g., T. Christian Miller, O.C. Meth Lab Bust Points up Boom in Drug, L.A.<br />

TIMES, July 22, 1993, at 1.<br />

100. See, e.g., Charlie Goodyear, Methamphetamine Abuse Called Epidemic, SAN<br />

FRANCISCO CHRON. Apr. 8, 1999, at A15 (describing an existing “epidemic”); Anastasia


862 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

The latest round <strong>of</strong> press articles describing the menace <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

surfaced in 2004 and 2005. 101 In those two years, major<br />

American newspapers and news magazine ran over one hundred<br />

articles discussing and bemoaning the scourge <strong>of</strong> meth. Accounts continued<br />

to portray methamphetamine use as an “epidemic” 102 or a<br />

“siege.” 103 Coverage was quick to emphasize the prevalence <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

in rural areas and to draw connections between methamphetamine<br />

use and rural poverty. 104 (A second strand <strong>of</strong> coverage<br />

that never gained quite as much traction emphasized the use <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

by urban, gay men and expressed concern about the<br />

possibility that meth use among gay men might retrigger the AIDS epidemic.<br />

105 ) Media coverage emphasized a variety <strong>of</strong> problems related to<br />

Toufexis, There Is No Safe Speed: Three Toddlers’ Deaths Spotlight the Nation’s Latest<br />

Drug Epidemic, TIME, Jan. 8, 1996, at 37, available at http://www.time.com/time/<br />

magazine/article/0,9171,983922,00.html (quoting a Drug Enforcement Administration <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />

as describing 1996 methamphetamine use as “absolutely epidemic”); Christopher S. Wren,<br />

Sharp Rise in Use <strong>of</strong> Methamphetamines Generates Concern, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 14, 1996, at A16<br />

(describing a “startling rise” in methamphetamine use in western states); Walter Kirn, Crank,<br />

TIME, June 22, 1998, at 24, available at http://www.time.com/time/magazine/<br />

0,9263,7601980622,00.html (describing methamphetamine use as “a powdery plague on America’s<br />

heartland”).<br />

101. See, e.g., John-Manuel Andriote, Meth Comes out <strong>of</strong> the Closet, WASH. POST, Nov.<br />

8, 2005, at F1, available at http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/<br />

2005/11/04/AR2005110402178.html (describing signs <strong>of</strong> increasing concern about methamphetamine);<br />

Joyce Pellino Crane, Lowell Police Voice Concern on Methamphetamine<br />

Threat, BOSTON GLOBE, Nov. 16, 2005, at A24 (describing police in several Massachusetts<br />

communities as being concerned, based on recent methamphetamine laboratory discoveries,<br />

that methamphetamine, “epidemic” in the Midwest, was establishing a toehold in<br />

Massachusetts); David J. Jefferson et al., America’s Most Dangerous Drug, NEWSWEEK,<br />

Aug. 8, 2005, at 41 (<strong>of</strong>fering hyperbolic account <strong>of</strong> impending crisis); Dirk Johnson, Policing<br />

a Rural Plague, NEWSWEEK, Mar. 8, 2004, at 41 (describing the use <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

as “soaring” and small towns as “[f]eeling under siege”); Paul F. Walsh, Jr., “May You Live<br />

in Interesting Times . . .” , 39 PROSECUTOR, Aug. 2005, at 5, available at http://<br />

www.ndaa.org/ndaa/about/president_message_july_august_2005.html (President <strong>of</strong> National<br />

District Attorneys Association describing methamphetamine as “continu[ing] to roar<br />

eastward across our country leaving destruction, pain and new criminal issues for prosecutors<br />

to contend with”); United <strong>State</strong>s: Instant Pleasure, Instant Ageing; Methamphetamine,<br />

ECONOMIST, June 18, 2005, at 47 (noting that methamphetamine “is in the eyes <strong>of</strong> many,<br />

America’s leading drug problem”).<br />

102. E.g., Crane, supra note 101, at A24.<br />

103. E.g., Johnson, supra note 101, at 41.<br />

104. See, e.g., id. (describing methamphetamine as a “rural plague”); Cameron McWhirter<br />

& Jill Young Miller, Meth Stalks Rural Georgia: Cheap, Easily Manufactured Stimulant Is<br />

Countryside’s Fastest-Growing Drug Problem, and Abuse Can Be Deadly, ATLANTA J. &<br />

CONST., June 6, 2004, at C1 (describing linkage between methamphetamine use and rural<br />

poverty); see also Joh, supra note 10, at 180 (identifying the rural white poor as one <strong>of</strong> the two<br />

groups who the media associated with methamphetamine use during this period).<br />

105. Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Joh treats this strand <strong>of</strong> coverage as on par with the depiction <strong>of</strong><br />

methamphetamine as a drug <strong>of</strong> the rural poor. See Joh, supra note 10, at 181-82; see also<br />

id. at 181 n.32 (collecting media sources from this period depicting purported epidemic <strong>of</strong><br />

meth use among urban, gay men); David J. Jefferson et. al., Party, Play — And Pay,<br />

NEWSWEEK, Feb. 28, 2005, at 38 (describing a “Party and Play” phenomenon in which gay<br />

men use methamphetamine prior to having risky sexual relations, and arguing that<br />

methamphetamine use is associated with HIV transmission rates).


2010] METHADEMIC 863<br />

methamphetamine manufacturing and consumption, paying particular<br />

attention to the explosiveness <strong>of</strong> the ingredients used in manufacturing<br />

the drug, 106 the alleged horrific effects <strong>of</strong> the drug on the oral<br />

health <strong>of</strong> its users, 107 and the many ways in which meth endangered<br />

children. 108 Advertising campaigns against methamphetamine include<br />

warnings <strong>of</strong> the environmental hazards posed to innocent bystanders<br />

when local residents manufacture methamphetamine. 109<br />

Has this coverage reflected a real, recent epidemic <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

use? As was the case with crack cocaine, the media coverage<br />

has not appeared to accurately depict trends in methamphetamine<br />

usage. 110 Methamphetamine use does not appear, by credible<br />

measures, to be on an upswing. 111 Among teenagers, methamphetamine<br />

use has steadily declined over the past five years, and was in<br />

decline during the 2005 uptick in methamphetamine articles. 112<br />

106. See, e.g., Arian Campo-Flores, The Fallout: ‘I Felt My Face Just Melting,’<br />

NEWSWEEK, Aug. 8, 2005, at 44.<br />

107. See, e.g., Paul Harris Crossville, Tragic Orphans <strong>of</strong> U.S. Drugs Epidemic: Crystal<br />

Meth Hits Rural Areas, OBSERVER, Aug. 14, 2005, at 22 (describing “meth mouth”). Whether<br />

the effects <strong>of</strong> “meth mouth” are actually attributable to methamphetamine use quickly<br />

became an object <strong>of</strong> substantial debate. Cf. Jack Shafer, The Meth-Mouth Myth: Our Latest<br />

Moral Panic, SLATE, Aug. 9, 2005, at A.21, http://www.slate.com/id/2124160 (expressing<br />

skepticism).<br />

108. See, e.g., Crossville, supra note 107, at 22.<br />

109. See, e.g., Steve Suo, Nationwide Ad Campaign Takes Aim at Methamphetamine<br />

Abuse, OREGONIAN, Dec. 3, 2005, at C7 (describing a national anti-methamphetamine<br />

televised commercial campaign by the Partnership for a Drug-Free America, including one<br />

dramatization in which a small child is exposed to methamphetamine fumes from a<br />

neighbor’s manufacturing enterprise, and a second dramatization in which a confused nonsmoker<br />

reports coughing symptoms to his medical care provider while a narrator intones<br />

that the man’s new home is a former methamphetamine lab).<br />

110. In contrast with earlier drug panics, some media sources openly doubted—and even<br />

directly critiqued—their competitors’ hyperbolic coverage <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine. In particular,<br />

Slate columnist Jack Shafer has mobilized data to aggressively critique some <strong>of</strong> the more exaggerated<br />

media accounts. See, e.g., Jack Shafer, Meth Madness at Newsweek: This Is Your<br />

Magazine on Drugs, SLATE, Jan. 31, 2007, at 5, http://www.slate.com/id/2123838; Shafer, supra<br />

note 107.<br />

111. A 2006 study suggests that approximately 731,000 Americans were using methamphetamine<br />

in 2006, a number that was roughly unchanged from four years earlier.<br />

See Joh, supra note 10, at 180 n.24. Quest Diagnostics, the largest administrator <strong>of</strong><br />

workplace drug tests in the United <strong>State</strong>s, reported similar overall rates <strong>of</strong> usage, but also<br />

noted a steeper pattern <strong>of</strong> decline. See Quest Diagnostics, USE OF METHAMPHETAMINE<br />

AMONG U.S. WORKERS AND JOB APPLICANTS DROPS 22 PERCENT IN 2007 AND COCAINE USE<br />

SLOWS DRAMATICALLY, in DRUG TESTING INDEX, (2008), available at http://<br />

www.questdiagnostics.com/employersolutions/dti/2008_03/dti_index.html (reporting that<br />

positive test results for methamphetamine peaked at 0.33% in 2004 and declined by between<br />

15 and 36 percent each year between 2004 and 2007). Those rates are substantially<br />

lower than the positive test results for marijuana (2.59%) or cocaine (0.70%). See id. As<br />

happened with crack cocaine, to the extent that methamphetamine use was at any point on<br />

an upswing—Quest reports that positive methamphetamine screens increased by some<br />

73% between 2002 and 2004—by the time media and public attention turned to the drug,<br />

usage, never particularly widespread, was on the decline. Id.<br />

112. According to in-school surveys conducted by the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Michigan’s Monitoring<br />

the Future study and supported by grants from the National Institute on Drug Abuse and the<br />

National Institutes <strong>of</strong> Health, methamphetamine use among teenagers has dropped fairly


864 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

While words like “epidemic” pepper articles about methamphetamine<br />

use, 113 most Americans do not use and have never used methamphetamine,<br />

114 and the 2007 usage figures continue to show decline, suggesting<br />

that most Americans never will. While methamphetamine<br />

use doubtlessly can be devastating, and while usage rates likely have<br />

increased in particular areas or communities, there is not what<br />

steadily since the survey began tracking self-reported methamphetamine use figures in 1999.<br />

In 1999, 4.5% <strong>of</strong> eighth graders, 7.3% <strong>of</strong> tenth graders, and 8.2% <strong>of</strong> twelfth graders reported<br />

having ever used methamphetamine; the 2005 figures were 3.1%, 4.1%, and 4.5% respectively,<br />

and the latest available figures, from 2007, put lifetime usage at 1.8%, 2.8%, and 3.0% respectively.<br />

See L.D. Johnson, et al., Overall, Illicit Drug Use by American Teens Continues<br />

Gradual Decline in 2007, Table 1 http://monitoringthefuture.org/data/<br />

07data.html#2007data-drugs. According to usage figures from 2007, more teenagers have<br />

tried marijuana, inhalants, non-LSD hallucinogens, MDMA (“ecstasy”), cocaine, other amphetamines,<br />

and tranquilizers. See id. Similarly, teens reporting that they have used methamphetamine<br />

at any point within the past year declined (for eighth, tenth, and twelfth graders<br />

respectively) from 3.2%, 4.6%, and 4.7% in 1999, to 1.8%, 2.9%, and 2.5%, respectively, in<br />

2005; the 2007 figures are 1.1, 1.5%, and 1.7%. See id., at Table 2. Self-reported methamphetamine<br />

use within the past thirty days follows the same pattern; in 1999, 1.1% <strong>of</strong> eighth<br />

graders, 1.8% <strong>of</strong> tenth graders, and 1.7% <strong>of</strong> twelfth graders reported such recent use; by 2005,<br />

those percentages had declined to 0.7%, 1.1%, and 0.9%, and they stood at 0.6%, 0.4%, and<br />

0.6% in 2007. See id., at Table 3. These survey results are similar to those produced by the<br />

Youth Risk Behavior Survey (YRBS), a Centers for Disease Control and Prevention survey<br />

that includes self-reported youth engagement in various risky behaviors, including drug use;<br />

according to the YRBS, among 9 th through 12 th graders, the percentage <strong>of</strong> students who reported<br />

that they ever had used methamphetamines showed “no change” between 1999 and<br />

2001 (hovering between 9.1 and 9.8%), and fell to 6.2% by 2005 and 4.4% by 2007. See CTR.<br />

FOR DISEASE CONTROL, TRENDS IN THE PREVALENCE OF MARIJUANA, COCAINE, AND OTHER<br />

ILLEGAL DRUG USE—NATIONAL YRBS: 1991-2007, available at http://<br />

www.cdc.gov/HealthyYouth/yrbs/pdf/us_drug_trend_yrbs.pdf.<br />

113. See supra notes 100-09.<br />

114. As noted above, see supra note 111, the most recent systematic data suggests that<br />

there are less than three-quarters <strong>of</strong> a million current users <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine. According<br />

to 2006 data from the Department <strong>of</strong> Health and Human Services’ Substance Abuse<br />

and Mental Health Services Administration, as <strong>of</strong> 2006, there were approximately 731,000<br />

current methamphetamine users in the United <strong>State</strong>s (about 0.3% <strong>of</strong> the population); about<br />

5.8% <strong>of</strong> Americans reported that they had tried methamphetamine. DEP’T OF HEALTH &<br />

HUMAN SERVS., SUBSTANCE ABUSE & MENTAL HEALTH SERVS. ADMIN., OFFICE OF APPLIED<br />

STUDIES, RESULTS FROM THE 2006 NATIONAL SURVEY ON DRUG USE AND HEALTH:<br />

NATIONAL FINDINGS 18, available at http://www.oas.samhsa.gov/nsduh/2k6nsduh/<br />

2k6Results.pdf. The same survey reports that about 5.2 million Americans were, in 2006,<br />

current recreational users <strong>of</strong> prescription drugs; 2.4 million were current cocaine users;<br />

and 14.8 million were marijuana users. Id. at 16, 18. See also KING, supra note 10, at 4-14<br />

(reviewing several different drug usage studies, including emergency room admissions and<br />

positive drug tests among arrestees, and concluding that methamphetamine is used regularly<br />

by a very small percentage <strong>of</strong> Americans, and that the rate <strong>of</strong> people using methamphetamine<br />

monthly has been stable over the past several years). Despite this data, even<br />

articles in law journals make statements to the effect that methamphetamine “has become<br />

one <strong>of</strong> the most abused drugs in America.” Lauren Grau, Comment, Cutting <strong>of</strong>f the Building<br />

Blocks to Methamphetamine Production: A Global Solution to Methamphetamine<br />

Abuse, 30 HOUS. J.INT’L L. 157, 161 (2007). Methamphetamine use does, however, vary by<br />

location—while positive drug tests among arrestees are fairly constant across jurisdictions,<br />

positive drug tests for methamphetamine specifically vary widely, reflecting provincial differences<br />

in drugs <strong>of</strong> choice. See KING, supra note 10, at 13-14; DEP’T OF HEALTH & HUMAN<br />

SERVS., supra, at 27 (reporting that methamphetamine use was approximately five times<br />

more widespread in the West than in the Northeast).


2010] METHADEMIC 865<br />

would appear to be a large-scale, widespread upswing in methamphetamine<br />

use.<br />

While “epidemic” thus appears an inflation <strong>of</strong> actual usage rates,<br />

the racial depictions <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine users are more accurate:<br />

most methamphetamine users are Caucasian. 115 About half <strong>of</strong> federal<br />

methamphetamine DEA arrests are <strong>of</strong> individuals identified as Caucasian;<br />

the majority <strong>of</strong> non-Caucasian methamphetamine DEA arrestees<br />

are Latino/Hispanic. 116<br />

B. Legislative Responses to Methamphetamine<br />

The central and most pervasive legislative responses to the perceived<br />

methamphetamine epidemic have been to constrain the ability<br />

<strong>of</strong> would-be home manufacturers to obtain necessary production ingredients<br />

and to educate the public against methamphetamine use<br />

and production. Recipes for methamphetamine production are readily<br />

available via print media and the internet 117 and use ingredients and<br />

hardware that historically have been easy to purchase at neighborhood<br />

stores. 118 The most important <strong>of</strong> those ingredients, pseudoephedrine—the<br />

active ingredient in certain kinds <strong>of</strong> cold medications—<br />

has anchored legislative action, as states, followed by Congress, have<br />

sought to limit the ability <strong>of</strong> prospective manufacturers to access necessary<br />

materials as well as to discourage people from becoming new<br />

users or producers <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine.<br />

In fact, the legislative response to methamphetamine in some areas<br />

preceded the perception <strong>of</strong> a regional methamphetamine problem.<br />

When, for example, Massachusetts <strong>State</strong> Senator Harriette L. Chandler,<br />

D-Worcester, introduced legislation seeking to restrict public ac-<br />

115. See, e.g., David E. Smith, Gantt P. Galloway & Richard B. Seymour, Methamphetamine<br />

Abuse, Violence and Appropriate Treatment, 31 VAL. U.L.REV. 661, 667 (1997)<br />

(providing data).<br />

116. See Mark Motivans, U.S. Dep’t <strong>of</strong> Just. Stat., BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS,<br />

BULLETIN: FEDERAL JUSTICE STATISTICS 2005 at 2 (Sept. 2008), available at http://<br />

www.bjs.ojp.usdoj.gov/content/pub/pdf/fjs05.pdf (reporting that <strong>of</strong> 6,461 methamphetamine<br />

arrests conducted by the DEA in 2005, 3,154 <strong>of</strong> the arrestees were white; 2,809 Hispanic/Latino;<br />

173 Asian/Pacific Islander; 143 black/African American; and 61 American Indian/Alaskan<br />

Native).<br />

117. Debra S. Peterson and R. Michael Jennings, Methamphetamine A Recipe for Disaster,<br />

73 J. KAN.B.ASS’N, Oct. 2004, at 7 (noting that bookstores, internet sites, and even court<br />

decisions provide recipes for manufacturing methamphetamine). For a description <strong>of</strong> the methamphetamine<br />

production process in laymen’s language, see id. at 8,44.<br />

118. Methamphetamine is similar in chemical structure to ephedrine and pseudoephedrine,<br />

making it relatively easy to synthesize in home- or vehicle-based “laboratories.” See,<br />

e.g., Samantha S. McKinley & Joseph L. Fink III, “Speed Limits”: <strong>State</strong>s’ Approaches to Regulating<br />

Access to Methamphetamine Chemical Precursors with Statutes and Regulations Limiting<br />

Pseudoephedrine Availability, 82 N.D. L. REV. 1217, 1220-21 (2006). Recipes generally include<br />

cold medication (for the active ingredient, ephedrine or pseudoephedrine), lithium extracted<br />

from lithium batteries, ether, and anhydrous ammonia or iodine (depending on the<br />

methamphetamine form produced), as well as other substances such as paint thinner, freon,<br />

drain cleaner, and lye. Id. at 1221-22.


866 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

cess to pseudoephedrine, she did not argue that this restriction was<br />

necessary to combat current methamphetamine production in the<br />

state; rather, she argued that such restrictions were necessary to avoid<br />

developing a methamphetamine problem in the state. 119 Similarly, the<br />

Partnership for a Drug Free America justified a major new government-backed<br />

public education campaign against methamphetamine<br />

manufacturing, launched in late 2005, as “true prevention” and an attempt<br />

to “deal[] with [the drug] before it’s a crisis.” 120<br />

The focus on education, treatment, and pseudoephedrine restriction<br />

has not been one settled on accidently; legislatures and executives<br />

explicitly and intentionally have privileged methamphetaminereduction<br />

options rather than focusing on criminal sanctions. 121 In<br />

the following Sections, I describe state and federal legislative responses<br />

to the perceived epidemic <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine use and manufacture.<br />

While jurisdictions have in some cases increased criminal<br />

penalties—in particular, where legislatures have believed that “innocent”<br />

nonusers, particularly children, are endangered—by and large,<br />

legislators have focused on preventative rather than incarcerative<br />

strategies, a response we might not have been conditioned to expect<br />

from the literature surrounding legislative reactions to the crack cocaine<br />

“epidemic” in particular.<br />

119. Dan Lamothe, ‘Meth’ Eyed as Latest Menace, REPUBLICAN, Sept. 26, 2005, at A1<br />

(quoting <strong>State</strong> Senator Chandler as saying, “[w]e’re looking to put [pseudoephedrine] behind<br />

the counter because we’re looking to avoid the problem that places like Oregon have<br />

had . . . . Nothing happens across the country that doesn’t eventually happen here”); see also<br />

Brian Scheid, Officials on the Watch for Meth in Bucks, INTELLIGENCER, Oct. 7, 2005, at<br />

3B (quoting Chief <strong>of</strong> County Detectives in Bucks County, Pennsylvania, as saying that methamphetamine<br />

could move into his area, and arguing for proactive action because “[i]t’s<br />

perfectly ripe for this problem to get out <strong>of</strong> hand if we don’t get our hands around it first”);<br />

Jennifer Sinco Kelleher, For Now, Meth’s LI Presence on Fire Island, NEWSDAY, Mar.15,<br />

2004, at A42 (quoting a local Nassau County <strong>of</strong>ficer, commenting on crystal methamphetamine,<br />

as saying: “It’s virtually nonexistent . . . . You keep hearing it’s going to come, but<br />

it hasn’t hit here yet”).<br />

120. Kenneth C. Crowe II, Ad Campaign Targets Meth Lab Dangers: TV Commercials are<br />

Designed to Shock to Mobilize Communities, ALBANY TIMES UNION, Dec. 13, 2005, at B8.<br />

121. For example, when Congress began considering comprehensive antimethamphetamine<br />

legislation in 2006, one <strong>of</strong> the prominent bills included harsh new mandatory<br />

minimum sentences. See Cassidy, supra note 10, at 134. However, after considering<br />

the matter, the House Judiciary Committee voted unanimously to strip them from the bill.<br />

See id.<br />

Some individuals involved in administering the legislative response to methamphetamine<br />

have made similar observations. For example, Anna M. Johnson, Director <strong>of</strong> Operations<br />

at a North Dakota recovery center, notes that “[d]uring North Dakota’s Fifty-Ninth<br />

Legislative Assembly in 2005, senators and representatives from across the state voted to<br />

respond to the methamphetamine epidemic with treatment rather than incarceration.”<br />

Johnson, supra note 90, at 1437. As Johnson notes, the relevant bill passed the North Dakota<br />

Senate by a 47-0 vote and the North Dakota House by an 88-5 vote (88 yeas, 5 nays, 1<br />

absent). See id., at 1437 n.8.


2010] METHADEMIC 867<br />

1. Precursor Regulations<br />

The primary way in which legislatures have responded to a perceived<br />

methamphetamine epidemic has been to make it more difficult<br />

for prospective methamphetamine manufacturers to obtain essential<br />

production ingredients. Many confused persons first encounter this<br />

central form <strong>of</strong> legislative response when attempting to self-medicate<br />

cold and allergy symptoms. Puzzled drug store patrons must request<br />

that Sudafed bottles be liberated from locked cabinets and behindcounter<br />

stashes; provide identification as they might for alcohol purchase;<br />

observe limits on the number <strong>of</strong> capsules they can purchase;<br />

and submit information to the commercial establishment to permit<br />

either the store or law enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficials to track the quantity and<br />

frequency <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine purchases. These changes in commercial<br />

practice comport with restrictions that states pioneered and the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s Patriot Act now essentially requires.<br />

Restrictions on the ability to purchase precursor ingredients for<br />

methamphetamine manufacture are not in themselves new. Western<br />

states began restricting precursor sales in the 1980s, 122 and Congress<br />

passed a half-hearted measure that imposed some restrictions in<br />

1996 in response to the first significant round <strong>of</strong> media stories positing<br />

a coming meth “epidemic.” 123 However, as described below, 124 the<br />

widespread introduction <strong>of</strong> precursor regulations did not occur until<br />

2004 to2005, when legislatures began to respond to the perceived epidemic<br />

<strong>of</strong> drug use described above. 125<br />

Prior to the recent round <strong>of</strong> relatively uniform restrictions, some<br />

prosecutors attempted to utilize then-existing criminal law to convince<br />

merchants to monitor sales <strong>of</strong> items associated with methamphetamine<br />

manufacturing and to avoid selling items where they might be<br />

used to manufacture meth. Merchants were, for example, prosecuted<br />

under general conspiracy laws for selling items such as cold medication,<br />

lighter fluid, matches, and ether in quantities or combinations<br />

that, according to law enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficials, put the merchants on notice<br />

that a customer intended to use the purchased items to manufac-<br />

122. See, e.g., CAL. HEALTH &SAFETY CODE § 11055(f)(1) (West Supp. 1990); IDAHO<br />

CODE ANN. § 37-2707(g)(1) (Supp. 1990); NEV. REV. STAT. § 453.146(2)(h) (Michie Supp.<br />

1989); OR. REV. STAT. §475.940 (1989); UTAH CODE ANN. §§ 58-37c-3(2)(p)-(q), 58-37c-4<br />

(1990); WASH.REV.CODE ANN. § 69.50.206 (g)(1) (West. Supp. 1990).<br />

123. See generally Comprehensive Methamphetamine Control Act <strong>of</strong> 1996, Pub. L. No.<br />

104-237, 110 Stat. 3099 (codified as amended in scattered sections <strong>of</strong> 19, 21, 28, and 42<br />

U.S.C.). As commentators have noted, the 1996 Act was largely ineffective in regulating<br />

precursors as it provided a blanket exception to purchase restrictions for approved overthe-counter<br />

cold medications. See, e.g., Jean C. O’Connor, Jamie F. Chriqui & Duane C.<br />

McBride, Developing Lasting Legal Solutions to the Dual Epidemics <strong>of</strong> Methamphetamine<br />

Production and Use, 82 N.D. L. REV. 1165, 1177 (2006).<br />

124. See infra notes 129-141and accompanying text.<br />

125. See supra Part III.B.


868 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

ture methamphetamine. 126 An individual who purchases or attempts to<br />

purchase such items in combinations and quantities that seem suspicious<br />

may still be detained by law enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficers to investigate<br />

intent to manufacture methamphetamine. 127 Some retailers voluntarily<br />

moved pseudoephedrine products behind their counters prior to any<br />

specific legislation requiring them to do so. 128<br />

The specific set <strong>of</strong> legal changes described in this Section passed<br />

quickly and without organized opposition. Some drug companies resisted<br />

restrictions on purchases and sales by lobbying against legislation,<br />

129 although those lobbying efforts proved unsuccessful. Also,<br />

some pharmaceutical manufacturers have replaced the pseudoephedrine<br />

in some cold medication products with phenylephrine, an active<br />

ingredient that may not be as effective as a decongestant. 130<br />

Within the past few years, virtually all states have passed legislation<br />

that in essence formalizes the assumption that purchasing partic-<br />

126. In one high-pr<strong>of</strong>ile law enforcement effort in Georgia, “Operation Meth Merchant,”<br />

undercover agents went to stores in several counties, told clerks in slang terms that<br />

they planned to “cook” methamphetamine, and purchased combinations <strong>of</strong> products that,<br />

according to prosecutors, should have put merchants on notice that they were selling items<br />

to be pressed into service for methamphetamine manufacture. Defendants were prosecuted<br />

for violating federal statutes that criminalize (i) selling legal but regulated drugs with reason<br />

to believe that the drugs are going to be used to manufacture illegal drugs, see 21<br />

U.S.C. § 841(c)(2) (2006), and (ii) selling materials or products with reason to believe that<br />

they will be used to manufacture illegal drugs, see 21 U.S.C. § 843(a)(7) (2006). See United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s v. Patel, No. 4:05-CR-27-02, slip. op. at 3-4 (N.D. Ga. Aug. 1, 2006), available at<br />

http://www.stopoperationmethmerchant.org/pdf/MotionDeniedOrder.pdf. Civil liberties<br />

groups and others criticized the operation for, as they perceived, targeting stores operated by<br />

South Asian immigrant families with limited English skills and a lack <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> manufacturing<br />

mechanics and methamphetamine lingo, as well as for using an informant who may<br />

have been unreliable, leading to the arrests <strong>of</strong> misidentified suspects. See, e.g., Jay Bookman,<br />

Editorial, Meth Sting Pointed at South Asians, ATLANTA J. CONST., Oct. 13, 2005, at A15 (noting<br />

that forty-three <strong>of</strong> forty-nine convenience store clerks and owners arrested in Operation<br />

Meth Merchant were south Asian immigrants); Jay Bookman, War on Crystal Meth Cooks Up<br />

Many Flimsy Charges, ATLANTA J. CONST., Oct. 10, 2005, at A13 (criticizing operation); Feature:<br />

Federal Meth Precursor Sting Targeting South Asian Convenience Stores Draws Protests,<br />

ACLU Intervention, Jan. 13, 2006, http://stopthedrugwar.org/<br />

chronicle/418/convenience.shtml (last visited Aug. 27, 2010). A federal district judge dismissed<br />

the collected defendant’s claim <strong>of</strong> selective prosecution. See United <strong>State</strong>s v. Patel, No.<br />

4:05-CR-27-02, slip. op. at 3-4 (N.D. Ga. Aug. 1, 2006), available at<br />

http://www.stopoperationmethmerchant.org/pdf/MotionDeniedOrder.pdf.<br />

127. See infra Part III.B.<br />

128. See Jim Puzzanghera, Putting Cold, Flu Drugs Out <strong>of</strong> Reach, SAN JOSE MERCURY<br />

NEWS, Dec. 15, 2005, at 1A (explaining that Walgreens, Target, Wal-Mart, Longs, and<br />

other stores in California put pseudoephedrine-containing products behind the counter in<br />

early 2005, prior to the passage <strong>of</strong> precursor restrictions requiring them to do so).<br />

129. For example, Pfizer, the manufacturer <strong>of</strong> Sudafed, and the Consumer Healthcare<br />

Products Association lobbied unsuccessfully against Oklahoma’s Bill 2176, which requires<br />

pseudoephedrine purchasers to present identification and sign a registry. See Mark Schone,<br />

The Epidemic on Aisle 6, LEGAL AFF., Dec. 2004, available at http://www.legalaffairs.org/<br />

issues/November-December-2004/feature_schone_novdec04.msp. The Consumer Healthcare<br />

Products Association lobbied with similarly unavailing results in several other states. Id.<br />

130. Robert Cohen, Many Cold Meds Aren’t What They Used to Be, MINNEAPOLIS STAR-<br />

TRIB., Nov. 24, 2006.


2010] METHADEMIC 869<br />

ular items denotes an intent to manufacture methamphetamine, and<br />

in general places the burden on stores to prevent customers from purchasing<br />

precursor items. 131 Oklahoma created the “model” for this sort<br />

<strong>of</strong> legislation in 2004, when it passed H.B. 2176. 132 Legislators hope<br />

that by choking <strong>of</strong>f ingredient supply lines, particularly the sizable<br />

quantities <strong>of</strong> ephedrine or pseudoephedrine essential to methamphetamine<br />

manufacture, local mom-and-pop methamphetamine producers<br />

will be forced to shut down—positing that when “[y]ou control pseudoephedrine,<br />

you control the meth.” 133 Restrictions on pseudoephedrine<br />

purchase and possession vary from state to state, 134 and while (as discussed<br />

below) federal law now provides a floor for precursor purchase<br />

restrictions, 135 state laws have the following general characteristics.<br />

First, states limit the amount <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine products a customer<br />

may purchase (without prescription) at any given time or location.<br />

A customer may purchase a specified quantity <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine<br />

products at one store or from several stores within a certain period<br />

<strong>of</strong> time. 136 In order to ensure that customers are not assuming<br />

new identities; returning repeatedly to a store or a series <strong>of</strong> stores in<br />

an attempt to cobble together a number <strong>of</strong> small purchases (a tactic<br />

known as “smurfing” 137 ); or otherwise attempting to circumvent purchase<br />

restrictions, legislation requires stores to demand that customers<br />

produce identification at the time <strong>of</strong> purchase or to sign into a<br />

131. In 2005 alone, thirty-five states passed such laws, generally known as “meth precursor”<br />

restrictions, bringing the total number <strong>of</strong> states with such restrictions well over forty.<br />

See Monica Cain & Cretson Dalmadge, The Effects <strong>of</strong> <strong>State</strong>-Level Methamphetamine<br />

Precursor Restriction on Drug Laboratory Seizures, 8 REV.BUS.RES. 36, 36 (2007) (summarizing<br />

2006 legislation).<br />

132. See Scott Ehlers, <strong>State</strong> Legislative Affairs Update, NAT’L ASS’N CRIM. DEF. LAW.<br />

CHAMPION MAG., Nov. 2005, at 58.<br />

133. Gaylord Shaw, When Meth Hits Home/Oklahoma Trooper’s Routine Check Turns<br />

Fatal, Prompting Focus on a Powerful Drug Gaining Popularity, NEWSDAY, Mar. 15, 2004,<br />

at A6 (quoting an Oklahoma state narcotics bureau <strong>of</strong>ficial in an article that describes multiple<br />

killings that state <strong>of</strong>ficials attribute to methamphetamine).<br />

134. For one fairly complete list <strong>of</strong> state regulations, see DUANE C. MCBRIDE ET AL.,<br />

INSTITUTE FOR PREVENTION OF ADDICTIONS, THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN STATE<br />

METHAMPHETAMINE PRECURSOR LAWS AND TRENDS IN SMALL TOXIC LABS (STL) SEIZURES<br />

60-61 (2008), available at http://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/grants/223467.pdf.<br />

135. See 21 U.S.C. § 830(e)(1)(A)(i) (2006) (imposing restrictions and reporting requirements<br />

on retailers who display and sell products identified as potential methamphetamine<br />

precursors); see also Patricia Stanley, Comment, The Combat Methamphetamine<br />

Epidemic Act: New Protection or New Intrusion?, 39 TEX. TECH L. REV. 379, 404-05 (2007)<br />

(summarizing the relevant federal provisions).<br />

136. For a summary <strong>of</strong> state purchase restrictions that notes some interesting differences<br />

between state laws, see O’Connor et al., supra note 123, at 1182-85; see also Stanley,<br />

supra note 135, at 393-94 (noting variations in state laws, in particular between states that<br />

simply limit the amount that can be purchased during a single transaction and states that<br />

limit the total amount that can be purchased within a given time period).<br />

137. See, e.g., Andrew C. Goetz, Note, One Stop, No Stop, Two Stop, Terry Stop: Reasonable<br />

Suspicion and Pseudoephedrine Purchases by Suspected Methamphetamine Manufacturers,<br />

105 MICH.L.REV. 1573, 1584 (2007) (explaining the term).


870 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

hard-copy or electronic log book so that purchase amounts and patterns<br />

can be tracked. 138<br />

Second, state laws place requirements on retailers who vend<br />

products that contain pseudoephedrine. Jurisdictions mandate that<br />

stores monitor pseudoephedrine products, put pseudoephedrine<br />

products under the control <strong>of</strong> pharmacists, or keep products secured<br />

behind a counter or in a locked case; and report thefts and suspicious<br />

behavior to authorities. 139 In this manner, some law enforcement<br />

functions are placed on retailers, who monitor customers and merchandise<br />

to ensure compliance with the law.<br />

Third, some states have criminalized possession <strong>of</strong> particular<br />

amounts <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine or permitted an inference <strong>of</strong> intent to<br />

manufacture from possession <strong>of</strong> a specified quantity <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine.<br />

140 While it may have always been possible to get a jury instruction<br />

to the effect that intent to manufacture methamphetamine can<br />

be inferred from the possession <strong>of</strong> a certain quantity or combination<br />

<strong>of</strong> precursor materials, this inference has been formalized by states<br />

into a statutory presumption. 141<br />

The efficacy <strong>of</strong> the relatively new precursor restrictions is debatable.<br />

Most law enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficials appear to believe that the restrictions<br />

have reduced the number <strong>of</strong> mom-and-pop methamphetamine<br />

labs, and media sources and police departments have reported fewer<br />

methamphetamine laboratory raids in many areas since restrictions<br />

have been put into place. 142 Reduced numbers <strong>of</strong> laboratories detected<br />

138. See O’Connor et al., supra note 123, at 1184-85 (describing a variety <strong>of</strong> identification<br />

and record-keeping requirements imposed by different states). Since 2006, Oregon has<br />

required a prescription for the purchase <strong>of</strong> products containing pseudoephedrine. See OR.<br />

REV. STAT. §475.950(2) (2008). Oregon Senator Ron Wyden has recently introduced federal<br />

legislation to impose a similar requirement, but the bill has made no significant legislative<br />

progress. See Dan Schiff, Pseudoephedrine Prescription Bill on the Way, OVER THE<br />

COUNTER TODAY (Feb. 24, 2009), available at http://www.overthecountertoday.com/<br />

2009/02/pseudoephedrine-prescription-bill-on-the-way.html (noting that Senator Wyden<br />

has drafted and was planning on introducing such a ban in “the Meth Lab Elimination Act<br />

<strong>of</strong> 2009”).<br />

139. For a summary <strong>of</strong> some such laws, see Stanley, supra note 135, at 395 (discussing<br />

restrictions imposed on retailers in Alabama, Missouri, and Oklahoma).<br />

140. See, e.g., IND. CODE §35-48-4-14.5 (2006) (classifying possession <strong>of</strong> more than ten<br />

grams <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine or ephedrine as a Class D felony); 35 PA. STAT. ANN. §780.113.1<br />

(2004) (criminalizing possession <strong>of</strong> any amount <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine or ephedrine if—but only<br />

if—the state can establish an intent to manufacture or distribute methamphetamine);<br />

S.C. CODE ANN. §44-53-375(E)(1) (2005) (criminalizing the possession <strong>of</strong> more than twelve<br />

grams <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine or ephedrine).<br />

141. See, e.g., MISS. CODE. ANN. § 41-29-313(2)(c)(ii) (2005) (“[P]ossession <strong>of</strong> one or<br />

more products containing more than twenty-four (24) grams <strong>of</strong> ephedrine or pseudoephedrine<br />

shall constitute a rebuttable presumption <strong>of</strong> intent to use the product as a precursor<br />

to methamphetamine or another controlled substance.”); OKLA. STAT. tit. 63, §2-332(B)<br />

(2004) (creating a rebuttable presumption that possession <strong>of</strong> more than nine grams <strong>of</strong><br />

pseudoephedrine evinces an intent to produce methamphetamine).<br />

142. See, e.g., Paul Bird, 3 Stores Cited in Meth Checks, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, Dec. 17,<br />

2005, at 1S (reporting that, as <strong>of</strong> December <strong>of</strong> 2005, state police had responded to 941 calls


2010] METHADEMIC 871<br />

can, however, reflect shifting law enforcement priorities or changing<br />

manufacturing strategies. <strong>Law</strong> enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficers might have other<br />

local crises, such as the contemporaneous uptick in violent crime, 143<br />

that shift their attention away from methamphetamine production;<br />

they might rely on precursor restrictions in part to reduce their need to<br />

actively work to detect methamphetamine laboratories; mom–and-pop<br />

producers might shift locations in order to be less detectable (sites that<br />

are more rural, more pr<strong>of</strong>essional “superlabs,” or mobile such as automobile<br />

trunks). Also, as discussed below, reducing local production<br />

may or may not reduce local methamphetamine use, although it certainly<br />

would reduce the number <strong>of</strong> persons in the United <strong>State</strong>s exposed<br />

to toxic and volatile methamphetamine production chemicals.<br />

<strong>State</strong> precursor restrictions <strong>of</strong> course leave several methods <strong>of</strong><br />

pseudoephedrine procurement open for the enterprising methamphetamine<br />

manufacturer. Not all jurisdictions passed precursor restrictions<br />

in the circa-2004 era, and options such as mail-order companies<br />

were not covered by state precursor statutes. In 2006, Congress<br />

stepped in to close some <strong>of</strong> these loopholes and establish national<br />

standards, adopting the Combat Methamphetamine Epidemic Act as<br />

part and parcel <strong>of</strong> a larger bill expanding and reauthorizing the Patriot<br />

Act. 144 The Methamphetamine Act created nationwide pseudoephedrine<br />

restrictions that largely mirrored the restrictions recently<br />

put into place in most states and restricted the international and<br />

mail-order sale <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine. 145<br />

about methamphetamine labs, compared to 1061 at the same point the year prior, before precursor<br />

restrictions were enacted); Vic Ryckaert, Meth Makers Outside U.S. Help Fill Void,<br />

INDIANAPOLIS STAR, Dec. 15, 2005, at 4A (quoting John P. Walters, Director <strong>of</strong> the White<br />

House Office <strong>of</strong> National Drug Control Policy, as saying that all Midwestern states had seen<br />

declines in home methamphetamine manufacturing since precursor restrictions were<br />

enacted); Michael A. Lindenberger, <strong>Law</strong> May Be Cutting Number <strong>of</strong> Meth Labs, (Louisville)<br />

COURIER-JOURNAL, Nov. 4, 2005, at A1 (<strong>of</strong>ficials in Kentucky credit precursor restrictions<br />

with reducing methamphetamine laboratory seizures). But see Matthew Hathaway, New <strong>Law</strong><br />

Isn’t Reducing Meth Lab Seizures, ST. LOUIS POST-DISPATCH, Dec. 14, 2005, at C5 (Jefferson<br />

County, Missouri drug task force members did not observe a drop in methamphetamine lab<br />

raids in the period following the implementation <strong>of</strong> precursor regulations in Missouri; according<br />

to one <strong>of</strong>ficial: “After the law went into effect, the (meth) cooks were confused for a few<br />

weeks . . . but after that it was back to the same-old, same-old”).<br />

Efforts to study the impact <strong>of</strong> such laws empirically—rather than anecdotally—are<br />

still in their infancy. For some <strong>of</strong> the early efforts in this vein, see, for example, MCBRIDE<br />

ET AL., supra note 134; Cain & Dalmadge, supra note 131.<br />

143. See, e.g., Dan Eggen, Violent Crime, a Sticky Issue for White House, Shows Steeper<br />

Rise, WASH. POST, Sept. 25, 2007, at A7 (noting that, after a long decline, violent crime<br />

rates rose in 2006 and rose more steeply in 2005).<br />

144. Combat Methamphetamine Epidemic Act <strong>of</strong> 2005, Pub. L. No. 109-177, 120 Stat.<br />

192 (2006) (codified as amended in scattered sections <strong>of</strong> 21 U.S.C. and 42 U.S.C.).<br />

145. For the core restrictions adopted by the Act, see 21 U.S.C. § 830(e)(1)(A)(i) (imposing<br />

restrictions and reporting requirements on retailers who display and sell products<br />

identified as potential methamphetamine precursors and on the mail order purchase <strong>of</strong><br />

such products). For an effective summary <strong>of</strong> the new federal provisions, see Stanley, supra<br />

note 135, at 404-05. Congress expressly indicated that the new federal restrictions were


872 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

2. Methamphetamine Registries<br />

Some states have created methamphetamine registries, similar to<br />

sex <strong>of</strong>fender registries, to permit private citizens to track persons convicted<br />

<strong>of</strong> methamphetamine <strong>of</strong>fenses. Tennessee pioneered the methamphetamine<br />

registry in 2005, providing public access to a web site<br />

that <strong>of</strong>fers the names, dates <strong>of</strong> birth, <strong>of</strong>fense category, and date <strong>of</strong> conviction<br />

for persons convicted <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine manufacturing <strong>of</strong>fenses.<br />

146 Legislatures passed bills creating similar registries in several<br />

other states. 147 These registries in general are less user-friendly and<br />

provide far less personal information than do sex <strong>of</strong>fender registries. 148<br />

Registries are not costless—they require administration and updates—<br />

but they are not as costly as continued incarceration.<br />

meant only as a floor and were not meant to preempt more stringent state restrictions. See<br />

Combat Methamphetamine Epidemic Act §711(g), 120 Stat. at 263 (codified at 21 U.S.C.<br />

§802 note).<br />

146. See Tennessee Meth Offender Database, http://www.tennesseeanytime.org/methorapp/search.jsp<br />

(last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

147. See, e.g., Illinois Methamphetamine Manufacture Registry, http://www.isp.state.il.us/<br />

meth/ (last visited Aug. 27, 2010); Minnesota Methamphetamine Offender Registry,<br />

https://mor.state.mn.us/OffenderSearch.aspx (last visited Aug. 27, 2010); Sexual or Violent Offender<br />

Registry, MT Dep’t <strong>of</strong> Justice, http://www.doj.mt.gov/svor/ (last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

148. National guidelines for sex <strong>of</strong>fender registries provide minimum standards for<br />

state sex <strong>of</strong>fender registries. According to these minimum standards, states should post to<br />

websites fairly comprehensive information about sex <strong>of</strong>fenders—their names, addresses,<br />

vehicle descriptions and license plate numbers, physical descriptions and current photographs<br />

<strong>of</strong> registered persons, and the sex <strong>of</strong>fenses for which the person has been convicted.<br />

DEP’T OF JUST., THE NATIONAL GUIDELINES FOR SEX OFFENDER REGISTRATION AND<br />

NOTIFICATION 33-34 (2008).<br />

When Oklahoma’s state legislature considered legislation to create a registry, Speaker<br />

Todd Hiett, who introduced the bill, argued that “Oklahomans have the right to know if<br />

a meth lab could be in their own neighborhood or community,” while Representative John<br />

Nance, who carried the bill, <strong>of</strong>fered that the registry would “be a useful tool to families as<br />

they look to buy a home. You need to be able to check out all aspects <strong>of</strong> that home’s history,<br />

including whether there has been a meth lab close by.” Press Release, Speaker <strong>of</strong> the Oklahoma<br />

House <strong>of</strong> Representatives Todd Hiett (Mar. 1, 2006), available at http:<br />

/www.okhouse.gov/OkhouseMedia/pressroom.aspx?NewsID=512. The focus was on protecting<br />

property values and avoiding nuisances, not on stigmatizing <strong>of</strong>fenders. Even still, Oklahoma<br />

never adopted a registry, and most <strong>of</strong> the established registries have been even less<br />

useful. See infra notes 149-150.<br />

The Illinois registry requires a last name to be submitted in order to search for a<br />

convicted person; unlike sex <strong>of</strong>fender registries, a private citizen accessing the registry<br />

cannot, for example, generate a neighborhood map showing where persons convicted <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

<strong>of</strong>fenses reside. The publicly-accessed record provides the convicted person’s<br />

full name, date <strong>of</strong> birth, and <strong>of</strong>fense <strong>of</strong> conviction; no photograph or address may be<br />

publicly accessed. See Illinois Methamphetamine Registry, supra note 147. In contrast, the<br />

Illinois sex <strong>of</strong>fender registry, available at http://www.isp.state.il.us/sor/, permits the general<br />

public to access lists <strong>of</strong> sex <strong>of</strong>fenders by city and zip code; to, in addition to viewing dates<br />

<strong>of</strong> birth and <strong>of</strong>fenses <strong>of</strong> conviction, access maps <strong>of</strong> sex <strong>of</strong>fender residence locations; and to<br />

view photographs, full physical descriptions, specific <strong>of</strong>fense details, and complete addresses<br />

<strong>of</strong> registered sex <strong>of</strong>fenders. Other states with methamphetamine registries similarly<br />

provide less information and less ease <strong>of</strong> access than <strong>of</strong>fered through sex <strong>of</strong>fender registries.<br />

Compare Tennessee’s methamphetamine registry, supra note 146, which permits<br />

citizens to search for persons convicted <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine manufacturing <strong>of</strong>fenses by<br />

county or by last name with a first initial, and provides the name, birth date, <strong>of</strong>fense title,


2010] METHADEMIC 873<br />

This methamphetamine registration trend never took root in most<br />

states, however. While a handful <strong>of</strong> states ultimately passed legislation<br />

creating registries, most states never formally considered methamphetamine<br />

registries as a strategy for reducing methamphetamine production,<br />

and not all jurisdictions that have considered methamphetamine<br />

registries actually created them. 149 In 2006, for example, Georgia, Oklahoma,<br />

West Virginia, and Washington <strong>State</strong> all considered legislation to<br />

create registries but ultimately declined to do so. 150<br />

The story <strong>of</strong> state legislative dalliance with methamphetamine registries<br />

is a telling allegory. Legislators looking for ways to crack<br />

down on methamphetamine floated proposals modeled on earlier gettough-on-crime<br />

strategies. Their bills were quickly reshaped to be<br />

less punitive and more public health oriented than the earlier legislation.<br />

Even then, when the costs <strong>of</strong> the programs became apparent<br />

and were weighed against their limited benefits, most such proposals<br />

quietly died on the vine.<br />

3. Property Regulations<br />

The methamphetamine-producing methods described above carry,<br />

in addition to immediate risks to producers, 151 longer-term problems<br />

<strong>of</strong> contamination and waste. 152 Methamphetamine manufacture gen-<br />

and date <strong>of</strong> conviction, with Tennessee’s sex <strong>of</strong>fender registry, available at<br />

http://www.ticic.state.tn.us/sorinternet/sosearch.aspx, which also permits searches by last<br />

name, city, and zip code, and which provides a photograph, address, and registration status<br />

information for listed persons. Minnesota’s methamphetamine registry permits searches by<br />

last name or by county. See Minnesota Methamphetamine Registry, supra note 147. Registry<br />

records include the convicted person’s full name, date <strong>of</strong> birth, and registry-triggering<br />

<strong>of</strong>fense, and provide a link to the person’s publicly accessible criminal history, if desired.<br />

The registry does not provide a photo, address, or further physical or biographical description.<br />

In contrast, the state’s sex <strong>of</strong>fender registry permits searches by county, city, zip code,<br />

or name, and provides a photograph, physical description, address, and specific <strong>of</strong>fense details<br />

for the registrant.<br />

149. For examples <strong>of</strong> bills introduced with great fanfare that were never adopted, see Ga.<br />

H. B. 793, (2006), available at http://www.legis.state.ga.us/legis/2007_08/fulltext/hb793.htm.;<br />

Okla. H. B. 3121, (2008), available at http://webserver1.lsb.state.ok.us/2007-08bills/HB/<br />

HB3121_hflr.rtf; W. Va. H. B. 4525, (2006), available at http://www.legis.state.wv.us/<br />

bill_status/bills_text.cfm?billdoc=hb4525%20intr.htm&yr=2010&sesstype=RS&i=4525.<br />

150. For national coverage <strong>of</strong> Georgia’s then-pending legislation, see Kari Huus, Click<br />

Here for Drug Offenders: Internet Listings Have Popular Appeal, But do they Really Protect<br />

the Public? , MSNBC, (Dec. 7, 2006), http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/15971396/. Press<br />

coverage throughout 2006 identified Oklahoma, Washington, and West Virginia, as other<br />

states considering the adoption <strong>of</strong> a registry. See, e.g., id. As <strong>of</strong> August 2008, none <strong>of</strong> those<br />

states had adopted a meth registry. See Jeff Lambert, Tennessee’s Meth Offender Registry<br />

Copied and Reviled, TIMES-NEWS, Aug. 24, 2008, http://www.timesnews.net/<br />

article.php?id=9007847 (reporting that only Tennessee, Illinois, Minnesota, Montana, and<br />

Kansas had established methamphetamine registries).<br />

151. For reports <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine laboratory explosions, see for example, Man Injured<br />

in Arnold Meth Lab Explosion, ST. LOUIS POST-DISPATCH, July 4, 2008; Deputies<br />

Blame Explosion on Meth Lab, ORLANDO SENTINEL, Sept. 19, 2006, at G2.<br />

152. See, e.g., McKinley & Fink, supra note 118, at 1223 (describing the environmental<br />

concerns arising from methamphetamine manufacture). News coverage <strong>of</strong> methampheta-


874 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

erates hazardous byproducts, including chemicals that do not easily<br />

degrade. Those chemicals can contaminate the property where the<br />

methamphetamine was produced, groundwater and soil in surrounding<br />

areas, and any other property or water supply where byproducts<br />

are dumped. Future property occupants face contamination hazards<br />

and possible health complications from exposure to toxins. These<br />

problems are neither new nor newly identified. 153<br />

These concerns about the environmental consequences <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

have spurred diverse policy responses and proposals.<br />

The Combat Methamphetamine Epidemic Act requires the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s Transportation Department and the Environmental Protection<br />

Agency to begin tracking and reporting on some chemicals that<br />

are byproducts <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine production. 154 Some states have<br />

adopted legislation putting notice and cleanup burdens on people<br />

seeking to transfer property, to ensure that unwary purchasers are<br />

not exposed to toxins. 155 Some state and federal programs <strong>of</strong>fer to pay<br />

some or all <strong>of</strong> the costs <strong>of</strong> cleaning up the toxic byproducts <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

when they are found on the property <strong>of</strong> innocent individuals.<br />

156 Advertising campaigns against methamphetamine have<br />

prominently incorporated warnings about the environmental hazards<br />

posed to innocent bystanders when local residents manufacture methamphetamine.<br />

157 Some commentators have advocated the aggres-<br />

mine production has routinely made reference to the environmental hazards posed by<br />

home methamphetamine laboratories. See, e.g., Hal Marcovitz, Congressmen Call for Limits<br />

on Sales <strong>of</strong> Cold Medication; Bill Aimed at Stopping Crystal Meth Operators, Two Tell<br />

Bucks County, THE MORNING CALL (Allentown, Pa.) , Oct. 7, 2005, at B1 (describing how<br />

methamphetamine lab operators dump hazardous waste into woods and streams). For recent<br />

academic discussion <strong>of</strong> environmental issues raised by methamphetamine production,<br />

see O’Connor et al., supra note 123, at 1172-73, 1187. See generally Smith, Cooking Up Solutions,<br />

supra note 10; Cheri-Lynn Wortham, Comment, Methamphetamine and Cocaine<br />

Manufacturing Effects on the Environment and Agriculture, 17 SAN JOAQUIN AGRIC. L.<br />

REV. 343 (2008).<br />

153. Several student notes on the environmental problems associated with<br />

methamphetamine labs appeared prior to the recent flurry <strong>of</strong> news articles about<br />

methamphetamine. See, e.g., Tamara B. Maher, Note, Legal Liabilities Faced by Owners <strong>of</strong><br />

Property Contaminated by Clandestine Methamphetamine Laboratories: The Oregon<br />

Approach, 27 WILLAMETTE L. REV. 325 (1991); Anna S. Vogt, Comment, The Mess Left<br />

Behind: Regulating the Cleanup <strong>of</strong> Former Methamphetamine Laboratories, 38 IDAHO L.<br />

REV. 251 (2001). <strong>State</strong>s had also previously enacted statutes for the purpose <strong>of</strong> addressing<br />

environmental hazards associated specifically with methamphetamine production. See,<br />

e.g., OR. REV. STAT. § 453.855 (2007); WASH. REV. CODE § 64.44.005 (2009). These statutes<br />

include provisions that require property owners to warn potential purchasers about<br />

contamination. See, e.g.., OR. REV. STAT. § 105.464(I)(8)(F)&(H)(2007); WASH REV. CODE §<br />

64.06.020 (2009).<br />

154. See Jeff Wyble, Methamphetamine—The New Epidemic, 11 MICH.ST.U.J.MED.&<br />

L. 115, 140 (2007) (collecting and describing scattered provisions <strong>of</strong> the Act that impose<br />

new environmental reporting requirements).<br />

155. See O’Connor et al., supra note 123, at 1187 (describing adoption <strong>of</strong> such reforms<br />

in Colorado and South Dakota).<br />

156. See Wortham, supra note 152, at 349-53 (describing some such programs).<br />

157. See, e.g., Suo, supra note 109, at C7.


2010] METHADEMIC 875<br />

sive use <strong>of</strong> nuisance and zoning laws to regulate, eliminate, and sanction<br />

methamphetamine laboratories. 158<br />

4. Child-Protective Measures<br />

Legislative responses to methamphetamine have <strong>of</strong>ten focused—<br />

both rhetorically and substantively—on the dangers that the manufacture<br />

and use <strong>of</strong> the drug pose to children. 159 Many such efforts<br />

have been educative or ameliorative. For example, the Combat Methamphetamine<br />

Epidemic Act included a twenty million dollar grant<br />

program to assist states in establishing programs to assist children<br />

exposed to methamphetamine. 160 Sponsors <strong>of</strong> a similar House provision<br />

emphasized the children’s innocence; as Representative Zach<br />

Wamp stated, “Through no fault <strong>of</strong> their own these children have<br />

been placed in an unconscionable position because their parents or<br />

guardians surrendered their wills to an incredibly addictive drug,”<br />

describing affected children as “orphans <strong>of</strong> the despicable meth<br />

trade.” 161 Public education campaigns have, likewise, focused on dangers<br />

to children. 162<br />

As might be expected when children are involved, initiatives in<br />

this area have also, at times, been punitive. While it is possible that<br />

a variety <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine <strong>of</strong>fenses might expose a parent or<br />

guardian to traditional child neglect or abuse charges, many states<br />

have enacted specific “child abuse by methamphetamine” statues<br />

that make it an <strong>of</strong>fense to expose a child or other helpless dependant<br />

to the production <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine or have passed sentence enhancement<br />

provisions that increase the punishment <strong>of</strong> those convicted<br />

<strong>of</strong> methamphetamine manufacturing if children are present<br />

during the manufacturing <strong>of</strong> the drug. 163 These statutes seek to limit<br />

the extent to which “innocents” in custodial care are exposed to toxic<br />

chemicals and possible explosions and fires through punishing parents<br />

and caregivers who facilitate that exposure.<br />

158. See, e.g., Smith, America’s Methamphetamine Crisis, supra note 10, at 624-34 (advocating<br />

aggressive use <strong>of</strong> nuisance laws).<br />

159. Expressions <strong>of</strong> particular concern for children “victimized” by methamphetamine<br />

are a familiar trope in the academic literature, see, e.g., Smith, America’s Methamphetamine<br />

Crisis, supra note 10, at 609 (describing children as one <strong>of</strong> “two classes <strong>of</strong> individuals”<br />

who “most consistently suffer from the harms <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine production”); in media<br />

coverage, see, e.g., Joh, supra note 10, at 183 (reviewing media coverage <strong>of</strong> the so-called<br />

meth “epidemic” and concluding that “the methamphetamine addict was construed as an<br />

immoral or amoral monster, whose addiction wreaked havoc upon children”); and in government<br />

reports, see, e.g., KAREN SWETLOW, U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, CHILDREN AT<br />

CLANDESTINE METHAMPHETAMINE LABS:HELPING METH’S YOUNGEST VICTIMS (2003).<br />

160. Combat Methamphetamine Epidemic Act <strong>of</strong> 2005, Pub. L. No. 109-177, § 755; see<br />

also Wyble, supra note 153, at 141 (explaining the intended uses <strong>of</strong> this grant money).<br />

161. Press Release, Rep. Jim Cooper, Meth-Endangered Children to Benefit from New<br />

Grant Program, U.S. FED.NEWS, Dec. 14, 2005, available at 2005 WLNR 20389395.<br />

162. See, e.g., Suo, supra note 109, at C7 (describing one such commercial).<br />

163. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> these developments, see infra Part III.B.


876 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

5. Methamphetamine Prisons<br />

During the round <strong>of</strong> concern about crack-cocaine <strong>of</strong>fenses, many<br />

people were sent to prison; the prisons were general prisons with a<br />

variety <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>fender types that may or may not have had specific substance<br />

abuse treatment or other rehabilitative programs available.<br />

In contrast, in response to methamphetamine, Montana and Illinois<br />

have created prisons specifically designed to house persons who<br />

have been convicted <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>fenses and are addicted to methamphetamine,<br />

164 while several other states have set up special units within<br />

other prisons dedicated to meth-addicted prisoners. 165 While obviously<br />

incarcerative, these prisons reflect a more nuanced—and more<br />

ambivalent—response to the problems raised by substance abuse.<br />

Certainly, prisons specially dedicated to the rehabilitative needs <strong>of</strong> a<br />

specific class <strong>of</strong> substance abusers were not part <strong>of</strong> prior legislative<br />

and executive responses to perceived drug epidemics.<br />

6. Drug Treatment Courts<br />

In confronting the problems posed by methamphetamine, states<br />

have increasingly utilized specialized drug courts to deal with a significant<br />

segment <strong>of</strong> those charged with violating criminal drug statutes.<br />

Many states have made drug courts a centerpiece <strong>of</strong> their antimethamphetamine<br />

efforts. 166 For example, Montana—a state that<br />

considers itself one <strong>of</strong> the hardest-hit regions <strong>of</strong> the country in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> its methamphetamine problem—has established family drug court<br />

programs in several jurisdictions, serving both adults and juveniles.<br />

167 The federal government has also endorsed the strategy, making<br />

over $70 million available annually to states to implement and<br />

maintain such courts. 168<br />

164. See Catharine Skipp & Arian Campo-Flores, Addiction: A “Meth Prison” Movement,<br />

NEWSWEEK, Apr. 24, 2006 (describing the new prisons in those states).<br />

165. See id. (describing experiences in other states, notably Indiana); see also NORTH<br />

DAKOTA LEGISLATIVE COUNCIL, METH PRISONS IN OTHER STATES (2006) (document prepared<br />

for North Dakota Assembly Budget Committee on Government Services), available<br />

at http://www.legis.nd.gov/assembly/59-2005/docs/pdf/79288.pdf (evaluating success <strong>of</strong><br />

“meth prisons” in Illinois, Indiana, and Montana in response to proposal for similar prison<br />

in North Dakota).<br />

166. See, e.g., C. WEST HUDDLESTON, III, U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, DRUG COURTS: AN<br />

EFFECTIVE STRATEGY FOR COMMUNITIES FACING METHAMPHETAMINE (2005), available at<br />

http://www.ojp.usdoj.gov/BJA/pdf/MethDrugCourts.pdf (discussing successful drug court<br />

programs in California, Utah, and Washington <strong>State</strong>); Melody Finnemore, Juggling Act:<br />

Rapidly Changing Judiciary Requires Judges to Take on More Complex Roles, 66 OR. ST.B<br />

BUL., Dec. 2005, at 17, 17 (discussing use <strong>of</strong> drug courts to combat methamphetamine in<br />

Oregon and crucial role <strong>of</strong> judges in such courts); Ed Kemmick, Drug Treatment Court: A<br />

Glimmer <strong>of</strong> Hope in the Fight Against Meth, BILLINGS GAZETTE, Aug. 24, 2005 (discussing<br />

Montana’s commitment to utilizing drug courts to combat its meth problem).<br />

167. See Kemmick, supra note 166 (describing program).<br />

168. Combat Methamphetamine Epidemic Act <strong>of</strong> 2005, Pub. L. No. 109-177, §§ 751-54<br />

(2006). The federal commitment to drug courts was not unconditional; in order to obtain


2010] METHADEMIC 877<br />

Drug courts generally provide alternatives to incarceration for participating<br />

defendants. 169 Defendants whose <strong>of</strong>fenses are considered<br />

linked to drug addiction—whether or not the <strong>of</strong>fense charged is a drug<br />

<strong>of</strong>fense—may be identified by judges, service personnel, prosecutors, or<br />

defense attorneys as persons who would benefit from substance abuse<br />

treatment, and who should avoid incarceration and/or conviction if<br />

they successfully complete treatment. These programs usually follow<br />

one <strong>of</strong> two formats: either the defendant enters the alternative program<br />

after arrest, but prior to conviction, 170 or, alternatively, the defendant<br />

may plead guilty and have an incarcerative sentence suspended<br />

pending completion <strong>of</strong> the drug court program. 171 Completion <strong>of</strong><br />

the program might lead to no conviction, the dismissal <strong>of</strong> a conviction,<br />

or a conviction that does not lead to a jail or prison sentence. 172<br />

Drug courts usually require the participant to complete drug<br />

abuse treatment, maintain employment or student status, be closely<br />

supervised by program personnel, and receive other services, such as<br />

family or mental health services, that the court might consider necessary.<br />

173 While drug courts are superficially similar to probation in<br />

that defendants are supervised and a failure to comply with the program’s<br />

terms may lead to consequences for the defendant, the level <strong>of</strong><br />

supervision provided to defendants is generally more intensive (defendants<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten appear in front <strong>of</strong> judges for status reports, and may<br />

attend several meetings with treatment providers and other rehabi-<br />

these funds states were required to design their drug courts to include mandatory drug<br />

testing and to impose graduated sanctions for failures to pass such test. See id. at §753; cf.<br />

HUDDLESTON, supra note 166 (mentioning a federal report encouraging states to adopt<br />

drug courts).<br />

169. On drug courts generally, see Eric J. Miller, Drugs, Courts, and the New Penology,<br />

20 STAN. L.&POL’Y REV.417, 417-25 (2009) (summarizing history, theory, and functions <strong>of</strong><br />

modern drug courts).<br />

170. See, e.g., California Courts, Drug Court, http://www.courtinfo.ca.gov/programs/<br />

collab/drug.htm (last visited Aug. 27, 2010) (“A preplea diversion program allows criminal<br />

proceedings to be suspended while the defendant participates in a program involving counseling,<br />

drug testing, education, or other requirements. If the defendant successfully completes<br />

the program, the criminal charges are dismissed.”). In some such systems, defendants<br />

may be required to sign confessions before entering the drug court program, so that,<br />

should they not successfully complete the program, the prosecutor’s burden <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> at trial<br />

will be easy to meet.<br />

171. See, e.g., Felony Drug Court: <strong>State</strong>ment from Judge Thomas A. Teodosio, http://<br />

www.summitcpcourt.net/fdc.html (last visited Aug. 27, 2010) (noting that the drug courts<br />

in Summit County, Ohio “will be based upon a post-adjudication model”).<br />

172. For comparison <strong>of</strong> the different consequences <strong>of</strong> completing and failing to complete<br />

different kinds <strong>of</strong> drug court programs, see, for example, JAMES L. NOLAN, REINVENTING<br />

JUSTICE: THE AMERICAN DRUG COURT MOVEMENT 41 (2001); Hon. Peggy Fulton Hora &<br />

Theodore Stalcup, Drug Treatment Courts in the Twenty-First Century: The Evolution <strong>of</strong><br />

the Revolution in Problem-Solving Courts, 42 GA.L.REV. 717, 725-26, 750 (2008).<br />

173. See generally, e.g., Hora & Stalcup, supra note 172, at 725-27 (describing normal<br />

operation <strong>of</strong> drug courts).


878 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

litative personnel each week), and intermittent noncompliance, such<br />

as an isolated positive drug test, generally is tolerated. 174<br />

To some extent, the willingness <strong>of</strong> states to experiment with drug<br />

courts as a mechanism for dealing with methamphetamine users<br />

(and the federal government’s encouragement <strong>of</strong> this experimentation)<br />

may reflect a judgment that methamphetamine use presents a<br />

different set <strong>of</strong> problems—or attracts a different set <strong>of</strong> users—than<br />

other illegal drugs. 175 However, drug treatment courts have existed<br />

for two decades now and have generally become more popular over<br />

the last few years. 176 To the extent that methamphetamine users<br />

charged with criminal <strong>of</strong>fenses are being diverted into specialized<br />

drug treatment courts, it is unclear whether they are benefiting from<br />

a special solicitude for meth users or from a general national trend. 177<br />

7. Educational Programs<br />

Both state and federal drug education programs, as well as campaigns<br />

funded by nonpr<strong>of</strong>it organizations, have created specific antimethamphetamine<br />

resources, including television and print advertisements<br />

as well as school-based workshops. 178 The educational<br />

campaigns have varied in tone and focus; some show innocent children<br />

exposed to methamphetamine production by parents or neighbors;<br />

some show ravaged producers frantically cooking methamphetamine;<br />

most focus on the potentially debilitating physical and<br />

oral health consequences <strong>of</strong> repeated methamphetamine use. 179 One<br />

174. See id.<br />

175. The question <strong>of</strong> whether our ambivalent policy response to methamphetamine reflects<br />

factors unique to methamphetamine or signals a more general s<strong>of</strong>tening <strong>of</strong> American<br />

drug policy is treated extensively infra Part V.<br />

176. See Miller, supra note 169, at 420 (noting creation <strong>of</strong> first modern drug court in<br />

1989); id. at 417 (“Perhaps the most important judicial response to the War on Drugs has<br />

been the creation <strong>of</strong> specialty ‘drug courts’ designed to ameliorate the impact <strong>of</strong> drug sentencing<br />

policy on individual drug users.”). One incomplete list <strong>of</strong> drug court programs lists<br />

programs in 43 states. See National Center for <strong>State</strong> Courts, Specialty Courts: Drug<br />

Courts: Drug Courts, Drug Indicators, and Drug Court Programs: <strong>State</strong> Links, http://<br />

www.ncsconline.org/wc/CourTopics/<strong>State</strong>Links.asp?id=24&topic=DrugCt (last visited Aug.<br />

27, 2010).<br />

177. Moreover, there are reasons to question whether diversion into a specialized drug<br />

court program is an unmitigated benefit for a criminal defendant. I explore these issues in<br />

a work in progress entitled “Thinking Outside the Cell: Criminal Justice Policy in a Post-<br />

Mass Incarceration World.” See also Miller, supra note 169 (criticizing aspects <strong>of</strong> contemporary<br />

drug courts as well).<br />

178. One <strong>of</strong> the most aggressive state-level programs has been the Montana Meth<br />

Project. For coverage <strong>of</strong> the Project and its advertising campaign, see, for example, Thomas<br />

W. Seibel & Steven A. Mange, The Montana Meth Project: “Unselling” a Dangerous Drug,<br />

20 STAN. L.&POL’Y REV. 405 (2009); Kate Zernike, With Scenes <strong>of</strong> Blood and Pain, Ads<br />

Battle Methamphetamine in Montana, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 26, 2006. The Project’s website,<br />

which includes many <strong>of</strong> the pictures and other material it uses to attempt to influence<br />

teens not to try meth, is available at http://www.montanameth.org/.<br />

179. See, e.g., Joh, supra note 10, at 182; Suo, supra note 109, at C7; Zernike, supra<br />

note 178. For one media expert’s compilation <strong>of</strong> the forty most effective anti-meth ads (in-


2010] METHADEMIC 879<br />

common tactic <strong>of</strong> such campaigns is to <strong>of</strong>fer “before” and “after” photographs<br />

<strong>of</strong> meth users. 180<br />

Other advertisements specifically target people already using methamphetamine.<br />

Here, the language and the imagery are less catastrophic;<br />

the pathos is laced with hope. In September <strong>of</strong> 2008, for example,<br />

the Office <strong>of</strong> National Drug Control Policy submitted an advertisement<br />

entitled “Rebuild After Meth.” Under a photograph <strong>of</strong> a<br />

smiling woman and child, the advertisement trumpets rising treatment<br />

and falling usage numbers and focuses on a story to be associated<br />

with the photograph:<br />

Consider Teresa. She is a mother, Girl Scout volunteer, and website<br />

developer. Her life took a sharp turn when she started using meth to<br />

lose weight. Her story went from bad to worse as she abandoned her<br />

family, including her 4-year-old daughter, for nearly a year in the<br />

search for her next high. She eventually entered a treatment program<br />

and made a commitment to conquer her addiction. Today, she<br />

is drug-free and a leader in anti-meth efforts in her community.<br />

There are thousands <strong>of</strong> people like Teresa out there, showing individuals<br />

and communities what they need to know. 181<br />

IV. MAKE NEW DRUG LAWS, BUT KEEP THE OLD<br />

Missing among these various legislative responses to methamphetamine<br />

is a dramatic increase in penalties for possession, manufacture,<br />

trafficking, and sale. Some legislatures have indeed increased<br />

penalties for various methamphetamine <strong>of</strong>fenses in the same<br />

way that we saw penalties increase for crack cocaine in the late<br />

1980s, 182 but, as discussed above, most legislatures have focused<br />

more on prevention, education, and treatment than on increased incarceration.<br />

183 Nevertheless, there are some familiar themes in the<br />

response to methamphetamine by legislatures, courts, and law enforcement<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials. In particular, courts have used methampheta-<br />

cluding both still images and videos), see 40+ Most Powerful Anti-Meth Advertisements,<br />

http://elitebydesign.com/anti-meth-ads/ (last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

180. The source for most such photographs is the “Faces <strong>of</strong> Meth” program administered<br />

by the Multnomah (Portland), Oregon County Sheriff’s Department. The photographs,<br />

which originally gained prominence as accompaniments to the hyperbolic methamphetamine<br />

stories THE OREGONIAN ran in 2004 and 2005, are most easily accessed through<br />

the Partnership for a Drug Free America’s website at http://www.drugfree.org/<br />

Portal/DrugIssue/MethResources/faces/index.html (last visited Aug. 27, 2010); see also Lisa<br />

Demer, Meth Ills Expand in Alaska, ANCHORAGE DAILY NEWS, Sept. 7, 2005 (noting that<br />

the United <strong>State</strong>s Attorney’s <strong>of</strong>fice in Alaska distributes before-and-after photos <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

users from the same series).<br />

181. OFFICE OF NAT’L DRUG CONTROL POL’Y,REBUILD AFTER METH (undated), available<br />

at http://www.theantidrug.com/openletter/Meth-Rebuild.pdf.<br />

182. See, e.g., Act <strong>of</strong> May 21, 2004, ch. 845, §§2-3, 2004 Tenn. Pub. Acts 1922, 1923 (codified<br />

at TENN. CODE. ANN. §39-17-417 (Supp. 2005)) (lowering the triggering quantity <strong>of</strong><br />

methamphetamine for certain sentences from 100 and 1000 grams to 26 and 300 grams).<br />

183. See supra Part III.B.


880 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

mine cases to carve out exceptions to Fourth Amendment protections,<br />

and legislatures and prosecutors have sought to protect fetuses and<br />

children from the effects <strong>of</strong> parental drug use, production, and sale.<br />

A. Familiar Fourth Amendment Developments<br />

A familiar narrative <strong>of</strong> drugs and the Fourth Amendment describes<br />

the expansion <strong>of</strong> exceptions to Fourth Amendment limitations<br />

on searches and seizures due to the perceived need to police the use,<br />

manufacture, and sale <strong>of</strong> drugs. 184 Based on the nature <strong>of</strong> drugs<br />

themselves—portable, fungible, and easy to conceal—courts have<br />

gifted law enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficers with the ability to search more intrusively<br />

and thoroughly than prior doctrine might have suggested. 185<br />

Courts have used the ease <strong>of</strong> illicit drug disposal, as well as the violence<br />

associated with drug sales, to support findings <strong>of</strong> exigent circumstances<br />

that permit <strong>of</strong>ficers to dispense with obtaining warrants<br />

and, when they do obtain warrants, knocking and announcing their<br />

presence when serving warrants they do obtain. 186<br />

The volatility <strong>of</strong> the chemicals used to produce methamphetamine<br />

has similarly provided a foundation for permitting <strong>of</strong>ficers to search<br />

without obtaining warrants. Officers generally establish probable<br />

cause in suspected methamphetamine lab cases by identifying by<br />

smell chemicals associated with methamphetamine production 187 or<br />

184. See, e.g., Glasser & Siegel, supra note 67, at 243. Graham Boyd, Director <strong>of</strong> the<br />

American Civil Liberties Union’s Drug Policy Litigation Project, argues that “the court cases<br />

that have most destroyed the Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, methodically abridging freedom <strong>of</strong> religion,<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> speech, freedom from unreasonable searches and seizures and property rights,<br />

have all concerned drugs.” Graham Boyd, Collateral Damage in the War on Drugs, 47 VILL.<br />

L. REV. 839, 840 (2002). In the context <strong>of</strong> the Fourth Amendment, Boyd argues that the expansion<br />

<strong>of</strong> exceptions based on the War on Drugs is inevitable, as drug <strong>of</strong>fenses lack complaining<br />

witnesses, meaning that police need to rely on informants, wiretapping, undercover<br />

operations, wiretapping, and other practices that implicate the Fourth Amendment. Id.<br />

at 842.<br />

185. A 2002 Villanova <strong>Law</strong> Review symposium provided some <strong>of</strong> the nation’s leading<br />

critics <strong>of</strong> current Fourth Amendment doctrine with an opportunity to explore the connections<br />

between drug policy and the decline <strong>of</strong> Fourth Amendment protections. For some <strong>of</strong><br />

the most powerful critiques, see Frank Rudy Cooper, The Un-Balanced Fourth Amendment:<br />

A Cultural Study <strong>of</strong> the Drug War, Racial Pr<strong>of</strong>iling and Arvizu, 47 VILL. L.REV. 851<br />

(2002); Kevin R. Johnson, U.S. Border Enforcement: Drugs, Migrants, and the Rule <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong>,<br />

47 VILL. L. REV. 897 (2002); Erik Luna, Drug Exceptionalism, 47 VILL. L.REV. 753 (2002);<br />

David A. Moran, The New Fourth Amendment Vehicle Doctrine: Stop and Search Any Car<br />

at Any Time, 47 VILL.L.REV. 815 (2002). See also Paul Finkelman, The Second Casualty <strong>of</strong><br />

War: Civil Liberties and the War on Drugs, 66 S. CAL. L.REV. 1389 (1993); David Rudovsky,<br />

The Impact <strong>of</strong> the War on Drugs on Procedural Fairness and Racial Equality, 1994<br />

U. CHI. LEGAL F. 237; Steven Wisotsky, Crackdown: The Emerging “Drug Exception” to the<br />

Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, 38 HASTINGS L.J. 889 (1987).<br />

186. On the various justifications <strong>of</strong>fered for loosening Fourth Amendment protections<br />

in the drug context, see Luna, supra note 185, at 765-77.<br />

187. A long line <strong>of</strong> recent Eighth Circuit cases find that both probable cause and exigent<br />

circumstances justifying a warrantless entry are established based on the smell <strong>of</strong><br />

methamphetamine manufacture and little or nothing else. See, e.g., United <strong>State</strong>s v.


2010] METHADEMIC 881<br />

by observing equipment and materials associated with methamphetamine<br />

manufacture. 188 Courts reason that, where an <strong>of</strong>ficer has<br />

probable cause to believe that an operational methamphetamine laboratory<br />

exists in a location, exigent circumstances permit the <strong>of</strong>ficer<br />

warrantless entry in order to protect residents, neighbors, and the <strong>of</strong>ficers<br />

themselves from the possibility that the methamphetamine lab<br />

might at any moment explode. 189<br />

Finally, as methamphetamine manufacturers have experimented<br />

with work-around strategies to avoid restrictions on pseudoephedrine<br />

purchases, courts have held that purchasing patterns can also provide<br />

reasonable suspicion to detain suspected producers. 190 Shopping<br />

companions who separately purchase pseudoephedrine may provide<br />

reasonable suspicion to support a stop. 191 Purchasing the maximum<br />

permitted amount <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine at several stores in succession<br />

may also provide reasonable suspicion to effectuate a stop. 192 As discussed<br />

above, a store clerk or operator who permits a person to make<br />

such purchases, aside from breaking precursor sales restrictions<br />

laws, may be providing investigating <strong>of</strong>ficers with reasonable suspi-<br />

Clarke, 564 F.3d 949, 959 (8th Cir. 2009); United <strong>State</strong>s v. Walsh, 299 F.3d 729, 734 (8th<br />

Cir. 2002).<br />

188. See, e.g., United <strong>State</strong>s v. Rhiger, 315 F.3d 1283, 1288 (10th Cir. 2003).<br />

189. See, e.g., United <strong>State</strong>s v. Clarke, 564 F.3d at 959; Williams v. <strong>State</strong>, 995 So. 2d<br />

915, 920-221 (Ala. Crim. App. 2008); <strong>State</strong> v. Simmons, 714 N.W.2d 264, 273 (Iowa 2006);<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s v. Walsh, 299 F.3d at 734; United <strong>State</strong>s v. Wilson, 865 F.2d 215, 217 (9th<br />

Cir. 1989). In Williams, the <strong>of</strong>ficers <strong>of</strong>fered memorable testimony explaining their reasons<br />

for proceeding without a warrant. 995 So. 2d at 917 (reporting that <strong>of</strong>ficers testified “we’ve<br />

been almost blew up in meth labs before”). But see <strong>State</strong> v. Moore, 183 P.3d 158, 161-162<br />

(N.M. Ct. App. 2008) (affirming district court’s finding that exigent circumstances did not<br />

justify <strong>of</strong>ficer’s warrantless entry into home; while an operational methamphetamine laboratory<br />

might provide an exigent circumstance supporting warrantless entry, the police<br />

did not “have knowledge <strong>of</strong> specific, articulable facts that demonstrate that immediate action<br />

is necessary”).<br />

190. See generally Andrew C. Goetz, Note, One Stop, No Stop, Two Stop, Terry Stop:<br />

Reasonable Suspicion and Pseudoephedrine Purchases by Suspected Methamphetamine<br />

Manufacturers, 105 MICH.L.REV. 1573 (2007).<br />

191. See, e.g., United <strong>State</strong>s v. Ameling, 328 F.3d 443, 448 (8th Cir. 2003) (upholding a<br />

finding <strong>of</strong> reasonable suspicion where two customers picked up pseudoephedrine products<br />

together, purchased them from separate cashiers, consolidated the purchases in the parking<br />

lot, and had also purchased a lithium battery that might be used in methamphetamine<br />

manufacture); <strong>State</strong> v. Heuser, 661 N.W.2d 157 (Iowa 2003) (finding police had sufficient<br />

suspicion to stop defendant’s vehicle when the defendant and a woman entered a Target<br />

store together but then separated and bought several boxes <strong>of</strong> cold medication containing<br />

pseudoephedrine at separate cash registers, before driving to a Walmart). But see <strong>State</strong> v.<br />

Bulington, 802 N.E.2d 435 (Ind. 2004) (finding, on similar facts, that police lacked reasonable<br />

suspicion to conduct a Terry stop).<br />

192. See, e.g., United <strong>State</strong>s v. Thurston, No. S1-4.02 CR 494 CDP DDN, 2003 U.S.<br />

Dist. LEXIS 14954, at *8-10 (E.D. Mo. May 14, 2003) (finding that police had reasonable<br />

suspicion to perform a Terry stop where customer purchased two boxes <strong>of</strong> pseudoephedrine<br />

products at a Target, proceeded to a Walgreens, and purchased two additional boxes <strong>of</strong><br />

pseudoephedrine).


882 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

cion or probable cause to believe that they are conspiring with or are<br />

an accessory to the manufacture <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine. 193<br />

B. “But What About the Children?”<br />

A second similarity in the criminal sanctions response to methamphetamine<br />

has been the focus on the effects <strong>of</strong> exposure to drug<br />

activity on children and the attempts <strong>of</strong> legislatures, courts, and<br />

prosecutors to devise ways in which criminal sanctions might curtail<br />

the effects <strong>of</strong> drug manufacture and use on minors. The exposure <strong>of</strong><br />

children to methamphetamine itself can support an exigent circumstances<br />

exception to the warrant requirement. 194<br />

While the legislative response to methamphetamine generally has<br />

not included radically increased sanctions for <strong>of</strong>fenses or wholesale<br />

creation <strong>of</strong> new crimes, one <strong>of</strong> the exceptions to this observation is in<br />

the area <strong>of</strong> child protection. Legislatures have appended methamphetamine<br />

exposure to existing child abuse and neglect <strong>of</strong>fenses or<br />

created new “child abuse by methamphetamine exposure” statutes; 195<br />

created special felonies criminalizing the manufacture <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

in the presence <strong>of</strong> a child or dependant adult; 196 and increased<br />

penalties for existing methamphetamine <strong>of</strong>fenses when<br />

children are present or involved. 197 In states with more general child<br />

193. See, e.g., supra note 126 (discussing one such incident).<br />

194. See, e.g., Richards v. <strong>State</strong>, 659 S.E.2d 651, 653 (Ga. App. 2008) (holding that the<br />

smell <strong>of</strong> chemicals normally associated with methamphetamine manufacturing and a<br />

glimpse <strong>of</strong> what looks like a meth lab were sufficient to create an exigent circumstance<br />

when there was reason to believe that a child was present); <strong>State</strong> v. Crabb, 835 N.E.2d<br />

1068, 1071 (Ind. App. 2005) (holding that the smell <strong>of</strong> ether and the rustling <strong>of</strong> curtains,<br />

“combined with credible evidence that a small child was on the premises and, thus, being<br />

exposed to both risks from explosions due to the flammability <strong>of</strong> the chemicals used in<br />

producing methamphetamine and from the effects that ether can have on the respiratory<br />

system,” provided <strong>of</strong>ficers with sufficient exigent circumstances to permit <strong>of</strong>ficers to make<br />

warrantless entry).<br />

195. See, e.g., WASH. REV. CODE § 9A.42.100 (Supp. 2007) (“A person is guilty <strong>of</strong> the<br />

crime <strong>of</strong> endangerment with a controlled substance if the person knowingly or intentionally<br />

permits a dependent child or dependent adult to be exposed to, ingest, inhale, or have contact<br />

with methamphetamine or ephedrine, pseudoephedrine, or anhydrous ammonia, including<br />

their salts, isomers, and salts <strong>of</strong> isomers, that are being used in the manufacture <strong>of</strong><br />

methamphetamine, including its salts, isomers, and salts <strong>of</strong> isomers. Endangerment with a<br />

controlled substance is a class B felony.”). Michigan, Iowa, and South Dakota have also<br />

enacted specific “child abuse by methamphetamine” statutes. See Feature: Methamphetamine<br />

as Child Abuse <strong>Law</strong>s Gain Ground, but Do They Help or Hurt?, DRUG WAR CHRON.,<br />

July 14, 2006, available at http://stopthedrugwar.org/chronicle/444/drug-child-abuse-laws.<br />

196. See, e.g., N.D. CENT. CODE § 19-03.1-22.2 (2004); TENN. CODE ANN. § 37-1-<br />

102(23)(D) (2006). Georgia, Idaho, and Ohio are among the other states that have specific<br />

felonies criminalizing the manufacture <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine in the presence <strong>of</strong> a child. See<br />

Feature: Methamphetamine as Child Abuse <strong>Law</strong>s Gain Ground, but Do They Help or Hurt?,<br />

supra note 195.<br />

197. For example, Washington provides a sentencing enhancement for methamphetamine<br />

manufacture where methamphetamine was produced in the presence <strong>of</strong> a child. See<br />

WASH.REV.CODE §9.94A.827(2) (Supp. 2009).


2010] METHADEMIC 883<br />

abuse statutes, courts have likewise expanded criminal liability,<br />

upholding convictions for child abuse for exposing children to methamphetamine<br />

manufacturing, even in the absence <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> harm<br />

to the child. 198<br />

As we saw with maternal use <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine, 199 prosecutors have<br />

sought to use existing child abuse statutes to sanction women who<br />

use methamphetamine during pregnancy. 200 As we also saw with respect<br />

to crack cocaine, 201 courts generally have not permitted such<br />

tactics. 202 In one high-pr<strong>of</strong>ile case, local prosecutors in Hawaii<br />

brought manslaughter charges against a woman whose two-day-old<br />

baby died after she smoked methamphetamine in the days leading up<br />

to its birth. 203 She entered a conditional guilty plea, reserving the<br />

right to contest the charges, and was vindicated when the Hawaii<br />

Supreme Court rejected the prosecutor’s interpretation <strong>of</strong> the statute<br />

The extent to which laws <strong>of</strong> these various types have been or will be effective in limiting<br />

the exposure <strong>of</strong> children to hazardous conditions has not been studied. The number<br />

<strong>of</strong> children endangered by methamphetamine manufacture, or who enter state child protective<br />

service programs because <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine exposure, is unclear; state departments<br />

do not keep statistics, and informal estimates range from half <strong>of</strong> child abuse cases to<br />

less than one percent. Statutes might protect children from toxic exposure by providing<br />

parents with a manufacturing disincentive or by making unavailable via imprisonment<br />

parents who produce methamphetamine; they might, on the other hand, drive parents who<br />

produce methamphetamine into greater secrecy, or place children who live in environmentally<br />

toxic environments in possibly unsafe foster care environments.<br />

198. See, e.g., People v. Toney, 90 Cal. Rptr. 2d 578, 581 (Cal. Ct. App. 1999) (upholding<br />

child abuse conviction when child was found in location where chemicals for the manufacturing<br />

<strong>of</strong> methamphetamine were found without requiring pro<strong>of</strong> that methamphetamine<br />

was actually manufactured there).<br />

199. See supra notes 64-68 and accompanying text. For a recent article decrying the<br />

trend <strong>of</strong> prosecuting mothers for harms allegedly inflicted on their fetuses, see generally<br />

Linda C. Fentiman, The New “Fetal Protection”: The Wrong Answer to the Crisis <strong>of</strong> Inadequate<br />

Health Care for Women and Children, 84 DENV.U.L.REV. 537 (2006).<br />

200. One difference between this wave <strong>of</strong> prosecutions and those relating to crack cocaine<br />

is that this time the community <strong>of</strong> criminal defense attorneys, public health <strong>of</strong>ficials,<br />

and advocates for pregnant women were ready with a concerted legal and scientific response.<br />

See generally Meth and Myth: Top Doctors, Scientists and Specialists Warn Mass<br />

Media on “Meth Baby” Stories, July 29, 2005, http://stopthedrugwar.org/<br />

chronicle/397/methandmyth.shtml (gathering medical evidence problematizing link between<br />

meth use and fetal health); KING, supra note 10, at 16 (criticizing media’s handling<br />

<strong>of</strong> scientific and medical data relating to methamphetamine); see also PROVINE, supra note<br />

10, at 165 (noting that media and politicians were much more skeptical about “meth baby”<br />

claims than they had been about “crack baby” stories).<br />

201. See discussion supra note 68. In this context, it is worth noting that the most highpr<strong>of</strong>ile<br />

homicide conviction against a pregnant woman who used crack cocaine was set<br />

aside on state post-conviction review in 2008, on the grounds that her lawyers were ineffective<br />

in failing to present sufficient expert testimony and to fully “investigate medical evidence<br />

contradicting the <strong>State</strong>’s experts’ testimony on the link between cocaine and stillbirth.”<br />

McKnight v. <strong>State</strong>, 661 S.E.2d 354, 354 (S.C. 2008).<br />

202. See, e.g., cases discussed infra notes 203-05 and accompanying text. See also Amos<br />

Bridges, Charge Filed after Baby Born with Meth Traces, SPRINGFIELD NEWS-LEADER, Dec.<br />

29, 2005, available at http://www.csdp.org/news/news/news_mometh_122905.htm (describing<br />

filing <strong>of</strong> child abuse charges against 19-year-old Missouri woman whose child was born with<br />

traces amounts <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine in its system).<br />

203. See <strong>State</strong> v. Aiwohi, 123 P.3d 1210, 1210-11 (Haw. 2008) (narrating events).


884 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

and reversed her conviction. 204 In another heavily followed case, a<br />

judge dismissed child endangerment charges brought against a<br />

Wyoming woman after her newborn child tested positive for methamphetamine.<br />

205 In one Oklahoma case, a woman spent two years<br />

in prison awaiting a trial on homicide charges stemming from the<br />

stillbirth <strong>of</strong> a child born after she ingested methamphetamine during<br />

the late stages <strong>of</strong> pregnancy, pled guilty to second-degree murder and<br />

received an ostensible fifteen-year sentence, but was released a year<br />

later after completing drug rehabilitation as part <strong>of</strong> an informal deal<br />

with the prosecutor and the trial judge. 206<br />

V. WHY IS THIS PANIC DIFFERENT FROM ALL OTHER PANICS?<br />

If we are in the midst <strong>of</strong> a methamphetamine panic, it is a panic<br />

that has produced a comparatively temperate result. Why has public<br />

and legislative concern about a drug described in terms <strong>of</strong> natural<br />

disasters and communicable deadly disease generated cold medication<br />

restrictions and educational programs rather than extensive new<br />

criminal law?<br />

1. Race<br />

A. Some Preliminary Theories<br />

The narrative provided by scholars <strong>of</strong> the crack cocaine legislative<br />

response, as detailed above, 207 is largely one <strong>of</strong> racial panic. Crack cocaine<br />

is and was associated with African-American users and sellers,<br />

goes the analysis, and this association facilitated draconian criminal<br />

sanctions and mass imprisonment. 208 The “War on Drugs” has largely<br />

been a war on people <strong>of</strong> color, waged against people citizens and leg-<br />

204. Id. at 1224-25.<br />

205. See Judge Drops ‘Meth Baby’ Charge, CASPER STAR-TRIB., Sept. 29, 2005, available at<br />

http://trib.com/news/state-and-regional/article_e76def07-3088-527f-8a9a-18f5f05ea9a6.html (detailing<br />

case).<br />

206. See Dana Stone, Is Meth Murder Charge Useful?, OKLAHOMAN, Dec. 19, 2007 (narrating<br />

story <strong>of</strong> Theresa Hernandez who spent two years in jail awaiting trial on first-degree<br />

murder charges before pleading guilty to second-degree murder and receiving a fifteen-year<br />

sentence); Jay F. Marks, Woman Was Charged in Her Stillborn Son’s Death — Meth Mom<br />

Wins Early Release, OKLAHOMAN, Nov. 20, 2008, at 1A (narrating later developments, including<br />

her release).<br />

Creative prosecution strategies have, <strong>of</strong> course, not been limited to cases involving<br />

pregnant and parenting women. Prosecutors in North Carolina, for example, have charged<br />

persons who operate methamphetamine labs under the state’s antiterrorism “weapons <strong>of</strong><br />

mass destruction” statute. O. Dean Sanderford, Terrorism Statutes Run Wild: Methamphetamine<br />

and Weapons <strong>of</strong> Mass Destruction, 82 N.C. L. REV 2142, 2142 (2004). See also Jaime<br />

Holguin, Terror <strong>Law</strong>s Used vs. Common Crimes: Critics Bothered by String <strong>of</strong> Increasing<br />

Cases, CBS NEWS, Sept. 14, 2003, available at http://www.cbsnews.com/<br />

stories/2003/09/14/national/main573155.shtml (noting that a North Carolina man charged<br />

under this law faced twelve years to life in prison).<br />

207. See supra Part III.B.<br />

208. See supra notes 74-79 and accompanying text.


2010] METHADEMIC 885<br />

islators already fear. 209 It is easier to embrace mass incarceration<br />

when you do not identify with the persons incarcerated and to the extent<br />

that you do think <strong>of</strong> them, it is with trepidation. Whether or not<br />

legislators and citizens consciously wish to harm people based on<br />

race, racial unease, antipathy, and panic facilitate the decisions to<br />

prosecute and punish. 210<br />

This narrative is appealing as applied to methamphetamine.<br />

While crack cocaine in particular has been associated with African<br />

Americans, and other illicit drugs have historically been linked to<br />

disfavored subgroups, methamphetamine is, accurately, characterized<br />

as a drug that is preferred by white populations. 211 As white<br />

Americans do not comprise a disfavored racial group, and as there<br />

are no characteristics associated with methamphetamine users (such<br />

as radical politics or generalized social dissent) 212 that might otherwise<br />

corral them into such a targeted subgroup, we would not expect<br />

to see the sorts <strong>of</strong> dramatic legislative responses that we have seen in<br />

the past. Unlike Chinese immigrants smoking opium, or Mexican<br />

immigrants smoking marijuana, methamphetamine use does not<br />

stoke racial anxieties.<br />

Media articles and legislative history provide some support for<br />

this argument. The portrayal <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine addicts in the<br />

popular press <strong>of</strong>ten has <strong>of</strong>ten been one <strong>of</strong> pity and sympathy. 213 Leg-<br />

209. Kennedy, supra note 20 at 1258.<br />

210. See supra note 208.<br />

211. Methamphetamine prosecutions have been credited with “whitening” to some extent<br />

the federal prison population; in 1994, for example, about 73% <strong>of</strong> new federal inmates<br />

convicted <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine <strong>of</strong>fenses were white. See Schone, supra note 129, at 35. By<br />

2005, the data was more ambiguous; while the plurality <strong>of</strong> those newly convicted <strong>of</strong> federal<br />

meth <strong>of</strong>fenses remained white, the number was not less than fifty percent. See Motivans,<br />

supra note 116, at 2. While the characterization <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine as a “white drug”<br />

has been fairly consistent, it has not proven universal. For example, some sources have<br />

linked methamphetamine use with the Native American population. See, e.g., Andrew<br />

Murr & Sarah Childress, A New Menace on the Rez, NEWSWEEK, Sept. 27, 2004, at 30 (<strong>of</strong>fering<br />

a story about methamphetamine use on Native American reservations and quoting a<br />

Bureau <strong>of</strong> Indian Affairs <strong>of</strong>ficial as arguing that “[m]eth is becoming the drug <strong>of</strong> choice in<br />

Indian Country”).<br />

212. Cf. supra Part II.A.3 (discussing mainstream culture’s unease about social groups<br />

associated with drug use during the 1960s).<br />

213. See, e.g., Joel Baird, Crazy about METH, DAILEY NEWS LEADER, Sept. 11, 2005 (on<br />

file with author) (pr<strong>of</strong>iling methamphetamine user whose methamphetamine use had led<br />

to the dissolution <strong>of</strong> his marriage and scars from picking his skin; the user described methamphetamine<br />

users as “everyday people,” “good people, educated people, uneducated<br />

people; white collar, blue collar; people who drive BMWs, people who drive grandma’s car<br />

that barely runs; housewives who’ve got two kids at home and are tired <strong>of</strong> washing<br />

clothes”); Melanie Bennett & Chuck Williams, Meth’s Human and Economic Costs are<br />

Enormous, COLUMBUS LEDGER-ENQUIRER, Oct. 26, 2005, available at 2005 WLNR<br />

17275992 (describing a man whose methamphetamine use, according to him, led to losing<br />

his land, houses, wife, children, savings, business, vehicles, and ultimately, liberty). David<br />

Sheff, My Son the Addict, OBSERVER, Oct. 23, 2005, available at 2005 WLNR 17193468<br />

(describing the author’s son, an upper-middle-class <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> California at Berkeley<br />

addict who struggled with methamphetamine addiction before successfully completing a


886 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

islators tell stories about relatives and community members whose<br />

lives have been savaged by methamphetamine use. 214 The public and<br />

political discourse about methamphetamine shows a degree <strong>of</strong> empathy<br />

for drug users that far exceeds anything seen in recent drug panics.<br />

The narrative that the racial status <strong>of</strong> persons associated with<br />

the use <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine—that <strong>of</strong> the white majority—has driven<br />

policy responses is thus an appealing one.<br />

This explanation does not, however, seem fully persuasive. In recent<br />

years, it is not just methamphetamine legislation and executive<br />

action that has been characterized by relative restraint, but other<br />

rehabilitation program and obtaining a job writing for an online magazine); Zernike, supra<br />

note 178 (describing Montana Meth Project’s anti-methamphetamine advertising campaign<br />

featuring televised images <strong>of</strong> a fictional teenager’s blood swirling in her shower drain from<br />

the cuts she has made while picking her skin during methamphetamine, and radio commercials<br />

using actual recovering methamphetamine addicts detailing prostituting themselves<br />

for methamphetamine and losing their homes and jobs).<br />

Newsweek pr<strong>of</strong>iled a police chief arrested for conspiring to produce methamphetamine<br />

and cited a scientist who studies methamphetamine as describing “high achievers”<br />

such as college students and law enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficials as one <strong>of</strong> the fastest-growing groups<br />

<strong>of</strong> methamphetamine users. See Sarah Childress, Crystal Handcuffs: Battling the Meth<br />

Scourge, a Police Chief is Charged, NEWSWEEK, May 16, 2005, at 36.<br />

Newsweek’s controversial methamphetamine cover story, America’s Most Dangerous<br />

Drug, tells the story <strong>of</strong> one woman in particular:<br />

The leafy Chicago suburb <strong>of</strong> Burr Ridge is the kind <strong>of</strong> place where people come to<br />

live the American dream in million-dollar homes on one-acre lots. Eight years ago<br />

Kimberly Fields and her husband, Todd, bought a ranch house here on a wooded<br />

lot beside a small lake, and before long they were parents, with two sons, a black<br />

Labrador and a Volvo in the drive. But somewhere along the way this blond<br />

mother with a college degree and a $100,000-a-year job as a sales rep for Apria<br />

Healthcare found something that mattered more: methamphetamine.<br />

Jefferson et al., supra note 101, at 41. After turning to methamphetamine, Kimberly was<br />

arrested three times for shoplifting, and:<br />

[B]y the time cops came banging on her door with a search warrant . . . Kimberly,<br />

now 37, had turned her slice <strong>of</strong> suburbia into a meth lab . . . . Dressed in a<br />

pink T shirt printed with the words ALL STRESSED OUT, Kimberly looked<br />

about 45 pounds thinner than when police first booked her for shoplifting two<br />

years ago. Her leg bore a knee-to-ankle scar from a chemical burn, and police<br />

found anhydrous ammonia, also used in cooking meth, buried in a converted<br />

propane tank in her backyard. As <strong>of</strong>ficers led Kimberly away in handcuffs, her<br />

6-year-old son Nicholas was “only concerned that his brother had his toys and<br />

diapers,” recalls Detective Mike Barnes. Meanwhile, police evacuated 96 nearby<br />

homes, fearing the alleged meth lab might explode.<br />

Id.<br />

Mom-and-pop local methamphetamine producers similarly are described in terms<br />

that suggest something other than organized criminal enterprise. As a district attorney in<br />

Georgia told a local newspaper, “I would not classify these as mom-and-pop operations. I<br />

would classify them as idiot operations. These are people who couldn’t pass high school<br />

chemistry.” Chuck Williams & Melanie Bennett, ‘Cocaine Times 10,’ COLUMBUS LEDGER-<br />

ENQUIRER, Oct. 21, 2005, at A1 (quoting Lee County District Attorney Nick Abbott); see also<br />

Schone, supra note 129, at 35 (describing mom-and-pop methamphetamine manufacturers<br />

as “the plague <strong>of</strong> Beavis and Butt-Head”).<br />

214. Cf. <strong>State</strong> Representative’s Son Faces Meth Charge, DULUTH NEWS-TRIB., Sept. 2, 2005.


2010] METHADEMIC 887<br />

skirmishes in the “War on Drugs.” 215 Crack cocaine, in particular—<br />

the drug which generated a rich literature detailing racialized drug<br />

policy—has enjoyed considerable reconsideration both in statute and<br />

in sentencing policy. 216 If the one-way ratchet can turn in reverse for<br />

a drug so closely associated with African-American users, it seems<br />

unlikely that race, while perhaps a partial explanation for focus on<br />

precursor restrictions and treatment programs, provides a full explanation.<br />

Ironically enough, the precursor restrictions may end up<br />

themselves testing the disfavored social group hypothesis: as precursors<br />

have arguably made it more difficult for mom-and-pop manufacturers<br />

to produce methamphetamine in home laboratories, methamphetamine<br />

has increasingly been imported from super labs located in<br />

Mexico. 217 If methamphetamine becomes associated less with white<br />

215. See supra note 15; infra Part IV.B.<br />

216. See, e.g., Emery, supra note 15 (detailing progress towards repealing crack-cocaine<br />

powder sentencing disparity and predicting that “this may be the year” that the disparity is<br />

eliminated and crack sentences are reduced); Kimbrough v. United <strong>State</strong>s, 552 U.S. 85 (2007)<br />

(allowing judges discretion to sentence individuals convicted <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine crimes to lesser<br />

terms based on judges’ personal disapproval <strong>of</strong> crack/powder disparity).<br />

In an interesting and representative incident, when South Carolina recently decided to<br />

address disparities across penalties for powder and crack cocaine possession (a two-year maximum<br />

sentence for simple possession <strong>of</strong> powder cocaine, in contrast to a five-year maximum<br />

sentence for simple possession <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine), it did so not by doing what might twenty<br />

years ago have been predicted (simply raise the maximum penalty for possession <strong>of</strong> powder<br />

cocaine to five years, as drug sentences can only increase), but by lowering the maximum penalty<br />

for crack cocaine and raising the maximum penalty for powder cocaine so that both carried<br />

a possible three years. See 2005-2006 Bill 16: Include Manufacturing Methamphetamine<br />

as a Violent Crime, S.C. Gen. Assem. http://www.scstatehouse.gov/sess116_2005-2006/<br />

bills/16.htm (last updated Dec. 4, 2009) (providing text <strong>of</strong> Bill and noting its passage).<br />

217. See, e.g., Bennett & Williams, supra note 213, at A1 (reporting on drug sting involving<br />

methamphetamine <strong>of</strong>ficers believed had been trafficked from Mexico); Sara Jean Green,<br />

U.S. Meth Roundup Snares 24 in Western Washington; 427 arrested in all – Increased Smuggling<br />

from Mexico, SEATTLE TIMES, Aug. 31, 2005 at B1 (quoting King County Sherriff Su<br />

Rahr as saying “as we’ve shut down the labs, we’re seeing meth coming up and U.S. Attorney<br />

for the Western District <strong>of</strong> Washington John McKay saying his <strong>of</strong>fice has observed “something<br />

<strong>of</strong> a trend” with a “shift from home-cooked methamphetamine” to methamphetamine<br />

“produced in super-labs”); Ryckaert, supra note 142, at A04 (quoting White House Office <strong>of</strong><br />

National Drug Control Policy director John P. Walters as saying that “Organized criminals<br />

now produce large quantities <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine in Mexico and are moving it across our<br />

borders”); Lloyd de Vries, CBS News, Mexican Meth Floods U.S., May 19, 2006,<br />

http://www.cbsnews.com/stories/2006/05/19/eveningnews/main1636846.shtml (reporting that,<br />

despite a decline in domestic methamphetamine production due to lab raids, “The epidemic <strong>of</strong><br />

meth use is still rampant because the drug is still plentiful on America’s streets . . . . This<br />

deadly [methamphetamine] is now a growth industry for Mexico’s deadly drug cartels.<br />

They’re replacing small U.S. kitchen labs with Mexican super labs”); Greenwood Officials Arrest<br />

More Suspects in Meth Ring Investigation, WIS-TV, Dec. 19, 2005, available at<br />

http://www.wistv.com/global/story.asp?s=4250657&ClientType=Printable (detailing workings<br />

<strong>of</strong> major ring importing methamphetamine into South Carolina from Mexico); Lisa Demer,<br />

Meth Ills Expand in Alaska, ANCHORAGE DAILY NEWS, Sept. 7, 2005, at B1 (noting a shift<br />

from homegrown methamphetamine to methamphetamine imported from Mexico);<br />

ABERDEEN AM. NEWS, Dec. 15, 2005, at B3, available at 2005 WLNR 20102925 (quoting director<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Iowa governor’s Office <strong>of</strong> Drug Control Policy says that since methamphetamine<br />

precursor restrictions were put into place, “organized criminals” are “now producing<br />

large bulk quantities <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine in Mexico,” and arguing that “[w]e’re being


888 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

stateside producers and users and more with Mexican manufacturers<br />

and importers, we will see if or how the legal response to methamphetamine<br />

changes.<br />

2. Media Coverage<br />

A second plausible explanation is that the language used to describe<br />

methamphetamine, methamphetamine addicts, and methamphetamine<br />

sellers/manufacturers, as employed by the media, legislators,<br />

and the public in general, differs in tone and content from the<br />

language that has surrounded past drug panics. Perhaps there simply<br />

isn’t a panic; writers, policymakers, and citizens are unperturbed<br />

by methamphetamine. While there are scattered pieces <strong>of</strong> evidence to<br />

support this claim, 218 it ultimately fails to persuade.<br />

It would be difficult to argue that the language surrounding methamphetamine<br />

in the media is substantially different in terms <strong>of</strong> its<br />

emphatic and hyperbolic qualities than it has been during past perceived<br />

epidemics <strong>of</strong> drug use. Articles about methamphetamine use<br />

“epidemic” and “plague” to describe the drug’s use. 219 Natural-disaster<br />

language also has characterized the media response to methamphetamine;<br />

media sources have pressed the tidal wave disaster analogy into<br />

repeat service, echoing perhaps the language <strong>of</strong> law enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficers<br />

describing the perceived entrance <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine into or<br />

outbreak <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine use within a state. 220 The tornado has<br />

also enjoyed employment as a metaphor for methamphetamine, used<br />

to describe the imminent approach <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine to areas<br />

where methamphetamine has not yet taken root. 221<br />

According to media sources, methamphetamine is—as were the<br />

drugs that anchored past drug “epidemics”—the worst drug <strong>of</strong> all<br />

killed with ‘Mexican ice,’” which he describes as substantially more pure than locallyproduced<br />

methamphetamine).<br />

218. See generally supra note 213 (collecting articles that <strong>of</strong>fer comparatively sympathetic<br />

portrayals <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine users and producers).<br />

219. See, e.g., Crane, supra note 101, at A24; Johnson, supra note 101, at 41. Politicians<br />

have also utilized this language. See, e.g., ABERDEEN AM. NEWS, supra note 217, at B3,<br />

(quoting Indiana Governor Mitch Daniels as saying that “we can trace [methamphetamine’s]<br />

path like a plague . . . . If we call this effort to eliminate this problem a war, for<br />

once, we’re not overstating it”). So, too, have academics. See, e.g., O’Connor et al., supra<br />

note 123 (article entitled Developing Lasting Legal Solutions to the Dual Epidemics <strong>of</strong> Methamphetamine<br />

Production and Use).<br />

220. See, e.g., Jill Young Miler & Craig Schneider, When Meth Hits Home: Meth’s Forsaken<br />

Children—When Parents Disappear into a Chaotic World <strong>of</strong> Drug Abuse, Danger and<br />

Heartbreak Follow for Their Sons and Daughters, ATLANTA J. CONST., Nov. 30 2003, at A1<br />

(quoting Georgia Bureau <strong>of</strong> Investigation Director Vernon Keenan as describing methamphetamine<br />

as having entered his state “like a tidal wave”).<br />

221. Lamothe, supra note 119, at A1 (discussing the possibility <strong>of</strong> crystal methamphetamine<br />

becoming prevalent in Massachusetts).


2010] METHADEMIC 889<br />

time, more devastating and addictive than any other drug. 222 Media<br />

sources <strong>of</strong>ten run “before and after” photos <strong>of</strong> users to illustrate the<br />

drug’s effects on individuals. 223 Methamphetamine in fact has been<br />

described explicitly as “the new crack,” 224 the latest drug to take the<br />

crown <strong>of</strong> most addictive and devastating. “It really has become the<br />

drug <strong>of</strong> choice. It’s taken over heroin and it’s taken over crack.” 225<br />

Media articles also have held methamphetamine responsible for the<br />

spread <strong>of</strong> sexually transmitted diseases. 226<br />

As we saw in the late 1980s with respect to crack cocaine, media<br />

sources have featured connections between methamphetamine use<br />

and external social effects. As noted above, media reports have highlighted<br />

the public health problems associated with methamphetamine<br />

production and extent to which methamphetamine producers<br />

endanger household members, children, and neighbors. 227 In addition<br />

to describing these physical and environmental dangers, media<br />

sources have detailed criminal <strong>of</strong>fenses in which methamphetamine<br />

addicts engage in order to provide funding for their habits. In particular,<br />

articles have focused on information theft (<strong>of</strong>ten referred to<br />

222. See, e.g., Jennifer Chambers, Police Offer Testing Kits as Meth Use Accelerates,<br />

DETROIT NEWS, Dec. 15, 2005, at 3B (quoting Oakland County Commissioner Eric Coleman,<br />

speaking on behalf <strong>of</strong> the National Association <strong>of</strong> Counties, as saying that methamphetamine<br />

“is bigger and worse than heroin or cocaine can ever be”); Nancy L<strong>of</strong>holm, Arrest<br />

Ends Meth-Ring Manhunt: Mesa County for Weeks has been Rattled by Violence Linked<br />

to the Drug’s Widespread Use, DENVER POST, Dec. 13, 2005, at A1 (describing a group <strong>of</strong><br />

suspected methamphetamine addicts who “had held Mesa County in a jittery grip <strong>of</strong> fear<br />

and violence for weeks,” linked methamphetamine to local shootings, and quoting a local<br />

law enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficers as saying that methamphetamine “is public safety’s and the community’s<br />

worst nightmare” and that “[t]his drug is different . . . . What it does to people is<br />

so much worse than anything else out there”); Marcovitz, supra note 152, at B1 (quoting a<br />

local district attorney as saying that “meth is a killer. It destroys communities. It is not<br />

like any other drug”); Puzzanghera, supra note 128, at A1 (“<strong>Law</strong> enforcement <strong>of</strong>ficials say<br />

[methamphetamine] is the most devastating drug they have ever encountered, hooking<br />

most users the first time they try it.”); A Commission at Work: Public Safety Advisers Have<br />

Their Hands Full in Dealing with Crystal Meth, LONG BEACH PRESS-TELEGRAM, Dec. 16,<br />

2005, at A16 (“[Methamphetamine] is far more addictive and far more dangerous stuff than<br />

cocaine, heroine, or other street drugs.”).<br />

223. See sources cited supra note 180.<br />

224. See, e.g., Bruce Ramsey, The Scourge <strong>of</strong> the New Crack, SEATTLE TIMES, June 14,<br />

2009, at H4 (reviewing REDING, supra note 10); Press Release, U.S. Senate, Schumer: New<br />

Stats Show Crystal Meth Quickly Becoming the New Crack—Seizures in New York Up<br />

31% Over Last Year, (Apr. 25, 2004), available at http://schumer.senate.gov/<br />

new_website/record.cfm?id=265406 (“Crystal meth is becoming the new crack, and we need<br />

tough new penalties that treat it like crack.”).<br />

225. Chambers, supra note 222, at 3 (quoting Police Chief William Dwyer <strong>of</strong> Farmington<br />

Hills, Michigan).<br />

226. See Patricia Guthrie, Drugs, Risky Sex Get Blame for Jump in Syphilis Cases,<br />

Nov. 9, 2005, ATLANTA J. CONST., at A9 (reporting that the Center for Disease Control has<br />

seen a rise in syphilis cases among men who have sex with men, and suggests a link<br />

between methamphetamine use and risky sexual behavior leading to disease<br />

transmission); Jefferson et. al., supra note 105, at 38.<br />

227. See, e.g., Kathleen Brady Shea, 8 Arrested in Methamphetamine Ring,<br />

PHILADELPHIA INQUIRER, Sept. 8, 2005, at B5.


890 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

as identity theft), a crime which even when uncoupled from methamphetamine<br />

generates a fair amount <strong>of</strong> panic, describing methamphetamine<br />

addicts as stealing personal information in order to obtain<br />

money to buy drugs. 228 In one newspaper article, a local sheriff estimated<br />

that eighty five percent <strong>of</strong> information theft <strong>of</strong>fenses he investigated<br />

were in fact committed by methamphetamine addicts. 229 Articles<br />

also have linked car thefts to methamphetamine, similarly portraying<br />

addicts as stealing cars to raise money for drugs. 230 The list <strong>of</strong><br />

devastating methamphetamine effects as outlined in media sources is<br />

lengthy, and the language used to describe its effects thus is emphatic.<br />

While these stories may or may not be grounded in reality—<br />

figures on crimes related to methamphetamine are not reliable 231 and<br />

figures on the percentage <strong>of</strong> foster cases related to methamphetamine<br />

have proven unverifiable 232 —it is fairly unpersuasive to argue that to<br />

the extent media might drive police responses, that a change in tone<br />

in media articles is responsible.<br />

3. Alternative Panics<br />

Another explanation for the legal response to methamphetamine<br />

is that we are indeed panicking about crime—but primarily about<br />

other kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>fenses, particularly sex <strong>of</strong>fenses against children.<br />

During the last two decades, there has been a major expansion <strong>of</strong> legislation<br />

increasing penalties for those who commit sexual <strong>of</strong>fenses<br />

228. See, e.g., Greg Risling, Meth Users Turn to ID Theft to Pay for Habit, CONTRA<br />

COSTA TIMES, Dec. 18, 2005, at F4 (“[M]ore and more desperate users <strong>of</strong> [methamphetamine]<br />

are turning to identity theft to pay for their habit, creating a criminal nexus costing<br />

Americans millions <strong>of</strong> dollars.”).<br />

229. See id.<br />

230. See, e.g., Jesse McKinley, The Distinction Modesto Didn’t Need: National Car-<br />

Theft Capital, N.Y. TIMES, June 3, 2006 (noting that Modesto, California leads the nation<br />

in car thefts per capita and largely blaming methamphetamine for that distinction); Janelle,<br />

supra note 217 (describing the investigation and arrest <strong>of</strong> thirty suspects in an alleged<br />

methamphetamine distribution ring and noting that the investigation revealed a vehicular<br />

“theft ring, a chop shop for stolen cars,” and a counterfeiting scheme).<br />

231. Efforts to evaluate extravagant claims <strong>of</strong> meth’s effects on crime rates have usually<br />

left the involved analysts skeptical. For one well-reported such effort, see Angela Valdez,<br />

Meth Madness: How The Oregonian Manufactured an Epidemic, Politicians Bought It and<br />

You’re Paying, WILLAMETTE WEEK, Mar. 22, 2006, available at http://www.wweek.com/<br />

popup/print.php?index=7368 (analyzing fourteen stories in The Oregonian that, inter alia, described<br />

the proportion <strong>of</strong> state property crimes “fuel[ed]” by methamphetamine as between 80<br />

and 90 percent and failing to find supporting data to verify the accuracy <strong>of</strong> this figure).<br />

232. In August <strong>of</strong> 2005, The Oregonian ran a front-page story with the subheadline: “Oregon’s<br />

Meth Epidemic Creates Thousands <strong>of</strong> ‘Orphans.’ ” See Joseph Rose, The Children <strong>of</strong> Meth<br />

OREGONIAN, Aug. 28, 2005 at A01. According to the story, a state Department <strong>of</strong> Human Services<br />

study found that half <strong>of</strong> the state’s foster cases involved children taken “from parents using or<br />

making the potent drug.” See id. There was no such study, and DHS does not track whether or<br />

not methamphetamine causes children to be removed from homes; rather, a DHS coordinator<br />

had compared a list <strong>of</strong> parents with a list <strong>of</strong> people who had received methamphetamine treatment<br />

and found a 50% correlation. See Valdez, supra note 231.


2010] METHADEMIC 891<br />

against children 233 and imposing onerous new collateral sanctions<br />

upon such individuals. 234 A wide variety <strong>of</strong> academic commentators<br />

have analyzed the legislative history and cultural politics <strong>of</strong> these<br />

laws and concluded that they are both disproportionate and vindictive,<br />

reflecting a predictable desire to take out our collective cultural<br />

anxieties on individuals who we can comfortably dismiss as “monstrous.”<br />

235 According to some scholars, we are in the midst—or perhaps<br />

at the tail end—<strong>of</strong> a full-fledged “sex panic.” 236<br />

While one panic does not rule out the possibility <strong>of</strong> another, it arguably<br />

reduces the odds. After all, given the limits <strong>of</strong> human emotion<br />

and energy, our capacity for moral indignation is not inexhaustible.<br />

Moreover, the creation <strong>of</strong> cultural images <strong>of</strong> monstrous <strong>of</strong>fenders who<br />

impose dramatic physical and psychological trauma on vulnerable<br />

children creates a very high standard for those whom might want to<br />

demonize methamphetamine users. 237 Next to those who sexually<br />

233. In the most extreme example, a handful <strong>of</strong> states adopted laws authorizing the<br />

death penalty for certain child sexual <strong>of</strong>fenses. In June 2008, a sharply divided Supreme<br />

Court found that such laws violate the Eighth Amendment to the United <strong>State</strong>s Constitution.<br />

Kennedy v. Louisiana, 128 S. Ct. 2641, 2646 (2008).<br />

234. Here, the most notable development is the growth <strong>of</strong> sexual <strong>of</strong>fender registration<br />

laws, <strong>of</strong>ten called “Megan’s <strong>Law</strong>s.” Since 1996, every <strong>State</strong> has had such a statute. See Corey<br />

Rayburn Yung, One <strong>of</strong> These <strong>Law</strong>s Is Not Like the Others: Why the Federal Sex Offender<br />

Registration and Notification Act Raises New Constitutional Questions, 46 HARV. J. ON<br />

LEGIS. 369, 370 n.6 (2009). The Supreme Court upheld two such statutes against constitutional<br />

challenges in 2003. See Smith v. Doe, 538 U.S. 84, 105-06 (2003); Conn. Dep’t Pub.<br />

Safety v. Doe, 538 U.S. 1, 8 (2003). More recently, we have begun to see an expansion <strong>of</strong><br />

laws that limit the ability <strong>of</strong> convicted sex <strong>of</strong>fenders to live in proximity to places where<br />

children congregate, <strong>of</strong>ten to the point that there are few or even no places where they can<br />

legally reside. For one academic analysis <strong>of</strong> this trend, see generally Wayne A. Logan, Constitutional<br />

Collectivism and Ex-Offender Residence Exclusion <strong>Law</strong>s, 92 IOWA L. REV. 1<br />

(2006).<br />

235. See generally, e.g., Daniel M. Filler, Making the Case for Megan’s <strong>Law</strong>: A Study in<br />

Legislative Rhetoric, 76 IND. L.J. 315 (2001); Joseph E. Kennedy, Monstrous Offenders and<br />

the Search for Solidarity Through Modern Punishment, 51 HASTINGS L.J. 829 (2000); Jonathan<br />

Simon, Managing the Monstrous: Sex Offenders and the New Penology, 4 PSYCHOL,<br />

PUB., POL’Y & L. 452 (1998).<br />

236. For descriptions <strong>of</strong> the recent decades as an era <strong>of</strong> “sex panic” or “sex crimes panic,”<br />

see, for example, James E. Bristol III, Free Expression in Motion Pictures: Childhood<br />

Sexuality and a Satisfied Society, 25 CARDOZO ARTS &ENT. L.J. 333, 352 (2007) (describing<br />

“sex panic”); Rose Corrigan, Making Meaning <strong>of</strong> Megan’s <strong>Law</strong>, 31 LAW &SOC.INQUIRY 267,<br />

274 (2006) (describing “sex crimes ‘panic’ ”); Lisa Duggan, Sex Panics, in SEX WARS:<br />

SEXUAL DISSENT AND POLITICAL CULTURE 74 (Lisa Duggan & Nan D. Hunter eds., 1995)<br />

(describing “sex panic”). The term “sex panic” is at times used to refer to our heightened<br />

and exaggerated concerns over sex crimes but is more <strong>of</strong>ten used to refer to a more general<br />

cultural anxiety about sexual behavior that manifests itself not only in sex crimes legislation<br />

but also in laws relating to pornography, obscenity, and gender relations. Used in the<br />

latter sense, the term is more <strong>of</strong>ten used with reference to the 1990s than to the most recent<br />

years. Id.<br />

237. If, as posited here, the relevant distinction is between those who threaten others—<br />

particularly the vulnerable and most especially children—and those whose behavior mostly<br />

damages themselves, then the shape <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine legislation described above<br />

makes sense. As discussed in Part II supra, much <strong>of</strong> the state legislation in response to methamphetamine<br />

has been designed to prevent young people from becoming addicted or to


892 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

traumatize children, scraggly, frantic meth users might well appear<br />

more pathetic than dangerous. 238<br />

Efforts to import restrictions developed in the sex-<strong>of</strong>fender context<br />

to the meth content have gained little traction. Though some were initially<br />

excited by the idea <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine registries, 239 for example,<br />

few states have adopted them 240 and those that have adopted<br />

them provide less information about those convicted <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine<br />

<strong>of</strong>fenses than upon those convicted <strong>of</strong> even the most minor<br />

sex <strong>of</strong>fenses. 241 With regard to sexual <strong>of</strong>fense registries, there has<br />

been near constant political pressure for more—more states participating,<br />

more <strong>of</strong>fenses included, more information provided, more<br />

access for the public, and more restrictions on where persons convicted<br />

<strong>of</strong> sex <strong>of</strong>fenses can reside, work, and socialize. In contrast,<br />

meth registries, as they have developed in the few states that maintain<br />

them, are limited tools; lacking photographs or extensive search<br />

features, they serve as little more than free, limited background<br />

checks for potential landlords, employers, and home buyers.<br />

4. Personal Responsibility as Political Focus<br />

The idea <strong>of</strong> being responsible for one’s own person, decisions, and<br />

fate is hardly novel. 242 The mobilization <strong>of</strong> this concept politically,<br />

protect third parties from explosions and other environmental harms resulting from drug<br />

manufacturing. As discussed in Part III.B supra, situations in which children are harmed<br />

or threatened is the one area in which legislators have been quick to add new criminal laws<br />

and penalties related to methamphetamine.<br />

238. For characterizations <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine users that emphasize their pathetic<br />

plight, see supra note 213 and sources cited therein.<br />

239. Representative Mike Coan, who introduced legislation to create a methamphetamine<br />

<strong>of</strong>fender registry in Georgia, argued that “[t]he registry is necessary because the production,<br />

distribution and use <strong>of</strong> this powerful street drug is the source <strong>of</strong> so much crime,<br />

ranging from robbery, theft, forgery, child abuse and neglect to a host <strong>of</strong> violent <strong>of</strong>fenses.”<br />

Mike Coan, My View: Registry for Meth Offenders Would Protect Residents—Metro Atlanta<br />

Area a Major Hub for Trafficking, ATLANTA J. CONST., Feb. 12, 2006 at JJ4. He focused<br />

specifically on the effects <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine <strong>of</strong>fenses on children, writing that “[j]ust as<br />

sex <strong>of</strong>fenders do irreparable harm to children, meth abusers also harm innocent children.<br />

The addiction to this street drug is so powerful that addicts neglect their families, spend all<br />

their wages buying meth and behave extremely erratically, sometimes abusing children<br />

and spouses.” Id. With a methamphetamine registry, “neighbors can watch for suspicious<br />

activities,” arguing that “[i]nformation is power, and when residents have the ability to<br />

find out who lives in their community—whether it is a sex <strong>of</strong>fender or a meth <strong>of</strong>fender—<br />

they can make better decisions about how they live their lives.” Id. Comparing persons<br />

convicted <strong>of</strong> sex crimes to persons convicted <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine <strong>of</strong>fenses, “we must now<br />

take the same steps to ‘out’ <strong>of</strong>fenders who bring this dangerous drug into our communities.”<br />

Id.<br />

240. See supra notes 149-150 and accompanying text.<br />

241. See supra notes 146-148 and accompanying text.<br />

242. See generally Michael B. Brennan, Essay, The Lodestar <strong>of</strong> Personal Responsibility,<br />

88 MARQ. L.REV. 365 (2004) (discussing historical roots <strong>of</strong> “personal responsibility” as philosophy<br />

and observing how the principle is applied in law).


2010] METHADEMIC 893<br />

however, has gained significant traction in recent years. 243 This sort<br />

<strong>of</strong> libertarian impulse perhaps explains some <strong>of</strong> the legal developments<br />

we have seen with respect to methamphetamine. The changes<br />

that legislatures have made that increase criminal penalties for methamphetamine<br />

<strong>of</strong>fenses generally focus on protecting “innocent”<br />

persons who have not made bad decisions and who are not in a position<br />

to protect themselves. 244 This may explain why legislatures have<br />

enacted lengthier sentences primarily where persons associated with<br />

methamphetamine expose others to the dangers <strong>of</strong> their activities:<br />

nonmethamphetamine producers do not make intrinsically bad decisions<br />

by having next-door neighbors or purchasing homes, and children<br />

are not making poor decisions when they are raised by methamphetamine<br />

producers. The language <strong>of</strong> self-sufficiency and personal<br />

responsibility in fact can be found directly in press releases supporting<br />

these legislative changes. 245 This focus may explain why, even if<br />

reducing domestic production were to do little to reduce addiction,<br />

curtailing the number <strong>of</strong> mom-and-pop methamphetamine labs would<br />

comprise success: shutting down local methamphetamine labs, even<br />

if it does nothing to stem the influx <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine into communities<br />

or the use <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine by addicts, will be help protect<br />

innocents from explosions and toxic chemicals. 246<br />

This explanation, like others, cannot be fully explanatory: legislatures<br />

are not ignoring the plight <strong>of</strong> addicts, but rather are allocating<br />

significant funding to educate potential users about the dangers <strong>of</strong><br />

methamphetamine and to rehabilitate users through drug courts,<br />

methamphetamine prisons, and other treatment programs. 247 Still, to<br />

the extent that the way in which we have been recognizing and dealing<br />

with “serious” social problems has been by ratcheting up criminal<br />

penalties, it is possible to view recent legislative responses to me-<br />

243. For example, the controversial 1996 law that, depending on your perspective, either<br />

reformed or eliminated welfare was entitled the “Personal Responsibility and Work<br />

Opportunity Reconciliation Act <strong>of</strong> 1996.” See Pub. L. No.104-193, 110 Stat. 2105 (codified at<br />

42 U.S.C. 1305).In 1999, then-Senator John D. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t similarly lauded Clarence Thomas<br />

for the extent to which he promotes in his public life notions <strong>of</strong> personal responsibility.<br />

John D. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t, Justice Clarence Thomas: Reviving Restraint and Personal Responsibility,<br />

12 REGENT U. L. REV. 313, 315 (1999).<br />

244. See generally Parts III.B and IV supra (exploring areas in which legislatures have<br />

chosen to focus their energies in regulating methamphetamine, including prevention, environmental<br />

remediation, and child protection).<br />

245. In explaining his support <strong>of</strong> legislation to provide grant money to states to establish<br />

programs to assist methamphetamine-exposed children, for example, Representative<br />

Zach Wamp argued that the legislation would give the children “the helping hand they<br />

need to begin climbing the ladder <strong>of</strong> life and have an opportunity at the American dream <strong>of</strong><br />

self-sufficiency.” Meth-Endangered Children to Benefit from New Grant Program, supra<br />

note 161.<br />

246. An assistant United <strong>State</strong>s Attorney in the Eastern District <strong>of</strong> Missouri<br />

commented, “Let the Mexicans have the meth trade. . . . We’ll have done a great thing if we<br />

take pseudoephedrine out <strong>of</strong> the game.” Schone, supra note 129, at 36.<br />

247. See supra Parts III.B(5)-(6).


894 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

thamphetamine as signaling that while the government will still be<br />

heavily punitive if that is necessary to protect innocent citizens, noninnocents<br />

who themselves ingest methamphetamine or are exposed<br />

to the hazards <strong>of</strong> their own methamphetamine production can be left<br />

to deal with the consequences <strong>of</strong> their own choices.<br />

5. Privatizing/Outsourcing<br />

Another possible explanation for current approaches to drug policy<br />

is the vogue for privatization and outsourcing—taking traditional<br />

government functions and committing them to private entities. 248<br />

Pseudoephedrine purchase restrictions place the burden for reducing<br />

methamphetamine production on private actors who have incentive<br />

for compliance. Police <strong>of</strong>ficers have less need to spend precious taxdollars<br />

to root out methamphetamine labs in far-flung rural houses.<br />

Instead, drugstore personnel check identification, maintain registries<br />

<strong>of</strong> purchasers, refuse pr<strong>of</strong>it-making purchases as required, and<br />

shelve pseudoephedrine inaccessibly or in view <strong>of</strong> surveillance mechanisms,<br />

all <strong>of</strong> which represent enforcement costs placed on business<br />

rather than on taxpayers. 249 In general, governments have<br />

shown a desire to privatize the cost <strong>of</strong> anti-methamphetamine programs,<br />

in some cases shifting primary responsibility for such programs<br />

to privately financed campaigns 250 and in at least one case<br />

seeking to finance the cost <strong>of</strong> drug treatment programs through the<br />

sale <strong>of</strong> special anti-methamphetamine license plates. 251<br />

The “outsourcing” <strong>of</strong> drug restrictions to private industry has<br />

precedent. The first rounds <strong>of</strong> drug legislation, as described above, 252<br />

looked similar to methamphetamine precursor restrictions in that<br />

they were civil requirements placed on doctors and pharmacists to<br />

restrict distribution <strong>of</strong> possibly dangerous drugs. Even after the primary<br />

approach to drug abuse became criminalization and imprisonment,<br />

private enterprise was considered a possible means for reducing<br />

drug use. During the late 1980s, for example, the Reagan administration<br />

encouraged private employers to drug test employees in an<br />

effort to fight the “War on Drugs.” 253 Placing such efforts at the center<br />

248. On the trend toward privatization <strong>of</strong> government functions, see, e.g., Abraham<br />

Bell, Private Takings, 76 U. CHI.L.REV. 517, 576 (2009) (“The much-noted current trend in<br />

public administration is toward privatization <strong>of</strong> public functions.”); Jody Freeman, Extending<br />

Public <strong>Law</strong> Norms Through Privatization, 116 HARV.L.REV. 1285, 1291-92 (2003) (noting<br />

the trend towards privatization in recent decades).<br />

249. See Part III.B(1) supra.<br />

250. See, e.g., supra note 178 (discussing one such organization, the Montana Meth Project).<br />

251. Minnesota Roundup, GRAND FORKS HERALD, Dec. 17, 2005, available at 2005<br />

WLNR 20363759.<br />

252. See Supra Part II.A(2).<br />

253. See Larry Martz et al., Trying to Say ‘No,’ NEWSWEEK, Aug. 11, 1986, at 14 (noting<br />

that then-president Ronald Reagan’s proposals for discouraging drug use included


2010] METHADEMIC 895<br />

<strong>of</strong> new drug policy is, however, something we have not seen during<br />

the last several rounds <strong>of</strong> drug panic. Perhaps what we are seeing is,<br />

at least in part, an effort on the part <strong>of</strong> legislators to find ways to reduce<br />

the harms <strong>of</strong> illicit drugs while placing the responsibility for enforcing<br />

new laws primarily upon private parties.<br />

B. An Age <strong>of</strong> Ambivalence<br />

Though many <strong>of</strong> these theories provide compelling partial explanations<br />

for the response to methamphetamine, even stitched together<br />

they fail to provide a complete explanation. While methamphetamine<br />

users may have benefited from the perception that theirs was a<br />

“white drug,” the prevalence <strong>of</strong> news stories about Native-American<br />

meth users and Mexican meth merchants have <strong>of</strong>fered levers if the<br />

culture was intent on racializing the drug; 254 moreover, poor rural<br />

whites are not exactly the kind <strong>of</strong> powerful group that can be confident<br />

in its immunity from social scapegoating. Similarly, while media<br />

portrayals <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine users have certainly been more empathetic<br />

than portraits <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine users, 255 they have not shied<br />

away from blaming meth users for a myriad <strong>of</strong> social problems, <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

portraying those problems in the most hyperbolic terms. 256 While legislatures<br />

may have been distracted by our cultural panic against sexually<br />

violent <strong>of</strong>fenders, 257 history is full <strong>of</strong> eras in which drug and sex<br />

panics coexisted or even mutually reinforced each other. 258 Finally,<br />

while the increasing popularity <strong>of</strong> arguments focusing on individual<br />

responsibility and the benefits <strong>of</strong> privatization may well have played<br />

some role in convincing legislators and voters to approve some particular<br />

pieces <strong>of</strong> anti-methamphetamine legislation, 259 there is no evidence<br />

that the content <strong>of</strong> the legislation was shaped by these—or any<br />

other—big ideas.<br />

What the legislative responses (and nonresponses) to methamphetamine<br />

cataloged in this Article reveal more than anything is an undercurrent<br />

<strong>of</strong> ambivalence about current drug policy. In an undertheorized,<br />

semi-rational way, legislators and citizens responding to<br />

methamphetamine were simply less persuaded by the drumbeat <strong>of</strong><br />

panic than they were in other recent episodes. While they spoke loud-<br />

requiring certain federal workers to be drug tested, <strong>of</strong>fering federal contractors incentives<br />

to drug test, and generally encouraging private businesses to drug test employees).<br />

254. See sources cited supra notes 211 & 217.<br />

255. See supra note 213 and sources cited therein.<br />

256. See supra note 219-230 and accompanying text.<br />

257. See supra Part V.A(3).<br />

258. For example, the recent crack cocaine panic overlapped with the beginning <strong>of</strong> the<br />

modern sex crimes panic. See also supra Part II.A(2) (explaining how cocaine panic <strong>of</strong> the<br />

1930s was fueled, in part, by fears <strong>of</strong> African-American men raping white women).<br />

259. See supra Part V.A(4).


896 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

ly and acted swiftly against methamphetamine, their response was<br />

more muted and, on the whole, less punitive.<br />

A string <strong>of</strong> developments since 2005 support this diagnosis <strong>of</strong> ambivalence.<br />

In recent years, both state legislatures and the United <strong>State</strong>s<br />

Sentencing Commission have taken steps to lower crack cocaine sentences<br />

in response to longstanding racial equity concerns, 260 the Supreme<br />

Court has granted trial judges freedom to reject hefty crack cocaine<br />

sentences on policy grounds, 261 and Congress has moved ever<br />

closer to abolishing the crack/powder sentencing disparities altogether.<br />

262 Meanwhile, in a move both symbolic and substantive, New York<br />

has drastically reworked its infamously draconian Rockefeller Drug<br />

<strong>Law</strong>s, 263 while other states have taken similar steps to scale back on<br />

mandatory minimum sentences. 264 Voters in nine states in eleven<br />

years have voted to approve initiatives and referenda decriminalizing<br />

medical marijuana. 265 Through this all, drug courts and other forms <strong>of</strong><br />

alternative sanctions have quietly established a foothold in nearly<br />

every jurisdiction. 266 Finally, in early 2009, the White House announced<br />

that the federal government would no longer utilize the term<br />

260. For the federal developments, see Cassidy, supra note 10, at 125 & n.176 (detailing<br />

Commission amendments and Congressional inaction that allowed amendments to<br />

pass into law). For one representative state development, see supra note 216 (detailing<br />

change in South Carolina law).<br />

261. See Kimbrough v. United <strong>State</strong>s, 552 U.S. 85 (2007) (allowing judges discretion to<br />

sentence individuals convicted <strong>of</strong> crack cocaine crimes to lesser terms based on judges’ personal<br />

disapproval <strong>of</strong> crack/powder disparity).<br />

262. For informed speculation that the disparities may finally be repealed this year,<br />

see Emery, supra note 15. For a list <strong>of</strong> recent or pending bills proposing to reduce the disparity<br />

or eliminate it entirely, see Cassidy, supra note 10, at 133 n.231. Interestingly, all<br />

the legislation now being considered either lowers crack sentences to the levels that currently<br />

apply to powder cocaine, lowers crack sentences part <strong>of</strong> the way towards current<br />

powder cocaine sentences, or sets new sentences for both crack and powder cocaine that are<br />

less severe than the current crack sentences. The direction <strong>of</strong> sentencing reform also reflects<br />

changing times. Cf. Marc Mauer, Race, Drug <strong>Law</strong>s, & Criminal Justice, 10 TEMP.<br />

POL. &CIV. RTS. L. REV. 321, 325 (2001) (noting that, at that time, efforts to equalize<br />

powder cocaine and crack cocaine sentences were taking the form <strong>of</strong> legislation that “basically<br />

says, ‘You want to equalize penalties, we can do that. We will increase the penalties<br />

for powder cocaine and put even more people in prison’ ”).<br />

263. For some <strong>of</strong> the first such changes, see Ehlers, supra note 132, at 58. For the<br />

more recent and drastic changes, see Jeremy W. Peters, Albany Reaches Deal to Repeal ‘70s<br />

Drug <strong>Law</strong>s, N.Y. TIMES., Mar. 26, 2009, at A1.<br />

264. In New Jersey, for example, the <strong>State</strong> Assembly recently adopted a bill to eliminate<br />

the <strong>State</strong>’s strict mandatory minimum sentences for drug crimes committed in school<br />

zones (though the <strong>State</strong> Senate has thus far declined to act). See N.J. Assem. B. 2762,<br />

213th Legislature, introduced May 19, 2008 (permitting judges to place a defendant on<br />

probation or to waive the minimum term <strong>of</strong> parole eligibility after consideration <strong>of</strong> the defendant’s<br />

prior record, the specific location <strong>of</strong> the drug <strong>of</strong>fense, whether or not school was in<br />

session at the time <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>fense, and whether or not children were present in the area <strong>of</strong><br />

the <strong>of</strong>fense).<br />

265. See Brown, supra note 1, at 243-44 (reporting this fact, though noting that this<br />

trend towards decriminalization <strong>of</strong> medical marijuana may be constrained by Gonzales v.<br />

Raich, 545 U.S. 1 (2005)).<br />

266. See generally Miller, supra note 169.


2010] METHADEMIC 897<br />

“War on Drugs,” retiring a divisive and militaristic locution that has<br />

been a flashpoint in the cultural struggle over drug policy. 267<br />

If our instincts about drug regulation are now more ambivalent<br />

and our policies more balanced, perhaps we have learned something<br />

from prior panics. With regard to methamphetamine in particular,<br />

study, scholarship, and activism surrounding the response to crack<br />

cocaine may have paid dividends in calming the waters during the<br />

early days <strong>of</strong> the meth panic. For example, when the predictable<br />

“meth baby” headlines surfaced during 2005, warning <strong>of</strong> an epidemic<br />

<strong>of</strong> new methamphetamine-addicted and damaged infants, 268 public<br />

health advocates were ready with a signed statement by ninety-two<br />

medical researchers and drug policy advocates arguing that “use <strong>of</strong><br />

stigmatizing terms, such as ‘ice babies’ and ‘meth babies,’ lack scientific<br />

validity and should not be used” noting that “[e]xperience with<br />

similar labels applied to children exposed parentally to cocaine” had<br />

impaired efforts to develop policies and treatments appropriate for<br />

cocaine-exposed children. 269 Similarly, when major news sources like<br />

Newsweek and The Oregonian <strong>of</strong>fered sensationalized account <strong>of</strong> an<br />

emerging methademic, investigative journalists and media critics<br />

were quick to question their unverifiable factual claims and intentionally<br />

inflammatory language. 270 It is now increasingly common for<br />

politicians to convene hearings or summits to evaluate, in a systematic<br />

way, the efficacy <strong>of</strong> the heavily punitive antidrug measures on<br />

which we have been relying. 271<br />

To take a less sanguine view, perhaps it is money that is driving<br />

our newfound ambivalence. In 1986, then-Democratic congressional<br />

campaign chair Tony Coehlo said that Congressional representatives<br />

“intend to bust the budget” on the War on Drugs, which he meant as<br />

a positive sign <strong>of</strong> commitment to eradicating drug abuse. 272 In con-<br />

267. See Fields, supra note 15.<br />

268. See, e.g., Christine Lagorio, Generation <strong>of</strong> Meth Babies: Heartland Doctors and<br />

Programs Help Meth-Addict Moms Cope, CBS NEWS, Apr. 28, 2005, http://<br />

www.cbsnews.com/stories/2005/04/28/eveningnews/main691764.shtml; Bennett & Williams,<br />

supra note 213 (quoting a doctor describing babies born to methamphetamine using<br />

mothers as “worse than crack babies”).<br />

269. Letter from Donald G. Miller to Whom It May Concern (July 27, 2005), <strong>General</strong><br />

Media Letter on “Meth Babies” and “Ice Babies,” available at http://www.jointogether.org/<br />

resources/pdf/Meth_Letter.pdf.<br />

270. See, e.g., Shafer, Meth-Mouth Myth, in SLATE, supra note 107; Shafer, in SLATE,<br />

Meth Madness, supra note 110; Valdez, supra note 231.<br />

271. See, e.g., David Lerman, Webb Urges Fresh Look at the War on Drugs, DAILY<br />

PRESS , June 20, 2008, at A2 (describing hearing by Joint Economic Committee convened<br />

by Senator Jim Webb to hear testimony from scholars and prosecutors who argue that incarceration<br />

has been costly and ineffective as a remedy for drug addiction); Diana Heil,<br />

Meth Use Claims 56 Lives, THE SANTA FE NEW MEXICAN, Oct. 28, 2005, at C-1 (describing<br />

drug summit convened by <strong>State</strong> Drug Czar that recommended primarily treatment, prevention,<br />

and environmental remediation efforts).<br />

272. Martz et al., supra note 253, at 14. According to Congressional representatives at<br />

the time, money would be no object in fighting the war on drugs. Id.


898 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841<br />

trast, budgetary and space constraints make increased incarceration<br />

less appealing in the 2000s. 273 For more than a decade, advocates and<br />

scholars have been pointing to the budget-breaking cost <strong>of</strong> mass incarceration<br />

policies. 274 The serious economic crisis that has engulfed<br />

this nation in the last two years may have forced states to take notice.<br />

Certainly, it is impossible to open a newspaper without reading<br />

a story about the devastating state <strong>of</strong> particular state budgets. 275 In<br />

almost every instance, coverage <strong>of</strong> state budge woes discusses either<br />

the role that prison costs have played in driving up state expenditures<br />

or proposed cuts to prison budgets or both. 276 In a time <strong>of</strong> belttightening<br />

and tough choices, spending tens <strong>of</strong> thousands <strong>of</strong> dollars a<br />

year to express your moral indignity towards a particular individual<br />

might, to some, come to seem an emotional extravagance.<br />

VI. CONCLUSION<br />

What if they threw a drug panic and nobody came?<br />

While the media, public, and legislatures clearly have identified<br />

methamphetamine use and production as a serious issue worthy <strong>of</strong> attention<br />

and concern, and while hyperbolic anecdotes and naturaldisaster<br />

analogies have worked their way into discourse, they have not<br />

leveraged a concomitantly hyperbolic criminal sanctions response.<br />

While we have seen criminal sanctions expand and increase<br />

somewhat in response to methamphetamine, and we have in particular<br />

seen movement to protect children and to authorize police to<br />

search with less preclearance and restriction, 277 the legislative response<br />

has focused on prevention, via restrictions on precursor purchases<br />

and education <strong>of</strong> potential users. 278 The focus <strong>of</strong> legislative<br />

change has been primarily on making it difficult for people to produce<br />

methamphetamine and protecting “innocents” from either trying the<br />

drug or being exposed to substances that are volatile and toxic.<br />

Certainly, the racial differences between methamphetamine users/producers<br />

and public perceptions <strong>of</strong>, for example, crack cocaine<br />

users/sellers can work to explain the differences between the choice<br />

273. See, e.g., Schone, supra note 129, at 32-33 (noting that Missouri’s state budget is<br />

strained, prison beds are filled, and the state lacks both funds and cells to incarcerate<br />

methamphetamine users and producers).<br />

274. See, e.g., id.<br />

275. See, e.g., Solomon Moore, California <strong>State</strong> Assembly Approves Prison Legislation, N.Y.<br />

TIMES, Sept. 1, 2009, at A19 (reporting on legislation dealing with California budget crisis).<br />

276. See, e.g. id. (reporting that the California Assembly passed a bill that will cut the<br />

state prison population by about 27,000 inmates, saving about one billion dollars per year).<br />

Underscoring that this is an age <strong>of</strong> ambivalence about drug policy, not an age <strong>of</strong> retreat,<br />

the article points out that the <strong>State</strong> Senate passed an even bolder bill but that, after extensive<br />

lobbying, the Assembly balked at the broader cuts. See id.<br />

277. See generally supra Part IV.<br />

278. See generally supra Part III.


2010] METHADEMIC 899<br />

to primarily control methamphetamine through limiting pseudoephedrine<br />

purchases and the choice to control crack cocaine through<br />

lengthy and mandatory prison terms. 279 As methamphetamine supply<br />

shifts to importation rather than mom-and-pop production, and as<br />

that importation is linked to Hispanic importers and illegal immigration,<br />

we may see the extent to which race and ethnicity drive legislative<br />

action; under the social group theory, 280 we will expect to see methamphetamine<br />

sanctions rise dramatically, and time will tell<br />

whether or not the prevention-education-personal regulation model is<br />

transitory or trend.<br />

In the meantime, the United <strong>State</strong>s appears to have entered a period<br />

in which the appetite for increased drug-related penalties has<br />

waned. 281 In part, this may be because <strong>of</strong> increased panic about violent<br />

crime, particularly sex <strong>of</strong>fenses against children; it may stem<br />

from norm shifts that encourage “personal responsibility” and privatization;<br />

or it may reflect, related to all <strong>of</strong> these theories, tight government<br />

budgets and a governmental desire to craft programs that<br />

cost little and place the onus on private parties to resolve social problems.<br />

In general, legislators and citizens seem more ambivalent<br />

about the ability <strong>of</strong> incarceration to address the problems associated<br />

with substance use and abuse, and willing to examine strategies that<br />

place less emphasis on costly prison programs and more emphasis on<br />

private industry and individual will.<br />

Is this a positive shift? The efficacy <strong>of</strong> methamphetamine responses<br />

remains to be seen. The general shift in focus from criminal<br />

punishment to education, alternatives to incarceration, and precursor<br />

control may be good news for foes <strong>of</strong> mass incarceration, and might<br />

represent a rational, evidence-based approach to a substance that inarguably<br />

has ill effects. Or perhaps it simply represents a damning <strong>of</strong><br />

expectations, some measure <strong>of</strong> fiscal austerity and economic reality<br />

as applied to government policy. Either way, I argue that what the<br />

response to methamphetamine has shown us is that we have entered<br />

an age <strong>of</strong> ambivalence—one where we are less certain that harsh<br />

criminal sanctions are the solution to social problems, and one where<br />

we are open to alternatives.<br />

279. See supra Part V.A(1).<br />

280. See supra note 19-20 and accompanying text.<br />

281. See supra Part V.B.


900 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:841


PEARSON, IQBAL, AND PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL<br />

ACTIVISM<br />

GOUTAM U. JOIS *<br />

ABSTRACT<br />

In its most recent term, the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> the United <strong>State</strong>s decided Pearson v. Callahan<br />

and Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal, two cases that, even at this early date, can safely be called<br />

“game changers.” What is fairly well known is that Iqbal and Pearson, on their own terms,<br />

will hurt civil rights plaintiffs. A point that has not been explored is how the interaction between<br />

Iqbal and Pearson will also hurt civil rights plaintiffs. First, the cases threaten to<br />

catch plaintiffs on the horns <strong>of</strong> a dilemma. Iqbal says, in effect, that greater detail is required<br />

to get allegations past the motion to dismiss stage. But a plaintiff who says too much<br />

at the pleading stage risks getting kicked out by Pearson; if the allegations are very specific,<br />

a court (deciding qualified immunity) will conclude that the constitutional right, if any, is<br />

so specific as not to be clearly established. If the litigant pleads at a level <strong>of</strong> generality to<br />

avoid the “clearly established” problem, he will get tripped up by Iqbal because the allegations<br />

will be deemed “conclusory” or too general to be “plausible.”<br />

Iqbal and Pearson also take divergent tacks with regard to the role <strong>of</strong> lower courts. In<br />

Pearson, lower courts are entrusted to decide which step <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity to decide<br />

first. Iqbal also expands courts’ authority by empowering them to determine “plausibility”<br />

based on their “common sense.” But at the same time, Iqbal takes away the district court’s<br />

ability to manage litigation (by using procedures explicitly provided in the Federal Rules<br />

and previously approved by the U.S. Supreme Court) in order to shield public <strong>of</strong>ficials, relying<br />

instead on the rather blunt instrument <strong>of</strong> dismissing the case entirely. The cases expand<br />

and restrict lower courts’ discretion, but only do so in a way that makes it easier to dismiss<br />

civil rights lawsuits. Pearson and Iqbal exemplify what I call “procedural judicial activism”:<br />

the invention <strong>of</strong> procedural rules to significantly curtail the availability <strong>of</strong> remedies in<br />

civil litigation, especially in the context <strong>of</strong> civil rights claims.<br />

In short, although Pearson and Iqbal are thought <strong>of</strong> as affecting different, and distinct,<br />

areas <strong>of</strong> law, they interact in ways that are detrimental to civil rights plaintiffs and, ultimately,<br />

all <strong>of</strong> us. This interaction was not addressed by the Court in either case, nor has it<br />

been recognized in the academic literature thus far.<br />

I. INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................. 902<br />

II. PEARSON AND IQBAL ......................................................................................... 907<br />

A. Pearson v. Callahan ................................................................................... 907<br />

B. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal ......................................................................................... 915<br />

III. HOW THE CASES HURT CIVIL RIGHTS PLAINTIFFS ............................................ 920<br />

A. The Obvious ............................................................................................... 921<br />

B. The Less Obvious ....................................................................................... 925<br />

1. The Horns <strong>of</strong> a Dilemma ...................................................................... 925<br />

2. Discretion that Only Cuts One Way ..................................................... 930<br />

C. So What? The Case Against Procedural Activism ..................................... 937<br />

IV. CONCLUSION ..................................................................................................... 942<br />

* J.D., Harvard, 2007; A.B., 2003, M.P.P., 2004, Georgetown. gjois@post.harvard.edu. I<br />

have received helpful comments and feedback at various stages <strong>of</strong> this project from Martha<br />

Field, Paul Pineau, Alexander Reinert, and Erez Reuveni. I have benefitted from the work <strong>of</strong><br />

two excellent research assistants, Debbie Chung and James Partridge. As always, thanks to my<br />

parents, Umesh and Indira; my sisters, Malasa and Mallika; and my wife, Elizabeth, for continued<br />

love and support. Any perceived errors are mine.


902 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

I. Introduction<br />

On the first day <strong>of</strong> Civil Procedure, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Arthur Miller tells<br />

his students that they probably will not like the class at first because<br />

it seems alien:<br />

When you come to law school, your prior experience tells you<br />

something about torts, for example. You know what a tort is. You<br />

know what an accident is. . . . You know what contracts are; you’ve<br />

signed contracts and sometimes, maybe you’ve even broken contracts.<br />

But the truth is, nothing in your prior experience prepares you for<br />

civil procedure. . . . [Y]ou don’t know what a motion to dismiss is. You<br />

don’t know what res judicata is. You don’t know what judgment notwithstanding<br />

the verdict means. So it’s strange. The concepts are<br />

strange. They don't seem to have any value judgment to them, the<br />

way torts and criminal law are all about value judgments. 1<br />

That value-neutrality, <strong>of</strong> course, is an illusion; “as the year<br />

progresses, you begin to discover that there are value judgments that<br />

lie beneath the surface <strong>of</strong> each and every aspect <strong>of</strong> civil procedure.<br />

But it simply takes you a long time to understand that.” 2<br />

* * *<br />

Procedural rules never exist in a vacuum. At every stage <strong>of</strong> litigation,<br />

rules dictate who may bring suit, for what reasons, and under<br />

what circumstances. They tell us when the suit must be brought in<br />

which jurisdiction, and they tell us the reasons it can be dismissed.<br />

Procedural rules govern whether your case will be heard by a judge<br />

or a jury, whether it will go to trial or be decided on the papers, and<br />

whether you have the right to an immediate appeal. Procedural rules<br />

tell us who can be sued and who is immune from suit. They tell us<br />

whether immunity is absolute or qualified, and in what circumstances<br />

immunity may be overcome.<br />

It is probably obvious that the Federal Rules <strong>of</strong> Civil Procedure contain<br />

(no surprise here) the procedural rules that govern civil litigation.<br />

What might not be obvious is that thousands <strong>of</strong> pages <strong>of</strong> judge-made<br />

law dramatically affect who can bring a lawsuit, against whom, in<br />

what substantive areas, when, in which jurisdiction, and for what reason.<br />

These judge-made rules, though they have no basis in an authoritative<br />

text, get cloaked with the mantle <strong>of</strong> “neutrality”—precisely because<br />

the rules are “strange[; t]he concepts are strange[, and t]hey<br />

don’t seem to have any value judgment to them.” 3 Yet these rules<br />

(which, if we are being uncharitable, we might say are simply made up<br />

by judges) are no less binding than those rooted in authoritative texts.<br />

1. Arthur R. Miller, Civil Procedure: Sum and Substance Audio CD Series (1996).<br />

2. Id.<br />

3. Id.


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 903<br />

In 2009, the U.S. Supreme Court decided two cases that elaborate<br />

upon judge-made doctrines in the procedural areas <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity<br />

and pleading standards. In January, the Court ruled unanimously<br />

in Pearson v. Callahan 4 that the two-step sequential analysis<br />

for qualified immunity, as outlined in Saucier v. Katz, 5 was no<br />

longer mandatory. In Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal, 6 decided a few months later,<br />

the Court held district courts could dismiss cases if the nonconclusory<br />

allegations in the complaint did not make out an entitlement to relief<br />

that was “plausible” (which the Court helpfully told us, is more than<br />

“possible” but less than “probable”). 7 Lower courts are to make this<br />

determination on the basis <strong>of</strong> “common sense.” 8 These cases seem obscure,<br />

and they turn on rather dry questions <strong>of</strong> procedural law. But<br />

just like procedural rules in general, these cases embody very important<br />

value judgments. Unless revisited, they will work a disservice to<br />

our nation’s promise <strong>of</strong> permitting victims <strong>of</strong> civil rights violations to<br />

achieve redress through civil litigation.<br />

Pearson and Iqbal are problematic for three reasons. First, there<br />

is the obvious: Pearson makes it easier for lower courts to dismiss<br />

lawsuits against government <strong>of</strong>ficials, which makes it commensurately<br />

harder for a civil rights plaintiff to prevail. Similarly, Iqbal<br />

makes it easier for courts to dismiss lawsuits at the outset, once<br />

again making it harder for plaintiffs to get past a defendant’s motion<br />

to dismiss.<br />

However, there are at least two other, more subtle reasons why<br />

Pearson and Iqbal are problematic. First, the interaction between the<br />

two cases threatens to catch civil rights plaintiffs on the horns <strong>of</strong> a dilemma.<br />

The problem runs something like this: under Pearson, lower<br />

courts are permitted to skip to “step two” <strong>of</strong> the qualified immunity inquiry;<br />

courts may conclude that the <strong>of</strong>ficer-defendant is entitled to<br />

immunity, even if a constitutional right was violated, if such right was<br />

not “clearly established” at the time <strong>of</strong> the alleged violation. This formulation<br />

will deter plaintiffs from saying “too much” in their pleadings:<br />

if the right is seen as very narrowly described (say, the right to be<br />

free from a hostile racial educational environment caused by studenton-student<br />

racial harassment in a public school), 9 courts will reason<br />

that, even if such a right existed, it is so specific as not to be “clearly<br />

established.” To avoid this problem, plaintiffs might try pleading at a<br />

level <strong>of</strong> generality (say, the right to be free from racial discrimination).<br />

4. 129 S. Ct. 808 (2009).<br />

5. 533 U.S. 194 (2001).<br />

6. 129 S. Ct. 1937 (2009).<br />

7. Id. at 1949 (citing Bell Atlantic Corp. v. Twombly, 550 U.S. 544, 570 (2007)).<br />

8. Id. at 1950.<br />

9. See, e.g., DiStiso v. Town <strong>of</strong> Wolcott, 539 F. Supp. 2d 562, 567-68 (D. Conn. 2008),<br />

vacated, Disito v.Town <strong>of</strong> Wolcott, No. 08-1865-CV, 2009 WL 3652096 (2d Cir. Nov. 5, 2009).


904 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

But this runs the risk <strong>of</strong> having the complaint dismissed by Iqbal. Allegations<br />

pled at a level <strong>of</strong> generality could be deemed “conclusory” or<br />

not “plausible” and insufficiently specific to put the defendant on notice<br />

<strong>of</strong> the claim against him. Thence arises the dilemma: say too<br />

much, and you’ll lose based on Pearson; say too little, and you’ll lose<br />

based on Iqbal. I illustrate this problem with reference to recent district<br />

and appeals court cases, including a case study.<br />

The second problem is that the Pearson-Iqbal interaction simultaneously<br />

enlarges and restricts lower courts’ discretion—but does so in<br />

a way that hurts civil rights plaintiffs in either case. Pearson holds<br />

that a court may skip the constitutional violation question and hold<br />

against the plaintiff if the right is not clearly established. In this<br />

way, courts have greater discretion to find a basis for holding the <strong>of</strong>ficer<br />

immune. Relatedly, Iqbal gives district courts wide latitude to<br />

rely on their “common sense” and conclude that allegations in a complaint<br />

are not “plausible.” This increases the chances that a plaintiff’s<br />

complaint will be dismissed. But at the same time, Iqbal also cuts<br />

back lower courts’ discretion: for decades, it has been assumed that<br />

courts could use various mechanisms to control the process <strong>of</strong> litigation<br />

to shield government <strong>of</strong>ficials from undue pretrial burdens. Iqbal<br />

has effectively cut away this discretion, holding instead that in situations<br />

where a discretionary shaping <strong>of</strong> discovery or requiring further<br />

pleading from the plaintiff might have been appropriate, 10 the com-<br />

10. See, e.g., Crawford-El v. Britton, 523 U.S. 574, 597-601 (1998) (noting that, in<br />

qualified immunity cases, a court has at its disposal mechanisms provided by Federal<br />

Rules <strong>of</strong> Civil Procedure 7, 11, 12, and 26, as well as its broad discretion to manage discovery,<br />

to ensure that defendants are not unduly burdened). In this Article, I take it as a given<br />

that the Court’s current framework—that qualified immunity must protect the defendant<br />

from “unnecessary and burdensome discovery or trial proceedings,” id. at 598—must still<br />

inform any development in the doctrine.<br />

I leave aside the antecedent normative question <strong>of</strong> whether this is a worthwhile goal<br />

at all. I note, however, that even sovereign immunity, perhaps the broadest immunity <strong>of</strong><br />

them all, is only an immunity against money damages and not a wholesale immunity from<br />

the “burdens” <strong>of</strong> litigation. And the idea that the possibility <strong>of</strong> liability would be “peculiarly<br />

disruptive <strong>of</strong> effective government,” Harlow v. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. 800, 817 (1982), seems<br />

to have been more armchair philosophizing than an empirical conclusion. The only citation<br />

Harlow provided was to a concurring opinion by Judge Gerhard A. Gessell <strong>of</strong> the D.C. District<br />

Court, from when he was sitting by designation on the D.C. Circuit. See id. at 817 n.29<br />

(citing Halperin v. Kissinger, 606 F.2d 1192, 1214 (1979) (Gessell, J., concurring), aff’d in<br />

pertinent part by an equally divided Court, 452 U.S. 713 (1981)). And Judge Gessell’s opinion<br />

contains no citation whatsoever. At bottom, it is simply a call to raise the bar on civil<br />

rights plaintiffs: “In short, I urge a more exacting standard be placed on the showing a<br />

plaintiff must make before proceeding to trial in the face <strong>of</strong> a properly presented qualified<br />

immunity claim.” Halperin v. Kissinger, 606 F.2d at 1215 (Gessell, J., concurring). If the<br />

rationale behind the current qualified immunity doctrine is simply one district judge’s belief,<br />

thirty years ago, that “a more exacting standard [should] be placed on” civil rights<br />

plaintiffs, id., perhaps it is time to revisit the rationale.<br />

Some might argue that it was an “activist” decision that revivified § 1983 claims in<br />

the first place and that this activism required subsequent judicial action to properly define<br />

the boundaries <strong>of</strong> such claims. This may be true in the context <strong>of</strong> Bivens claims against


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 905<br />

plaint should instead be dismissed. In sum, whether by expanding or<br />

restricting district courts’ discretion, the Supreme Court has narrowed<br />

the universe <strong>of</strong> civil rights complaints that will proceed to the<br />

merits and ultimately succeed.<br />

Recent years have brought much talk <strong>of</strong> “judicial activism.” Political<br />

commentators, generally on the right, have successfully framed<br />

activism as the province <strong>of</strong> liberals—those who disregard the meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Constitution and tradition to limit capital punishment,<br />

grant “special status” to homosexuals, prohibit display <strong>of</strong> the Ten<br />

Commandments at school, and so on. 11 But one thing that Iqbal and<br />

Pearson make clear is that “activism,” at least as that term is popularly<br />

conceived, is not solely the province <strong>of</strong> liberals. Iqbal presented<br />

a departure from over seventy years’ understanding <strong>of</strong> the meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> Federal Rule <strong>of</strong> Civil Procedure 8(a)(2) and arguably conflicts with<br />

the plain language <strong>of</strong> the Federal Rules and long-standing case law.<br />

Pearson deviates from two decades <strong>of</strong> precedent and is part <strong>of</strong> a line<br />

<strong>of</strong> cases shielding government <strong>of</strong>ficials from liability, a notion that<br />

appears nowhere in the Constitution and that has never been described<br />

in congressional statutes. 12 Shrinking access to civil rights<br />

federal <strong>of</strong>ficers. See Bivens v. Six Unknown Named Agents, 403 U.S. 388 (1971). But it is<br />

clear that the plain language § 1983 contemplates personal liability:<br />

Every person who, under color <strong>of</strong> any statute, ordinance, regulation, custom, or<br />

usage, <strong>of</strong> any <strong>State</strong> or Territory or the District <strong>of</strong> Columbia, subjects, or causes<br />

to be subjected, any citizen <strong>of</strong> the United <strong>State</strong>s or other person within the jurisdiction<br />

there<strong>of</strong> to the deprivation <strong>of</strong> any rights, privileges, or immunities secured<br />

by the Constitution and laws, shall be liable to the party injured in an action<br />

at law, suit in equity, or other proper proceeding for redress, except that in<br />

any action brought against a judicial <strong>of</strong>ficer for an act or omission taken in such<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficer’s judicial capacity, injunctive relief shall not be granted unless a declaratory<br />

decree was violated or declaratory relief was unavailable.<br />

42 U.S.C. § 1983 (emphasis added).<br />

Thus, it is clear that § 1983: (1) contemplates personal liability; (2) provides a certain<br />

limitation on liability with regard to judicial <strong>of</strong>ficers; and (3) contains no other similar limitation<br />

or immunity. Judicially created immunity doctrines might have some purchase in<br />

the Bivens context, but they are less persuasive in the § 1983 context. Nonetheless, the two<br />

have typically been treated identically. See Butz v. Economou, 438 U.S. 478, 500-01 (1978).<br />

Butz is still good law. See Bunting v. Mellen, 541 U.S. 1019, 1022 (2004) (Scalia, J., dissenting)<br />

(describing the same two-step qualified immunity analysis in connection with §<br />

1983 claims and Bivens claims).<br />

11. See, e.g., Judicial Activism: the Biggest 2002 Election Issue, 36 THE PHYLLIS<br />

SCHLAFLY REPORT (Oct. 2002), http://www.eagleforum.org/psr/2002/oct02/psroct02.shtml.<br />

12. The phrase “qualified immunity” appears twice in the United <strong>State</strong>s Code. Of<br />

these, only one even indirectly addresses the qualified immunity doctrine as explicated by<br />

the Supreme Court. First, 6 U.S.C. § 1104(a) (2006) provides, in essence, that an individual<br />

who voluntarily reports suspected terrorist activity will not be liable for making such report<br />

unless he made the report knowing it to be false or with a reckless disregard from the<br />

truth. The statute goes on to specify that government <strong>of</strong>ficials who respond to such reports<br />

“shall have qualified immunity from civil liability for such action, consistent with applicable<br />

law in the relevant jurisdiction.” Id. § 1104(b)(1). However, the legislative history<br />

makes clear that the law was not intended “to amend, limit, or reduce existing qualified


906 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

remedies is no less “activist” merely because it happens under the<br />

guise <strong>of</strong> ostensibly neutral procedural rules.<br />

Iqbal is typically thought <strong>of</strong> as a case about pleading standards, 13<br />

and Pearson is typically thought <strong>of</strong> as a case about qualified immunity.<br />

14 Although these formulations are correct, my goal in this Article<br />

is to highlight the intersection <strong>of</strong>, and interaction between, these two<br />

cases. In so doing, I will demonstrate that Iqbal and Pearson are not<br />

only harmful to civil rights plaintiffs separately but also when taken<br />

together. 15 This Article is the first (in print or online) to explain this<br />

dilemma, awareness <strong>of</strong> which is <strong>of</strong> the utmost importance to attorneys<br />

litigating civil rights claims against government defendants.<br />

These insights are important from an academic perspective as<br />

well. The law <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity has been a muddle—and now, so<br />

is the law regarding pleading standards. Courts are inconsistent,<br />

both between circuits and among different panels <strong>of</strong> the same circuit,<br />

immunity or other defenses pursuant to Federal, <strong>State</strong>, or local law that may otherwise be<br />

available to authorized <strong>of</strong>ficials as defined by this section.” CONFERENCE REPORT ON H.R.<br />

1, IMPLEMENTING RECOMMENDATIONS OF THE 9/11 COMMISSION ACT OF 2007, 153 Cong.<br />

Rec. H8496-01, H8583 (Jul. 25, 2007). Thus, although § 1104 recognizes the defense <strong>of</strong><br />

qualified immunity, it does not define it in the statute, or even explicitly state that the doctrine<br />

should be applied as explicated by the courts. If Congress wanted to adopt the federal<br />

common law <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity, it could have done so explicitly. In several other contexts,<br />

Congress specifically leaves rules up to common law decisionmaking. See, e.g., 12<br />

U.S.C.A. § 2279aa-14(2) (“All civil actions to which the [Federal Agricultural Mortgage]<br />

Corporation is a party shall be deemed to arise under the laws <strong>of</strong> the United <strong>State</strong>s and, to<br />

the extent applicable, shall be deemed to be governed by Federal common law.”); 42 U.S.C.<br />

§ 1988(a) (providing that, in instances where the district courts do not have the power to<br />

fully vindicate civil rights claims, “the common law [subject to certain limitations] shall be<br />

extended to and govern the said courts in the trial and disposition <strong>of</strong> the cause . . . .”); FED.<br />

R. EVID. 501 (“Except as otherwise required . . . , the privilege <strong>of</strong> a witness, person, government,<br />

<strong>State</strong>, or political subdivision there<strong>of</strong> shall be governed by the principles <strong>of</strong> the<br />

common law as they may be interpreted by the courts <strong>of</strong> the United <strong>State</strong>s in the light <strong>of</strong><br />

reason and experience.”).<br />

The phrase also appears in 42 U.S.C. § 1320a-7c(a)(3)(B)(iii) (2006), which references<br />

the limitation on personal liability <strong>of</strong> government <strong>of</strong>ficials in a particular context. However,<br />

this statutory immunity, though described as “qualified immunity,” does not use the term<br />

in the sense that it is employed by the Supreme Court.<br />

13. See, e.g., Posting <strong>of</strong> Howard Wasserman to PrawfsBlawg, Iqbal and the Death <strong>of</strong><br />

Notice Pleading: Part I, at http://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/prawfsblawg/2009/05/iqbal-andthe-death-<strong>of</strong>-notice-pleading-part-i.html<br />

(May 18, 2009).<br />

14. See, e.g., Jack Ryan, United <strong>State</strong>s Supreme Court Changes Qualified Immunity<br />

Rules for Civil Rights <strong>Law</strong>suits Brought Against <strong>Law</strong> Enforcement Officers, PUBLIC<br />

AGENCY TRAINING COUNCIL, January 21, 2009, http://www.patc.com/weeklyarticles/<br />

qualified_immunity_pearson_v_callahan.shtml.<br />

15. It is true that Iqbal applies to all civil actions, not just civil rights claims. But Iqbal<br />

itself noted that the concerns that motivated moving to a higher, plausibility standard<br />

in civil litigation were especially acute in the civil rights context. See 129 S. Ct. at 1953.<br />

Indeed, Judge Posner believes that Iqbal may even be limited to that context. See infra,<br />

note 19 and accompanying text. Thus, whatever the scope <strong>of</strong> Iqbal, it is clear that it has its<br />

greatest force in the civil rights context.


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 907<br />

as to the precise test for qualified immunity. 16 The lower courts cited<br />

Iqbal more than 500 times in the two months after the decision was<br />

handed down, 17 but there is disagreement as to the meaning <strong>of</strong> the<br />

new case. Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg believes the Iqbal “ ‘majority<br />

messed up the federal rules’ governing civil litigation.” 18 Judge Richard<br />

A. Posner <strong>of</strong> the Seventh Circuit, however, believes Iqbal is<br />

“special in its own way” and perhaps limited to the context <strong>of</strong> civil<br />

rights claims against high government <strong>of</strong>ficials or in complex cases. 19<br />

The same divide—between those who think Iqbal is far-reaching and<br />

those who believe it is limited in application—exists in the commentary<br />

about the case. 20<br />

Thus, in addition to explaining the problem posed by the Pearson-<br />

Iqbal interaction, this Article will contribute to the still-evolving discourse<br />

on the precise contours and meaning <strong>of</strong> these areas <strong>of</strong> law.<br />

II. PEARSON AND IQBAL<br />

In this Part, I provide a brief overview <strong>of</strong> the relevant aspects <strong>of</strong><br />

Pearson and Iqbal. In these sections, I will also discuss the development<br />

<strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity and pleading standards, respectively.<br />

This discussion is not intended to be exhaustive. Rather,<br />

my goal is to provide sufficient background to illuminate the discussion<br />

in this Part and the thesis I advance in Part III.<br />

A. Pearson v. Callahan<br />

In Saucier v. Katz, 21 the Supreme Court directed lower courts to<br />

conduct a two-step, ordinal inquiry with regard to qualified immunity.<br />

First, courts were to determine whether the facts pled, shown,<br />

16. Compare Higazy v. Templeton, 505 F.3d 161, 169 n.8 (2d Cir. 2007) (“To rule on the<br />

issue <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity, this Court generally proceeds in two steps.”) with Harhay v.<br />

Town <strong>of</strong> Ellington Bd. <strong>of</strong> Educ., 323 F.3d 206, 211 (2d Cir. 2003) (“Our analysis <strong>of</strong> a qualified<br />

immunity claim consists <strong>of</strong> a three step inquiry.”). This inconsistency—two steps versus three<br />

steps—is or has been present in cases in at least the First, Second, Third, Sixth, Ninth, Tenth<br />

and Eleventh Circuits. I address this problem in a forthcoming article, “An Additional Hurdle”:<br />

How the Circuit Courts Messed Up Qualified Immunity (on file with author).<br />

17. Adam Liptak, 9/11 Case Could Bring Broad Shift on Civil Suits, N.Y. TIMES, Jul.<br />

21, 2009, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2009/07/21/us/21bar.html?_r=1.<br />

18. Id.<br />

19. See Smith v. Duffey, 576 F.3d 336, 340 (7th Cir. 2009).<br />

20. Compare Kevin M. Clermont & Stephen C. Yeazell, Inventing Tests, Destabilizing Systems,<br />

95 IOWA L. REV. 821, 823 (2010) (“The headline need no longer equivocate. . . . [Bell Atlantic<br />

Corp. v. Twombly, 550 U.S. 544 (2007), and Iqbal] have destabilized the entire system <strong>of</strong> civil<br />

litigation.”) with Maxwell S. Kennerly, Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal: Not Nearly As Important As You Think,<br />

http://www.litigationandtrial.com/2009/06/articles/the-law/for-lawyers/ashcr<strong>of</strong>t-v-iqbal-notnearly-as-important-as-you-think/<br />

(last visited Aug. 27, 2010) (suggesting that Iqbal should be<br />

limited to Bivens claims against high-ranking government <strong>of</strong>ficials).<br />

21. 533 U.S. 194 (2001).


908 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

or found (depending on the stage <strong>of</strong> litigation) made out a constitutional<br />

violation.<br />

In the course <strong>of</strong> determining whether a constitutional right was violated<br />

on the premises alleged, a court might find it necessary to<br />

set forth principles which will become the basis for a holding that a<br />

right is clearly established. This is the process for the law’s elaboration<br />

from case to case, and it is one reason for our insisting upon<br />

turning to the existence or nonexistence <strong>of</strong> a constitutional right as<br />

the first inquiry. 22<br />

If, and only if, a court answers this question in the affirmative, it is<br />

to proceed to the second step <strong>of</strong> the analysis: “if a violation could be<br />

made out on a favorable view <strong>of</strong> the parties’ submissions, the next,<br />

sequential step is to ask whether the right was clearly established.” 23<br />

Fully understanding how we got to Saucier, however, requires a bit <strong>of</strong><br />

background on the nature <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity in general.<br />

When a state <strong>of</strong>ficial’s conduct causes the deprivation <strong>of</strong> an individual’s<br />

constitutional rights, 42 U.S.C. § 1983 enables the victim to<br />

bring a damages claim against the <strong>of</strong>ficial in the <strong>of</strong>ficer’s personal capacity,<br />

i.e., in a suit against the <strong>of</strong>ficial himself, not the state government<br />

or agency. Although § 1983 had formally been on the books<br />

since 1871, its potential was not fully exploited until after the Supreme<br />

Court’s decision in Monroe v. Pape. 24 Ten years later, Bivens v.<br />

Six Unknown Named Agents <strong>of</strong> the Federal Bureau <strong>of</strong> Narcotics, held<br />

that individuals have an analogous cause <strong>of</strong> action against federal<br />

government <strong>of</strong>ficials. 25 In circumstances where constitutional rights<br />

have been violated, damages claims are one <strong>of</strong> the primary vehicles<br />

for the individual’s enforcement <strong>of</strong> his or her civil rights as enumerated<br />

in the Constitution. 26<br />

Very shortly after Bivens, the Supreme Court began cutting back<br />

the scope <strong>of</strong> this remedy. The Court became concerned about the risk<br />

<strong>of</strong> unsubstantiated legal claims against government actors, which, it<br />

has claimed, pose a threat to the operation <strong>of</strong> government by deterring<br />

the zealousness and enthusiasm with which public <strong>of</strong>ficials<br />

might execute their <strong>of</strong>fice and by deterring able citizens away from<br />

public service out <strong>of</strong> an aversion to the expenses <strong>of</strong> litigation. 27 The<br />

Supreme Court has recognized a policy interest in allowing govern-<br />

22. Id. at 201 (2001).<br />

23. Id.<br />

24. 365 U.S. 167 (1961) (holding actions are taken “under color” <strong>of</strong> state law when the<br />

“wrongdoer is clothed with the authority <strong>of</strong> the state” as opposed to actions taken by <strong>of</strong>ficials<br />

pursuant to state law) (quoting United <strong>State</strong>s v. Classic, 313 U.S. 325, 326 (1941)).<br />

25. 403 U.S. 388 (1971).<br />

26. See, e.g., Wilson v. Garcia, 471 U.S. 261, 276 (1985) superseded by statute on other<br />

grounds, Judicial Improvements Act <strong>of</strong> 1990, Pub. L. No. 101-650, 104 Stat 5089, as recognized<br />

in Jones v. R.R. Donnelley & Sons Co., 541 U.S. 369, 377-81 (2004).<br />

27. See, e.g., Wood v. Strickland, 420 U.S. 308, 319-20 (1975).


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 909<br />

ment <strong>of</strong>ficials facing frivolous or meritless lawsuits to enjoy immunity<br />

from “the costs <strong>of</strong> trial or . . . the burdens <strong>of</strong> broad-reaching discovery,”<br />

which would divert their energy away from the fulfillment <strong>of</strong><br />

their <strong>of</strong>ficial responsibilities. 28<br />

Qualified immunity, the Court tells us, is “the best attainable accommodation<br />

<strong>of</strong> competing values.” 29 This affirmative defense is designed<br />

to achieve the dual aims <strong>of</strong> permitting the prosecution <strong>of</strong> civil<br />

rights torts while ensuring that “[i]nsubstantial lawsuits can be<br />

quickly terminated by federal courts . . . .” 30 The Court has determined<br />

that where “clearly established rights are not implicated, the<br />

public interest may be better served by action taken ‘with independence<br />

and without fear <strong>of</strong> consequences.’ ” 31 Therefore, the defendant<br />

in a § 1983 action may, prior to discovery, move that the trial court<br />

dismiss the claim, contingent on a showing that the conduct alleged<br />

by the plaintiff does not appear to have violated the plaintiff’s clearly<br />

established constitutional rights. In particular, qualified immunity is<br />

granted when the facts alleged show that the <strong>of</strong>ficer was acting reasonably<br />

“as measured by reference to clearly established law.” 32 Government<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials are granted immunity from suit “as long as their actions<br />

could reasonably have been thought consistent with the rights<br />

they are alleged to have violated”; 33 and this protects “all but the<br />

plainly incompetent or those who knowingly violate the law.” 34<br />

The important thing to note here is that the qualified immunity<br />

doctrine is not just an immunity from having to pay money damages<br />

(as is state sovereign immunity, for example) but an immunity from<br />

having to endure any litigation at all in the first instance.<br />

Though § 1983 does not enumerate any immunities from litigation,<br />

the Court in Wood v. Strickland held Congress could not have<br />

intended to abolish the traditional common law immunities for legislators,<br />

judges, police and administrators. 35 Wood framed the test as a<br />

subjective one: the <strong>of</strong>ficer would not be liable if he acted in “good<br />

faith” and with the absence <strong>of</strong> malice. 36 Thus, the <strong>of</strong>ficer would be liable<br />

if he should have known he was violating a right or was acting<br />

maliciously. 37 Wood’s subjective test was soon replaced. But its core<br />

28. Harlo w v. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. 800, 817-18 (1982).<br />

29. Id. at 814.<br />

30. Butz v. Economou, 438 U.S. 478, 507 (1978).<br />

31. Harlow, 457 U.S. at 819 (quoting Pierson v. Ray, 386 U.S. 547, 554 (1967)).<br />

32. Id. at 818.<br />

33. Anderson v. Creighton, 483 U.S. 635, 638 (1987).<br />

34. Malley v. Briggs, 475 U.S. 335, 341 (1986).<br />

35. 420 U.S. 308, 316-18 (1975) (“Common-law tradition, recognized in our prior decisions,<br />

and strong public-policy reasons also lead to a construction <strong>of</strong> § 1983 extending a<br />

qualified good-faith immunity . . . .”).<br />

36. Id. at 322.<br />

37. See id.


910 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

motivation—the policy that <strong>of</strong>ficials should be protected from suit,<br />

even though no such immunity appears in § 1983—lives on.<br />

Seven years later, Harlow v. Fitzgerald replaced the subjective<br />

test (whether the <strong>of</strong>ficer knew he was violating rights) with an objective<br />

one (whether a reasonable <strong>of</strong>ficer could have known that the actions<br />

violated rights). 38 Again, the Court was concerned with the policy<br />

goal <strong>of</strong> terminating civil rights litigation as quickly as possible:<br />

some courts had held the <strong>of</strong>ficer’s state <strong>of</strong> mind (under the Wood<br />

standard) was a matter <strong>of</strong> fact and could not be decided on summary<br />

judgment, whereas the objective standard could be. 39<br />

The basic formulation in Harlow persists: government <strong>of</strong>ficials<br />

will be immune when “their conduct does not violate clearly established<br />

statutory or constitutional rights <strong>of</strong> which a reasonable person<br />

would have known . . . [o]n summary judgment, the judge appropriately<br />

may determine, not only the currently applicable law, but<br />

whether that law was clearly established at the time an action occurred.”<br />

40 This is a test <strong>of</strong> the state <strong>of</strong> the relevant law, not the <strong>of</strong>ficer’s<br />

state <strong>of</strong> mind. 41 The Court elaborated on the relevant standard in<br />

Anderson v. Creighton, holding that to be clearly established, “[t]he<br />

contours <strong>of</strong> the right must be sufficiently clear that a reasonable <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />

would understand that what he is doing violates that right.” 42<br />

The exact conduct alleged need not previously have been held unlawful,<br />

but in the light <strong>of</strong> pre-existing law its unlawfulness must be “apparent.”<br />

43 Anderson emphasized the question was not merely whether<br />

the right had been clearly established in some general sense, but<br />

whether on these facts the right was established. 44<br />

The Court began to distill the Harlow standard into a more workable<br />

analytic framework a few years later. Frederick Siegert had filed<br />

a Bivens claim against his former employer, a federal hospital administrator,<br />

who had released an unfavorable employment evaluation to<br />

his current employer, with allegedly “bad faith motivation,” which re-<br />

38. Harlow v. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. 800, 818 (1982).<br />

39. See, e.g., Halperin v. Kissinger, 606 F.2d 1192, 1209 (D.C. Cir. 1979) (“On the subjective<br />

criterion [<strong>of</strong> the Wood test] which ‘turns on <strong>of</strong>ficials’ knowledge and good faith belief’<br />

summary action may be more difficult. Questions <strong>of</strong> intent and subjective attitude frequently<br />

cannot be resolved without direct testimony <strong>of</strong> those involved.”); see also Wood, 420<br />

U.S. 308; FED.R.CIV. P. 56.<br />

40. Harlow, 457 U.S. at 818 (citing Procunier v. Navarette, 434 U.S. 555, 556 (1978)<br />

and Wood, 420 U.S. at 322).<br />

41. Id.<br />

42. 483 U.S. 635, 640 (1987).<br />

43. Id.<br />

44. See id. This period also included an important case regarding the procedure <strong>of</strong><br />

qualified immunity. In Mitchell v. Forsyth, 472 U.S. 511 (1985), the Court underscored the<br />

fact that qualified immunity is an immunity from litigation itself, and held that interlocutory<br />

appeals could be taken from a denial <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity.


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 911<br />

sulted in his termination. 45 The District Court had held the <strong>of</strong>ficials<br />

were not entitled to qualified immunity because the plaintiff had<br />

made sufficient allegations <strong>of</strong> malice. However, the Supreme Court<br />

disagreed. The first, threshold inquiry, the Court said, had to be<br />

whether Siegert had, on the facts alleged, made out a constitutional<br />

violation at all. Chief Justice Rehnquist explained that the task <strong>of</strong><br />

identifying the particular right which is alleged to have been violated<br />

had to be undertaken at an “analytically earlier stage <strong>of</strong> the inquiry”<br />

when handling a qualified immunity claim. 46 The Court said it was<br />

incorrect to “examine the sufficiency <strong>of</strong> the allegations <strong>of</strong> malice”<br />

without first resolving the “threshold immunity question” <strong>of</strong> whether<br />

or not, in claiming malicious defamation by a federal employer, a<br />

constitutional rights violation had even been alleged. 47 Chief Justice<br />

Rehnquist again focused on the motivating policy concern behind this<br />

line <strong>of</strong> cases, reasoning that the merits-first sequence would “permit[]<br />

courts expeditiously to weed out suits which fail the test” when the<br />

allegations did not make out a constitutional violation. 48 The Court<br />

applied this two-step sequence, found that Siegert’s claim failed at<br />

the first step, and ruled in favor <strong>of</strong> the defendants. 49<br />

Siegert was the first case to explain qualified immunity in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

a sequential analysis. Chief Justice Rehnquist reasoned that a claim<br />

that had not even made out a constitutional violation should get<br />

kicked out, regardless <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>ficer’s malice (or lack there<strong>of</strong>) in his<br />

treatment <strong>of</strong> the plaintiff. 50 However, this sequencing was not explicitly<br />

made mandatory. 51 Seven years later, in County <strong>of</strong> Sacramento<br />

v. Lewis, 52 Justice Souter described sequencing as the “better approach.”<br />

53 He explained that sequencing was necessary to guard<br />

against constitutional stagnation:<br />

What is more significant is that if the policy <strong>of</strong> avoidance were always<br />

followed in favor <strong>of</strong> ruling on qualified immunity whenever<br />

there was no clearly settled constitutional rule <strong>of</strong> primary conduct,<br />

standards <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial conduct would tend to remain uncertain, to<br />

the detriment both <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficials and individuals. An immunity de-<br />

45. Siegert v. Gilley, 895 F. 2d 797, 803 (D.C. Cir. 1990).<br />

46. Siegert v. Gilley, 500 U.S. 226, 227 (1991).<br />

47. Id. at 232.<br />

48. Id.<br />

49. Id. at 233-34.<br />

50. Id.<br />

51. Paul Hughes points out that many circuits did make the two-step approach mandatory,<br />

despite the fact that the Supreme Court had not required it at the time. See Paul<br />

W. Hughes, Not a Failed Experiment: Wilson-Saucier Sequencing and the Articulation <strong>of</strong><br />

Constitutional Rights, 80 U. COLO. L.REV. 401, 410 (2009) (“Many courts adopted such an<br />

analysis[,] holding sequencing as mandatory, including panels in the First, Second, Third,<br />

Fifth, Sixth, Seventh, Eighth, Tenth, Eleventh, and D.C. Circuits.”) (citations omitted).<br />

52. 523 U.S. 833 (1998).<br />

53. Id. at 841 n.5.


912 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

termination, with nothing more, provides no clear standard, constitutional<br />

or nonconstitutional. In practical terms, escape from<br />

uncertainty would require the issue to arise in a suit to enjoin future<br />

conduct, in an action against a municipality, or in litigating a<br />

suppression motion in a criminal proceeding; in none <strong>of</strong> these instances<br />

would qualified immunity be available to block a determination<br />

<strong>of</strong> law. But these avenues would not necessarily be open,<br />

and therefore the better approach is to determine the right before<br />

determining whether it was previously established with clarity. 54<br />

The judiciary, however, was not vigilant about observing the two-step<br />

sequence. In Conn v. Gabbert, 55 the Court made the two-step sequence<br />

mandatory: “a court must first determine whether the plaintiff<br />

has alleged the deprivation <strong>of</strong> an actual constitutional right at<br />

all,” only then can a court “proceed to determine whether that right<br />

was clearly established at the time <strong>of</strong> the alleged violation.” 56 Just as<br />

in Siegert, Chief Justice Rehnquist explained that an <strong>of</strong>ficer is denied<br />

immunity if “the <strong>of</strong>ficial [is] shown to have violated ‘clearly established<br />

statutory or constitutional rights <strong>of</strong> which a reasonable person<br />

would have known,’ ” and that the determination as to the actual<br />

presence or not <strong>of</strong> an alleged constitutional rights violation is logically<br />

prior to any considerations as to the degree to which such a right is<br />

established in the law. 57 A similar problem arose in Wilson v. Layne. 58<br />

There, the Fourth Circuit granted the defendant-<strong>of</strong>ficers immunity<br />

but “declined to decide whether the actions <strong>of</strong> the police violated the<br />

Fourth Amendment.” 59 The Supreme Court disagreed, reasoning that<br />

determining the constitutional question first “promotes clarity in the<br />

legal standards for <strong>of</strong>ficial conduct, to the benefit <strong>of</strong> both the <strong>of</strong>ficers<br />

and the general public.” 60<br />

Two terms later, Saucier v. Katz 61 firmly established the two-step<br />

sequence. The Court wrote:<br />

A court required to rule upon the qualified immunity issue must<br />

consider . . . this threshold question: Taken in the light most favorable<br />

to the party asserting the injury, do the facts alleged show<br />

the <strong>of</strong>ficer’s conduct violated a constitutional right? This must be<br />

the initial inquiry. . . . If no constitutional right would have been<br />

violated were the allegations established, there is no necessity for<br />

further inquiries concerning qualified immunity. On the other<br />

54. Id. (emphasis added, internal citations omitted).<br />

55. 526 U.S. 286 (1999).<br />

56. Id. at 290.<br />

57. Gabbert, 526 U.S. at 290.<br />

58. 526 U.S. 603 (1999).<br />

59. Id. at 608.<br />

60. Id. at 609. The Court held police <strong>of</strong>ficers bringing media representatives along<br />

during the execution <strong>of</strong> an arrest warrant violated the Fourth Amendment but found qualified<br />

immunity on the ground that the law was not clearly established. Id. at 605-06.<br />

61. 533 U.S. 194 (2001).


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 913<br />

hand, if a violation could be made out on a favorable view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

parties’ submissions, the next, sequential step is to ask whether<br />

the right was clearly established. 62<br />

Like Chief Justice Rehnquist in Wilson and Justice Souter in Lewis,<br />

Justice Kennedy in Saucier was concerned about the elaboration <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional rights. Sequencing, he wrote, is important to ensure<br />

“the law’s elaboration from case to case.” 63 The role <strong>of</strong> the courts was<br />

to explain the scope and nature <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights; “[t]he law<br />

might be deprived <strong>of</strong> this explanation were a court simply to skip<br />

ahead to the question whether the law clearly established that the <strong>of</strong>ficer’s<br />

conduct was unlawful in the circumstances <strong>of</strong> the case.” 64<br />

To recap: the Court in the 1960s and 70s held § 1983 and Bivens<br />

actions could be used to vindicate constitutional rights. But the scope<br />

<strong>of</strong> liability was almost immediately curtailed: substantively by Wood<br />

and Harlow (which established the defense <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity)<br />

and procedurally by Mitchell (which permitted interlocutory appeals).<br />

As to the substantive analysis, the Court was insistent that the constitutional<br />

question be decided first: to weed out insubstantial claims,<br />

to put defendant-<strong>of</strong>ficers on notice <strong>of</strong> the law, and to ensure that the<br />

constitutional law did not stagnate. The failure <strong>of</strong> lower courts to follow<br />

this process post-Siegert was what forced the Court to press, with<br />

increasing insistence, the mandatory two-step sequence.<br />

That all changed in January 2009 with Pearson v. Callahan. 65<br />

That case concerned a warrantless search and application <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Fourth Amendment’s “consent-once-removed” doctrine. 66 If you don’t<br />

know what this doctrine is, don’t worry: the Court bypassed this issue<br />

entirely. Sua sponte, it ordered briefing as to whether Saucier’s<br />

mandatory two-step should be overruled. 67 A few months later, the<br />

Court unanimously overruled Saucier. 68<br />

It is important, however, to note what the Court did not do. Many<br />

critiques <strong>of</strong> Saucier had argued that the mandatory merits-first sequence<br />

was unconstitutional or otherwise legally infirm. 69 But the<br />

Court did not overrule Saucier on constitutional grounds, or really<br />

anything that might be described as “legal reasoning.” In fact, it left<br />

the two steps <strong>of</strong> the Saucier analysis entirely undisturbed. Instead,<br />

62. Id. at 201.<br />

63. Id.<br />

64. Id.<br />

65. 129 S. Ct. 808 (2009).<br />

66. Id.<br />

67. Pearson v. Callahan, 128 S. Ct. 1702, 1702-03 (2008) (order granting certiorari).<br />

68. Pearson, 129 S. Ct. 808.<br />

69. See, e.g., Pierre N. Leval, Judging Under the Constitution: Dicta About Dicta, 81<br />

N.Y.U. L. REV. 1249, 1275–81 (2006); Thomas Healy, The Rise <strong>of</strong> Unnecessary Constitutional<br />

Rulings, 83 N.C. L. REV. 847, 920 (2005).


914 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

the Court found that the mandatory process was inefficient. 70 Saucier<br />

was thus overruled on entirely prudential grounds:<br />

On reconsidering the procedure required in Saucier, we conclude<br />

that, while the sequence set forth there is <strong>of</strong>ten appropriate, it<br />

should no longer be regarded as mandatory. The judges <strong>of</strong> the district<br />

courts and the courts <strong>of</strong> appeals should be permitted to exercise<br />

their sound discretion in deciding which <strong>of</strong> the two prongs <strong>of</strong><br />

the qualified immunity analysis should be addressed first in light<br />

<strong>of</strong> the circumstances in the particular case at hand. 71<br />

In the very next paragraph, the Court again reiterated that Saucier<br />

sequencing is “<strong>of</strong>ten beneficial.” 72 But the mandatory two-step was<br />

no more.<br />

Of course, the Court was then left with the task <strong>of</strong> justifying its<br />

departure from Saucier, Anderson, Siegert, Gabbert and Harlow. Justice<br />

Alito wrote there was no stare decisis problem because those considerations<br />

applied primarily to contract or property cases, not those<br />

involving judge-made rules. 73 And the Court focused on the practical<br />

effects: lower courts found the mandatory sequencing problematic,<br />

and that weighed in favor <strong>of</strong> abandoning the standard. 74<br />

What about constitutional elaboration? With a little hand waving,<br />

that problem was made to go away, too:<br />

Most <strong>of</strong> the constitutional issues that are presented in § 1983 damages<br />

actions and Bivens cases also arise in cases in which that defense is<br />

not available, such as criminal cases and § 1983 cases against a municipality,<br />

as well as § 1983 cases against individuals where injunctive<br />

relief is sought instead <strong>of</strong> or in addition to damages. 75<br />

Moreover, the Court asserted that decisions on constitutional questions<br />

may in some cases “have scant value,” for example, when the issue<br />

is pending in a higher court, or hinges on the interpretation <strong>of</strong> an<br />

ambiguous state statute. 76 The Court recognized the protocol <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

contributes to the goal <strong>of</strong> efficiently weeding out unsubstantial claims<br />

when a complaint can be targeted as not making out a constitutional<br />

violation but held the lower courts are better able to determine those<br />

cases in which this benefit is available. 77<br />

The obvious reply, <strong>of</strong> course, is that courts had come up with ready<br />

solutions to these “problems.” For example, a federal court faced with a<br />

question <strong>of</strong> state law could certify the state law issue to the state’s<br />

70. Pearson, 129 S. Ct. at 818-19.<br />

71. Id. at 818.<br />

72. Id.<br />

73. Id. at 816.<br />

74. Id. at 818.<br />

75. Id. at 822.<br />

76. Id. at 819.<br />

77. Id. at 821.


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 915<br />

highest court, retain jurisdiction, and decide the immunity issue accordingly.<br />

78 Indeed, Pearson’s citation for the proposition that constitutional<br />

rights may be elaborated through other avenues was Lewis. But<br />

Lewis itself had reasoned that “these avenues would not necessarily be<br />

open, and therefore the better approach is to determine the right before<br />

determining whether it was previously established with clarity.” 79 It is<br />

curious that the argument in favor <strong>of</strong> the “better approach” is used, a<br />

decade letter, to justify abandoning that same approach.<br />

And so this is the legacy <strong>of</strong> Pearson: throughout the 1990s, even after<br />

Siegert, courts were not adhering to the strongly suggested twostep<br />

analysis. The Ninth Circuit had even developed its own two-step<br />

procedure that bypassed Siegert’s first step entirely. 80 From 1999 to<br />

2001, from Wilson to Saucier, the Court tightened the screws and<br />

made the two-step mandatory. And then, about a decade later, just as<br />

the lower courts finally came into line, the Court abandoned its efforts.<br />

B. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal<br />

Before discussing Iqbal, some background is in order. In 2007, the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s Supreme Court decided Bell Atlantic Corp. v. Twombly,<br />

81 a telecommunications antitrust case. The plaintiffs alleged, inter<br />

alia, that the defendants had engaged in an illegal, anticompetitive<br />

conspiracy; the defendants countered by arguing that their actions,<br />

while parallel, were independent. Although the complaint contained<br />

detailed allegations regarding the actions taken by each company,<br />

the allegations regarding the existence <strong>of</strong> a conspiracy were<br />

much thinner. 82<br />

Justice Souter, writing for the Court, found the complaint lacking.<br />

Pleading the existence <strong>of</strong> the conspiracy merely upon information<br />

and belief, or in conclusory terms, was held insufficient. For example,<br />

he noted, parallel conduct was also consistent with the companies<br />

acting in their own pr<strong>of</strong>it-maximizing self interest in the marketplace.<br />

Although the competitors’ conduct was “consistent” with a conspiracy,<br />

it was not “plausible” that a conspiracy had taken place; 83<br />

the plaintiffs “mentioned no specific time, place, or person involved in<br />

78. The Sixth Circuit followed a similar procedure in Waeschle v. Dragovic, 576 F.3d<br />

539 (6th Cir. 2009). The court concluded that any right was not clearly established and (because<br />

it was post-Pearson) held that the defendants were entitled to immunity. Id. at 550.<br />

However, in order to determine the claims against the municipal defendant, it certified the<br />

question <strong>of</strong> whether a property interest existed to the Michigan Supreme Court. Id. at 551.<br />

79. County <strong>of</strong> Sacramento v. Lewis, 523 U.S. 833, 841 n.5 (1998) (emphasis added).<br />

80. See Saucier v. Katz, 533 U.S. 194, 199-201 (2001).<br />

81. 550 U.S. 544 (2007).<br />

82. See generally id. at 550-52.<br />

83. See id. at 564-65.


916 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

the alleged conspiracies.” 84 Therefore, they “ha[d] not nudged their<br />

claims across the line from conceivable to plausible.” 85<br />

Twombly sent shock waves through the civil procedure field. Although<br />

it was an antitrust case, it was not clear its holding was so<br />

limited: the Supreme Court was interpreting Federal Rule <strong>of</strong> Civil<br />

Procedure 8(a)(2), 86 and the Rules apply equally to all civil actions. 87<br />

The destabilizing effect <strong>of</strong> Twombly was due in part to the fact that<br />

the current pleading regime had been in place for at least fifty years<br />

(since 1957, when the Supreme Court decided Conley v. Gibson 88 ) and<br />

probably more like seventy (since 1938, when the Rules were<br />

adopted). In Conley, the Court instructed that a complaint was not to<br />

be dismissed unless there was “no set <strong>of</strong> facts” that would entitle the<br />

plaintiff to relief. 89 And since 1938, Rule 8(a)(2) required only “a short<br />

and plain statement <strong>of</strong> the claim” showing an entitlement to relief, 90<br />

Twombly, for the first time, invited a federal judge to decide how likely<br />

it was that the allegations in the complaint were true. Only if they<br />

were “plausible” was the case to go forward.<br />

Justice Stevens dissented in Twombly. In so doing, he noted,<br />

“[w]hether the Court’s actions will benefit only defendants in antitrust<br />

treble-damages cases, or whether its test for the sufficiency <strong>of</strong> a<br />

complaint will inure to the benefit <strong>of</strong> all civil defendants, is a question<br />

that the future will answer.” 91<br />

Iqbal provided that answer. Javaid Iqbal was a Pakistani Muslim<br />

who was detained by the federal government after the September 11,<br />

2001, terrorist attacks. Iqbal claimed he was subjected to harsh interrogation<br />

and abuse because <strong>of</strong> his race. Iqbal therefore sued the<br />

“street-level” <strong>of</strong>ficials who were responsible for his alleged abuse. But<br />

he did not stop there. Iqbal also claimed that John D. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t, the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s Attorney <strong>General</strong> on September 11, 2001, and Robert<br />

Mueller, the Director <strong>of</strong> the Federal Bureau <strong>of</strong> Investigation at the<br />

time, directed and implemented a conspiracy to deprive him <strong>of</strong> his<br />

rights because <strong>of</strong> his race. 92 Serious allegations, maybe even true al-<br />

84. Id. at 565 n.10.<br />

85. Id. at 570.<br />

86. See Twombly, 550 U.S. at 554-55.<br />

87. FED.R.CIV. P. 1. The Supreme Court has consistently rejected the notion <strong>of</strong> heightened<br />

pleading standards in particular contexts. See, e.g., Swierkiewicz v. Sorema, 534 U.S.<br />

506, 512-513 (2002); Leatherman v. Tarrant County Narcotics Intelligence and Coordination<br />

Unit, 507 U.S. 163, 168 (1993).<br />

88. 355 U.S. 41 (1957).<br />

89. 355 U.S. at 45-46.<br />

90. FED.R.CIV. P. 8(a)(2).<br />

91. Twombly, 550 U.S. at 596 (Stevens, J., dissenting).<br />

92. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal, 129 S. Ct. 1937 (2009).


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 917<br />

legations, but—in the view <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court’s 5-4 majority—not<br />

plausible allegations. 93<br />

The Supreme Court followed a two-step process in dismissing Iqbal’s<br />

claims against Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t and Mueller. First, it disregarded the<br />

allegations that were deemed “conclusory.” 94 Then, it determined that<br />

the remaining (nonconclusory) allegations, standing alone, were insufficient<br />

to form an entitlement to relief:<br />

On the facts respondent alleges the arrests Mueller oversaw were<br />

likely lawful and justified by his nondiscriminatory intent to detain<br />

aliens who were illegally present in the United <strong>State</strong>s and<br />

who had potential connections to those who committed terrorist<br />

acts. As between that “obvious alternative explanation” for the arrests,<br />

and the purposeful, invidious discrimination respondent<br />

asks us to infer, discrimination is not a plausible conclusion. 95<br />

Thus, Iqbal’s claim—and all others—were to be judged by the new<br />

standard, which the Court explained as follows:<br />

[A] court considering a motion to dismiss can choose to begin by [1]<br />

identifying pleadings that, because they are no more than conclusions,<br />

are not entitled to the assumption <strong>of</strong> truth. While legal conclusions<br />

can provide the framework <strong>of</strong> a complaint, they must be supported by<br />

factual allegations. [2] When there are well-pleaded factual allegations,<br />

a court should assume their veracity and then determine<br />

whether they plausibly give rise to an entitlement to relief. 96<br />

This is the two-step framework by which courts are to judge complaints<br />

at the motion to dismiss; first, disregard all conclusory allegations;<br />

second, determine whether the remaining allegations make out<br />

a “plausible” entitlement to relief.<br />

That, at least, is how most people have taken Iqbal. 97 It is also the<br />

conception I work with in this Article. But before going forward, I want<br />

to pause to highlight two aspects <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court’s formulation<br />

that render it problematic even on its own terms (i.e., apart from the<br />

problems I highlight in this Article as regarding civil rights plaintiffs).<br />

First, Iqbal does not say that lower courts must use this formulation.<br />

Rather, it says that a court “can choose to” apply the two-step approach.<br />

98 Although courts seem to have taken Iqbal to be mandatory, ra-<br />

93. Id. at 1952.<br />

94. Id. at 1951.<br />

95. Id. at 1951-52 (quoting Bell Atlantic Corp. v. Twombly, 550 U.S. 544, 567 (2007)<br />

(emphasis added and citation omitted).<br />

96. Id. at 1950.<br />

97. See, e.g., Adam N. Steinman, The Pleading Problem, 62 STAN. L REV. 1293,<br />

1316 (2010).<br />

98. Iqbal, 129 S. Ct. at 1950 (quoting Bell Atlantic Corp. v. Twombly, 550 U.S. 544,<br />

567 (2007) (emphasis added)).


918 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

ther than discretionary, 99 this somewhat curious phrase is worth noting.<br />

Iqbal, unlike Pearson, does not explicitly give courts the choice between<br />

different frameworks for analyzing the legal question.<br />

Second, Iqbal says that conclusory allegations are not entitled to<br />

the presumption <strong>of</strong> truth. But in so doing, the Court conflates two<br />

types <strong>of</strong> “conclusions.” The relevant passage in Iqbal reads,<br />

[t]hreadbare recitals <strong>of</strong> the elements <strong>of</strong> a cause <strong>of</strong> action, supported<br />

by mere conclusory statements, do not suffice. (Although for the<br />

purposes <strong>of</strong> a motion to dismiss we must take all <strong>of</strong> the factual allegations<br />

in the complaint as true, we “are not bound to accept as<br />

true a legal conclusion couched as a factual allegation . . . .”). 100<br />

But this paragraph is sloppy. It equates “conclusory statements” with<br />

“legal conclusion[s],” even though these terms are used to mean two<br />

different things.<br />

Take this example: “X was negligent” is an allegation not entitled<br />

to the presumption <strong>of</strong> truth because the allegation is pleading nothing<br />

more than a legal conclusion (negligence). However, the allegation,<br />

“X was walking down Fifth Avenue” is an allegation that is entitled<br />

to the presumption <strong>of</strong> truth—even though it is “conclusory.” 101<br />

The allegation provides no facts that would establish that X actually<br />

was walking down the street. It “mention[s] no specific time, place, or<br />

person involved in the alleged” walking down the street. 102 Yet this<br />

statement is entitled to the presumption <strong>of</strong> truth. The distinction is<br />

not that one is “conclusory” while the other is not. The distinction is<br />

that one is a legal conclusion while the other is a factual conclusion.<br />

Iqbal conflates the two, and in so doing, opens a can <strong>of</strong> worms. Justice<br />

Souter suggested in his Iqbal dissent that the only factual conclusions<br />

disentitled to the presumption <strong>of</strong> truth are those “that are<br />

sufficiently fantastic to defy reality as we know it: claims about little<br />

green men, or the plaintiff’s recent trip to Pluto, or experiences in<br />

time travel.” 103 But the majority did not limit the plausibility standard<br />

in this way. Instead, a court is to rely on its “judicial experience<br />

99. See, e.g., Torn Ranch, Inc. v. Sunrise Commodities, Inc., No. C 09-02674, 2009 WL<br />

2834787, at *2 (N.D. Cal. Sept. 3, 2009) (“A court must ‘begin by identifying pleadings that,<br />

because they are no more than conclusions, are not entitled to the assumption <strong>of</strong> truth.’ ”)<br />

(quoting Iqbal) (emphasis added); Mohammad v. N.Y. <strong>State</strong> Higher Educ. Servs. Corp., No.<br />

08-CV-4943, 2009 WL 1514635, at *4 (E.D.N.Y. June 1, 2009) (“I must begin by ‘identifying<br />

pleadings that, because they are no more than conclusions, are not entitled to the assumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> truth.’ ”) (quoting Iqbal) (emphasis added).<br />

100. Iqbal, 129 S. Ct. at 1949-50 (emphasis added and citation omitted).<br />

101. Black’s <strong>Law</strong> Dictionary defines “conclusory” as “[e]xpressing a factual inference<br />

without stating the underlying facts on which the inference is based.” BLACK’S LAW<br />

DICTIONARY 308 (8th ed. 2004).<br />

102. Bell Atlantic Corp. v. Twombly, 550 U.S. 544, 565 n.10 (2007).<br />

103. Iqbal, 129 S. Ct. at 1959 (Souter, J., dissenting).


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 919<br />

and common sense” in determining whether a claim is plausible, after<br />

disregarding “conclusory” allegations. 104<br />

To be sure, Iqbal attempts to frame the discussion as one <strong>of</strong> legal,<br />

not factual, conclusions. 105 But the Court went on to disregard various<br />

allegations because they were factually conclusory, writing, “[i]t<br />

is the conclusory nature <strong>of</strong> respondent’s allegations, rather than their<br />

extravagantly fanciful nature, that disentitles them to the presumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> truth.” 106 Of course, a legal conclusion, standing alone, is neither<br />

fanciful nor plausible; it simply is. What would make a claim<br />

fanciful are the facts supporting that legal conclusion. “The doctor<br />

negligently harmed me by operating on me while drunk” is not fanciful;<br />

“the doctor negligently harmed me by operating on me after his<br />

brain had been removed from his skull by aliens who were using him<br />

in an inter-galactic biological study” is fanciful. The difference has<br />

nothing to do with the legal conclusion (negligence in both cases) and<br />

turns entirely on the facts. By directing courts to disregard “conclusory”<br />

factual allegations (as opposed to legal statements), the Court<br />

does grave violence to the long-standing proposition that a plaintiff’s<br />

factual allegations are entitled to be taken as true.<br />

The passage also conflates what are ostensibly the two prongs <strong>of</strong><br />

the Iqbal analysis. Recall that a court is first to disregard conclusory<br />

allegations, and second, determine whether the remaining allegations<br />

entitle the pleader to relief. Yet the decision as to whether an<br />

allegation is conclusory cannot be made in a vacuum. It is necessarily<br />

affected by the cause <strong>of</strong> action pled, the type <strong>of</strong> relief sought, and the<br />

court’s ability (or lack there<strong>of</strong>) to award such relief, among other<br />

things. An allegation along the lines <strong>of</strong> “X singled me out because <strong>of</strong><br />

my race” apparently does not pass muster under Iqbal. 107 This seems<br />

to be because the allegation embodies a “legal conclusion,” “because<br />

<strong>of</strong> my race.” But Iqbal also disregarded allegations that Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t was<br />

the “principal architect” <strong>of</strong> an illegal policy. 108 This statement embodies<br />

no legal conclusion and is simply a fact that either is or is not<br />

true. Once again, the Court blurs the line between legal allegations<br />

and factual allegations, improperly disregarding the latter.<br />

Finally, the discussion indicates how the Court is elevating form<br />

over substance. Though “X singled me out because <strong>of</strong> my race” does<br />

not pass muster, “X singled me out; I am an Arab Muslim; non-Arab,<br />

non-Muslims were not singled out” probably would. This is so, ostensibly,<br />

because the allegations do not contain a legal conclusion (“because<br />

<strong>of</strong> my race”), even though the new allegations could be based on<br />

104. Id. at 1950 (Opinion <strong>of</strong> the Court).<br />

105. See id.<br />

106. Id. at 1951 (emphasis added).<br />

107. Cf. id. at 1950-51.<br />

108. Id. at 1951.


920 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

identical facts and, as a substantive matter, add nothing. A court can<br />

only conclude that the first formulation is “conclusory” by (1) making<br />

reference to something beyond the allegations themselves, suggesting<br />

that the factual allegation/legal conclusion dichotomy further breaks<br />

down, or (2) elevating form over substance. Both are bad options.<br />

In just a few short months, Iqbal has spawned a substantial corpus<br />

<strong>of</strong> commentary. Commentators have argued the Court made important<br />

policy judgments in Twombly and Iqbal that it should not<br />

have made 109 or that Iqbal is part <strong>of</strong> the desirable evolution <strong>of</strong> federal<br />

pleading standards. 110 Though the standard view appears to be that<br />

Iqbal raised the bar on plaintiffs, 111 others have argued that Iqbal<br />

can be fully reconciled with pre-Towmbly precedent. 112 There are also<br />

questions as to whether the sample forms contained in the Federal<br />

Rules are valid anymore, since the statements in those forms might<br />

be deemed “conclusory.” 113 My intention is not to explain or even fully<br />

engage these critiques, which I note merely for the sake <strong>of</strong> completeness.<br />

Instead, I provide a doctrinally and conceptually distinct criticism<br />

<strong>of</strong> Iqbal: that the interaction between Iqbal and Pearson works<br />

to the detriment <strong>of</strong> civil rights plaintiffs. This is the project <strong>of</strong> the<br />

next part.<br />

III. HOW THE CASES HURT CIVIL RIGHTS PLAINTIFFS<br />

Having described the two cases that are the focus <strong>of</strong> this Article, I<br />

now describe the ways in which they harm civil rights plaintiffs. 114 First,<br />

there is the obvious way: Pearson makes it easier to grant government<br />

109. Clermont & Yeazell, supra note 20, at 831-32.<br />

110. Douglas G. Smith, The Evolution <strong>of</strong> a New Pleading Standard: Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal, at<br />

http://ssrn.com/papers=1463844, at 4-5 (Iqbal “presents a welcome evolution <strong>of</strong> pleading<br />

standards that is likely to have beneficial effects in terms <strong>of</strong> the efficiency <strong>of</strong> civil litigation”).<br />

111. See, e.g., Courie v. Alcoa Wheel & Forged Prods., 577 F.3d 625, 629 (6th Cir. 2009)<br />

(noting Iqbal “raised the bar for pleading requirements”); Smith, supra note 110, at 2 (“Iqbal<br />

thus represents a further raising <strong>of</strong> the bar plaintiffs must meet before they are allowed<br />

to proceed with discovery”); Robert L. Rothman, Twombly and Iqbal: A License to<br />

Dismiss, 35 No. 3 LITIG. 1, 2 (2009) (“Iqbal drastically changed the landscape for Rule<br />

12(b)(6) motions”).<br />

112. See Steinman, supra note 97, at 1299-1300 (arguing that defining conclusory in<br />

“transactional terms” could reconcile Iqbal with pre-Twombly precedent).<br />

113. Federal Civil Form 11, for example, which ostensibly would be sufficient in a negligence<br />

action, reads simply, “On [date], at [place], the defendant negligently drove a motor<br />

vehicle against the plaintiff. As a result, the plaintiff was physically injured, lost wages or<br />

income, suffered physical and mental pain, and incurred medical expenses <strong>of</strong> $[amount].”<br />

Allen Ides has suggested that Form 11 may not pass muster under the new standard. See<br />

Allan Ides, Bell Atlantic and the Principle <strong>of</strong> Substantive Sufficiency Under Federal Rule <strong>of</strong><br />

Civil Procedure 8(a)(2): Toward a Structured Approach to Federal Pleading Practice, 243<br />

F.R.D. 604, 633 (2008).<br />

114. Iqbal, <strong>of</strong> course, is not limited to civil rights cases. However, it arose in that context<br />

and will probably have its greatest effect in that field. Even those who argue that Iqbal<br />

is <strong>of</strong> limited effect, see Clermont & Yeazell, supra note 20, acknowledge that it must, at<br />

a minimum, apply to these cases.


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 921<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials immunity and, by permitting courts to skip “step one,” inhibits<br />

development <strong>of</strong> constitutional law. Iqbal, by raising the bar for pleading,<br />

makes it harder for plaintiffs to survive a motion to dismiss.<br />

But my focus in this Article is not only the shortcomings <strong>of</strong> the<br />

cases on their own terms but also on the deleterious effects <strong>of</strong> the interaction<br />

<strong>of</strong> the two cases. The cases interact in three ways that are<br />

harmful to civil rights plaintiffs.<br />

First, there is this dilemma: a plaintiff who describes the constitutional<br />

right in question in great detail runs the risk <strong>of</strong> losing on<br />

Saucier step two, when a court holds that his right is not clearly established.<br />

If the plaintiff tries to avoid this possibility by pleading at<br />

a level <strong>of</strong> generality, he or she risks losing on Iqbal—either because<br />

the allegations are deemed “conclusory” or because they are taken to<br />

be “implausible.”<br />

Second, the Court gives short shrift to the fact that the first step<br />

<strong>of</strong> qualified immunity—whether there are allegations or facts that<br />

could make out a constitutional violation—is the same as the test for<br />

whether a plaintiff has stated a cognizable claim. In other words, Iqbal<br />

not only raises the bar for pleading but also raises the bar for<br />

Saucier step one.<br />

Third, the cases take divergent tracks with regard to lower courts’<br />

discretion. They expand discretion in some regards (in determining<br />

which step <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity to address first (Pearson) and in determining<br />

which allegations are “conclusory” or “implausible” (Iqbal)).<br />

However, discretion is also cut back: the Court in Iqbal explicitly<br />

rejected the notion <strong>of</strong> using litigation management to shield government<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials, directing courts instead to dismiss cases outright.<br />

The combined effect is that discretion is expanded in some regards,<br />

limited in others, but always in a way that makes it easier to dismiss<br />

civil rights lawsuits.<br />

A. The Obvious<br />

As others have noted, there are some fairly obvious ways in which<br />

Pearson and Iqbal hurt civil rights plaintiffs. First, Pearson, as described<br />

above, permits courts to skip to the second step <strong>of</strong> the qualified<br />

immunity inquiry and award the <strong>of</strong>ficer immunity because the<br />

constitutional right in question was not “clearly established.” But if<br />

courts do this regularly, then there is a very real risk that constitutional<br />

rights will never get clearly established. Second, Iqbal is problematic<br />

because it makes it easier for courts to dismiss civil rights<br />

lawsuits. I discuss each <strong>of</strong> these in turn. 115<br />

115. There are critiques <strong>of</strong> Saucier, and arguments against sequencing, that sound in<br />

constitutional law. See, e.g., Thomas Healy, The Rise <strong>of</strong> Unnecessary Constitutional Rul-


922 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

This problem has been identified for some time in the academic literature.<br />

As far back as 1991, Fallon and Meltzer explained that after<br />

the early qualified immunity cases, courts would “deny relief<br />

without deciding whether a constitutional violation in fact occurred.”<br />

116 They criticized this process, arguing that it “restrict[s] the<br />

opportunity for judges to address novel claims . . . [and] thus tend[s]<br />

to freeze the development <strong>of</strong> constitutional law.” 117 Just before Saucier,<br />

Greabe wrote the defense <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity, when “it encourages<br />

merits bypasses, is . . . a substantial impediment to the development<br />

<strong>of</strong> new constitutional law in civil rights damages actions.” 118<br />

Shortly after Saucier, Kamin wrote, “if the question <strong>of</strong> the entitlement<br />

to qualified immunity is addressed before the substance <strong>of</strong> a<br />

plaintiff's claim, [then] the contours <strong>of</strong> the law will never become<br />

well-defined, and the entitlement <strong>of</strong> defendants to qualified immunity<br />

will continue in perpetuity.” 119<br />

These risks—mitigated during the Siegert era and reduced to near<br />

zero in the Wilson-Saucier era—are back to the fore now. And these<br />

problems are not merely theoretical. As a recent article demonstrates,<br />

there is empirical support for the proposition that Wilson-<br />

Saucier sequencing furthers the development <strong>of</strong> the constitutional<br />

law. 120 Hughes argues compellingly that courts have been more will-<br />

ings, 83 N.C. L. REV. 847, 930 (2005). I do not focus on these criticisms here for two reasons.<br />

First, there are compelling responses to these criticisms. See, e.g., Sam Kamin, An Article<br />

III Defense <strong>of</strong> Merits-First Decisionmaking in Civil Rights Litigation: The Continued<br />

Viability <strong>of</strong> Saucier v. Katz, 16 GEO. MASON L. REV. 53 (2009) (disposing <strong>of</strong> the argument<br />

that merits-first adjudication violates the Article III ban on advisory opinions). Second, so<br />

long as the Supreme Court gave its approval to merits-first decisions, the constitutional<br />

problems were, at least as a practical matter, moot. Cf. Brown v. Allen, 344 U.S. 443, 540<br />

(1953) (Jackson, J., concurring in the result) (“We are not final because we are infallible,<br />

but we are infallible only because we are final.”). In my view, so long as the constitutional<br />

questions were bracketed (because the Supreme Court said so), the only relevant issue was<br />

whether merits-first ordering was worthwhile. The Supreme Court’s stated justification for<br />

this ordering, from Seigert to Wilson to Saucier, was the need for elaboration <strong>of</strong> the constitutional<br />

law. Therefore, I proceed from the premise that (1) the Court saw constitutional<br />

elaboration as a worthwhile goal, and (2) this is the value most likely to be lost when mandatory<br />

ordering is abandoned.<br />

116. Richard H. Fallon, Jr. & Daniel J. Meltzer, New <strong>Law</strong>, Non-Retroactivity, and Constitutional<br />

Remedies, 104 HARV.L.REV. 1731, 1735 (1991).<br />

117. Id. at 1735, 1797-98 (1991). Fallon and Meltzer were discussing Harlow as juxtaposed<br />

against Teague v. Lane, 489 U.S. 288 (1989), a case involving post-conviction habeas<br />

corpus review. They point out that, per Teague, a habeas petition that relied on new law—<br />

i.e., law that was not “clearly established”—is to be dismissed without any discussion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

constitutional merits. At least for some time, the civil rights and habeas contexts diverged,<br />

as lower courts were instructed, from Siegert through Pearson, to address the constitutional<br />

merits first, even in a claim that would fail under step two, on a claim that would get<br />

summarily dismissed under Teague.<br />

118. John M.M. Greabe, Mirabile Dictum!: The Case for “Unnecessary” Constitutional<br />

Rulings in Civil Rights Damages Actions, 74 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 403, 411 (1999).<br />

119. Sam Kamin, Harmless Error and the Rights/Remedies Split, 88 VA. L.REV. 1,<br />

50 (2002).<br />

120. Hughes, supra note 51, at 422-23.


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 923<br />

ing to elaborate on the nature <strong>of</strong> constitutional rights in the post-<br />

Siegert, and especially the post-Saucier, eras much more so than they<br />

were doing in the post-Harlow, pre-Siegert era. 121 Before Siegert,<br />

courts reached the constitutional merits in only about two-thirds <strong>of</strong><br />

all cases. 122 After Saucier, that figure was up to almost ninety-nine<br />

percent. 123 It is true that the rate at which courts rejected claims <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional violations almost doubled from the 1980s to the post-<br />

Saucier era. 124 However, the rate at which courts did recognize such<br />

violations also grew. 125 This is undoubtedly a net positive for civil<br />

rights litigants. Moreover, as Hughes points out, 126 even negative articulation<br />

can have value because it furthers predictability and may<br />

even spur Congress to act. 127 But I would go one step further. Suppose<br />

the right X has been clearly established and a litigant is now<br />

pressing a claim based on X1, a related but novel theory. It would be<br />

ideal for the plaintiff if the court finds a constitutional violation. But<br />

even if the court finds no violation, the ruling is beneficial to civil<br />

rights litigants. The next time a similar case comes up, lawyers are<br />

on notice that a claim <strong>of</strong> X1 will fail. Therefore, they will shift their<br />

energies to now arguing X2. Or, they will explain how this case differs<br />

from the previous one. But in the absence <strong>of</strong> mandatory sequencing,<br />

subsequent cases would keep relitigating X1, leading to a Groundhog<br />

Day-esque repetition.<br />

It is already clear is that courts are regularly dismissing cases on<br />

the ground that the right in question is not clearly established and not<br />

discussing the constitutional merits. 128 And it is clear the contours <strong>of</strong><br />

these rights would be defined with clarity in a pre-Pearson world. The<br />

effects <strong>of</strong> this avoidance may be felt beyond the realm <strong>of</strong> civil rights litigation.<br />

If the court decides to pass on a constitutional question regard-<br />

121. Id.<br />

122. Id.<br />

123. Id. at 424. Another empirical study contends that the constitutional law has only<br />

developed in a negative direction after Saucier, i.e., has almost always refused to recognize<br />

new rights. See Nancy Leong, The Saucier Qualified Immunity Experiment: An Empirical<br />

Analysis, 36 PEPP. L.REV. 667, 670 (2009). However, Hughes provides a compelling response<br />

to this position in his article. Hughes, supra note 51, at 428-29 n.122.<br />

124. Hughes, supra note 51, at 422-23.<br />

125. Id.<br />

126. Id. at 428 n.122.<br />

127. See id.<br />

128. See, e.g., Cole v. Buchanan County Sch. Bd., No. 08-1105, 2009 WL 1336720, at *2<br />

(4th Cir. May 14, 2009) (skipping to step two and declining to decide whether a member <strong>of</strong><br />

the press has the right not to be excluded from school property that is otherwise open to<br />

the public); Dean v. Blumenthal, 577 F.3d 60, 66 (2d Cir. 2009) (declining to decide whether<br />

a candidate for <strong>of</strong>fice has a First Amendment right to receive campaign contributions);<br />

Rodis v. City & County <strong>of</strong> San Francisco, 558 F.3d 964, 970 (9th Cir. 2009) (declining to decide<br />

whether passing a counterfeit note, without more, provides probable cause for arrest);<br />

Starling v. Bd. <strong>of</strong> County Comm’rs, No. 08-80008-CIV, 2009 WL 281051, at *8 (S.D. Fla.<br />

Feb. 2, 2009) (declining to decide if there is a protected liberty interest in an adulterous<br />

sexual relationship).


924 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

ing criminal law, criminal defendants and prosecutors are denied the<br />

benefits <strong>of</strong> constitutional articulation. And if the court, in skipping the<br />

merits inquiry, disposes <strong>of</strong> the case by way <strong>of</strong> an unpublished decision,<br />

the case has no precedential effect whatsoever.<br />

So this is the obvious way Pearson harms civil rights plaintiffs: by<br />

permitting courts to skip step one, it makes it more likely that they<br />

will elect not to address the merits <strong>of</strong> constitutional claims. This has<br />

the potential to stagnate the constitutional law. And if the recent<br />

empirical work is any indication, it will reverse the trend <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />

elaboration that has been under way for two decades. 129<br />

There is also a straightforward way in which Iqbal hurts civil rights<br />

plaintiffs. Simply put, Iqbal raises the bar on civil rights plaintiffs and,<br />

indeed, all plaintiffs. Regardless <strong>of</strong> how the Court may have characterized<br />

its decision, the fact remains that lower courts nationwide are<br />

applying a stricter standard post-Iqbal than they were before it. 130<br />

The academic commentary has recognized these and related problems<br />

with Iqbal. Kilaru notes in his article 131 that Iqbal calls into<br />

question the Supreme Court’s decisions in Crawford-El v. Britton 132<br />

(a point I describe below) as well as Pullman-Standard v. Swint. 133<br />

Klein argues that Iqbal may be unconstitutional as the “heightened”<br />

pleading standard it imposes runs afoul <strong>of</strong> the Seventh Amendment’s<br />

jury trial guarantee. 134 I do not focus on these problems here because<br />

I am interested in the more subtle—but no less harsh—ways that the<br />

interaction between the two cases is problematic for civil rights plaintiffs.<br />

I turn to these issues next.<br />

129. See, e.g., Hughes, supra note 51.<br />

130. See, e.g., al-Kidd v. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t, 580 F.3d 949, 977 (9th Cir. 2009) (“Post-Twombly,<br />

plaintiffs face a higher burden <strong>of</strong> pleading facts, and courts face greater uncertainty in evaluating<br />

complaints.”); Coles v. Eagle, No. 09-00167 DAE-BMK, 2009 WL 2700210, at *4 (D.<br />

Haw. Aug. 27, 2009) (“A careful review <strong>of</strong> [the complaint] reveals that, under the stricter<br />

pleading standard recently set forth by the Supreme Court in Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal . . . Coles<br />

fails to state a claim against the [defendants.]”) (emphasis added); Ibrahim v. Dep’t <strong>of</strong> Homeland<br />

Sec., No. C 06-00545 WHA, 2009 WL 2246194, at *1 (N.D. Cal. July 27, 2009) (“As<br />

to [plaintiff’s] damage claims for past violations, a different problem arises, namely the<br />

stricter pleading standard in Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal . . . .”) (second emphasis added); In re Bishop,<br />

No. 08-11156-MWV, 2009 WL 2231197, at *2 n.4 (Bankr. D.N.H. July 24, 2009) (noting<br />

“the higher pleading requirements established in the Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t decision”); In re Caremerica,<br />

409 B.R.737, 754 (Bankr. E.D.N.C. 2009) (“[T]he court admits that claims for relief<br />

are more difficult to plead sufficiently following Twombly and Iqbal.”).<br />

131. See Rakesh N. Kilaru, The New Rule 12(b)(6): Twombly, Iqbal, and the Paradox <strong>of</strong><br />

Pleading, 62 STAN. L.REV. (forthcoming 2010) available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/<br />

papers.cfm?abstract_id=1434254, at 104.<br />

132. 523 U.S. 574 (1998).<br />

133. 456 U.S. 273 (1982).<br />

134. Kenneth S. Klein, Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal Crashes Rule 8 Pleading Standards on to Unconstitutional<br />

Shores, 88 NEB.L.REV. 261 (2009).


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 925<br />

B. The Less Obvious<br />

There are at least two (and probably three) other, more indirect,<br />

ways in which these cases harm civil rights plaintiffs.<br />

1. The Horns <strong>of</strong> a Dilemma<br />

First, the Pearson-Iqbal interaction threatens to catch a civil<br />

rights plaintiff on the horns <strong>of</strong> a dilemma. Put crudely, the problem is<br />

this: a plaintiff who says enough to satisfy Iqbal will find that he has<br />

said too much and loses because his purported right is not clearly established,<br />

per Pearson. If he says less to survive the qualified immunity<br />

analysis, he will find that he has not said enough to survive dismissal<br />

because <strong>of</strong> Iqbal.<br />

Consider this hypothetical: an aggrieved civil rights plaintiff<br />

(Pete) 135 will file a complaint that alleges the violation <strong>of</strong> some constitutional<br />

right—say, the right to be free from excessive force. Suppose,<br />

though, that the incident involved some relatively unusual circumstances:<br />

a stop-and-frisk, in a car, parked in the garage <strong>of</strong> the individual’s<br />

home. The plaintiff might argue that his constitutional rights<br />

were violated, namely, his right to be free from excessive force during<br />

a stop-and-frisk that occurs in or adjacent to one’s home.<br />

Now, however, the Supreme Court has decided Pearson. The right<br />

to be free from excessive force during a stop-and-frisk in one’s car adjacent<br />

to one’s house is a rather narrow definition <strong>of</strong> the right in<br />

question. Suppose that Pete lives in a circuit that has not decided<br />

whether such a right exists. Pete is concerned, having read Pearson,<br />

that the district court will simply conclude that the right is not clearly<br />

established and he will be left high-and-dry.<br />

But Pete is a bright fellow, as hypothetical individuals tend to be.<br />

So Pete decides he will simply claim a violation <strong>of</strong> his right to be free<br />

from excessive force at the hands <strong>of</strong> a police <strong>of</strong>ficer. This right is<br />

clearly established, and he does not run into the Pearson problem.<br />

Alas, it is not to be for our friend Pete. “Threadbare recitals <strong>of</strong> the<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> a cause <strong>of</strong> action, supported by mere conclusory statements,<br />

do not suffice[!]” 136 By reframing his cause <strong>of</strong> action in more<br />

general terms, he has avoided the Scylla <strong>of</strong> Pearson only to get<br />

caught on the Charybdis <strong>of</strong> Iqbal: his more general pleading will be<br />

seen as conclusory. And if it is not, a court exercising its “common<br />

sense” (as Iqbal instructs) could well conclude that the claim was not<br />

“plausible”—if Pete really had a claim, why would he frame it so<br />

135. The plaintiff’s name in a hypothetical always begins with “P.” For the uninitiated,<br />

that’s how these things work.<br />

136. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal, 129 S. Ct. 1937, 1949 (2009).


926 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

broadly instead <strong>of</strong> focusing on the specific facts and cause <strong>of</strong> action<br />

that he is pressing?<br />

And so this is the dilemma: say too much, and you lose because <strong>of</strong><br />

Pearson; say too little, and you lose because <strong>of</strong> Iqbal.<br />

The problem can be more vividly illustrated by the facts <strong>of</strong> a case<br />

recently decided by the federal district court in Connecticut. In DiStiso<br />

v. Wolcott, Robin DiStiso sued various school <strong>of</strong>ficials on behalf <strong>of</strong><br />

Nicholas, her minor son. 137 Robin alleged, inter alia, that the other<br />

students at school harassed, taunted, and assaulted Nicholas because<br />

<strong>of</strong> his race. 138 She further alleged that she complained to Nicholas’s<br />

first-grade teacher, Tammy Couture, and the principal, John Cook,<br />

and they did nothing to respond to the complaints. 139 Robin and her<br />

husband testified to this effect at their depositions. 140 For their part,<br />

Couture and Cook stated in affidavits that they never observed such<br />

conduct and never received such complaints from the parents. 141<br />

It is clear that these allegations do not make out a claim <strong>of</strong> intentional<br />

discrimination against Nicholas. It is not as if, for example,<br />

Couture gave Nicholas a failing grade because <strong>of</strong> her racial animus<br />

toward him. Instead, Robin proceeded on a theory <strong>of</strong> deliberate indifference.<br />

The Second Circuit had at least partially explained how such<br />

suits should proceed some years earlier, writing that “deliberate indifference<br />

can be found when the defendant’s response to known discrimination<br />

‘is clearly unreasonable in light <strong>of</strong> the known circumstances.’<br />

” 142 Robin therefore had to demonstrate that there was evidence<br />

from which a rational fact-finder could conclude that (1) the<br />

students were harassing Nicholas on the basis <strong>of</strong> his race; (2) Couture<br />

and Cook were aware <strong>of</strong> this harassment; and (3) their response,<br />

or lack there<strong>of</strong>, was “clearly unreasonable.” 143<br />

What this leaves out is any consideration <strong>of</strong> the effect <strong>of</strong> the deliberate<br />

indifference on Nicholas himself. The courts had, however,<br />

spoken to the question in the context <strong>of</strong> deliberate indifference to<br />

student-on-student sexual harassment. The Supreme Court held in<br />

Davis v. Monroe County 144 that, in the context <strong>of</strong> Title IX, a school<br />

could be liable if it is deliberately indifferent to student-on-student<br />

sexual harassment. But Davis also held that, in order to prevail, the<br />

137. 539 F. Supp. 2d 562, 563 (D. Conn. 2008), vacated and remanded, 352 F. App’x<br />

478 (2d Cir. 2009). The Second Circuit remanded because the District Court’s treatment <strong>of</strong><br />

qualified immunity was “cursory,” although this does not really affect my analysis here.<br />

138. Id. at 564.<br />

139. Id. at 566.<br />

140. Id. at 568.<br />

141. See id. There were other claims in the complaint, but in my analysis here I only<br />

focus on the deliberate indifference discrimination claim.<br />

142. Gant v. Wallingford Bd. <strong>of</strong> Educ., 195 F.3d 134, 141 (2d Cir. 1999).<br />

143. DiStiso, 539 F. Supp. 2d at 567.<br />

144. 526 U.S. 629, 633 (1999).


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 927<br />

harassment must have been “so severe, pervasive, and objectively <strong>of</strong>fensive<br />

that it can be said to deprive the victims <strong>of</strong> access to the educational<br />

opportunities or benefits provided by the school.” 145 Gant, the<br />

Second Circuit case regarding student-on-student racial harassment,<br />

had declined to decide whether such a racially-hostile educational<br />

environment was necessary in a deliberate indifference race discrimination<br />

claim brought under the Equal Protection Clause. 146<br />

If this case had come about after Pearson-Iqbal, Robin and Nicholas<br />

would find themselves caught on precisely the dilemma I described<br />

above. 147 If they pled a very specific constitutional right—the<br />

right to be free from race discrimination, premised on a theory <strong>of</strong> deliberate<br />

indifference—they might find their claim dismissed by Pearson;<br />

a court could conclude that the right in question is not “clearly<br />

established” because no relevant court had decided whether a hostile<br />

educational environment was a required part <strong>of</strong> such a claim. If Robin<br />

and Nicholas pled their claim at a level <strong>of</strong> generality—say, simply<br />

the right to be free from racial discrimination—they would almost<br />

certainly lose because <strong>of</strong> Iqbal. Any allegations regarding intentional,<br />

active discrimination by Cook or Couture would be conclusory because<br />

the real nub <strong>of</strong> the claim against them (on this count) was not<br />

that they did discriminatory things to Nicholas; it was that they willfully<br />

ignored others’ discriminatory treatment. In such a context, any<br />

allegation Cook or Couture actively engaged in discriminatory conduct<br />

would be seen as “conclusory,” as the allegations discarded by<br />

the Supreme Court in Iqbal.<br />

And so, in a Pearson-Iqbal world, Robin and Nicholas would be<br />

stuck. They could plead the violation <strong>of</strong> a specific constitutional<br />

right—indeed, the one that is most directly applicable to the fact pattern—and<br />

risk getting tossed by Pearson. Or they could plead the violation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a more general constitutional right and risk getting thrown<br />

out by Iqbal.<br />

There are several important implications here. The first, <strong>of</strong> course,<br />

is the interaction between Pearson and Iqbal makes life very difficult<br />

for civil rights litigants and their lawyers. The second is the interaction<br />

between the two cases makes a stand-alone problem even worse.<br />

Recall that Pearson, by its own terms, would be undesirable because<br />

it risks stagnation <strong>of</strong> constitutional law. This dissuades litigants from<br />

pressing novel constitutional theories. However, when operating in<br />

tandem, the cases make it difficult even to plead existing constitutional<br />

theories. The Second Circuit had already held school <strong>of</strong>ficials<br />

145. Id. at 650.<br />

146. See Gant, 195 F.3d at 140 n.5 (declining to answer the question and noting some <strong>of</strong><br />

the aspects <strong>of</strong> Davis may have turned on the fact it was a Title IX case).<br />

147. The difference, <strong>of</strong> course, would be that the real-life plaintiffs’ names do not necessarily<br />

start with “P.”


928 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

could be liable by virtue <strong>of</strong> their deliberate indifference. 148 Robin and<br />

Nicholas would get tripped up by Pearson-Iqbal even if they pled a<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> race discrimination that had been recognized since 1999.<br />

Of course, there is no guarantee this case would get tripped up by<br />

the interaction effect. But rather than mitigate the problem, this possibility<br />

actually underscores it. Pearson gives courts the discretion to<br />

decide which step <strong>of</strong> the qualified immunity analysis to address first,<br />

and Iqbal tells courts to make “common sense” decisions. But this rather<br />

wide-ranging discretion makes it nearly impossible to predict<br />

how a court will respond to a particular fact pattern. 149<br />

In its decision in Iqbal, the Second Circuit recognized a version <strong>of</strong><br />

the problem I describe. 150 The court noted Rule 8 establishes a rather<br />

liberal pleading standard. However, this standard, “when applied<br />

mechanically without countervailing discovery safeguards, threatens<br />

to create a dilemma between adhering to the Federal Rules and abiding<br />

by the principle that qualified immunity is an immunity from suit<br />

as well as from liability.” 151 The Supreme Court avoided this dilemma<br />

by raising the pleading bar in Iqbal and permitting courts to more<br />

easily dismiss claims on the basis <strong>of</strong> immunity in Pearson. But the<br />

pendulum has swung too far; in trying to shield government <strong>of</strong>ficials<br />

from liability, the Court has thrust civil rights litigants into an untenable,<br />

damned-if-you-do-damned-if-you-don’t position.<br />

After making this rather sweeping point I will qualify it in two respects.<br />

First, it must be acknowledged that Iqbal and Pearson do not<br />

necessarily interact in every single case. Iqbal’s standards apply to<br />

the allegations a plaintiff must make regarding the actions that the<br />

defendant(s) took toward him. Pearson applies to the showing a<br />

plaintiff must make regarding the constitutional right that was violated.<br />

Although these will <strong>of</strong>ten overlap—as in the examples<br />

above—they need not overlap in every case. For example, we could<br />

modify the facts <strong>of</strong> Nicholas’s case slightly. Imagine that Nicholas’s<br />

teachers regularly made him sit in the corner <strong>of</strong> the classroom,<br />

picked on him, and otherwise singled him out for derogatory treatment<br />

on account <strong>of</strong> his race. The right to be free from intentional racial<br />

discrimination by the defendants (as opposed to deliberate indifference<br />

discrimination) has long been clearly established. Therefore,<br />

the claim would proceed to trial.<br />

Suppose, though, that Nicholas wants to also press a claim that the<br />

discrimination he suffered was not just because Couture hated him but<br />

148. Gant, 195 F.3d at 150.<br />

149. I discuss the problem with the cases’ approach to lower court discussion in more<br />

detail in Subsection III.B.2 infra.<br />

150. Iqbal v. Hasty, 490 F.3d 143 (2d Cir. 2007).<br />

151. Id. at 159.


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 929<br />

also because Cook had directed a conspiracy to deprive black students<br />

<strong>of</strong> an education. Nicholas would have to allege facts sufficient to establish<br />

that Couture discriminated against him (a straight discrimination<br />

claim), but he would also have to allege facts regarding the conspiracy<br />

involving Cook (a § 1985 civil rights conspiracy claim). In this scenario,<br />

fairly simple allegations would get Nicholas past a motion to dismiss<br />

as against Couture. The Iqbal problem would come up—just as it did<br />

in Iqbal—in the context <strong>of</strong> attempting to plead sufficient allegations to<br />

make out a conspiracy claim. But this problem would be one <strong>of</strong> pleading<br />

alone and would not implicate the constitutional right at issue, and<br />

therefore would not implicate Pearson.<br />

The real question (and one that is unknowable at this early stage)<br />

is how many cases will involve the dilemma I identify and how many<br />

will be relatively straightforward. What we can say is this: Iqbal will<br />

be problematic in any case where the very detail a plaintiff has to<br />

plead (per Iqbal) to make her claim takes her out <strong>of</strong> the clearly established<br />

realm. Pre-Pearson, she could at least plead enough “Iqbal detail,”<br />

so to speak, and be assured that she would get a ruling on the<br />

constitutional right at issue (Saucier step 1). Now, she is not even assured<br />

that much and will likely get kicked out on a motion to dismiss.<br />

Moreover, as Nicholas’s example demonstrates, this can be problematic<br />

even in non-cutting-edge cases. For example, in Saucier, the<br />

issue was one <strong>of</strong> excessive force. But the Court was clear it was not<br />

testing whether the general right to be free from excessive force during<br />

an arrest was clearly established; the right has to be defined at a<br />

greater level <strong>of</strong> particularity. So the § 1983 plaintiff’s attorney has to<br />

decide: “how specifically am I going to define this right?” Even in the<br />

variation on Nicholas’s case I gave above, one could imagine that<br />

Cook had promulgated a policy that might be read as being “aggressive”<br />

toward certain students (or some such), a policy that might<br />

plausibly suggest a “discrimination conspiracy.” But if the right must<br />

be defined at a greater level <strong>of</strong> particularity (per Anderson, etc.), then<br />

we are back to the interaction problem: more specificity risks the<br />

possibility the pleadings are no longer “Iqbal compliant” (though they<br />

may have been when operating at a level <strong>of</strong> generality).<br />

There is another issue. At the motion to dismiss stage, a court<br />

must determine, as a threshold matter, whether the facts alleged by<br />

the plaintiff, viewed most favorably to him, make out a constitutional<br />

violation. However, as a group <strong>of</strong> law pr<strong>of</strong>essors explained in their<br />

amicus brief in Iqbal:<br />

[W]hat is now described as the first step is, in fact, only a reflection<br />

<strong>of</strong> the plaintiff’s standard obligation to show her entitlement to relief<br />

under Rule 8(a)(2). As a matter <strong>of</strong> trans-substantive procedural law,<br />

a failure to make such a showing in any case would trigger a Rule<br />

12(b)(6) motion to dismiss for failure to state a claim. No different


930 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

rule applies to constitutional claims, for nothing in this Court’s qualified<br />

immunity jurisprudence suggests that the first element should<br />

be accorded any specialized treatment or scrutiny. 152<br />

In other words, if the facts viewed most favorably to the plaintiff<br />

did not make out a constitutional violation, not only would the defendant<br />

be entitled to qualified immunity, the complaint (at least as to<br />

that claim) would also be dismissed.<br />

This demonstrates another interaction effect between Pearson and<br />

Iqbal. Because Iqbal effectively raises pleading standards, thus requiring<br />

more for a plaintiff to defeat a Rule 12(b)(6) motion to dismiss,<br />

it correspondingly has the effect <strong>of</strong> raising the bar for plaintiffs<br />

at the first step <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity. Again, Iqbal makes no mention<br />

<strong>of</strong> this fact.<br />

In sum, there are two ways the interaction between Pearson and<br />

Iqbal is bad for civil rights plaintiffs. First, a plaintiff faces a potentially<br />

untenable situation with regard to how narrowly to define the<br />

constitutional right at issue. Pleading the claim narrowly might<br />

render the claim so novel as not to be “clearly established,” and the<br />

plaintiff would lose straight away because <strong>of</strong> Pearson and not even<br />

get a ruling on the constitutional merits. But pleading the claim<br />

broadly might require allegations at a level <strong>of</strong> generality and therefore<br />

get discarded because they are “conclusory” or otherwise not<br />

“plausible.” Second, by raising the pleading standard, Iqbal has effectively<br />

raised the bar for “Saucier step one.” 153 Neither the subsequent<br />

case law nor the academic commentary—let alone Pearson and Iqbal<br />

themselves—recognizes this problem.<br />

2. Discretion That Only Cuts One Way<br />

The second way in which Pearson and Iqbal are problematic relates<br />

to their treatment <strong>of</strong> the discretion a lower court has. The cases<br />

simultaneously expand and contract the permissible bounds <strong>of</strong> a district<br />

court’s discretion—but only do so in a way that makes it easier<br />

to dismiss civil rights lawsuits.<br />

Pearson gives district courts the discretion to skip directly to step<br />

two <strong>of</strong> the qualified immunity analysis. “The judges <strong>of</strong> the district<br />

courts and the courts <strong>of</strong> appeals should be permitted to exercise their<br />

sound discretion in deciding which <strong>of</strong> the two prongs <strong>of</strong> the qualified<br />

immunity analysis should be addressed first in light <strong>of</strong> the circums-<br />

152. Brief <strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essors <strong>of</strong> Civil Procedure and Federal Practice as Amici Curiae in<br />

Support <strong>of</strong> Respondents at 29-30, Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal, 129 S. Ct. 1937 (2009) (No. 07-1015).<br />

153. This will be most problematic for plaintiffs who have already prevailed on a motion<br />

to dismiss (pre-Iqbal) but who now face a motion to dismiss on the basis <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity<br />

(post-Iqbal). Such a plaintiff would have made the requisite showing under the old standard<br />

but will now lose if those allegations are deemed insufficient under the new standard.


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 931<br />

tances in the particular case at hand.” 154 To be sure, this does not<br />

mean that courts will never use Saucier sequencing. The Supreme<br />

Court has noted the sequence is “<strong>of</strong>ten beneficial,” 155 and courts have<br />

heeded this advice and continued to adhere to the sequence in certain<br />

cases. For example, in Kelsey v. County <strong>of</strong> Schoharie, 156 the Second<br />

Circuit noted the sequential analysis “is said to be appropriate in”<br />

certain types <strong>of</strong> cases, and “[t]his is such a case.” 157 The court explained<br />

that:<br />

[D]evelopment <strong>of</strong> constitutional precedent is especially important<br />

here, where (1) this Court has not spoken on the issue <strong>of</strong> the constitutionality<br />

<strong>of</strong> [the procedure sub judice] although the issue has<br />

been presented in district courts in this circuit . . . ; and (2) the<br />

constitutionality <strong>of</strong> [the procedure] may never be developed if this<br />

Court were to dispose <strong>of</strong> all challenges relating to the procedures<br />

simply because the procedure is not “clearly established.” 158<br />

In so holding, the Second Circuit recognized (and avoided) the<br />

problem I identified above, namely, that courts’ regularly moving to<br />

“step two” would restrict the development <strong>of</strong> constitutional law. 159<br />

However, far more courts—dozens, in just a few months after Pearson—have<br />

skipped directly to the second step <strong>of</strong> the analysis. 160<br />

As Hughes’s empirical study makes clear, when sequencing is<br />

mandatory—or at least strongly suggested—courts will engage in it<br />

more <strong>of</strong>ten. My early survey <strong>of</strong> post-Pearson cases indicates courts<br />

are indeed engaging in sequencing less frequently.<br />

Although this point is related to the one made earlier (that Pearson<br />

harms civil rights plaintiffs because it limits the development <strong>of</strong><br />

constitutional law), it is distinct. My point in this section is not just<br />

that it is easier to dismiss civil rights claims against personal-<br />

154. Pearson v. Callahan, 129 S. Ct. 808, 818 (2009).<br />

155. Id.<br />

156. 567 F.3d 54 (2d Cir. 2009).<br />

157. Id. at 61.<br />

158. Id. at 61-62 (citations omitted).<br />

159. See supra Part 0.<br />

160. See, e.g., Swanson v. Town <strong>of</strong> Mountain View, 577 F.3d 1196, 1199, (10th Cir.<br />

2009) (“The <strong>of</strong>ficers contend that even assuming a constitutional violation . . . it was not<br />

clearly established . . . . We agree.”); Waeschle v. Dragovic, 576 F.3d 539, 544 (6th Cir.<br />

2009) (resolving the constitutional merits “is unnecessary because . . . [the] purported constitutional<br />

right is not clearly established”); Dean v. Blumenthal, 577 F.3d 60, 66 (2d Cir.<br />

2009) (“[W]e conclude that, regardless <strong>of</strong> whether a right to receive campaign contributions<br />

exists, it was not clearly established . . . and Blumenthal is therefore entitled to qualified<br />

immunity.”); Lewis v. City <strong>of</strong> West Palm Beach, Fla., 561 F.3d 1288, 1291 (11th Cir. 2009)<br />

(“Even if the <strong>of</strong>ficers’ actions violated Lewis’s Fourth Amendment rights, the appellant did<br />

not demonstrate that the <strong>of</strong>ficers’ conduct was an intrusion on a clearly established right.”);<br />

Christensen v. Park City Mun. Corp., 554 F.3d 1271, 1278 (10th Cir. 2009)(“Police <strong>of</strong>ficers<br />

are not constitutional lawyers, and they should not have to fear personal damages liability<br />

when they enforce the plain terms <strong>of</strong> an ordinance that has not been challenged in court,<br />

let alone overturned, unless its unconstitutionality is patent.”).


932 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

capacity defendants. It is that the Supreme Court has given lower<br />

courts the discretion to do so, even though it has given them no corresponding<br />

discretion to preserve such constitutional claims.<br />

Consider, for example, this illustration: a prisoner, who holds certain<br />

religious beliefs, sues prison <strong>of</strong>ficials for failing to provide him a<br />

diet that comports with his religious beliefs (say, vegan). Suppose a<br />

prisoner-plaintiff makes all <strong>of</strong> the necessary showings at the summary<br />

judgment stage regarding the constitutional violation. However,<br />

the district court concludes that, at the time <strong>of</strong> the alleged violation,<br />

the right was not clearly established. Per Pearson, the court will<br />

be free to grant the defendant(s) immunity.<br />

Now suppose the prisoner has demonstrated at the summary<br />

judgment stage that prison <strong>of</strong>ficials knew he was a vegan, denied him<br />

vegan meals, and knew he adhered to a particular religion. Suppose<br />

further that this alleged violation took place at such a time that the<br />

right was clearly established within the relevant jurisdiction. However,<br />

it was not clear whether there was evidence from which a jury<br />

could conclude that the prisoner’s veganism derived from a sincerely<br />

held religious belief, the threshold belief in any such case. 161 Under<br />

the prevailing law, the court would be within its rights to dismiss the<br />

claim because the plaintiff had not put forth evidence from which a<br />

fact-finder could conclude his rights had been violated. But nothing<br />

in Pearson—or any other case—explicitly directs courts to exercise<br />

their discretion to require further elaboration <strong>of</strong> threshold questions.<br />

And although district courts are routinely said to possess various inherent<br />

powers, 162 a court that went out <strong>of</strong> its way to exercise discretion<br />

on behalf <strong>of</strong> a civil rights plaintiff in this context would probably<br />

be held to have exceeded its discretion. This is because, as the Supreme<br />

Court has repeatedly instructed, qualified immunity is not<br />

just an immunity from having to pay damages, but immunity from<br />

having to participate in litigation at all. 163 A defendant who makes a<br />

poor showing on Saucier step one can still appeal to the district<br />

court’s discretion to decide step two first. But a plaintiff who makes a<br />

poor showing on either step very likely cannot appeal to such discretion<br />

because the court’s discretion is limited, if it exists at all. 164<br />

161. See, e.g., DeHart v. Horn, 227 F.3d 47, 51 (3d Cir. 2000).<br />

162. See, e.g., Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. <strong>of</strong> Educ., 402 U.S. 1, 15 (1971)<br />

(“Once a right and a violation have been shown, the scope <strong>of</strong> a district court’s equitable<br />

powers to remedy past wrongs is broad, for breadth and flexibility are inherent in equitable<br />

remedies.”); United <strong>State</strong>s v. $40,955.00 in U.S. Currency, 554 F.3d 752, 758 (9th Cir.<br />

2009) (noting a district court’s “inherent power to control litigation”).<br />

163. See, e.g., Pearson v. Callahan, 129 S. Ct. 808, 815 (2009).<br />

164. As described earlier, see supra Part 0, the Court’s jurisprudence over the last<br />

three decades has been in the direction <strong>of</strong> limiting the scope <strong>of</strong> civil rights litigation, both<br />

substantively (by establishing the qualified immunity doctrine, see Harlow v. Fitzgerald,


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 933<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the justifications for this one-way discretion is that it will be<br />

more efficient. Yet this justification does not hold water on closer inspection.<br />

This is because an attorney—wanting to cover all bases—<br />

would presumably argue (1) there was no constitutional violation, and<br />

(2) even if there was, the purported right was not clearly established.<br />

This is precisely what the defendant-appellants did in Green v.<br />

Post, to take an example that came about shortly after Pearson. 165<br />

The Tenth Circuit concluded the <strong>of</strong>ficer’s conduct did not violate a<br />

constitutional right. 166 However, the court continued, “[a]lternatively,<br />

even were we to conclude that the Greens can establish a constitutional<br />

violation . . . we would conclude that Deputy Post is entitled to<br />

qualified immunity because the law was not clearly established at<br />

the time <strong>of</strong> the incident.” 167 This discussion is plainly unnecessary to<br />

the result in the case: having concluded that no constitutional violation<br />

had occurred, the court could end the qualified immunity inquiry<br />

under any standard, including Saucier. 168 Pearson permits, and as a<br />

practical matter, probably requires, litigants to argue in the alternative.<br />

And as Green demonstrates, this presents the risk <strong>of</strong> courts<br />

speaking to unnecessary legal questions—one <strong>of</strong> the very charges leveled<br />

at Saucier.<br />

Iqbal also expands and contracts district courts’ discretion in a<br />

way that is problematic for civil rights litigants. The Second Circuit,<br />

in its decision, was acutely aware <strong>of</strong> the tension between Rule 8’s liberal<br />

pleading rules and the policy underlying qualified immunity,<br />

viz., the need to protect government <strong>of</strong>ficials not only from liability<br />

but also from litigation itself. Therefore, though the court concluded<br />

that Iqbal’s complaint had stated a viable claim, it cautioned the district<br />

court to keep a close eye on the litigation. The discussion focused<br />

principally on the discretion that district courts possess. For example,<br />

“mindful <strong>of</strong> the need to vindicate the purpose <strong>of</strong> the qualified<br />

immunity defense by dismissing non-meritorious claims against public<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials at an early stage <strong>of</strong> litigation,” a district court could “consider<br />

exercising its discretion to permit some limited and tightly con-<br />

457 U.S. 800 (1982)) and procedurally (by authorizing interlocutory appeals, see Mitchell v.<br />

Forsyth, 472 U.S. 511, 526-27 (1985)).<br />

165. See Appellants’ Opening Brief, Green v. Post, 574 F.3d 1294 (10th Cir. 2009) (No.<br />

08-1122). Post presumably raised the alternative arguments because Saucier still controlled<br />

at the time. But the problem persists to this day. See, e.g., Appellee’s Opening Brief,<br />

Olseth v. Larson, No. 10-4015, 2010 WL 2397296, at *23 (June 4, 2010) (“Even if this Court<br />

[concludes that there was a constitutional violation], Larson is still entitled to qualified<br />

immunity because Olseth cannot demonstrate that Larson’s decision to shoot her was contrary<br />

to clearly established law at the time <strong>of</strong> the violation.”).<br />

166. See Green, 574 F.3d at 1304.<br />

167. Id.<br />

168. See Saucier v. Katz, 533 U.S. 194, 201 (2001) (“If no constitutional right would<br />

have been violated were the allegations established, there is no necessity for further inquiries<br />

concerning qualified immunity.”).


934 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

trolled reciprocal discovery so that a defendant may probe for amplification<br />

<strong>of</strong> a plaintiff's claims and a plaintiff may probe such matters<br />

as a defendant’s knowledge <strong>of</strong> relevant facts and personal involvement<br />

in challenged conduct.” 169<br />

The court was particularly concerned about the prospect <strong>of</strong> “current<br />

or former senior <strong>of</strong>ficials <strong>of</strong> the Government, against whom<br />

broad-ranging allegations <strong>of</strong> knowledge and personal involvement are<br />

easily made.” 170 Therefore, it suggested,<br />

a district court [could] structure such limited discovery by examining<br />

written responses to interrogatories and requests to admit before<br />

authorizing depositions, and by deferring discovery directed to<br />

high-level <strong>of</strong>ficials until discovery <strong>of</strong> front-line <strong>of</strong>ficials has been<br />

completed and has demonstrated the need for discovery higher up<br />

the ranks. If discovery directed to current or former senior <strong>of</strong>ficials<br />

becomes warranted, a district court might also consider making all<br />

such discovery subject to prior court approval. 171<br />

The Second Circuit explained that the liberal standard <strong>of</strong> Rule 8,<br />

“when applied mechanically without countervailing discovery safeguards,<br />

threatens to create a dilemma between adhering to the Federal<br />

Rules and abiding by the principle that qualified immunity is an<br />

immunity from suit as well as from liability.” 172 Therefore, it explained<br />

that in cases such as Iqbal, a lower court “not only may, but ‘must exercise<br />

its discretion in a way that protects the substance <strong>of</strong> the qualified<br />

immunity defense.’ ” 173 The district court was also required to provide<br />

an opportunity for defendants to move for summary judgment as<br />

soon as it was apparent “that certain <strong>of</strong> the Defendants were not sufficiently<br />

involved in the alleged violations to support a finding <strong>of</strong> personal<br />

liability, or that no constitutional violation took place.” 174<br />

The Second Circuit’s focus on district courts’ discretion was not<br />

isolated or unusual. For years, the Supreme Court had instructed<br />

courts to exercise their discretion in precisely the way the Second<br />

Circuit suggested, managing the course <strong>of</strong> litigation in such a way<br />

that gave plaintiffs the opportunity to determine facts not within<br />

their power to ascertain at the complaint stage while simultaneously<br />

preserving the essence <strong>of</strong> the immunity defense for defendants.<br />

More than a decade ago, in Crawford-El v. Britton, 175 the Supreme<br />

Court explained this process. The court has the power to order a reply<br />

169. Iqbal v. Hasty, 490 F.3d 143, 158 (2d Cir. 2007).<br />

170. Id.<br />

171. Id.<br />

172. Id. at 159.<br />

173. Id. (quoting Crawford-El v. Britton, 523 U.S. 574, 597-98 (1998) (emphasis in Iqbal)).<br />

174. Id. at 159 (citing Harlow v. Fitzgerald, 457 U.S. 800, 821 (1982) (Brennan,<br />

J. concurring)).<br />

175. 523 U.S. 574 (1998).


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 935<br />

to the defendant’s answer per Rule 7 or require a more definite statement<br />

<strong>of</strong> the plaintiff’s claims per Rule 12. “Thus, the [district] court<br />

may insist that the plaintiff put forward specific, nonconclusory factual<br />

allegations that establish improper motive causing cognizable injury in<br />

order to survive a prediscovery motion for dismissal or summary<br />

judgment.” 176 This passage is important. In Iqbal, the Court instructed<br />

that conclusory allegations must be disregarded altogether. Yet in<br />

Crawford-El, the Court explained that judges had the discretion to order<br />

fuller explication <strong>of</strong> claims pertaining to a defendant’s state <strong>of</strong><br />

mind. Iqbal makes no mention <strong>of</strong> Crawford-El (in either the majority<br />

or dissent), and therefore litigants and commentators must assume it<br />

is still good law. 177 Yet it is difficult, if not impossible, to square the<br />

two. Crawford-El devotes an entire section to “the existing procedures<br />

available to federal trial judges in handling claims that involve examination<br />

<strong>of</strong> an <strong>of</strong>ficial’s state <strong>of</strong> mind.” 178 Iqbal flatly states, without any<br />

acknowledgement <strong>of</strong> Crawford-El, “We have held . . . that the question<br />

presented by a motion to dismiss a complaint for insufficient pleadings<br />

does not turn on the controls placed upon the discovery process.” 179 The<br />

only citation for this proposition is Twombly, though Twombly did not<br />

implicate “claims that involve examination <strong>of</strong> an <strong>of</strong>ficial’s state <strong>of</strong><br />

mind,” 180 and thus it is unclear why Twombly has more relevance to<br />

the case than Crawford-El.<br />

Courts have regularly permitted narrow or otherwise carefully<br />

managed discovery as a method to test the viability <strong>of</strong> a plaintiff’s<br />

claims while shielding a defendant from the burdens <strong>of</strong> full-blown<br />

discovery. For example, district courts routinely permit or deny limited<br />

discovery to determine whether personal jurisdiction exists in<br />

a given district, based on the facts <strong>of</strong> the particular cases. 181 Although<br />

the precise standard regarding jurisdictional discovery varies by cir-<br />

176. Id. at 598 (emphasis added and internal quotation marks omitted).<br />

177. See, e.g., Agostini v. Felton, 521 U.S. 203, 238 (1997) (“ ‘[I]f a precedent <strong>of</strong> [the Supreme]<br />

Court has direct application in a case, yet appears to rest on reasons rejected in some<br />

other line <strong>of</strong> decisions, the Court <strong>of</strong> Appeals should follow the case which directly controls,<br />

leaving to this Court the prerogative <strong>of</strong> overruling its own decisions.’ ”) (emphasis added)<br />

(quoting Rodriguez de Quijas v. Shearson/American Express, Inc., 490 U.S. 477, 484 (1989)).<br />

178. Crawford-El, 523 U.S. at 597.<br />

179. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal, 129 S. Ct. 1937, 1953 (2009).<br />

180. Crawford-El, 523 U.S. at 597.<br />

181. See, e.g., Mother Doe I v. Al Maktoum, 632 F. Supp. 2d 1130, 1144 (S.D. Fla. 2007)<br />

(“It is well-accepted that a qualified right to jurisdictional discovery exists.”); Pettengill v.<br />

Curtis, 584 F. Supp. 2d 348, 361 (D. Mass. 2008) (denying plaintiff’s motion for jurisdictional<br />

discovery because he failed to provide “specific allegations that might give rise to<br />

personal jurisdiction,” but noting that if discovery “develops evidence demonstrating personal<br />

jurisdiction” over the dismissed defendants, plaintiff “may move to have them added<br />

as parties again”); 7240 Shawnee Mission Holding, LLC v. Memon, No. 08-2207-JWL, 2008<br />

WL 4001159, *4 (D. Kan., Aug. 26, 2008) (“The court finds that based on these exhibits and<br />

the showing <strong>of</strong> controverted facts related to jurisdiction, Plaintiffs should be allowed limited<br />

discovery regarding personal jurisdiction.”).


936 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

cuit, 182 these and similar decisions are described as being within the<br />

discretion <strong>of</strong> the district court. 183 The Supreme Court has even recently<br />

held that a district court has the discretion to decide a defendant’s<br />

motion to dismiss on the basis <strong>of</strong> forum non conveniens, even before<br />

deciding whether it has subject matter jurisdiction. 184 The viability <strong>of</strong><br />

such procedures is in some doubt after Iqbal, since a borderline complaint<br />

is now to be dismissed outright. 185<br />

Consider, in this same vein, Rule 9(b)’s requirement that fraud<br />

must be pled with particularity. The Supreme Court explained in Iqbal<br />

that “particularity” is a relative term; it simply indicates that<br />

more is required for a fraud claim, not that state <strong>of</strong> mind and the like<br />

(which may be alleged “generally”) can pass muster with less than<br />

the Rule 8 minimum. 186 Yet the circuits were in agreement, pre-<br />

Iqbal, that Rule 9(b)’s requirements were relaxed when the facts material<br />

to a fraud claim were in the defendant’s exclusive possession<br />

and could be obtained only through discovery. 187 These cases, too, are<br />

apparently still good law; at least one district court has recently applied<br />

this standard, even after Iqbal. 188 But again, the case law is<br />

hard to square. Iqbal did not permit a case to go forward when there<br />

were general allegations against government <strong>of</strong>ficials. It is hard to<br />

imagine that the common practice <strong>of</strong> permitting cases that were subject<br />

to a heightened standard to go forward can be maintained after<br />

182. GTE New Media Services, Inc. v. BellSouth Corp., 199 F.3d 1343, 1351 (D.C. Cir.<br />

2000) (permitting jurisdictional discovery even when plaintiff’s complaint did not make out<br />

a prima facie case); Jazini v. Nissan Motor Co., Ltd., 148 F.3d 181, 185-86 (2d Cir. 1998)<br />

(holding that the district court acted within its discretion to deny jurisdictional discovery<br />

when plaintiffs did not establish a prima facie showing <strong>of</strong> jurisdiction); Central <strong>State</strong>s,<br />

Southeast and Southwest Areas Pension Fund v. Reimer Express World Corp., 230 F.3d<br />

934, 946-47 (7th Cir. 2000) (same).<br />

183. See, e.g., Af-Cap, Inc. v. Chevron Overseas (Congo), Ltd., 475 F.3d 1080, 1096 (9th<br />

Cir. 2007) (“The district court did not abuse this broad discretion when it limited discovery<br />

related to whether there was personal jurisdiction . . . .”); Sunview Condo. Ass’n v. Flexel<br />

Int’l, Ltd., 116 F.3d 962, 964 (1st Cir. 1997) (permitting jurisdictional discovery subject to<br />

the discretion <strong>of</strong> the district court).<br />

184. Sinochem Int’l Co., Ltd. v. Malaysia Int’l Shipping Corp., 549 U.S. 422, 425 (2007).<br />

185. This may overstate the issue somewhat, but only somewhat. Even pre-Iqbal,<br />

courts had long held that bare assertions <strong>of</strong> contact with the forum were insufficient to<br />

trigger jurisdictional discovery. See, e.g., McLaughlin v. McPhail, 707 F.2d 800, 806-07 (4th<br />

Cir. 1983). However, Iqbal still changes this landscape because a marginal complaint is<br />

never to proceed to discovery, limited, carefully managed, or otherwise. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal,<br />

129 S. Ct. 1937, 1953 (2009).<br />

186. Iqbal,129 S. Ct. at 1954.<br />

187. See, e.g., Emery v. Am. Gen. Fin., Inc., 134 F.3d 1321, 1323 (7th Cir. 1998); In re<br />

Burlington Coat Factory Securities Litigation, 114 F.3d 1410, 1418 (3d Cir. 1997); Kowal v.<br />

MCI Comm. Corp., 16 F.3d 1271, 1279 n.3 (D.C. Cir. 1994) (noting that pleading on information<br />

and belief is permitted when the evidence at issue is within the defendant’s control);<br />

Devaney v. Chester, 813 F.2d 566, 569 (2d Cir. 1987) (noting “the degree <strong>of</strong> particularity<br />

required [by Rule 9(b)] should be determined in light <strong>of</strong> such circumstances as<br />

whether the plaintiff has had an opportunity to take discovery <strong>of</strong> those who may possess<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> the pertinent facts.”).<br />

188. Morrison v. YTB Int’l, Inc., 641 F. Supp. 2d 768, 774-75 (S.D. Ill. 2009).


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 937<br />

Iqbal. But if that line <strong>of</strong> cases must be considered abrogated, then it<br />

is clear Iqbal’s analysis, ostensibly in the context <strong>of</strong> Rule 8, has disrupted<br />

the standards applicable to Rule 9(b) cases as well.<br />

So Iqbal effectively ratchets back district courts’ discretion, instructing<br />

them to dismiss a complaint outright when a complaint’s<br />

well-pleaded factual allegations are deemed implausible. But it also<br />

expands district courts’ discretion in another, important direction: it<br />

instructs courts to make this decision based on their “judicial experience<br />

and common sense.” 189 The problem, <strong>of</strong> course, is that this kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> a determination is so open-ended as to be almost unreviewable. 190<br />

And <strong>of</strong> course there is the question <strong>of</strong> how a case should proceed<br />

when the appellate court’s “common sense” deviates from that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

district court (or when there is a split within an appellate panel).<br />

Common sense should be, well, common—shared by diverse individuals.<br />

Courts will now have the task <strong>of</strong> formulating a workable standard<br />

for “common sense” (The court’s? Which court? The litigants? A<br />

reasonable third-party observer’s?), and then determining the proper<br />

standard <strong>of</strong> review for such a determination. 191<br />

C. So What? The Case Against Procedural Activism<br />

On one level, this might seem like much ado about nothing. District<br />

courts are vested with wide discretion in many areas <strong>of</strong> law, including<br />

some <strong>of</strong> the most important decisions that are made in criminal<br />

sentencing. 192 And different doctrinal areas <strong>of</strong> law intersect—and<br />

interact—all the time. To cite one relevant example, Rule 9(b)’s requirement<br />

<strong>of</strong> particularized allegations <strong>of</strong> fraud is at least arguably<br />

in tension with the “broad and liberal” 193 interpretation that is to apply<br />

to the discovery rules. What’s the big deal here?<br />

The big deal, at least in my view, is the interactions between<br />

Pearson and Iqbal all cut in the same direction. For example, in the<br />

context <strong>of</strong> fraud claims, Rule 9’s particularity requirement cuts<br />

189. Iqbal, 129 S. Ct. at 1950.<br />

190. See Joan Steinman, Irregulars: The Appellate Rights <strong>of</strong> Persons Who Are Not Full-<br />

Fledged Parties, 39 GA. L.REV. 411, 441 (2005) (noting appellate courts “rarely” conclude<br />

that a district court’s course <strong>of</strong> action was in excess <strong>of</strong> its allowable discretion).<br />

191. As <strong>of</strong> this writing, no Circuit Court <strong>of</strong> Appeals has formulated a standard <strong>of</strong> review<br />

for a district court’s “common sense” determination. So as not to render a “common<br />

sense” finding unreviewable, I suggest the analysis must have two elements: first, it must<br />

not be framed in conclusory terms. Second, the nonconclusory facts that support the determination<br />

must lead to a plausible (not merely possible) conclusion that the plaintiff’s<br />

claims do not meet the “common sense” standard. This formulation, one might notice, has<br />

much in common with the Twombly-Iqbal pleading regime. I <strong>of</strong>fer it only slightly tonguein-cheek;<br />

I do submit that such a standard would <strong>of</strong>fer a reviewing court a better record to<br />

review than a statement by the trial court that was, well . . . conclusory.<br />

192. See United <strong>State</strong>s v. Booker, 543 U.S. 220 (2005); Kimbrough v. United <strong>State</strong>s,<br />

552 U.S. 85 (2007).<br />

193. Hickman v. Taylor, 329 U.S. 495, 507 (1947).


938 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

against plaintiffs (who must plead more to get past a motion to dismiss)<br />

while the liberal discovery rules cut against defendants (who<br />

must subject themselves to greater scrutiny from plaintiffs and their<br />

attorneys). Motions to dismiss under Rule 12 or for summary judgment<br />

under Rule 56 benefit defendants (who can terminate litigation<br />

before trial), but the facts at each stage are, at least in theory, viewed<br />

most favorably to the plaintiff (who may ultimately prove disputed<br />

facts if the case does go to trial). Indeed, even the most important issue<br />

<strong>of</strong> a civil trial—liability—reflects this balance: a finding <strong>of</strong> liability<br />

cuts against the defendant (who must pay up), but getting to that<br />

point is harder for the plaintiff (who bears the burden <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>).<br />

This kind <strong>of</strong> one-hand, other-hand balancing is conspicuously absent<br />

from Pearson-Iqbal. As I describe above, Pearson (in some cases)<br />

requires a plaintiff to say less, while Iqbal requires a plaintiff to say<br />

more. Neither <strong>of</strong> these cases so much as recognizes this dilemma, let<br />

alone provides a way out. And a way out is not impossible to conceive:<br />

for example, a plaintiff might be permitted to plead “Pearson generality”<br />

at the motion to dismiss stage but be required to adduce some<br />

evidence <strong>of</strong> “Iqbal detail” at the summary judgment stage. This<br />

would not even be much <strong>of</strong> a departure from pre-Iqbal case law: a<br />

plaintiff at the motion to dismiss stage was always entitled to rely on<br />

his pleadings and allegations, while he was generally required to<br />

show more at the summary judgment stage. Pearson-Iqbal, however,<br />

forecloses this kind <strong>of</strong> sliding scale.<br />

So too with the discretion that all cuts one way. Pearson’s rule that<br />

sequencing is now voluntary increases a court’s discretion to dismiss<br />

civil rights claims; Iqbal’s rule that discovery management is an inadequate<br />

tool decreases a court’s ability to preserve civil rights claims;<br />

Iqbal’s directive to rely on common sense increases a court’s ability to<br />

dismiss such claims. Once again, it is possible to devise a rule that<br />

balances the interests <strong>of</strong> civil rights plaintiffs and defendants. For example,<br />

the Supreme Court could have (and I submit should have) announced<br />

the following rule, consistent with Twombly and pre-Twombly<br />

authority: (1) civil rights claims require no heightened pleading standard;<br />

(2) if the allegations regarding a particular defendant’s actions<br />

are “conclusory,” a court is to determine whether the claims against<br />

him are consistent with liability and, if so, whether the facts necessary<br />

to support such a claim are likely to be in the defendant’s possession. If<br />

so, the court could order limited discovery or use other procedural<br />

tools—as described in Crawford-El—to permit the plaintiff an opportunity<br />

to determine if he can make out a claim against the defendant.<br />

If he did, the case would proceed in the normal course; if not, the case<br />

would be dismissed. Again, such a formulation preserves the defendant’s<br />

interest in avoiding discovery intended only to harass, while<br />

permitting the district court to operate with a scalpel rather than a


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 939<br />

mallet (and a rather one-dimensional mallet at that, since a court’s only<br />

option in such a context is dismissal). 194<br />

That is my answer to the “so what?” question. The point is not<br />

that there are new rules (the merits <strong>of</strong> which we can debate) or even<br />

that various rules interact. It is that these rules interact in a way<br />

that harms civil rights plaintiffs and that there has been inadequate<br />

recognition <strong>of</strong> this fact. As a result, the Supreme Court has sharply<br />

constricted the universe <strong>of</strong> potentially successful civil rights claims.<br />

And this is my argument against “procedural judicial activism.”<br />

As Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Miller points out, value judgments underlie every aspect<br />

<strong>of</strong> civil procedure. 195 By cloaking important value judgments in the<br />

seemingly-neutral terms <strong>of</strong> procedure, the Supreme Court has dramatically<br />

altered the landscape for civil rights plaintiffs but managed<br />

to do so largely under the radar. Yet these decisions are no less “activist”<br />

because they involve procedural rules rather than substantive<br />

rights. So I use the term “procedural judicial activism” to refer to a<br />

course <strong>of</strong> action taken by a court that significantly expands, abridges,<br />

alters, or modifies substantive rights by way <strong>of</strong> the operation <strong>of</strong> procedural<br />

rules. A court enlarging or restricting the statute <strong>of</strong> limitations,<br />

for example, would be an example <strong>of</strong> procedural judicial activism.<br />

Similarly, a court altering rules regarding standing, justiciability,<br />

or similar topics qualifies as activist under this definition because<br />

modifications to these rules have a trans-substantive effect. Although<br />

a case could be made that the very creation <strong>of</strong> such rules was activist,<br />

I use a narrower conception <strong>of</strong> the phrase, in which a decision is categorized<br />

as activist if it significantly departs from prior precedent<br />

(even if the prior precedent might be categorized as activist). Thus,<br />

Harlow itself might be characterized as activist for creating the modern<br />

qualified immunity doctrine. However, I bracket that question,<br />

and label a decision activist if it departs from the post-Harlow understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity.<br />

There are others who have written about this kind <strong>of</strong> judicial activism,<br />

or something like it, 196 and an exhaustive analysis <strong>of</strong> the case<br />

194. It is a relevant, but not wholly satisfactory, response to say that dismissal might<br />

be without prejudice. Cf. Iqbal v. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t, 574 F.3d 820 (2d Cir. 2009) (remanding to the<br />

district court to determine, in the first instance, whether plaintiffs should be given leave to<br />

amend their complaint). First, it is likely that only cases “on the bubble,” i.e., pending at<br />

the time Iqbal was decided, will get this benefit; future cases will likely be dismissed outright<br />

for failure to state a claim. Second, leave to replead, while s<strong>of</strong>tening the blow, does<br />

not change the fact that the process is time-consuming and expensive, particularly in civil<br />

rights cases that may be litigated pro bono with the hope <strong>of</strong> attorneys’ fees on the other<br />

end. See 42 U.S.C. § 1988 (permitting attorneys’ fees for a prevailing plaintiff in a civil<br />

rights action).<br />

195. Miller, supra note 1.<br />

196. Soree, for example, writes, “Procedural activism . . . may be suspected when a<br />

court chooses to reach the merits <strong>of</strong> an issue despite justiciability rules that would (or<br />

should) otherwise restrain the court from so doing, or when a court decides more than is


940 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

law and academic literature is beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> this Article. However,<br />

I bring up the issue to highlight an important feature <strong>of</strong> both<br />

Pearson and Iqbal: these decisions were not compelled, either by<br />

precedent or by the questions presented in the cases themselves.<br />

Consider, for example, that overruling Saucier was not even on<br />

the radar when Pearson petitioned the Court for certiorari. It was the<br />

Court, sua sponte, that raised the issue. In its order granting certiorari,<br />

the Court wrote,<br />

Petition for writ <strong>of</strong> certiorari to the United <strong>State</strong>s Court <strong>of</strong> Appeals<br />

for the Tenth Circuit granted. In addition to the questions presented<br />

by the petition, the parties are directed to brief and argue<br />

the following question: “Whether the Court's decision in Saucier v.<br />

Katz, 533 U.S. 194, 121 S. Ct. 2151, 150 L.Ed.2d 272 (2001) should<br />

be overruled?” 197<br />

In so doing, the Court reached out to decide an issue that was neither<br />

raised by the parties nor the court below. Such a course <strong>of</strong> action is<br />

“activist” by virtually any definition. 198<br />

A similar problem afflicts Iqbal. As the dissent points out, the parties<br />

assumed that actual knowledge <strong>of</strong> unconstitutional conduct by<br />

subordinate <strong>of</strong>ficers would subject petitioners Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t and Mueller<br />

to liability. The question was not whether they could be liable; it was<br />

whether, assuming they could be liable, the allegations in the complaint<br />

were sufficient. 199 Thus, the Court’s majority put Iqbal in a rather<br />

unfortunate position: he did not brief or argue the issue <strong>of</strong> liability,<br />

relying on petitioners’ concession, and this issue turned out to be<br />

necessary to dispose <strong>of</strong> the case before it.” Nadia B. Soree, The Demise Of Fourth Amendment<br />

Standing: From Standing Room To Center Orchestra, 8 NEV. L.J. 570, 572 (2008). Susan<br />

Hauser uses the term “passive judicial activism,” to refer “to a court’s uncompelled use<br />

<strong>of</strong> procedural doctrines to preclude future litigation or legislative action.” Susan E. Hauser,<br />

Predatory Lending, Passive Judicial Activism, and the Duty to Decide, 86 N.C. L. REV.<br />

1501, 1507 n.31 (2008); see also id. at 1551 (“The uncompelled use <strong>of</strong> procedural doctrines<br />

to preclude future litigation . . . does not square with Bickel’s passive virtues or Sunstein’s<br />

decisional minimalism; instead, it is a form <strong>of</strong> disguised judicial activism.”). This is similar<br />

to the concept described recently in Laurin’s article, “remedial rationing.” Laurin explains<br />

that criminal procedural rights can be vindicated either in a criminal case or in a civil case<br />

(in a damages action under § 1983). But when civil and criminal law both <strong>of</strong>fer means to<br />

vindicate a particular right, the Court “is likely to channel enforcement into one regime or<br />

the other,” not permit both to flourish. Jennifer E. Laurin, Melendez-Diaz v. Massachusetts,<br />

Rodriguez v. City Of Houston, and Remedial Rationing, 109 COLUM. L.REV.SIDEBAR<br />

82, 85 (2009). What Laurin calls remedial rationing would also qualify as procedural activism<br />

in my framework because it involves imposing judge-made rules to curtail the remedies<br />

available for the vindication <strong>of</strong> one’s constitutional rights.<br />

197. Pearson v. Callahan, 128 S. Ct. 1702, 1702-03 (2008) (order granting certiorari).<br />

198. See, e.g., Ernest A. Young, Judicial Activism and Conservative Politics, 73 U.<br />

COLO. L.REV. 1139, 1152 (2002) (“When we call the Court ‘activist’ because it ‘reaches out’<br />

to decide an issue not strictly before it . . . we are complaining about judicial maximalism.<br />

This form <strong>of</strong> activism shares with the other types . . . a refusal to defer to other actors in<br />

the system.”).<br />

199. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal, 129 S. Ct. 1937, 1955-57 (2009) (Souter, J., dissenting).


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 941<br />

dispositive. 200 The majority thus decided an issue <strong>of</strong> liability “that . . .<br />

has no bearing on its resolution <strong>of</strong> the case.” 201<br />

After deciding the (unnecessary) question <strong>of</strong> Bivens liability, the<br />

court turned to the sufficiency <strong>of</strong> the pleadings. But as Justice Souter<br />

pointed out in his dissent, it was not clear what separated the “conclusory”<br />

allegations from the ones that were “nonconclusory.” 202 And<br />

where there is no “principled basis” for treating different allegations<br />

differently, 203 an observer is left to wonder if the majority’s conclusion<br />

in Iqbal stemmed from results-driven reasoning simply based on a<br />

policy belief that a government <strong>of</strong>ficial’s right to be free from a vexatious<br />

lawsuit trumps an aggrieved civil rights plaintiff’s entitlement<br />

to relief.<br />

In fact one does not have to look far to see if that was the case. In<br />

response to the argument that discovery could be managed to shield<br />

government <strong>of</strong>ficials from expense, the Court writes:<br />

Our rejection <strong>of</strong> the careful-case-management approach is especially<br />

important in suits where Government-<strong>of</strong>ficial defendants are entitled<br />

to assert the defense <strong>of</strong> qualified immunity. The basic thrust<br />

<strong>of</strong> the qualified-immunity doctrine is to free <strong>of</strong>ficials from the concerns<br />

<strong>of</strong> litigation, including “avoidance <strong>of</strong> disruptive discovery.”<br />

There are serious and legitimate reasons for this. If a Government<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficial is to devote time to his or her duties, and to the formulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> sound and responsible policies, it is counterproductive to require<br />

the substantial diversion that is attendant to participating in litigation<br />

and making informed decisions as to how it should proceed.<br />

Litigation, though necessary to ensure that <strong>of</strong>ficials comply with<br />

the law, exacts heavy costs in terms <strong>of</strong> efficiency and expenditure<br />

<strong>of</strong> valuable time and resources that might otherwise be directed to<br />

the proper execution <strong>of</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> the Government. The costs <strong>of</strong><br />

diversion are only magnified when Government <strong>of</strong>ficials are<br />

charged with responding to, as Judge Cabranes aptly put it, “a national<br />

and international security emergency unprecedented in the<br />

history <strong>of</strong> the American Republic.” 204<br />

The policy motivation is clear: civil rights litigation “exacts heavy<br />

costs” and “it is counterproductive” to require government <strong>of</strong>ficials to<br />

litigate claims that may turn out to be meritless. Of course, one<br />

might draw just the opposite conclusion: that unconstitutional conduct<br />

by government <strong>of</strong>ficials extracts heavy costs and it is counterproductive<br />

to shield such individuals from civil rights claims that<br />

may turn out to be meritorious. The issue is not one <strong>of</strong> law. It is a pol-<br />

200. See id. at 1958.<br />

201. Id.<br />

202. Id. at 1961.<br />

203. Id.<br />

204. Id. at 1953 (citations omitted).


942 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

icy preference and nothing more. Yet, rather than defer to the judgment<br />

<strong>of</strong> the elected branches, or follow the procedure for amendment<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Federal Rules as described in the Rules Enabling Act, 205 the<br />

Court took it upon itself to make these judgments on its own.<br />

My point is not really that the Court got the policy judgment<br />

wrong (although, if it was not clear, I do believe that it got it wrong).<br />

My point, like the one made by Clermont and Yeazell, is that there<br />

were policy judgments to be made, and that they should not have<br />

been made by the Court. 206 In other words, if the Rules Enabling Act<br />

process had resulted in a higher pleading standard, or a curtailment<br />

<strong>of</strong> district courts’ ability to manage litigation, or any similar change,<br />

such a modification would be presumptively legitimate in a way that<br />

the Court’s recent action is not.<br />

In the criminal context, where all <strong>of</strong> the procedural chips fall in<br />

the same direction—presumption <strong>of</strong> innocence, automatic access to<br />

material exculpatory evidence, exclusionary rule, Miranda rights,<br />

rule <strong>of</strong> lenity, and so on—they do so because we as a society have<br />

made an explicit choice that defendants are presumed innocent and<br />

that they are entitled to all <strong>of</strong> the “breaks” in this regard. We have<br />

made no such decision, implicitly or explicitly, regarding civil rights<br />

plaintiffs. The only congressional authority on the subject is § 1983,<br />

which speaks <strong>of</strong> liability in almost unqualified terms. Section 1983’s<br />

criminal analogue, 18 U.S.C. § 242, is even broader, prescribing a<br />

criminal punishment for those who violate another’s rights under the<br />

color <strong>of</strong> any law (i.e., state or federal law, as opposed to § 1983, which<br />

only covers those acting under color <strong>of</strong> state law). Section 1983 was<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the Civil Rights Act <strong>of</strong> 1871 and, though the civil rights laws<br />

have been amended in the century-plus since, it exists today unaltered<br />

from the original. In short, to the extent that there is a political<br />

consensus in any direction, it is in favor <strong>of</strong> avenues to vindicate civil<br />

rights. The Pearson-Iqbal interaction reverses (or at least sharply<br />

curtails) this consensus, but does it sub silentio. Such a course <strong>of</strong> action<br />

should be problematic both for liberals who favor expanded<br />

access to civil rights remedies and for conservatives who oppose<br />

courts deciding cases more broadly than they should.<br />

IV. CONCLUSION<br />

Much has been written about Pearson and Iqbal in the past year.<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> that commentary has even noted that the cases could be<br />

harmful to civil rights plaintiffs.<br />

205. 28 U.S.C. §§ 2071-77.<br />

206. Clermont & Yeazell, supra note 20.


2010] PROCEDURAL JUDICIAL ACTIVISM 943<br />

However, no article (online or in print) explores the interaction between<br />

these two cases. When viewed in this light, it is clear that the<br />

cases bode poorly for those pressing civil rights claims. First, a plaintiff<br />

risks getting caught between a rock (Iqbal) and a hard place<br />

(Pearson). If he pleads his claim in great detail, a court deciding qualified<br />

immunity will simply conclude his right is not clearly established<br />

and not even give him a ruling on the constitutional merits. If<br />

he pleads generally to avoid this problem, he will get dismissed per<br />

Iqbal, as his broad allegations could be seen as conclusory or otherwise<br />

not plausible because <strong>of</strong> the lack <strong>of</strong> detail. 207 Moreover, the cases<br />

do not recognize, at least explicitly, that at the motion to dismiss<br />

stage the first step <strong>of</strong> the qualified immunity analysis is the same as<br />

the analysis under Rule 12(b)(6). By changing the standard for motions<br />

to dismiss, the Court has also implicitly changed the standard<br />

for “Saucier step one.”<br />

The cases also interact with regard to lower courts’ discretion, but<br />

only in a way that hurts civil rights claimants. Pearson gives courts<br />

the discretion to decide which step <strong>of</strong> the immunity analysis to take<br />

up first, but this discretion only makes it easier to dismiss claims on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> immunity. Iqbal expands courts’ discretion by instructing<br />

them to rely on common sense—a standard that, unless Courts <strong>of</strong><br />

Appeals cabin it, could turn out to be effectively unreviewable. At the<br />

same time, Iqbal restricts courts’ discretion to carefully manage litigation,<br />

thus forcing them to dismiss claims outright when in the past<br />

some targeted or limited discovery might have preserved the claims.<br />

In other contexts, the interaction between rules either “cancels<br />

out” (because, for example, Rule 9’s particularity requirement is <strong>of</strong>fset<br />

by liberal discovery rules) or the procedural rules favor one side<br />

because <strong>of</strong> an explicit policy choice (as in the case <strong>of</strong> criminal defendant).<br />

Neither is the case here. Instead, the Supreme Court has set<br />

up a regime where these cases, individually and jointly, work to the<br />

detriment <strong>of</strong> civil rights plaintiffs and, ultimately, all <strong>of</strong> us. It has<br />

done so by endorsing certain policy preferences and rejecting others,<br />

thus making political choices that should have been resolved through<br />

other mechanisms. The mere fact that the rules are procedural is <strong>of</strong><br />

no moment; the decisions are just as far-reaching, and curtail civil<br />

rights litigation just as much, as if they had come up in an area <strong>of</strong><br />

“substantive” law.<br />

Though they may be hidden, “there are value judgments that lie<br />

beneath the surface <strong>of</strong> each and every aspect <strong>of</strong> civil procedure. . . . [I]t<br />

207. Cf. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t v. Iqbal, 129 S. Ct. 1937, 1954 (2009) (“Rule 8 does not empower [a<br />

plaintiff] to . . . plead the bare elements <strong>of</strong> his cause <strong>of</strong> action, affix the label “general allegation,”<br />

and expect his complaint to survive a motion to dismiss.”).


944 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:901<br />

simply takes you a long time to understand that.” 208 We can only hope<br />

that countless meritorious civil rights claims do not fall by the wayside<br />

before academics, litigants, and judges come to this realization.<br />

208. Miller, supra note 1.


KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET<br />

ERIK S. KNUTSEN *<br />

ABSTRACT<br />

This Article explores the tensions between the perceived public and private aspects <strong>of</strong> the<br />

litigation system by using the debate surrounding whether or not the public civil justice system<br />

can and should tolerate secret settlements in standard, nonaggregate private law disputes.<br />

By evaluating the arguments against secret settlements in this context, the Article argues<br />

that the public and private aspects are not exclusory, oppositional perspectives but instead<br />

lie on a nonlinear continuum in which both may inform the other. The proper place on<br />

the continuum on which a certain procedural solution may lie <strong>of</strong>ten depends upon what type<br />

<strong>of</strong> dispute is at the center <strong>of</strong> the debate. When reforming and designing the civil justice system,<br />

either in whole or in part—like whether or not to allow secret settlements—one can expect<br />

a fuller, more balanced normative dialogue by thinking <strong>of</strong> the private and public views<br />

<strong>of</strong> civil litigation as operating on a nonexclusive and nonlinear continuum. This Article<br />

delves behind the seemingly oppositional perspectives <strong>of</strong> the public and private conceptions<br />

<strong>of</strong> civil litigation to reveal the utility <strong>of</strong> thinking about the two not as exclusive but cohesive.<br />

A decidedly private view <strong>of</strong> secret settlements does not, in all instances, negate the concerns<br />

<strong>of</strong> a view closer toward the public side <strong>of</strong> the continuum. In the end, the private view <strong>of</strong> litigation<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten has far more “public” to the “private” than one might expect.<br />

I. WHAT ARE SECRET SETTLEMENTS? .................................................................. 949<br />

A. Secret Settlements in Standard, Nonaggregate Private <strong>Law</strong> Disputes ..... 949<br />

B. Secret Settlements Revealed ....................................................................... 950<br />

C. Why Use Secret Settlements? ...................................................................... 951<br />

1. Defendants ........................................................................................... 951<br />

2. Plaintiffs .............................................................................................. 952<br />

II. THE PUBLIC AND PRIVATE VIEWS OF SECRET SETTLEMENTS (AND THE CIVIL<br />

JUSTICE SYSTEM) .............................................................................................. 954<br />

A. The Public View <strong>of</strong> Secret Settlements ....................................................... 954<br />

B. The Private View <strong>of</strong> Secret Settlements ...................................................... 955<br />

C. Why “Public” and “Private”? ...................................................................... 957<br />

III. PUBLIC VIEW CRITICISMS OF SECRET SETTLEMENTS ........................................ 959<br />

A. Secret Settlements Defy Systemic Transparency ....................................... 959<br />

B. Secret Settlements Do Not Contribute to the Public Good ......................... 962<br />

C. Secret Settlements Perpetuate Danger ....................................................... 965<br />

D Secret Settlements Take Advantage <strong>of</strong> the Vulnerable.............................. 971<br />

E. Government Entities Should Not Enter into Secret Settlements ............... 974<br />

IV. CONCLUSION ..................................................................................................... 976<br />

The civil justice system operates by maintaining multiple levels <strong>of</strong><br />

secrecy. <strong>Law</strong>yer-client privilege, litigation privilege, settlement privilege,<br />

judicial pretrial conferences, and confidential mediations are all<br />

cornerstones <strong>of</strong> the adversarial civil litigation process. They are de-<br />

* Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor, Queen’s <strong>University</strong> Faculty <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong>, Kingston, Ontario, Canada<br />

(LL.M., Harvard <strong>Law</strong> School). The author would like to thank William Araiza, Elizabeth<br />

Burch, David Fagundes, Brian Galle, Andrew Hessick, Carissa Hessick, Paul Horwitz,<br />

Robin Kar, Zak Kramer, Dan Markel, Lesley Wexler, and the participants <strong>of</strong> the<br />

McGill–Queen’s Young Scholars’ Conference 2009 for helpful comments and conversations.<br />

The author would also like to thank the organizers and participants <strong>of</strong> the Cornwall Public<br />

Inquiry policy roundtable on confidential settlements for providing an important platform<br />

for discussion.


946 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

signed, in one way or another, to protect a party’s right to prosecute<br />

his or her case as he or she sees fit.<br />

Yet the civil justice system is <strong>of</strong>ten touted as a “public” dispute<br />

resolution system. The system uses public resources to fund judges,<br />

courthouses, and the administrative machinery behind them. The<br />

end product <strong>of</strong> litigation may be a written judicial decision with precedential<br />

value to other future litigants. Judicial precedent also has<br />

the potential to modify undesirable behavior <strong>of</strong> nonlitigants who can<br />

arrange their affairs in the shadow <strong>of</strong> the law. The civil justice system<br />

itself is supposed to be transparent and, if possible, apolitical.<br />

How are the perceived values embedded in the civil justice system<br />

reconciled when a dispute settles confidentially? The vast majority <strong>of</strong><br />

cases that settle require as a condition <strong>of</strong> settlement that the litigating<br />

parties keep some aspect <strong>of</strong> the settlement a secret. 1 To complete<br />

a settlement for a typical civil case, parties generally execute a written<br />

settlement agreement. A standard term in such agreements is a<br />

confidentiality clause that stipulates what the parties can and cannot<br />

disclose about the settlement. These “secret settlements” <strong>of</strong>ten require<br />

confidentiality regarding the identity <strong>of</strong> the parties, the settlement<br />

amount, or other specific facts. 2 How is it that a dispute resolution<br />

system that prides itself on being public can tolerate secrecy at<br />

the settlement stage <strong>of</strong> a dispute occurring within the public justice<br />

system? The tensions between “public” rights and “private” rights are<br />

strongest when a dispute concludes in a “secret” settlement.<br />

This Article reinvigorates the debate between these two perspectives<br />

about public and private rights in civil litigation by arguing<br />

that the two perspectives, by operating on a nonexclusive, nonlinear<br />

continuum, are not as oppositional as one might believe. 3 The key is<br />

1. Most cases in the civil litigation system settle. Most also settle in secrecy. Although<br />

settlement rate estimates for civil cases vary, they generally point toward the 96%<br />

range. See, e.g., Marc Galanter & Mia Cahill, “Most Cases Settle”: Judicial Promotion and<br />

Regulation <strong>of</strong> Settlements, 46 STAN. L.REV. 1339, 1341 (1994) (concluding that most cases<br />

settle “in the shadow <strong>of</strong> the law” without judicial intervention but use the rule <strong>of</strong> law as<br />

predictor for outcomes). See also Laurie Kratky Doré, Secrecy By Consent: The Use and<br />

Limits <strong>of</strong> Confidentiality in the Pursuit <strong>of</strong> Settlement, 74 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 283, 384<br />

(1999) (discussing that many cases settle without any court involvement whatsoever).<br />

2. Doré, supra note 1, at 385-86.<br />

3. Indeed, Minna J. Kotkin has described the past academic debate over confidential<br />

settlement agreements as having “the sides sharply drawn” between the public and private<br />

views <strong>of</strong> these procedural tools. See Minna J. Kotkin, Invisible Settlements, Invisible Discrimination,<br />

84 N.C. L. REV. 927, 946 (2006). However, Leandra Lederman has come closest to recognizing<br />

the non-oppositional characteristics <strong>of</strong> public and private elements <strong>of</strong> settlement. In<br />

examining the public need for legal precedents as a product <strong>of</strong> litigation and the private need<br />

for settlement as resolution <strong>of</strong> expensive disputes, Lederman argues that these two needs<br />

must somehow be balanced in the civil dispute resolution system. This article pushes her arguments<br />

past the realm <strong>of</strong> precedent versus settlement and instead argues that these public<br />

and private qualities exist on a continuum, as opposed to being bipolar, oppositional aspects.


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 947<br />

to see the “public” in the “private view” and the “private” in the “public<br />

view” and then evaluate the merits <strong>of</strong> one end <strong>of</strong> the continuum<br />

over the other, depending on the procedural context one is trying to<br />

analyze. In some instances, such as securities fraud class actions in<br />

which decisionmaking in litigation operates very differently than it<br />

does in private tort or contract lawsuits because <strong>of</strong> the more “public”<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> the dispute, it may be appropriate to design a civil dispute<br />

resolution system with a more balanced public-private perspective.<br />

However, for the typical two party private law dispute, a view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

civil litigation system closer on the continuum toward the private<br />

view actually addresses an array <strong>of</strong> concerns previously associated<br />

exclusively with the public view <strong>of</strong> litigation.<br />

The Article therefore <strong>of</strong>fers a framework through which one can<br />

view not only the civil justice system but scholarly perspectives on<br />

that system as well. Past scholarship has <strong>of</strong>ten divided largely along<br />

the public-private lines. This Article explores the tensions between<br />

the perceived public and private aspects <strong>of</strong> the litigation system by<br />

focusing on the current debate about whether or not the “public” civil<br />

justice system can and should tolerate secret settlements. By evaluating<br />

the arguments against secret settlements, the Article argues<br />

that, in typical two party disputes over private rights, the public<br />

rights inherent in the system must necessarily be secondary in priority<br />

to the private rights <strong>of</strong> the individual litigants. To do otherwise<br />

would upset the balance <strong>of</strong> the adversarial method that is the bedrock<br />

<strong>of</strong> the civil justice system. The system has some public aspects,<br />

but when such aspects attempt to trump private dispute settlement<br />

concerns in all contexts and for all claims, the very public values<br />

sought to be protected are actually jeopardized. Thus, the oper-<br />

ation <strong>of</strong> the civil justice system, and simultaneously the perspec-<br />

tives from which one evaluates that operation, lie on a continuum between<br />

a public rights oriented perspective and private rights oriented<br />

perspective. The appropriate blend <strong>of</strong> public and private interests<br />

on that continuum <strong>of</strong>ten depends on what type <strong>of</strong> dispute is before<br />

the court.<br />

This Article uses one procedural concept—secret settlements in<br />

typical private law disputes—to explore and evaluate the limits and<br />

effectiveness <strong>of</strong> this seemingly oppositional continuum. Such an exploration<br />

can inform debates about just how far toward “publicoriented”<br />

or “private-oriented” any future civil justice reforms should<br />

swing. The Article posits—likely to the surprise <strong>of</strong> most readers—that<br />

along the public-private continuum for standard private law disputes,<br />

the private, party-centric view <strong>of</strong> the system is actually the<br />

See Leandra Lederman, Precedent Lost: Why Encourage Settlement, and Why Permit Nonparty<br />

Involvement in Settlements?, 75 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 221 (1999).


948 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

more effective perspective from which to design an all-encompassing<br />

civil justice system that preserves private rights and also protects<br />

some valuable public interest rights. Therefore, it is essential to acknowledge<br />

this inverse relationship along the continuum <strong>of</strong> the public<br />

view and the private view when one is considering reforms to the<br />

system, such as whether to foster or ban secret settlements.<br />

Part I <strong>of</strong> this Article begins by mapping the scope <strong>of</strong> the discussion,<br />

explaining the public-private continuum and this Article’s<br />

choice <strong>of</strong> the typical private law dispute as the lens through which to<br />

view the continuum. The Article then discusses what a secret settlement<br />

is, how it operates, and how secret settlements are used by both<br />

defendants and plaintiffs in civil litigation. Part II <strong>of</strong> this Article<br />

canvasses the continuum <strong>of</strong> what appear to be two opposing views <strong>of</strong><br />

the purpose <strong>of</strong> the civil justice system: the public view and the private<br />

view. These views, however, are not exactly oppositional and exclusive,<br />

but instead operate on a continuum and may shift the blend<br />

<strong>of</strong> public and private depending upon the type <strong>of</strong> dispute examined<br />

and the type <strong>of</strong> procedural mechanism behind the dispute. The Article<br />

explores how public law perspective proponents like David Luban,<br />

4 Owen Fiss, 5 and Abram Chayes 6 have developed largely ideologically<br />

weighted, results-based, public-centric views about secret settlements<br />

that may lead to some untenable conclusions when applied<br />

to standard, private law disputes. In this line <strong>of</strong> thinking, the litigants<br />

themselves take second seat to the public interest and, more<br />

curiously, the public interest and the litigants’ interests appear to be<br />

presented as ideologically opposite.<br />

Instead, the Article argues that approaches to the civil litigation<br />

system closer to the rights-driven, more party-centric end <strong>of</strong> the continuum<br />

such as those taken by Arthur Miller, 7 Carrie Menkel-<br />

Meadow, 8 and Christopher Drahozal and Laura Hines 9 actually do a<br />

better job <strong>of</strong> balancing both private and public interests in the system<br />

itself when designing procedural mechanisms for standard private<br />

law disputes. Part III reviews key public view criticisms about secret<br />

settlements and demonstrates that the solution to these criticisms is<br />

actually better informed by a perspective closer to the private view <strong>of</strong><br />

4. David Luban, Settlements and the Erosion <strong>of</strong> the Public Realm, 83 GEO. L.J.<br />

2619 (1995).<br />

5. Owen M. Fiss, Against Settlement, 93 YALE L.J. 1073 (1984).<br />

6. Abram Chayes, The Role <strong>of</strong> the Judge in Public <strong>Law</strong> Litigation, 89 HARV. L.REV.<br />

1281 (1976).<br />

7. Arthur R. Miller, Confidentiality, Protective Orders, and Public Access to the<br />

Courts, 105 HARV.L.REV. 427 (1991).<br />

8. Carrie Menkel-Meadow, Whose Dispute Is It Anyway?: A Philosophical and Democratic<br />

Defense <strong>of</strong> Settlement (In Some Cases), 83 GEO. L.J. 2663 (1995).<br />

9. Christopher R. Drahozal & Laura J. Hines, Secret Settlement Restrictions and Unintended<br />

Consequences, 54 KAN.L.REV. 1457 (2006).


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 949<br />

litigation for most private law disputes. The public view postulates<br />

that secret settlements defy transparency, do not contribute to the<br />

public good, perpetuate danger, take advantage <strong>of</strong> vulnerable litigants,<br />

and should not be used in litigation where the government is a<br />

party. However, the private view <strong>of</strong> secret settlements turns the public<br />

view criticisms upside-down and exposes the problematic, exclusively<br />

public nature <strong>of</strong> the public view such that the norms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

public view are not nearly as achievable in actual operation as one<br />

might otherwise expect at first blush.<br />

Part IV <strong>of</strong> this Article concludes by noting the importance <strong>of</strong> understanding<br />

the nonexclusive relationship between two seemingly<br />

oppositional viewpoints that exist not as absolutes but on a continuum.<br />

Depending on the type <strong>of</strong> case (i.e., civil rights versus a slip<br />

and fall case) and the amount <strong>of</strong> public procedural safeguards already<br />

installed in the procedural matrix (i.e., certification for class<br />

actions or judicial approval <strong>of</strong> settlements), it is more helpful to analyze<br />

procedural reforms based on either a more public or private<br />

view, or perhaps something somewhere in the middle <strong>of</strong> the continuum.<br />

For example, when reforming and designing the civil justice<br />

system for standard, nonaggregate private law litigation, one can expect<br />

a fuller, more balanced normative dialogue by using a perspective<br />

closer to the private view <strong>of</strong> the continuum. In the end, the private<br />

view <strong>of</strong> litigation <strong>of</strong>ten has far more “public” to the “private”<br />

than one might expect.<br />

I. WHAT ARE SECRET SETTLEMENTS?<br />

A. Secret Settlements in Standard, Nonaggregate Private <strong>Law</strong> Disputes<br />

This Article discusses settlements in the civil justice system only.<br />

To more coherently delve into the dynamics <strong>of</strong> the public and private<br />

views <strong>of</strong> civil litigation, this Article restricts its analysis to common<br />

civil settlements that operate in the standard, nonaggregate litigation<br />

setting. This includes typical tort, contractual, and property disputes<br />

between parties, such as an automobile accident, a commercial<br />

deal gone sour between suppliers, a dispute about property between<br />

neighbors, or a products liability lawsuit between consumer and<br />

manufacturer. However, while not the focus <strong>of</strong> this Article, it is useful<br />

to note that in aggregate litigation situations, such as mass torts<br />

or class actions, the balance between public and private may tip towards<br />

the public end <strong>of</strong> the spectrum.<br />

Aggregate litigation involves a more complex process and departs<br />

from the traditional procedural landscape <strong>of</strong> the simple private law


950 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

dispute. 10 Indeed, there is a great deal <strong>of</strong> “public” purposely injected<br />

into the class action’s special procedures because <strong>of</strong> the need to safeguard<br />

the rights <strong>of</strong> class members who must operate in a very different<br />

decisionmaking capacity than those plaintiffs in a standard twoparty<br />

lawsuit (i.e., class certification and judicial settlement approval).<br />

11 Settlement in aggregate litigation, therefore, may be a<br />

unique hybrid situation where decidedly stronger public interests are<br />

necessarily implicated because the settlement involves a multidimensional<br />

decision on behalf <strong>of</strong> a great many litigants who exercise<br />

little control over the lawsuit. 12 Therefore, to more fully explore the<br />

fundamental tensions between how the public and private views operate<br />

on a continuum and perhaps inform each other, this Article<br />

uses as its primary focus the typical tort, contractual, or property<br />

claim between two parties: plaintiff and defendant. How and where<br />

to place the more “public law” oriented cases on the continuum such<br />

as civil rights or the aggregate litigation situation is left for another<br />

day. The point <strong>of</strong> this Article is to delve into the seemingly oppositional<br />

perspectives <strong>of</strong> public and private views to reveal the utility <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking about the two not as exclusive, but as cohesive and complementary.<br />

A decidedly private view <strong>of</strong> secret settlements does not, in<br />

all instances, negate the concerns <strong>of</strong> a view closer toward the public<br />

side <strong>of</strong> the continuum.<br />

B. Secret Settlements Revealed<br />

A secret settlement is a settlement <strong>of</strong> a civil dispute about which<br />

some aspect has been agreed upon by the parties to remain confidential.<br />

The legal vehicle for this is typically a contractual agreement<br />

with a clause where the parties promise to keep some or all <strong>of</strong> the<br />

settlement details secret. Secrecy could refer to any aspect <strong>of</strong> the settlement.<br />

Most <strong>of</strong>ten, parties agree to keep one or more <strong>of</strong> the following<br />

a secret:<br />

a) the identity <strong>of</strong> the parties;<br />

b) the amount <strong>of</strong> the settlement;<br />

c) the admission or denial <strong>of</strong> fault by one or more parties;<br />

10. See, e.g., Judith Resnik, Aggregation, Settlement, and Dismay, 80 CORNELL L.<br />

REV. 918 (1995) (discussing the movement in class actions away from a model <strong>of</strong> individual<br />

adjudication toward a model <strong>of</strong> mass administrative processing <strong>of</strong> claims and settlements).<br />

Resnik, however, questions whether the settlement dynamic is indeed all that different between<br />

the class action and the individual case. Id. at 938. She concludes that more empirical<br />

evidence is needed to determine whether this is true. Id.<br />

11. See, e.g., Elizabeth Chamblee Burch, Securities Class Actions as Pragmatic Ex<br />

Post Regulation, 43 GA. L.REV. 63, 106-11 (2008) (noting the importance <strong>of</strong> transparency<br />

and public values in the securities class action context).<br />

12. See, e.g., Elizabeth Chamblee Burch, CAFA’s Impact on Litigation as a Public<br />

Good, 29 CARDOZO L. REV. 2517, 2548 (2008) (noting how aggregate litigation affects public<br />

norms, especially at the settlement phase).


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 951<br />

d) facts relating to the loss; or<br />

e) sensitive financial or trade information. 13<br />

The effective clause in the settlement agreement could be quite<br />

simple, such as “the terms <strong>of</strong> this settlement shall remain confidential.”<br />

The clause may include exceptions to the agreed-upon secrecy.<br />

Such exceptions can exclude confidentiality obligations for a party’s<br />

communications with immediate family members, lawyers, accountants,<br />

the government, or for the purposes <strong>of</strong> obtaining therapy. The<br />

clause could also include certain conditions in which secrecy is allowed<br />

to be broken—for example, if a court must review the agreement<br />

or if other legal obligations arise. Finally, the clause could detail<br />

the sanctions for breaking secrecy, such as whether the breach <strong>of</strong><br />

secrecy constitutes a fundamental breach <strong>of</strong> the settlement, thereby<br />

voiding the contract. Alternatively, there may be liquidated damages<br />

clauses for breaches <strong>of</strong> secrecy that detail precisely how much is to be<br />

paid upon breach. 14 None <strong>of</strong> these conditions appear to be common in<br />

standard settlement agreements at present.<br />

1. Defendants<br />

C. Why Use Secret Settlements?<br />

Defendants use secret settlements in civil lawsuits to create value<br />

in the settlement. 15 There is a price for secrecy. A defendant is <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

willing to pay more to a plaintiff if the plaintiff keeps some terms <strong>of</strong><br />

the settlement confidential. Secret settlements are frequently used<br />

for products liability cases, medical negligence, employment cases,<br />

and cases involving physical and emotional abuse. 16 Defendants use<br />

confidentiality as a bargaining chip to avoid two potentially detrimental<br />

outcomes: negative publicity and future lawsuits. 17 If a defendant<br />

can suppress information about the settlement, such information<br />

is unlikely to find its way into a public forum and the media.<br />

This creates value for a defendant. The reasons could be varied, the<br />

most obvious <strong>of</strong> which is to avoid dissemination <strong>of</strong> any information<br />

regarding a defendant’s potential fault or wrongdoing. There is also a<br />

strong incentive to suppress the fact that the defendant was sued, regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> fault or wrongdoing. The presence <strong>of</strong> a lawsuit alone can<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten create aspersions <strong>of</strong> fault when no fault, in fact, exists. This can<br />

damage the defendant’s reputation and client base.<br />

13. Doré, supra note 1, at 385-86.<br />

14. Id. at 386.<br />

15. See generally id.; Drahozal & Hines, supra note 9; Menkel-Meadow, supra note 8.<br />

16. See, e.g., Drahozal & Hines, supra note 9, at 1457-58.<br />

17. See, e.g., Hon. Jack B. Weinstein, Secrecy in Civil Trials: Some Tentative Views, 9<br />

J.L. &POL’Y 53, 56 (2000).


952 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

The defendant will also usually want to keep confidential the facts<br />

about any payments to the plaintiff. There are many reasons, unrelated<br />

to any admission <strong>of</strong> fault, why a defendant might settle a lawsuit with a<br />

plaintiff. If, however, information about a payment or settlement is disseminated,<br />

the public can infer, rightly or wrongly, that there must have<br />

been some fault on the part <strong>of</strong> the defendant. In reality, the dispute may<br />

have settled for reasons wholly unrelated to fault. The defendant, for<br />

example, could have decided it was less costly to settle the dispute than<br />

fight about the merits. Defendants may also use secret settlements to<br />

protect proprietary information, such as trade or business secrets discovered<br />

in the process <strong>of</strong> the litigation. Confidential settlement agreements<br />

avoid these negative, costly, and <strong>of</strong>ten incorrect, public exposures<br />

for defendants. To a defendant, the contractual opportunity to bargain<br />

for secrecy about some element <strong>of</strong> the dispute <strong>of</strong>ten has value. It is an<br />

important part <strong>of</strong> the dynamics <strong>of</strong> settlement.<br />

2. Plaintiffs<br />

Plaintiffs also use confidential settlement agreements to create<br />

value in settlement negotiations. 18 Plaintiffs can capitalize on the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> secrecy to defendants and increase available settlement options.<br />

A secret settlement is <strong>of</strong>ten worth more to a defendant than a<br />

settlement with no disclosure restrictions. A plaintiff will therefore<br />

have one more aspect <strong>of</strong> the case, beyond allegations <strong>of</strong> fault, with<br />

which to bargain.<br />

Theoretically, it could be possible that a plaintiff’s only bargaining<br />

chip in a dispute is secrecy itself. 19 Imagine a case in which the plaintiff<br />

either has limited evidence <strong>of</strong> a defendant’s fault 20 or, as would be<br />

more common, it is too risky and expensive for a plaintiff to gamble on<br />

a trial to prove fault. The plaintiff at least has the option to bargain for<br />

secrecy if a particular defendant values secrecy to any degree.<br />

Plaintiffs also use confidential settlement agreements because, as<br />

with defendants, privacy can be paramount in certain disputes.<br />

Plaintiffs may want to keep their identities secret. There could be<br />

sensitive reputational information at stake in a lawsuit, such as in a<br />

wrongful dismissal case. Plaintiffs could also be concerned about intimate<br />

privacy issues that were disclosed in the lawsuit, such as medical<br />

or family information. Victimization concerns could also be pa-<br />

18. See id.<br />

19. For example, consider an instance where the plaintiff has a difficult task <strong>of</strong> proving<br />

an essential element in the claim and is woefully out-lawyered and out-financed by a<br />

defendant. If secrecy is <strong>of</strong> great value to a defendant, that defendant may not even wish to<br />

risk any pretrial wranglings such as a motion for summary judgment, as such would put<br />

the facts squarely in the public eye.<br />

20. For example, complex evidence about causation in a tort trial which might not<br />

equate to a balance <strong>of</strong> probabilities.


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 953<br />

ramount where the dispute concerns alleged wrongdoings that are<br />

emotionally damaging to the plaintiff. A plaintiff may want to keep<br />

all details <strong>of</strong> such a dispute confidential.<br />

Lastly, like defendants, plaintiffs may <strong>of</strong>ten want to keep the<br />

monetary value <strong>of</strong> the settlement a secret. If the amount <strong>of</strong> the settlement<br />

is large, plaintiffs may be concerned about the undue and<br />

unwanted attention that a sudden financial influx may bring. 21 Secret<br />

settlements avoid this problem. Conversely, if the amount <strong>of</strong> the<br />

settlement is not large, a plaintiff may be concerned that the public<br />

may view her settled dispute as frivolous or unsuccessful (even if, in<br />

fact, it is not). The public has a skewed perception <strong>of</strong> settlement value<br />

and is unable to evaluate the efficacies <strong>of</strong> civil settlements. There<br />

could be multiple reasons why the monetary amount <strong>of</strong> a settlement<br />

is not large, yet the plaintiff still considers the settlement a success.<br />

The plaintiff may have bargained to implement organizational<br />

changes with the defendant. Perhaps the plaintiff’s case was nearly<br />

impossible or too expensive to prove in court, and some settlement<br />

amount would be better than a court-sanctioned cost award after a<br />

failed trial. The public is not exposed to the settlement dynamics that<br />

went into the agreement between the parties. To avoid public scorn<br />

in instances where the public’s expected outcome differs from the<br />

plaintiff’s actual monetary outcome, the plaintiff may wish to keep<br />

the settlement amount confidential.<br />

Plaintiffs and defendants alike use confidential settlement agreements<br />

to achieve goals that the otherwise simplistic monetization 22 <strong>of</strong><br />

the dispute cannot solve. As discussed later, secret settlements can<br />

be used as effective value-creation tools that benefit both plaintiffs<br />

and defendants in certain circumstances. 23 Removing such tools from<br />

the settlement negotiation toolbox hampers parties in their efforts to<br />

resolve disputes using non-monetary approaches. Secret settlements<br />

thus have the potential to engineer social outcomes that provide additional<br />

value to the settlement.<br />

21. For example, a long-lost family member suddenly appears, looking for a cash handout.<br />

22. See Luban, supra note 4, at 2646 (discussing how the “monetization” <strong>of</strong> civil litigation<br />

disputes has flattened the “normative landscape” <strong>of</strong> the public view <strong>of</strong> litigation); cf.<br />

Menkel-Meadow, supra note 8, at 2674 (arguing that litigation, not settlement, has led to<br />

the monetization <strong>of</strong> disputes).<br />

23. Scholars <strong>of</strong> negotiation and alternative dispute resolution have for the past few<br />

decades trumpeted the importance <strong>of</strong> nonmonetary value creation in creatively solving civil<br />

disputes. See, e.g., ROGER FISHER &WILLIAM URY, GETTING TO YES (Bruce Patton ed.<br />

1991); DAVID A. LAX &JAMES K. SEBENIUS, THE MANAGER AS NEGOTIATOR: BARGAINING<br />

FOR COOPERATION AND COMPETITIVE GAIN (1986).


954 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

II. THE PUBLIC AND PRIVATE VIEWS OF SECRET SETTLEMENTS (AND<br />

THE CIVIL JUSTICE SYSTEM)<br />

How anyone views the efficacy <strong>of</strong> secret settlements in the civil<br />

justice system depends on how one views the role <strong>of</strong> the civil justice<br />

system in general. 24 That view also necessarily drives whether or not<br />

one argues to curb, ban, or foster secret settlements. In the past,<br />

scholars have presented what <strong>of</strong>ten appear to be two competing views<br />

as to how the civil justice system as a whole operates and should operate:<br />

the public view and the private view. 25 Unpacking these two<br />

views through the lens <strong>of</strong> secret settlements in standard private law<br />

disputes helps explain the real debate behind how one sculpts a normative<br />

perspective <strong>of</strong> the civil justice system as a whole. That debate<br />

should focus not on oppositional ideals but on the fact that these<br />

perspectives actually operate on a continuum. The private view <strong>of</strong><br />

civil litigation can (and as will be shown, <strong>of</strong>ten does) preserve some<br />

values inherent in the public view. The key is to recognize that these<br />

two views are not mutually exclusive when procedural matters are<br />

put into actual operation in the real world <strong>of</strong> litigation.<br />

A. The Public View <strong>of</strong> Secret Settlements<br />

The public view <strong>of</strong> the civil litigation system typically sees the system<br />

as a publicly funded, open system operating with transparency to<br />

engineer greater social good. 26 Litigation and court decisions contribute<br />

to the public commons and enrich social debate through dispute resolution.<br />

Those who hold tight to the public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation are either<br />

against the notion <strong>of</strong> confidential settlement agreements altogether<br />

or clamor for increasing regulation <strong>of</strong> secret settlements.<br />

The public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation owes its genesis to those scholars<br />

who see the civil litigation system, and indeed dispute resolution, as<br />

capable <strong>of</strong> transforming society into something better. 27 Courts medi-<br />

24. See, e.g., Doré, supra note 1, at 289 (contending that the question <strong>of</strong> “who owns a<br />

lawsuit” affects one’s stance on confidentiality in the litigation process).<br />

25. For an excellent summary <strong>of</strong> the public and private views in relation to secrecy in<br />

the discovery process, see Jack H. Friedenthal, Secrecy in Civil Litigation: Discovery and<br />

Party Agreements, 9 J.L. &POL’Y 67, 69 (2000) (describing the two positions as being on<br />

“two quite different levels, one involving philosophical concepts <strong>of</strong> the role <strong>of</strong> the courts in<br />

society and the other concerning the practical effects <strong>of</strong> disclosure or nondisclosure on parties<br />

to disputes and to the public at large”).<br />

26. See Fiss, supra note 5 (arguing that American’s litigation system should operate in<br />

the public sphere and that settlements remove valuable public discourse); Luban, supra note<br />

4 (stating that settlement and litigation are primarily about promoting public values);<br />

Chayes, supra note 6 (describing an emerging model <strong>of</strong> “public law litigation,” in which private<br />

lawsuits concern the operation <strong>of</strong> public policy instead <strong>of</strong> merely private rights between<br />

disputants); Lloyd Doggett & Michael J. Mucchetti, Public Access to Public Courts: Discouraging<br />

Secrecy in the Public Interest, 69 TEX. L.REV. 643 (1991) (arguing in favor <strong>of</strong> TEX. R.<br />

CIV. P. 76(a), which makes public access to court records the standard rule for courts).<br />

27. See Luban, supra note 4; Fiss, supra note 5; Chayes, supra note 6.


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 955<br />

ate a social and political dialog, performing an integral service to the<br />

public at large. Court decisions perpetuate discussion about the<br />

boundaries <strong>of</strong> the law and provide a positive externality to the public:<br />

the deterrent effect <strong>of</strong> knowing what happened to who and what cost<br />

was borne. This is a decidedly public law-inspired vision <strong>of</strong> the civil<br />

litigation system. The detriments <strong>of</strong> secret settlements as catalogued<br />

by public view scholars lead such scholars to emphasize a balance<br />

toward public, not private, benefit, arguing that secret settlements<br />

hinder the values <strong>of</strong> the public litigation process.<br />

B. The Private View <strong>of</strong> Secret Settlements<br />

The private view <strong>of</strong> the civil litigation system sees the system as a<br />

party-driven mechanism for efficiently resolving private disputes between<br />

parties. 28 Those who espouse the private view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation<br />

are <strong>of</strong>ten supportive <strong>of</strong> a disputing party’s opportunity to bargain<br />

with secrecy. Secret settlements are thus a positive dynamic in the<br />

civil litigation system. 29<br />

The private view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation rests on the idea <strong>of</strong> party autonomy<br />

in the adversary system. 30 The parties within a dispute have<br />

complete control as to how the dispute is handled. 31 Further, the disputing<br />

parties themselves choose to bring a dispute into the public<br />

justice system in the first place, deciding what issues will comprise<br />

the dispute. The parties also have complete control over settlement. 32<br />

The parties can also choose when to settle and how to structure the<br />

settlement. Courts, by contrast, can take only the cases brought before<br />

them. 33 Therefore, the public nature <strong>of</strong> any dispute in the civil<br />

justice system is a mere by-product or, as Arthur Miller puts it, “col-<br />

28. See Miller, supra note 7 (arguing against the public law reform movement to permit<br />

complete public access to all court information); Menkel-Meadow, supra note 8 (arguing<br />

that disputants own the dispute and should be able to control settlement processes<br />

because the litigation process is designed to put the disputants’ interests first, not the public’s);<br />

Drahozal & Hines, supra note 9 (arguing that regulation <strong>of</strong> secret settlements may be<br />

ineffective and counter-productive).<br />

29. Miller notes that by regulating confidentiality in the civil litigation process, one<br />

upsets the balance <strong>of</strong> the adversarial nature <strong>of</strong> the framework for resolving civil disputes<br />

because there is a direct symbiosis between procedural rules and the pursuit <strong>of</strong> substantive<br />

rights. See Miller, supra note 7, at 466.<br />

30. See, e.g., Doré, supra note 1, at 286 (explaining the underlying value <strong>of</strong> party autonomy<br />

in the civil litigation system).<br />

31. See Menkel-Meadow, supra note 8, at 2669 (arguing that the public view’s focus<br />

on litigation’s structural and institutional goals has ignored the role <strong>of</strong> the actual disputants<br />

who are involved in the litigation).<br />

32. See id. at 2696 (stating that the litigation process is a “party-initiated and partycontrolled<br />

legal system”).<br />

33. See, e.g., Avedis H. Sefarian & James T. Wakley, Secrecy Clauses in Sexual Molestation<br />

Settlements: Should Courts Agree to Seal Documents in Cases Involving the Catholic<br />

Church?, 16 GEO.J.LEGAL ETHICS 801, 807 (2003).


956 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

lateral” 34 to the actual private dispute between the parties. Parties<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten do not even require interaction with the public justice system to<br />

solve their disputes. Instead, they bargain within the “shadow <strong>of</strong> the<br />

law,” knowing that certain legal rules will apply if the case proceeds<br />

to trial. 35 The shift <strong>of</strong> the civil justice system from one <strong>of</strong> trial as the<br />

main event to pretrial procedures as the main event has led to a decreasing<br />

role for final adjudication on the merits in civil litigation. 36<br />

In fact, most cases settle. 37 The strong arm <strong>of</strong> the law is not necessarily<br />

applied within the courtroom. With so little “public” in the public<br />

dispute resolution system, the public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation seems to<br />

forget that much <strong>of</strong> what is driving the system are disputes about<br />

private law issues.<br />

In fact, the public view may well be an uncomfortable fit with the<br />

down-and-dirty world <strong>of</strong> real-life litigation. The majority <strong>of</strong> disputes<br />

in the civil litigation system are not broad-reaching societal watermarks<br />

exploring important public rights but are instead disputes involving<br />

injury or simple contract breach. 38 The public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation<br />

thus appears to be more suitable for a society in which every<br />

second civil case is about school segregation or civil rights instead <strong>of</strong><br />

fender-benders and fence disputes between neighbors.<br />

The private view’s difficulty with the public view conception <strong>of</strong> civil<br />

settlements stems largely from the fact that civil disputes live,<br />

breathe, and die by the parties themselves. 39 In the eyes <strong>of</strong> the parties,<br />

private civil litigation is not conducted for the benefit <strong>of</strong> the pub-<br />

34. See Miller, supra note 7, at 431 (“[P]ublic access to information produced in litigation<br />

has always been a secondary benefit” or side effect to the real purpose <strong>of</strong> the litigation:<br />

dispute resolution between private parties); see also Richard L. Marcus, The Discovery<br />

Confidentiality Controversy, 1991 U. ILL.L.REV. 457 (1991) (arguing that the collateral informational<br />

disclosure in civil litigation should not eclipse the main purpose <strong>of</strong> litigation–to<br />

solve private disputes).<br />

35. See Galanter & Cahill, supra note 1, at 1341 (concluding that most cases settle<br />

without judicial intervention but “in the shadow <strong>of</strong> the law,” using the rule <strong>of</strong> law as predictor<br />

for outcomes); see also Doré, supra note 1, at 384 (indicating that many cases settle<br />

without any court involvement whatsoever).<br />

36. The reduced importance <strong>of</strong> the trial in the civil litigation process is marked by the<br />

reference to the civil trial as presently nothing more than a failed settlement in the justice<br />

system. Samuel R. Gross & Kent D. Syverud, Getting to No: A Study <strong>of</strong> Settlement Negotiations<br />

and the Selection <strong>of</strong> Cases for Trial, 90 MICH.L.REV. 319, 320 (1991).<br />

37. Ninety-five percent <strong>of</strong> civil litigation cases end in settlement, though that rate may<br />

vary slightly depending on the type <strong>of</strong> case. While there is some divergence <strong>of</strong> opinion as to<br />

the precise settlement rate, it is certain that the majority <strong>of</strong> cases in the civil litigation system<br />

settle before trial. See, e.g., Marc Galanter & Mia Cahill, “Most Cases Settle”: Judicial<br />

Promotion and Regulation <strong>of</strong> Settlements, 46 STAN.L.REV. 1339, 1339-40 (1994); Frank E.A.<br />

Sander, The Obsession with Settlement Rates, 11 NEGOTIATION J. 329, 331 (1995).<br />

38. See Miller, supra note 7, at 467.<br />

39. See id. at 431-32 (arguing that forcing full disclosure <strong>of</strong> all litigation information<br />

goes against the civil justice system’s ideals <strong>of</strong> improved efficiency and settlement promotion<br />

in the hopes <strong>of</strong> reducing cost and delay in dispute resolution).


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 957<br />

lic. 40 Private litigants pay the costs and are saddled with the risks <strong>of</strong><br />

litigation. Therefore, private litigants should be free to bargain with<br />

whatever tools are available, including their rights to disclose matters<br />

about their own case. Ask any litigant in the middle <strong>of</strong> a lawsuit<br />

why he or she sued in the first place. The answer will undoubtedly be<br />

something along the lines <strong>of</strong> “I was hurt.” The public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation<br />

and secret settlements thus appears to be far removed from<br />

the individual litigants who are the actors in the litigation system<br />

and who control it by their own decisions. 41<br />

C. Why “Public” and “Private”?<br />

David Luban refers to these competing visions <strong>of</strong> the civil justice<br />

system as the “problem-solving view” and the “public-life conception”<br />

<strong>of</strong> litigation. 42 This Article chooses instead to refer to the two different<br />

perspectives as the public and private views <strong>of</strong> the civil litigation<br />

system, along similar lines to Leandra Lederman who, in examining<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> precedent as an integral part <strong>of</strong> litigation outcomes, posits<br />

that balancing settlement and precedent concerns necessarily requires<br />

a balancing <strong>of</strong> both public and private aspects <strong>of</strong> litigation. 43<br />

There are three reasons for using Lederman’s “public” and “private”<br />

terminology when examining secret settlements. Each reason underlines<br />

the fact that these two views may not be mutually exclusive (as<br />

has traditionally been presented in most scholarly thinking to date)<br />

but instead operate on a graduated continuum which may shift, depending<br />

upon the type <strong>of</strong> case and the type <strong>of</strong> procedural solution<br />

best suited to the problem.<br />

First, there is already a traditional analytic division among scholars<br />

between private law and public law norms and modalities <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking. Private law encompasses individual rights at stake<br />

amongst individuals–property, tort, and contract. Even if an individual<br />

litigant is a government entity, that entity exercises options and<br />

control in the litigation process as would a cognoscente living party.<br />

When to settle, how to settle, and if to settle at all become the decisions<br />

<strong>of</strong> the party itself. The idea <strong>of</strong> party control and party autonomy<br />

is thus synonymous with the idea <strong>of</strong> private actors exercising private<br />

rights in a private law context (e.g., A harms B, B sues A under a<br />

negligence theory to seek redress from A).<br />

A public law standpoint, however, places greater emphasis on the<br />

state-as-party concept, where the state is representative stakeholder<br />

40. Although that certainly may not be true in the eyes <strong>of</strong> the public, which funds the<br />

court system as a public dispute resolution system.<br />

41. Menkel-Meadow dubs the public view’s tendency to minimize the role <strong>of</strong> individual<br />

disputants a kind <strong>of</strong> “litigation romanticism.” See Menkel-Meadow, supra note 8, at 2669.<br />

42. See Luban, supra note 4, at 2632-33.<br />

43. See Lederman, supra note 3.


958 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

for the rights <strong>of</strong> a group <strong>of</strong> people. Collective interests subsume individual<br />

rights. Public law involves a certain shared consciousness<br />

about shaping the political conversation and the polity. The values<br />

laden in public law topics are assumed to be collective values–<br />

fundamental freedoms and rights, and state punishment for wrongdoing<br />

in society. Therefore, constitutional law and criminal law <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

must balance the rights <strong>of</strong> the individual with the rights <strong>of</strong> society as<br />

a whole. Thus, using the terms “public view” and “private view” as<br />

descriptors for how one views the civil litigation system are designed<br />

to hearken to the traditional academic division between public and<br />

private law norms and doctrine.<br />

Second, the terms “public view” and “private view” are perhaps<br />

more appropriate than Luban’s “problem-solving” and “public-life<br />

conception” labels because many litigants in the civil justice system<br />

are concerned with solving problems, even though the rights at issue<br />

are decidedly “public-life” rights. In essence, all litigation is an attempt<br />

to solve problems. Litigation about school desegregation had a<br />

decidedly “public-life” element in operation and effect, but no one<br />

would argue against the fact that its ultimate purpose was also to<br />

solve a problem. Luban’s labels have thus stated normative goals<br />

that are not mutually exclusive. Private cases can solve public problems<br />

and contribute to the common public good, and public cases can<br />

be remarkably private and singular in effect. Labels such as “public”<br />

and “private” that use descriptors that are not normative results but<br />

rather modalities <strong>of</strong> viewing the legal landscape might, therefore, be<br />

more helpful when one is designing the conversation about if and in<br />

what context the civil litigation system needs redirection.<br />

Finally, using the terms “public” and “private” jettisons the valueladen<br />

prescriptive baggage that may be inherent in Luban’s terms.<br />

Labeling one way <strong>of</strong> thinking about the justice system as “problemsolving”<br />

and another as the “public-life conception” requires one to<br />

take a side with certain values and approach litigation system design<br />

issues with those values at hand. The danger is an ideologically exclusive<br />

approach that perhaps clouds judgment along the way. There<br />

is no room for the private in the public view conception <strong>of</strong> civil litigation.<br />

The most sensible solutions to problems may not always line up<br />

exclusively with “public-life” benefits. Alternatively, the solutions<br />

may not be completely internally consistent with the individualistic<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> Luban’s “problem-solving” label. Using the terms public<br />

and private instead as descriptors for charting the debate does not<br />

require participants to initially value solutions based on perceived<br />

outcomes. Instead, it allows for viewing these perspectives along a<br />

graduated continuum. While one procedural solution may fit best<br />

with a decidedly private view, another (such as a procedural solution


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 959<br />

for mass harms in an aggregate litigation context) may require a<br />

more blended public-private approach.<br />

III. PUBLIC VIEW CRITICISMS OF SECRET SETTLEMENTS<br />

There is an interesting dyadic relationship between secret settlement<br />

criticisms or benefits and one’s view <strong>of</strong> litigation. Criticisms <strong>of</strong><br />

secret settlements emanate largely from those who adopt a public<br />

view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation. Those who adopt a private view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation<br />

tend to be more accepting <strong>of</strong> secret settlements. What is considered<br />

a criticism from one viewpoint is <strong>of</strong>ten a benefit seen by the<br />

other. That is why an examination <strong>of</strong> this particular aspect <strong>of</strong> the civil<br />

justice system holds potential to reveal elements <strong>of</strong> the larger theoretical<br />

dynamic behind charting the design <strong>of</strong> the system.<br />

A. Secret Settlements Defy Systemic Transparency<br />

The public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation holds that secret settlements defy<br />

systemic transparency. Curiously, however, the civil justice system<br />

already operates within layers <strong>of</strong> transparency. Furthermore, transparency<br />

as publicity comes at a cost to some key values engendered<br />

by the public view. 44 The private view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation actually ensures<br />

more than enough protection for reasonable levels <strong>of</strong> public<br />

view-inspired disclosure.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the main tenets <strong>of</strong> the public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation is that<br />

it is a decidedly public process. The state funds the court system. The<br />

public participates in a transparent conversation about legal rights.<br />

To that end, citizens have some ownership, at least in spirit, <strong>of</strong> what<br />

happens within that system. Secret settlements are therefore anathema<br />

in a system that is, at heart, for the public good because the<br />

bedrock <strong>of</strong> the system is transparency <strong>of</strong> information. 45 The whole<br />

reason for a public dispute resolution system is that it operates for<br />

the benefit <strong>of</strong> the public. Therefore, participants in the system must<br />

submit to such publicity. Making secret the outcome <strong>of</strong> a settled dispute<br />

that began in such a system removes the public’s ability to learn<br />

from the dispute. The parties have, therefore, for their sole selfish<br />

benefit, compromised the values that make a public system public.<br />

44. This notion about questioning transparency as an absolute value in civil litigation<br />

tracks Mark Fenster’s broader criticism <strong>of</strong> transparency theory’s “abstract normative<br />

commitments and consequentialist assumptions . . . .” Mark Fenster, The Opacity <strong>of</strong><br />

Transparency, 91 IOWA L. REV. 885, 933 (2006).<br />

45. See, e.g., Anne-Thérèse Béchamps, Sealed Out-<strong>of</strong>-Court Settlements: When Does<br />

the Public Have a Right to Know?, 66 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 117, 156 (1990) (calling for an<br />

open judicial system not trumped by private party interests).


960 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

However, the mere act <strong>of</strong> filing a claim with a public court generates<br />

instant public access to an incredible array <strong>of</strong> information. 46<br />

The claim itself lays out the dispute, particulars <strong>of</strong> material facts,<br />

identities <strong>of</strong> parties, theories <strong>of</strong> liability, and some notion <strong>of</strong> remedies<br />

and value <strong>of</strong> the claims. This is all available to the public. Even if a<br />

case settles with a confidentiality requirement as part <strong>of</strong> the settlement,<br />

the claim is still accessible in the public court file. If publicity<br />

and transparency are so important to the public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation,<br />

why then is it that there are not more individuals peeking into<br />

civil court files? 47<br />

The civil litigation system already operates with a great deal <strong>of</strong><br />

secrecy in order to foster party-driven dispute resolution. 48 There is<br />

very little in a civil litigation case that is completely open to the public.<br />

In fact, secrecy is purposely built into the litigation system in a<br />

variety <strong>of</strong> ways. Discovery is a private, confidential fact-finding<br />

process. The concepts <strong>of</strong> lawyer-client privilege and litigation privilege<br />

are designed to keep certain classes <strong>of</strong> information out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

public realm so that parties can be at liberty to construct their disputing<br />

strategies in an adversarial fashion. Settlement negotiations<br />

are also deemed privileged, precisely for the purpose <strong>of</strong> fostering the<br />

settlement <strong>of</strong> disputes. Alternative dispute resolution processes such<br />

as mediation are nearly always, by consent, a confidential process.<br />

Pretrial settlement conferences in front <strong>of</strong> a judge are confidential in<br />

order to prompt settlement. Jury deliberations are also secret.<br />

With the main facts <strong>of</strong> a dispute made public by the filing <strong>of</strong> a<br />

claim, and with much <strong>of</strong> the disputing process shrouded in secrecy by<br />

design, it is puzzling how the loss to the public <strong>of</strong> mere settlement information<br />

can harm the public good. Often the only information not<br />

disclosed to the public as a result <strong>of</strong> a secret settlement is the monetary<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> the settlement. 49 Rarer still is the secrecy about the<br />

fault <strong>of</strong> the parties or perhaps specific detailed facts about the dispute.<br />

Transparency is not an absolute for resolution <strong>of</strong> disputes utilizing<br />

the public justice system. Further, since the vast majority <strong>of</strong><br />

cases settle, secret settlements are likely not denying the public any-<br />

46. See Miller,supra note 7, at 502; Menkel-Meadow, supra note 8, at 2695 (asserting that<br />

parties seeking settlement approval by a court necessarily waive the secrecy <strong>of</strong> the settlement).<br />

47. Indeed, Ben Depoorter surveys the present potential feedback effect <strong>of</strong> settlement<br />

information as it is disseminated through various sources (i.e. the media and lawyers). See<br />

Ben Depoorter, <strong>Law</strong> in the Shadow <strong>of</strong> Bargaining: The Feedback Effect <strong>of</strong> Civil Settlements,<br />

95 CORNELL L. REV. 101 (2010).<br />

48. See Miller, supra note 7, at 429.<br />

49. For example, many in the media use language such as “the parties settled for an<br />

undisclosed amount” when reporting on the details <strong>of</strong> a settlement. See, e.g., Lisa Sink,<br />

Sexual Assault <strong>Law</strong>suit Settled for Undisclosed Amount, MILWAUKEE JOURNAL SENTINEL,<br />

Mar. 5, 1997, at 2, available at http://news.google.com/newspapers?nid=1683&dat=<br />

19970325&id=RHUaAAAAIBAJ&sjid=Fy4EAAAAIBAJ&pg=5604,1538704.


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 961<br />

thing anyway. Public adjudication is the exception, not the norm.<br />

There is currently no mechanism demanding public publishing <strong>of</strong> settlement<br />

agreements. Settlement agreements are not usually entered<br />

into court. 50 This begs the question: what is it that secret settlements<br />

are hiding that would not already be hidden in a public trial?<br />

In fact, by not allowing confidentiality in the final settlement<br />

agreement, this forced transparency may actually increase public<br />

harm because no party will discuss the details <strong>of</strong> the dispute other<br />

than in the context <strong>of</strong> a trial. 51 A ban on secrecy may incentivize information<br />

suppression during settlement negotiations. 52 Without the<br />

shield <strong>of</strong> secrecy, research results, safety issues, and crucial liability<br />

facts may not be revealed at all. Secrecy has the inverse property <strong>of</strong><br />

prompting disclosure between the litigants who can rely on the facts<br />

not being made public. Secrecy is not always harmful. Thus, transparency<br />

<strong>of</strong> the public system is not compromised with secret settlements.<br />

53 It may even be indirectly enhanced because at least “someone”<br />

(i.e., the parties) will have access to some information. It follows<br />

that publicity <strong>of</strong> information reduces the value <strong>of</strong> confidentiality to<br />

the parties, making it worthless in settlement negotiations. 54<br />

Maintaining secret settlements (a decidedly private view notion)<br />

thus inversely assists in achieving the public view value <strong>of</strong> at least<br />

some transparency. The same cannot be said <strong>of</strong> strict adherence to<br />

the public view’s notion <strong>of</strong> full transparency in settlements. Litigants<br />

lose some bargaining power, and the public may be deprived <strong>of</strong> more<br />

open litigation communication as the end result. The private view <strong>of</strong><br />

civil litigation, therefore, leads to a more blended solution in effect.<br />

Perhaps, then, the private view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation is not a competing<br />

normative view incapable <strong>of</strong> reconciliation with the public view but is<br />

instead more flexible, interdependent, and dynamic in nature.<br />

50. Although they can be, such as to enforce a future settlement in a court order.<br />

51. See Emily Fiftal, Respecting Litigants’ Privacy and Public Needs: Striking Middle<br />

Ground in an Approach to Secret Settlements, 54 CASE W. RES.L.REV. 503, 528 (2003).<br />

52. Or, as Miller argues, removing confidentiality in the litigation process will burden,<br />

rather than facilitate, litigants’ use <strong>of</strong> the system. See Miller, supra note 7, at 432; see<br />

also Drahozal & Hines, supra note 9, at 1458 (claiming that restrictions on secret settlements<br />

may restrict information about health and safety hazards that would otherwise be<br />

made available to the public).<br />

53. James M. Anderson surmises that civil justice concepts <strong>of</strong> transparency and publicity<br />

are actually a transaction tax that creates a deadweight cost in derailing settlement<br />

agreements that the plaintiff and defendant would otherwise accept if confidentiality were<br />

allowed. See James M. Anderson, Understanding Mass Tort Defendant Incentives for Confidential<br />

Settlements: Lessons from Bayer’s Cerivastatin Litigation Strategy, at 12 (RAND<br />

Inst. for Civil Justice, Working Paper No. WR-617-ICJ, 2008).<br />

54. Id. at 23.


962 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

B. Secret Settlements Do Not Contribute to the Public Good<br />

According to the public view <strong>of</strong> secret settlements, settling a dispute<br />

in a confidential fashion does not contribute to the public good. 55 The<br />

public is not equipped with the tools necessary to evaluate the particular<br />

dispute’s resultant place in the firmament <strong>of</strong> legal proceedings, or<br />

so the thinking goes. Without information about a settlement in a public<br />

proceeding, courts, lawyers and future litigants are deprived <strong>of</strong> the<br />

facts and the predictive value <strong>of</strong> the settled case. 56 Thus, no one knows<br />

how factually similar cases may be resolved at trial. Scholars who espouse<br />

the public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation <strong>of</strong>ten decry settlement itself for<br />

removing valuable legal precedents from the public commons. 57 Making<br />

settlement information unavailable to the public is doubly stinging<br />

because the dispute will not progress to adjudication, while the public<br />

is also denied the informational value contained in the facts <strong>of</strong> the settlement.<br />

Yet, the private view’s determination to maintain secret settlements<br />

does not completely eclipse public view concerns. In fact,<br />

maintaining secret settlements preserves some important public view<br />

cost concerns, which is completely aligned with the public view’s normative<br />

goals about the public good.<br />

According to the public view, secret settlements also deny future<br />

litigants information about the dispute. 58 Supporters <strong>of</strong> the public<br />

view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation point to the inefficiency <strong>of</strong> allowing disputants<br />

to keep confidential information that might otherwise assist future<br />

parties. If a plaintiff in a products liability lawsuit, for example, signs<br />

a confidential settlement agreement with a particular defendant<br />

manufacturer, the information gleaned in that lawsuit will not be<br />

available for other plaintiffs who may want to pursue similar lawsuits<br />

against that same manufacturer. This could result in inefficiencies<br />

in administrative and information costs, as future litigants will<br />

have to go to the expense and trouble <strong>of</strong> essentially relitigating disputes<br />

that have already been resolved.<br />

55. See, e.g., Luban, supra note 4, at 2653 (asserting that other litigants have an interest<br />

in information created through the litigation process); Jules Coleman & Charles Silver,<br />

Justice in Settlements, 4 SOC.PHIL.&POL’Y 102, 114-19 (1986) (judicial precedent as a<br />

public good).<br />

56. See Luban, supra note 4, at 2639 (noting that settlement information has some<br />

precedential value for lawyers who are repeat players in the litigation system).<br />

57. See, e.g., id. at 2622; Fiss, supra note 5, at 1085; Lederman, supra note 3, at 256,<br />

268 (arguing that the public need for precedent must be balanced by the private need for<br />

settlement); but see Menkel Meadow, supra note 8, at 2682 (arguing that overburdened<br />

and prolific courts surely must be producing an optimal amount <strong>of</strong> precedent for suitable<br />

public discourse).<br />

58. See Luban, supra note 4, at 2653 (arguing that facts in a lawsuit are public goods<br />

that are purchased by one litigant and should be made available to the public).


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 963<br />

The private view’s answer to the public good criticism <strong>of</strong> secret settlements<br />

is simple: it is not the public’s dispute. 59 If the normative goal<br />

<strong>of</strong> the civil justice system is to contribute to the public good, achieving<br />

that goal necessarily requires a kind <strong>of</strong> “tax” be borne by the litigants<br />

themselves for the good <strong>of</strong> the public. Public disputes are resolved<br />

within the confines <strong>of</strong> the adversarial system, and party autonomy is<br />

key. 60 Parties themselves make all decisions about the subject matter<br />

<strong>of</strong> the dispute and whether to settle. The parties in the dispute pay the<br />

costs <strong>of</strong> litigation. The public purse provides the administrative<br />

framework for the dispute resolution process: the judge, the rules <strong>of</strong><br />

civil procedure, and the courthouse forum. However, that is the extent<br />

<strong>of</strong> the public’s contribution to the dispute. The parties also bear the<br />

risk <strong>of</strong> losing and having to pay a portion <strong>of</strong> the successful litigant’s legal<br />

costs as well. This risk is not borne by the public. It is a rosy picture<br />

<strong>of</strong> the litigation world indeed if one believes that litigants expend<br />

resources, time, and emotional energy in a lawsuit with the sole l<strong>of</strong>ty<br />

goal <strong>of</strong> somehow contributing to the public commons. 61 While such a<br />

goal may certainly be collateral to one’s use <strong>of</strong> the public justice system,<br />

it is dangerous if it supplants the private view’s goal <strong>of</strong> solving<br />

individual disputes as the primary modality for the system.<br />

Even viewing the system as a whole, it is difficult to understand<br />

why settlement tools like the option to bargain for secrecy should be<br />

removed so that the public can benefit from the settlement information.<br />

Those who endorse this public view have perhaps not spent<br />

enough time watching a litigant, 62 who, in pursuit <strong>of</strong> her case, spends<br />

her life’s savings on legal fees, risks her house by facing adverse legal<br />

fees awards, has her most private secrets relived in discovery, and<br />

lives with the entire process for nearly a decade as it chugs through<br />

the system. If not for her case, the system would not have her information<br />

to disclose. Should she have to surrender the right to control<br />

access to that information in exchange for access to the marginally<br />

tangential public administrative aspects <strong>of</strong> the system? Is the appropriate<br />

“tax” she must pay for using the public system really the removal<br />

<strong>of</strong> what might be a valued settlement tool?<br />

Forced public settlement disclosure may also actually encourage<br />

litigation. Surely this cannot be in the common public good. If infor-<br />

59. See, e.g., Miller, supra note 7, at 431; Menkel-Meadow, supra note 8, at 2692.<br />

60. See Doré, supra note 1, at 297-98 (asserting that party autonomy exists even in<br />

public cases in the civil justice system, as the parties themselves bear the risks and costs <strong>of</strong><br />

the litigation).<br />

61. Although many litigants may have as a residual reason for starting a civil action—to<br />

prevent others from experiencing the harm they had experienced—the focus <strong>of</strong><br />

this altruistic motivation is still on the individual harm the initial litigant faced. The individual<br />

had to first suffer in order to gain the motivation, or reason, to sue. The lawsuit is<br />

about the individual, and the individual is in control.<br />

62. Or a lawyer acting on a contingent fee on her client’s behalf.


964 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

mation about a typical lawsuit is disclosed to the public, there is a<br />

real possibility that lawsuits that would not have otherwise been<br />

brought will suddenly appear. While the public view considers this<br />

an efficiency in cost savings for future litigants, the private view<br />

takes a more longitudinal approach to this information disclosure. As<br />

more potential litigants are made aware <strong>of</strong> a pending lawsuit, the likelihood<br />

that additional future cases will be brought is similarly increased.<br />

The fact remains that settling cases, secret or not, clears up<br />

the court’s docket so that it can take the necessary time when a more<br />

“public” dispute enters the system. 63 Free informational discovery<br />

removes the barrier to entry for litigants. It also institutionalizes an<br />

obvious free-rider problem as the initial litigant must bear the costs<br />

to sue, but each subsequent litigant benefits from the first’s outlays. 64<br />

If one takes the civil litigation system’s fact-finding adversarial<br />

process as designed to foster truth-seeking, forced public settlement<br />

disclosure becomes a dangerous shortcut. When disclosed, what is<br />

properly relevant information in one lawsuit may do no more than<br />

encourage other litigants to take a shot at a similar lawsuit, whether<br />

meritorious or not. The upfront investment required for fact-finding<br />

in civil disputes can and does act as a clearinghouse for frivolous cases.<br />

Removing that feature may, in effect, overburden the system.<br />

Wrong-headed or opportunistic lawsuits surely do not contribute to<br />

the public good, nor does an overwhelmed public litigation system. It<br />

is far more efficient to leave the proprietary nature <strong>of</strong> the dispute in<br />

the hands <strong>of</strong> the parties who started it, including the choice to keep<br />

the settlement secret. 65<br />

The public view’s notion <strong>of</strong> contribution to the caselaw commons<br />

as a necessary product <strong>of</strong> litigating in the public system creates a<br />

63. Menkel-Meadow notes that if courts are so overburdened, there may already be an<br />

optimal amount <strong>of</strong> legal precedent available to achieve the level <strong>of</strong> public discourse that<br />

Luban and others desire. See Menkel-Meadow, supra note 8, at 2682.<br />

64. Jillian Smith argues that settlement disclosure increases lawsuit efficiency so<br />

that similarly injured individuals can share in the informational spoils <strong>of</strong> the first litigant<br />

to sue. See Jillian Smith, Secret Settlements: What You Don’t Know Can Kill You!, 2004<br />

MICH.ST.L.REV. 237, 255 (2004).<br />

65. Interestingly, Luban appears to sidestep the value-creation quality <strong>of</strong> secret settlements,<br />

where he acknowledges that banning secret settlements may eliminate the ability<br />

<strong>of</strong> “weak plaintiff[s]” to bargain toward settlement. Luban, supra note 3, at 2657. Luban<br />

does not counter this fact but instead notes that if secret settlements were banned, defendants<br />

would still have the same incentives to settle. See id. at 2657-58. This rationalization<br />

falls short because removing secrecy from the bargaining process removes a compelling<br />

reason to settle in the usual course <strong>of</strong> litigation. Defendants may, in fact, have less incentive<br />

to settle, as they may be just as well-<strong>of</strong>f in a public courtroom if the settlement information<br />

is to be made public in any event. The problem with Luban’s logic is that the “weak<br />

plaintiff” is just the type <strong>of</strong> litigant who cannot afford to run the risk <strong>of</strong> trial. Id. Menkel-<br />

Meadow additionally counters Luban’s reasoning for ignoring the fact that plaintiffs, and<br />

not just defendants, want to keep secrecy as a settlement option for privacy concerns. See<br />

Menkel-Meadow, supra note 8, at 2684.


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 965<br />

burdensome tax on users <strong>of</strong> the system. First, it assumes that cases<br />

are better <strong>of</strong>f in the system than out. Yet the civil justice system is<br />

designed to foster settlement in many ways, such as pretrial motions<br />

to remove unmeritorious cases, threats <strong>of</strong> adverse legal fees, and<br />

judicial case conferences. It is, in effect, a system with a singular<br />

purpose: to get users out <strong>of</strong> the system. For the public view’s notion<br />

to operate properly, cases must stay in the system. That has serious<br />

public resource consequences. In contrast, the private view <strong>of</strong> litigation<br />

is completely compatible with the current system’s process <strong>of</strong><br />

funneling cases toward settlement. In addition, the removal <strong>of</strong> secret<br />

settlements as an option for litigants may actually increase unwanted<br />

litigation, which is the opposite effect the public view expects.<br />

While the public view acknowledges that transparency will assist<br />

other litigants in bringing their cases forward with lower transaction<br />

costs, it does nothing to assess whether that is a desirable outcome.<br />

And the public view <strong>of</strong>fers nothing to assist in determining which<br />

cases are meritorious enough to benefit from the wholesale litigation<br />

clearinghouse that an absence <strong>of</strong> secrecy would bring. In litigation,<br />

quantity certainly cannot ever supplant quality as a sensible option.<br />

The private view <strong>of</strong> litigation is perhaps better equipped to balance<br />

this particular dynamic than its public counterpart.<br />

C. Secret Settlements Perpetuate Danger<br />

Some public view scholars and commentators argue that secret<br />

settlements can kill. 66 This is powerful rhetoric, but it makes little<br />

sense when the arguments are deconstructed, particularly in light <strong>of</strong><br />

private view concerns about the importance <strong>of</strong> secrecy in the settlement<br />

dynamic as it pertains to safety information. In fact, what<br />

sounds like the most compelling reason to ban secret settlements–<br />

public safety–may actually end up making the public less safe by incentivizing<br />

selective reporting rather than the reporting <strong>of</strong> useful<br />

66. See, e.g., Fiftal, supra note 51, at 508; Luban, supra note 4, at 2653 (arguing that<br />

litigation information can save lives and inform public deliberation about matters <strong>of</strong> political<br />

significance). See also David S. Sanson, The Pervasive Problem <strong>of</strong> Court-Sanctioned Secrecy<br />

and the Exigency <strong>of</strong> National Reform, 53 DUKE L.J. 807, 827 (2003) (arguing for legislative<br />

reform that would mandate court disclosure <strong>of</strong> information deemed a threat to public<br />

safety); Amie Sloane, Secret Settlements and Protecting Public Health and Safety: How Can<br />

We Disclose With Our Mouths Shut?, 3 APPALACHIAN J.L. 61, 68-70 (2004) (contending that<br />

environmental legislation should prompt disclosure <strong>of</strong> health and safety information in settlements);<br />

Smith, supra note 64, at 268 (arguing for uniform federal legislation requiring<br />

disclosure <strong>of</strong> settlements that affect public health or safety); Richard A. Zitrin, The Case<br />

Against Secret Settlements (Or, What You Don’t Know Can Hurt You), 2 J. INST. FOR STUDY<br />

LEGAL ETHICS 115, 122-23 (1999) (proposing code <strong>of</strong> conduct changes to preclude lawyers<br />

from entering into confidential agreements that keep secret matters <strong>of</strong> public health or<br />

safety). It is quite a bold assertion to argue that confidentiality clauses in settlements “cost<br />

lives.” There are simply too many dependent precursor variables and actions required for<br />

the publication <strong>of</strong> settlement information to even have any noticeable impact on safety.


966 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

safety information. Finally, the public view’s distaste for secret settlements<br />

may actually be driven by a deeper, hidden preference to<br />

use civil settlements as state-like regulatory or quasi-criminal punishment<br />

mechanisms–a strong public law notion.<br />

According to the public view, secret settlements allow information<br />

pertaining to safety to remain undisclosed. 67 Such information could<br />

include things like product failures or the identity <strong>of</strong> potential criminals.<br />

Without such information made public, the danger remains a secret<br />

and people could again be hurt. By endorsing secret settlements,<br />

the litigation system misses the opportunity to warn those at risk and<br />

punish wrongdoers. Plaintiffs <strong>of</strong>ten place great value on the assistance<br />

their cases will provide to others, be it future litigants or those whose<br />

safety might be similarly affected. Secret settlements hinder this altruistic<br />

motivation. Safety concerns hold within them a powerful rhetoric—who<br />

would not want to see society more safe? Hidden dangers<br />

lurking within manufactured products need to be brought to the consuming<br />

public’s attention. Toxic torts bubbling near someone’s home<br />

need to be revealed. The identities <strong>of</strong> sexual perpetrators need to be<br />

exposed to keep a community safe, so the logic goes. 68<br />

This argument against secret settlements has a number <strong>of</strong> assumptions<br />

that do not hold together. First, settlement is not adjudication.<br />

A defendant, be it a manufacturer, an alleged polluter, or an<br />

alleged sexual perpetrator, may settle for a variety <strong>of</strong> reasons other<br />

than admitted fault. Cost, risk, valuation <strong>of</strong> time, or a desire to end<br />

the matter could be prime motivators for settlement. A settlement<br />

does not mean the party has been found to be negligent under the<br />

rule <strong>of</strong> law; it means the parties compromised. A settlement also does<br />

not mean a plaintiff is free <strong>of</strong> issues affecting her case, such as contributory<br />

negligence, lack <strong>of</strong> evidence, credibility issues, or blackmailstyle<br />

motivations. Settlement does not mean that the manufacturer<br />

is negligent, that the polluter is poisoning the environment, or that<br />

the alleged perpetrator is guilty or dangerous. In the most extreme<br />

example, settlement could be no more than an agreement to dismiss<br />

the lawsuit without the risk <strong>of</strong> the defendant pursuing legal costs.<br />

That surely does nothing to establish fault or lack there<strong>of</strong> on anyone’s<br />

part. Such information is simply not publicly available to assist<br />

in making any fault or danger assessments.<br />

67. Fiftal surmises that the very information most likely to be helpful to the public–<br />

safety is the information that is also most likely to be held secret by the wealthiest corporations.<br />

Fiftal, supra note 51, at 508-09. What Fiftal’s analysis misses is that there is no<br />

empirical evidence that, even if available to the public, such settlement information would<br />

or even could do anything to promote safety and deter public hazards, except perhaps in<br />

the rarest <strong>of</strong> cases.<br />

68. See id. at 554-56.


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 967<br />

Therefore, it is wrong to assume that settlement equals a finding<br />

<strong>of</strong> fault. 69 This dangerous logical leap may actually be a strong reason<br />

to have secret settlements in a litigation system. The public cannot<br />

reliably evaluate what settlement information means. The public can<br />

only evaluate based on inaccurate assumptions, prime among them<br />

that settlement equals fault.<br />

Second, the public view <strong>of</strong> safety as paramount vastly overestimates<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> safety-related information that could be gleaned from a<br />

settlement document. Only the rarest <strong>of</strong> cases would truly have hidden<br />

information that could not already be found from the claim alone,<br />

which is already a public document. 70 What possible information could<br />

be hidden from society in a settlement agreement? 71 The public view<br />

proponents would argue that party identities would be important to<br />

know, as well as the existence <strong>of</strong> unsafe products. But what would the<br />

world do with such information? Put an alleged perpetrator on a list <strong>of</strong><br />

sex <strong>of</strong>fenders merely because he settled a claim? As demonstrated<br />

above, settlement is not adjudication—it is compromise.<br />

There is also no evidence that a public settlement does anything to<br />

increase safety in a generalized fashion. 72 This becomes evident when<br />

one traces the steps necessary to make some hypothetically relevant<br />

information public, in order that someone can act to augment safety.<br />

Imagine a settlement where a manufacturer settles a claim for a defective<br />

product. How does the public gain access to that information if the<br />

settlement is not secret? First, someone must discover that the lawsuit<br />

was even filed, which requires a search <strong>of</strong> the public records. Second,<br />

once the claim is found, someone (presumably the media) must read it<br />

69. See, e.g., Weinstein, supra note 17, at 61 (noting the possibility <strong>of</strong> the public misunderstanding<br />

settlement information, such as settlement amounts).<br />

70. Laleh Ispahani argues that lawyers should have an “affirmative ethical duty” to<br />

refuse to enter into confidential settlement agreements if there is information which might<br />

“prevent adverse health and safety consequences for the public.” Laleh Ispahani, Note, The<br />

Soul <strong>of</strong> Discretion: The Use and Abuse <strong>of</strong> Confidential Settlements, 6 GEO. J.LEGAL ETHICS<br />

111, 112 (1992). However, as noted above, it is difficult to determine what, if any, information<br />

would lead to such prevention <strong>of</strong> harm. Usually, prevention is contingent on an array<br />

<strong>of</strong> regulatory and reporting steps occurring outside the confines <strong>of</strong> the settlement. This<br />

makes putting the ethical burden on the lawyer somewhat problematic and conflicting in<br />

that, for this particular decision, the lawyer’s client shifts from the individual to the public<br />

as a whole. Id. See also Zitrin, supra note 66, at 122-23 (proposing code <strong>of</strong> conduct changes<br />

to preclude lawyers from entering into confidential agreements that keep secret matters <strong>of</strong><br />

public health or safety).<br />

71. Arthur Miller notes that the “vast majority <strong>of</strong> litigation” has very little “public interest”<br />

to it. Miller, supra note 7, at 467 (internal quotation marks omitted). Ben Depoorter also<br />

notes the ambiguous effect that forced settlement would have on litigation, stating that information<br />

about settlements is already widely available in a variety <strong>of</strong> fora, and usually simultaneously<br />

with the settlement information. See Depoorter, supra note 47, at 127-128.<br />

72. See Miller, supra note 7, at 482. Luban argues that when litigants settle, they<br />

pass the costs <strong>of</strong> secrecy on to an innocent third party not present at the bargaining table.<br />

Luban, supra note 4, at 2653. This, however, assumes that this information has value to<br />

the third party.


968 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

and understand it. Third, the settlement agreement must somehow also<br />

be in the court file. Currently, that is not a standard step in every<br />

case, unless the parties attach a copy <strong>of</strong> the agreement to the requested<br />

court order dismissing the action, or unless the parties request<br />

that the judge make the settlement terms a part <strong>of</strong> the order dismissing<br />

the action. Even assuming that there is somehow a settlement<br />

agreement in the public file, what can one do with that information in<br />

the name <strong>of</strong> safety? Report it, the argument goes, so that other members<br />

<strong>of</strong> the public may benefit from the information.<br />

There is a real risk that the reporting <strong>of</strong> such a selective amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> information could do more harm than good. Imagine if a settlement<br />

is reported between a pharmaceutical manufacturer and a patient.<br />

The reporting <strong>of</strong> the settlement accomplishes nothing more than to<br />

spur on other litigants to try their hand at a lawsuit if they have<br />

been taking that drug. Certainly, some claims may be meritorious.<br />

Others, perhaps not. Perhaps proponents hope that some government<br />

watchdog agency will investigate the pharmaceutical company. It is<br />

unclear, however, just how that might come about. In fact, such a<br />

press release could be part <strong>of</strong> the terms <strong>of</strong> the negotiated settlement,<br />

even though the identity, fault, and amount <strong>of</strong> the settlement remain<br />

secret. Now imagine if a settlement is reported between a church minister<br />

and an alleged abuse victim. The reporting <strong>of</strong> that information,<br />

without the full facts available, can certainly do reputational harm<br />

to both the minister and the victim. Is this the proper balance society<br />

should seek to achieve, all in the name <strong>of</strong> safety—publication on settlement<br />

information alone? It could be argued that such disclosure<br />

tramples over privacy rights in the name <strong>of</strong> perceived public safety.<br />

Not all settlements contain information that benefits the public. 73<br />

Of the thousands <strong>of</strong> civil lawsuits filed each year, the large majority<br />

will be for personal injury or contractual disputes. Therefore, it is <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

difficult to understand how the removal <strong>of</strong> the secret settlement<br />

tool in the name <strong>of</strong> safety will benefit society if the bulk <strong>of</strong> information<br />

floating about the court system in settlements is, for all practical<br />

purposes, useless when it comes to safety. Furthermore, it is difficult<br />

and costly to separate those few cases that might actually have publicly<br />

beneficial information from those displaying information that<br />

amounts to no more than titillating, newsy gossip. 74 In fact, just<br />

73. See Miller, supra note 7, at 467 (noting that the vast majority <strong>of</strong> civil litigation involves<br />

complex and technical details with fact situations unhelpful to daily life); see also<br />

Andrew D. Goldstein, Sealing and Revealing: Rethinking the Rules Governing Public<br />

Access to <strong>Information</strong> Generated Through Litigation, 81 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 375, 405-06<br />

(2006) (noting that the public’s interest in discovery materials is qualitatively different<br />

than the use the public could make <strong>of</strong> information in settlement agreements).<br />

74. See Miller, supra note 7, at 467 (arguing that courts would be overburdened if<br />

they had to distinguish between curiosity and voyeurism interests as opposed to legitimate<br />

public safety concerns).


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 969<br />

about any case can be skewed to appear to have an aspect <strong>of</strong> health<br />

and safety to it, from an automobile accident in which the driver<br />

failed to wear a seatbelt to a wrongful dismissal case in which unsafe<br />

working conditions are alleged. The danger <strong>of</strong> violating real privacy<br />

interests, therefore, likely outweighs tangential, ephemeral, and difficult-to-define<br />

safety concerns. 75<br />

A contextual approach to limiting secrecy for certain cases in the<br />

name <strong>of</strong> safety is also problematic. 76 It is nearly impossible to define<br />

which cases should lose the right to bargain with secrecy. It is even<br />

more difficult to attempt to define why those particular cases should<br />

lose that right. Should all litigants involved in sexual assault cases<br />

be forbidden to bargain with secrecy? What if that is the only leverage<br />

available to the plaintiff? Do all products liability settlements<br />

have beneficial information to the public, such that disclosure always<br />

outweighs the opportunity cost that is lost when secret settlements<br />

are banned?<br />

<strong>Florida</strong> and Texas, for example, have enacted “sunshine” laws designed<br />

to further public access to settlements, all in the name <strong>of</strong> safety.<br />

In <strong>Florida</strong>, a settlement cannot conceal a “public hazard.” 77 In<br />

Texas, all court documents must be made public if they contain information<br />

that might have an “adverse effect on the public.” 78 Other<br />

states, such as Arkansas 79 and Washington, 80 have enacted more narrowly<br />

tailored responses to secret settlements. These legislative<br />

measures have been met with much controversy and criticism. 81 Tell-<br />

75. There would be, <strong>of</strong> course, a slightly different informational dynamic for a mass<br />

torts case where there is a significant number <strong>of</strong> people injured as a result <strong>of</strong> someone<br />

else’s action. In those instances, a more public-centered stance may be needed to balance<br />

out the various competing concerns. This Article, however, leaves the aggregate and mass<br />

litigation cases to be categorized on the continuum another day.<br />

76. See, e.g., Fiftal, supra note 51, at 548, 554 (arguing that confidentiality should be<br />

the norm for settlements, with the exception <strong>of</strong> cases about national security, government<br />

entities, products liability, sexual violence, and substantial public health and safety<br />

threats); see also Béchamps, supra note 45, at 144 (proposing a statutory regime for sealing<br />

court decisions with exceptions militating against secrecy for a variety <strong>of</strong> lawsuits).<br />

77. See FLA. STAT. § 69.081 (2009) (prohibiting a court order or settlement from concealing<br />

a “public hazard”).<br />

78. See TEX.R.CIV. P. 76a(1)(a)(2) (mandating that all court documents are public, including<br />

settlement documents, if such contain information that might have an adverse effect<br />

upon the general public health or safety); see also Doggett & Mucchetti, supra note 26<br />

(arguing in favor <strong>of</strong> TEX. R.CIV. P. 76a, which makes public access to court records the<br />

standard rule).<br />

79. ARK. CODE ANN. § 16-55-122 (2009) (permitting a court to void settlement provisions<br />

that restrict a person’s right to disclose an environmental hazard).<br />

80. WASH. REV. CODE ANN. § 4.24.611(4)(b) (2009) (stating that confidential settlements<br />

<strong>of</strong> products liability or hazardous substances are only allowed when a court finds<br />

such confidentiality to be in the public interest).<br />

81. See, e.g., Miller, supra note 7, at 436; Laurie Kratky Doré, Public Courts Versus<br />

Private Justice: It’s Time to Let Some Sun Shine In On Alternative Dispute Resolution, 81<br />

CHI.-KENT L. REV. 463 (2006) (discussing the possibilities for transparency for disputes resolved<br />

through alternative dispute resolution other than litigation).


970 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

ingly, there appears to be no caselaw to date interpreting what these<br />

provisions mean. What is a “public hazard?” Is it an environmental<br />

spill, a sexual perpetrator, a drunk driver, or any tortfeasor? And<br />

what information could have an “adverse effect on the public?” Could<br />

such cases include fraudulent stock trading or a slip and fall at a national<br />

grocery store chain? The statutory mechanisms <strong>of</strong>fer no guidance<br />

as to when and how these provisions are to be applied. Perhaps<br />

this is real evidence that the “public good” aspect <strong>of</strong> informational exchange,<br />

which is so important to the public view <strong>of</strong> secret settlements,<br />

is actually not at all important in practical reality. The statutes<br />

may be no more than toothless appeasements to those who hold<br />

the public view <strong>of</strong> litigation and worry about any remote possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

concealment <strong>of</strong> safety information. 82 Even with a contextual, categorical<br />

approach to secret settlement bans, parties can still negotiate<br />

around such restrictions.<br />

Public view scholars <strong>of</strong>ten point to potential safety benefits when<br />

arguing in favor <strong>of</strong> such high levels <strong>of</strong> settlement disclosure. But, as<br />

the above examples demonstrate, settlement should never be a substitute<br />

for punitive criminal sanctions. 83 Relying on an inefficient and<br />

vague substitute for the criminal law without a full factual record is<br />

perhaps reckless in and <strong>of</strong> itself. The chances <strong>of</strong> inaccuracy and harm<br />

may be higher than the harm one is attempting to curb through disclosure.<br />

Private parties litigating typical private law bilateral disputes<br />

are also not expected to be private attorneys general. 84 As the<br />

system currently stands, the private civil lawsuit is not the vehicle<br />

for public punitive goals. For the most part, safety information for<br />

the public is a by-product <strong>of</strong> the private litigation system. That byproduct<br />

should not be elevated to an inappropriate and perhaps unsafe<br />

level that compromises settlement dynamics respecting privacy.<br />

What public view proponents are likely concerned about is settlement<br />

generally. Secrecy is a secondary concern. Settlement takes the<br />

82. See, e.g., Fiftal, supra note 51, at 525-26 (indicating that courts rarely use<br />

sunshine laws).<br />

83. In advocating for uniform federal legislation requiring the disclosure <strong>of</strong> settlements<br />

touching on matters <strong>of</strong> public health and safety, Jillian Smith reasons that such legislation<br />

would help hold wrongdoers accountable. See Smith, supra note 64, at 254-55.<br />

84. As opposed to more decidedly public-centric types <strong>of</strong> cases, such as class actions<br />

and securities fraud, which by their very procedural design implicate plaintiffs in the role<br />

<strong>of</strong> quasi-private attorneys general. Dan Markel discusses the idea <strong>of</strong> having private attorneys<br />

general bring actions in the name <strong>of</strong> the public for cases involving punitive damages,<br />

in which such actions have some state regulation and the private actors become entitled to<br />

a “finder’s fee” in exchange for doing the investigative work <strong>of</strong> the state. See Dan Markel,<br />

Retributive Damages: A Theory <strong>of</strong> Punitive Damages as Intermediate Sanction, 94 CORNELL<br />

L. REV. 239, 280 (2009); see also Dan Markel, How Should Punitive Damages Work?, 157<br />

U. PA. L.REV. 1383 (2009). Interestingly, his proposal is an insightful blend <strong>of</strong> the benefits<br />

<strong>of</strong> some select aspects <strong>of</strong> the public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation with a frank acknowledgment <strong>of</strong><br />

the value <strong>of</strong> the private view. Such a theoretical blending can prove equally insightful<br />

when viewing secret settlements in the context <strong>of</strong> the litigation system.


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 971<br />

dispute out <strong>of</strong> the adjudicatory process and keeps informational control<br />

in the hands <strong>of</strong> the parties in the private sphere. Yet, as mentioned in<br />

the previous section, the civil litigation system already operates with a<br />

great deal <strong>of</strong> secrecy. No one is clamoring for the end <strong>of</strong> litigation privilege<br />

in the name <strong>of</strong> safety. Menkel-Meadow notes that there is a distinct<br />

romanticism <strong>of</strong> civil litigation among some scholars. 85 Perhaps<br />

this has led to a romanticism <strong>of</strong> settlement among public view proponents.<br />

Regardless, the public view’s advocacy <strong>of</strong> safety concerns as a<br />

reason for rejecting the concept <strong>of</strong> secret settlements is turned upsidedown<br />

when one assesses the safety results through the private view’s<br />

lens in a litigation world without secret settlements.<br />

D. Secret Settlements Take Advantage <strong>of</strong> the Vulnerable<br />

The public view proponents also express perhaps misdirected concerns<br />

that secret settlements take advantage <strong>of</strong> vulnerable litigants.<br />

This assumption leads to the conclusion that the private view <strong>of</strong> litigation<br />

cannot–or will not–properly balance the needs <strong>of</strong> various parties.<br />

In other words, the ability to freely contract out <strong>of</strong> litigation<br />

should be fettered by some state control in order to protect the vulnerable.<br />

The problem with the public view’s solution (a ban on secret<br />

settlements) is that it targets the freedom to contract, instead <strong>of</strong> the<br />

actual problem: why are some litigants vulnerable? This is perhaps a<br />

not-so-subtle normative slip that underlines why the public view <strong>of</strong><br />

civil litigation, in a vacuum, is <strong>of</strong>ten ideologically driven to somewhat<br />

illogical ends because it assumes the result must be incompatible<br />

with private view thinking. Instead, the private view <strong>of</strong> litigation fosters<br />

a risk analysis approach that preserves freedom to contract<br />

while attempting to protect vulnerable interests.<br />

According to the public view, the power and informational imbalance<br />

inherent in much litigation tips in favor <strong>of</strong> the defendant. A lone<br />

plaintiff suing a corporation in a products liability lawsuit may be<br />

pressured to accept a settlement with a confidentiality clause because<br />

that plaintiff is out-resourced, out-lawyered, and outmaneuvered.<br />

The plaintiff is not a repeat player in the litigation system,<br />

whereas the defendant <strong>of</strong>ten is. This imbalance is all the more<br />

important if the plaintiff has been harmed in a particularly damaging<br />

fashion, such as in physical, psychological or sexual abuse cases.<br />

Vulnerable people may not be in a position to evaluate their needs at<br />

the time <strong>of</strong> settlement. Confidentiality, which seemed to be a bargaining<br />

chip at the time, may take on greater importance after the<br />

settlement is complete and the plaintiff regrets having lost the right<br />

to speak about the settlement. There is another concern that confus-<br />

85. See Menkel-Meadow, supra note 8, at 2669.


972 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

ing confidentiality clauses have the potential, after particularly trying<br />

disputes, to disrupt therapy and the healing process for plaintiffs.<br />

The concerns here are very real, but the target <strong>of</strong> the angst may<br />

be misplaced. The target is the secret settlement. Perhaps the target<br />

should instead be lawyers who do not effectively advise their particular<br />

clients. Removing a value-creation bargaining tool from vulnerable<br />

people may not be the most sensible way to protect those peoples’<br />

long-term interests in the settlement process. 86 In fact, it may cause<br />

more harm precisely because the plaintiff may not have that tool<br />

with which to bargain. 87 Because vulnerable plaintiffs <strong>of</strong>ten face such<br />

informational and resource power imbalances, a trial is <strong>of</strong>ten a less<br />

palatable option. 88 The toll <strong>of</strong> litigation on any person cannot be overestimated.<br />

The weight <strong>of</strong> such a process on one who is already in a<br />

precarious position can be debilitating. Settlement may be the only<br />

option. The plaintiff may not be able to finance or even survive a full<br />

trial. The evidentiary record may not be full enough for a trial. Settlement,<br />

not adjudication, becomes the goal.<br />

If that is the landscape that most <strong>of</strong> these vulnerable plaintiffs<br />

face, why remove a tool that may garner more compensation for the<br />

plaintiff and end the dispute more quickly, with less cost and less<br />

stress? The vulnerable plaintiff cannot usually use a trial as a credible<br />

threat, while the defendant can. 89 The only real tool in the vulnerable<br />

plaintiff’s arsenal may be the threat <strong>of</strong> public exposure. Removing<br />

the option <strong>of</strong> secret settlements for such litigants is akin to<br />

assuming that all plaintiffs cannot think for themselves and would<br />

not choose to bargain away secrecy for a price. This assumes the<br />

worst <strong>of</strong> the plaintiff–decisionary incapacity. It assumes that the<br />

86. Two studies revealed interesting results about the presence and absence <strong>of</strong> secrecy<br />

in a litigation context. Andrew F. Daughety and Jennifer F. Reinganum found that early<br />

claimants have negotiating leverage that allows them to get a higher settlement payout<br />

from a defendant in exchange for a secret settlement. However, later claimants fare worse<br />

in settlement scenarios in which secrecy is a factor. See Andrew F. Daughety & Jennifer F.<br />

Reinganum, Secrecy and Safety, 95 AM. ECON. REV. 1074 (2005); Andrew F. Daughety &<br />

Jennifer F. Reinganum, Hush Money, 30 RAND J. ECON. 661 (1999). Alison Lothes extended<br />

Daughety and Reinganum’s analysis to find that nonsecret settlements between defendants<br />

and early claimants induced later claimants to bring more frivolous claims.<br />

Secrecy in the civil litigation system therefore may lead to a reduction in vexatious litigation<br />

by free-riding secondary litigants relying on public information from an initial lawsuit.<br />

See Alison Lothes, Quality, Not Quantity: An Analysis <strong>of</strong> Confidential Settlements and Litigants’<br />

Economic Incentives, 154 U. PA.L.REV. 433 (2005).<br />

87. See, e.g., Fiftal, supra note 51, at 527 (arguing that secret settlements may be the<br />

only way a vulnerable plaintiff can get any compensation at all).<br />

88. See id.<br />

89. Avedis H. Sefarian and James T. Wakley argue that settlement agreements in a<br />

litigation context usually operate in a pareto-optimal trade-<strong>of</strong>f. See Sefarian & Wakley, supra<br />

note 33, at 803. No party is worse <strong>of</strong>f, and at least one party is better <strong>of</strong>f after settlement.<br />

Id. Secrecy may prompt settlement negotiations to get closer to pareto efficiency in a<br />

more expedient manner.


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 973<br />

plaintiff will always be taken advantage <strong>of</strong>, when in fact it removes a<br />

potential advantage for those very plaintiffs. 90<br />

One other possibility is to make it the plaintiff’s prerogative<br />

whether or not to settle with a confidentiality clause. 91 At first blush,<br />

this appears to be empowering plaintiffs. If the plaintiff does not<br />

wish to submit to a confidentiality clause, a plaintiff does not have to<br />

do so. But this takes an overly simplistic view <strong>of</strong> how settlement negotiations<br />

are conducted. The negotiation landscape already makes<br />

settlement the plaintiff’s choice. Defendants in this sort <strong>of</strong> regime<br />

would know that the plaintiffs have the power to institute confidentiality;<br />

so too would plaintiffs. The dynamic remains the same. Merely<br />

placing the ability to mention confidentiality as an option in the<br />

hands <strong>of</strong> the plaintiff will do nothing to curb settlement practices involving<br />

secrecy. Both parties would be foolish not to explore in negotiations<br />

whether secrecy has any value-added component for the settlement.<br />

In fact, the plaintiff has the power to reject a secret settlement<br />

at any time if confidentiality provisions are at all an issue.<br />

It falls then on the shoulders <strong>of</strong> lawyers to protect their vulnerable<br />

clients’ needs. That is where the public view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation can be<br />

quite helpful, but only if tempered with the private view’s notion <strong>of</strong><br />

the adversarial litigation process. The lawyer is the individual looking<br />

out for the best interests <strong>of</strong> her client. If the client is likely to require<br />

therapy in the future, the lawyer should advise the client to not<br />

accept, or at the very least rework, a confidentiality clause to accommodate<br />

such future needs. If the client is unable to predict her future<br />

needs, the lawyer should be trained to provide that foresight for their<br />

client. Simply banning the option to bargain with secrecy takes away<br />

the ability <strong>of</strong> an informed but vulnerable plaintiff and her lawyer to<br />

bargain creatively with additional leverage. 92<br />

90. For example, in the Canadian case <strong>of</strong> Milne v. Pfizer, Inc., 2005 ABQB 236 (CanLII),<br />

the court approved a minor’s settlement and ordered the terms <strong>of</strong> the settlement confidential.<br />

The court determined it was in the minor’s best interests for the settlement to be approved,<br />

even with a confidentiality agreement, rather than to receive no settlement at all.<br />

91. As was recommended by the <strong>Law</strong> Commission <strong>of</strong> Canada for cases involving government<br />

institutional abuse in RESTORING DIGNITY: RESPONDING TO CHILD ABUSE IN<br />

CANADIAN INSTITUTIONS 410 (2000). The Report recommends that government defendants<br />

should not impose confidentiality provisions on settlements with survivors <strong>of</strong> institutional<br />

abuse; rather, the choice should remain with the plaintiff. Curiously, there was no discussion<br />

about the loss <strong>of</strong> value-creation to these same vulnerable plaintiffs if secret settlements<br />

were removed from the settlement dynamic.<br />

92. Minna J. Kotkin, while arguing against secret settlements for employment discrimination<br />

cases and simultaneously decrying many aspects <strong>of</strong> the private view <strong>of</strong> civil litigation,<br />

notes that there can be a sort <strong>of</strong> selective secrecy that may balance both perspectives.<br />

See Kotkin, supra note 3, at 977. Kotkin suggests that a court could make available<br />

public data about the nature and extent <strong>of</strong> a settlement but keep the parties’ identities a<br />

secret, purely to assist in aggregating information about settlement rates. Id. The value <strong>of</strong><br />

such information could assist in making the public aware <strong>of</strong> the prevalence <strong>of</strong> such claims<br />

in the workplace. See also Ross E. Cheit, Tort Litigation, Transparency, and the Public In-


974 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

This particular public view desire to ban secret settlements becomes<br />

less compelling when one considers that the enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

confidentiality clauses is inconsistent at best. Would any court truly<br />

prohibit an injured plaintiff from seeking psychological counseling after<br />

an injury, merely because <strong>of</strong> a broadly-worded confidentiality<br />

clause? If the plaintiff thinks she is barred from seeking therapy,<br />

even though she may not be in reality, the real concern is with her<br />

lawyer. Why did the lawyer fail to explain the practical ramifications<br />

<strong>of</strong> the clause to the client, or that enforcement is questionable at<br />

best? Here, awareness and education <strong>of</strong> lawyers can play a significant<br />

role. Removing a settlement tool and upsetting the settlement<br />

dynamic in the name <strong>of</strong> vague concerns for the vulnerable assumes<br />

the worst. It may, in the end, remove the only real settlement tool a<br />

vulnerable plaintiff may have.<br />

E. Government Entities Should Not Enter into Secret Settlements<br />

The public view <strong>of</strong> litigation holds that governments should never<br />

enter into secret settlements because the state is a public entity beholden<br />

to the public. 93 The public has a right to know what the government<br />

is doing. The government-as-party justification for a ban on<br />

secret settlements also hearkens back to the transparency arguments<br />

against secret settlements. If the government is a litigant using public<br />

tax dollars, the government should not be allowed to bargain away<br />

confidentiality because the public has a right to know what the government<br />

is doing with the public’s money. 94 The government is then<br />

not a normal party but a super-party in litigation, representing more<br />

than just an individual’s private interests. The private view <strong>of</strong> litiga-<br />

terest, 13 ROGER WILLIAMS U. L. REV. 232, 272 (2008) (discussing a similar positive externality<br />

toward a modified secret settlement regime in the form <strong>of</strong> improving public data collection).<br />

Blanca Fromm argues that this type <strong>of</strong> partial settlement disclosure regime might<br />

actually begin to operate as an informal system <strong>of</strong> precedent for lawyers. See Blanca<br />

Fromm, Bringing Settlement Out <strong>of</strong> the Shadows: <strong>Information</strong> About Settlement in an Age<br />

<strong>of</strong> Confidentiality, 48 UCLA L. REV. 663 (2001). Of course the benefits <strong>of</strong> any such model<br />

still depend on the lawyer’s ability to accurately interpret what may be ambiguous information<br />

in a settlement agreement (i.e., “fault,” factual information, and monetary<br />

amounts). It is difficult to predict the utility <strong>of</strong> much settlement information without more<br />

background regarding the dispute under which it arose.<br />

93. See Sedona Conference Working Group, The Sedona Guidelines: Best Practices<br />

Addressing Protective Orders, Confidentiality & Public Access in Civil Cases, 8 SEDONA<br />

CONF. J. 141, 177 (2007) (recommending that, absent exceptional circumstances, settlements<br />

with public entities should not be confidential, so as to adhere to the principle <strong>of</strong><br />

transparency in government).<br />

94. This is likely the motivation behind the <strong>Law</strong> Commission <strong>of</strong> Canada’s recommendations<br />

that government defendants should not impose confidentiality provisions on settlements<br />

with survivors <strong>of</strong> institutional abuse. See <strong>Law</strong> Commission <strong>of</strong> Canada, supra note<br />

91, at 410. The Report does not, however, call for a ban on secrecy but instead recommends<br />

placing control <strong>of</strong> secrecy in the hands <strong>of</strong> the plaintiff only. Curiously, there was no discussion<br />

about the loss <strong>of</strong> value-creation to these same vulnerable plaintiffs if secret settlements<br />

were removed from the settlement dynamic.


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 975<br />

tion, however, would uphold the principles <strong>of</strong> party autonomy and<br />

party prosecution regardless <strong>of</strong> who the party is. Even the government<br />

as litigant needs the discretion to keep some things secret.<br />

Treating the government as a special party that would not have<br />

access to the option <strong>of</strong> secrecy in settlement creates a host <strong>of</strong> problems.<br />

First, most government entities already operate with some degree<br />

<strong>of</strong> secrecy. It would be difficult and problematic to attempt to categorize<br />

precisely which settlements are to be made public and which<br />

should be kept secret. What about cases involving sensitive matters<br />

<strong>of</strong> national security? What about cases <strong>of</strong> institutional abuse within<br />

government organizations? Do the victims not have the right to keep<br />

the settlement secret if they so choose? Must the settlement be disclosed<br />

just because the defendant is a government entity? And if so,<br />

does this further compromise settlement prospects? In many instances,<br />

the government is the most formidable law firm with the<br />

most resources a party will ever encounter.<br />

The public view <strong>of</strong> government litigation helps highlight one important<br />

fact–the settlement dynamic with the government as a party<br />

may be unique. If discretion is granted to the government to enter<br />

the lawsuit, to defend the lawsuit, or to settle the lawsuit, all in the<br />

public interest, why should the option <strong>of</strong> a secret settlement be disallowed<br />

if is in the public interest? In fact, precisely because the litigant<br />

is the government, there may be a variety <strong>of</strong> publicly available<br />

informational resources with which to gain far more access to settlement<br />

information than with any other private entity. These informational<br />

resources may provide such data in a different form than the<br />

actual settlement agreement, but they would be no less revelatory.<br />

What is special about the agreement itself that it must be disclosed<br />

in its entirety? Using the public interest to restrict the government’s<br />

capacity to bargain in the public interest is a very odd dichotomy.<br />

The real target <strong>of</strong> the public view’s concern <strong>of</strong> government-as- litigant<br />

is the issue <strong>of</strong> informational disclosure <strong>of</strong> data that may be useful<br />

in the public domain. One must make a pr<strong>of</strong>ound assumption to conclude<br />

that every settlement entered into by the government-as-litigant<br />

holds important data useful for the public domain. There are many<br />

acts a government undertakes each day that are shrouded in secrecy.<br />

Furthermore, a government performs many acts each day utilizing<br />

public funds. None <strong>of</strong> these acts are automatically reviewable by the<br />

public, automatically informative <strong>of</strong> anything the government has<br />

done or plans to do, or even automatically interesting or additive to the<br />

political conversation <strong>of</strong> the day. This is not secrecy for secrecy’s sake<br />

but administrative efficiency and delegated discretion.<br />

Essentially, then, the banning <strong>of</strong> secret settlements by government<br />

entities is no more than a signal <strong>of</strong> government distrust and an


976 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

institutionalized mechanism for government review by the public.<br />

Rather than enhancing the political conversation with its constituents,<br />

forced settlement disclosure may actually bind the hands <strong>of</strong> the<br />

delegated government body to get its job done efficiently, fairly, and<br />

in the interests <strong>of</strong> the public. The public view assumes as an immutable<br />

rule that it is never in the public interest to keep settlements secret.<br />

Interestingly, this is more in keeping with what one might expect<br />

the private view <strong>of</strong> litigation to conclude about government involvement<br />

in lawsuits.<br />

In contrast, the private view simply treats the government as any<br />

other party, subject to the same rules and permitted to use the same<br />

settlement tools. In the end, this might prove to be the most efficient<br />

way to conceive <strong>of</strong> the government-as-litigator in the civil justice system.<br />

Government informational disclosure requirements are, or<br />

should be, more than adequate to deal with the public’s thirst for information,<br />

for whatever reason, be it accountability concerns or media<br />

gossip. Removing secret settlements as an option for the government<br />

so as to enhance governmental informational disclosure may<br />

actually cause the public more harm than good. Litigation may become<br />

protracted, discretion fettered, the interests <strong>of</strong> the vulnerable<br />

not heeded, and the public may not know what to do with the information<br />

even if it had it. Further yet, the public may misinterpret the<br />

information. In fact, all <strong>of</strong> the problems with the public view’s desire<br />

to ban secret settlements–transparency, public contribution, safety,<br />

and the vulnerable–are completely turned on their heads when the<br />

public itself is the litigator. Secret settlements are a litigation settlement<br />

tool, not an informational prospectus.<br />

IV. CONCLUSION<br />

The public view’s charge to ban secret settlements does not sit<br />

comfortably with much <strong>of</strong> what public view scholars want to see in<br />

the civil litigation system itself. Perhaps the most important final<br />

flaw in thinking <strong>of</strong> the civil justice system from the public view<br />

standpoint is revealed when extrapolating what would occur if secret<br />

settlements were actually banned for any one <strong>of</strong> the reasons cited by<br />

public view scholars. Banning secret settlements altogether may<br />

have absolutely no effect on the use <strong>of</strong> secret settlements in litigation<br />

because parties will just work around the ban. 95 This is a decidedly<br />

95. Indeed, Scott Moss notes that while a ban on secret settlements would have an effect<br />

on the incidence <strong>of</strong> settling a lawsuit after it has been filed, there would be a resultant<br />

increase in settlements reached before the lawsuit is filed. While Moss notes that settlements<br />

reached before a lawsuit is filed are most certainly cheaper to the litigation system<br />

in economic terms, it is difficult to predict the total net effect <strong>of</strong> a secret settlement ban because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the variety <strong>of</strong> factors and behaviors in the settlement dynamic. At the very least,<br />

Moss concedes that uncertainty costs prevent economic analysis <strong>of</strong> secret settlements from


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 977<br />

private view result. A legislative ban on secret settlements may incentivize<br />

parties to opt out <strong>of</strong> the public justice system and into private<br />

arbitration or alternative dispute resolution, where the ban may<br />

not apply. 96 Disputing parties may forum shop or use contractual<br />

choice <strong>of</strong> law language to select a jurisdiction that allows secret settlements.<br />

97 Parties may also agree to never file a suit with the public<br />

justice system. 98 One could imagine a defendant demanding, as part<br />

<strong>of</strong> settlement negotiations, that the plaintiff dismiss the publicly filed<br />

lawsuit so that the parties negotiate beyond the shadow <strong>of</strong> the law altogether,<br />

with secrecy as a possible bargaining chip once the dispute<br />

is completely outside the public system. What is the point <strong>of</strong> a ban if<br />

any party can still contract around the ban? 99<br />

The civil justice system is built to favor settlement over trial. For<br />

the typical private law dispute, it is a system with values most compatible<br />

with the private view <strong>of</strong> litigation because the private view<br />

can accommodate some public view concerns in a nonlinear fashion.<br />

100 It appears that the public view is far less effective at accommodating<br />

private view concerns. To that end, it makes most<br />

sense to allow parties to bargain with secrecy if they see fit. Regulation<br />

does no more than reduce opportunities for settlement and upset<br />

the dynamic <strong>of</strong> settlement negotiations and, in some cases, the very<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> settlement at all.<br />

In fact, by keeping secret settlements in effect for nonaggregate private<br />

law disputes in the civil justice system, the private view’s<br />

strength is in its malleability at the system design level. One can focus<br />

on individual private concerns and <strong>of</strong>ten simultaneously meet public<br />

providing a clear answer as to whether or not a total ban is beneficial. See Scott A. Moss,<br />

Illuminating Secrecy: A New Economic Analysis <strong>of</strong> Confidential Settlements, 105 MICH. L.<br />

REV. 867 (2007). See also Depoorter, supra note 47 (noting the ambiguous effect that a ban<br />

on secret settlements would have on litigation behavior).<br />

96. See, e.g., Sedona Conference Working Group, supra note 93, at 173; Luban, supra<br />

note 4, at 2622 (arguing that if public courts cannot compete with private dispute resolution,<br />

litigants will switch to private providers).<br />

97. See Drahozal & Hines, supra note 9, at 1481-82.<br />

98. See id. at 1459 (proposing that parties could circumvent secrecy bans by settling<br />

before the claimant actually files a lawsuit).<br />

99. Unless, <strong>of</strong> course, the legislative ban also prohibited contracting around the ban<br />

on secret settlements. This creates a host <strong>of</strong> enforceability and fairness concerns. What if,<br />

for example, it is perfectly appropriate in a highly sensitive case to keep the settlement a<br />

secret? Ontario’s recent experience with a blanket ban on contracting around limitation<br />

periods in section 22 <strong>of</strong> the Ontario Limitations Act, 2002 is a prime example <strong>of</strong> how statutory<br />

enforcement can create chaos and confusion. In Ontario, the statute eventually had to<br />

be amended to provide greater clarity for citizens and reasonableness <strong>of</strong> result. Ontario<br />

risked losing commercial deals through forum-shopping to a jurisdiction that did not have<br />

such a ban on contracting behavior. See, e.g., R. John Cameron, New Limitation Periods—<br />

Contracting in Ontario, 40 CAN. BUS. L.J. 109 (2004) (citing the problems with a ban on<br />

contracting around the newly enacted two year standard limitation period).<br />

100. See Drahozal & Hines, supra note 9, at 1466-67 (arguing that secrecy in the litigation<br />

system makes settlements more likely).


978 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945<br />

interest concerns. For example, keeping secrecy as a viable bargaining<br />

tool can prompt creative settlement solutions that add unique value to<br />

the settlement. The obvious instances are when secrecy has a price for<br />

one party. The price paid to settle the case is higher if secrecy is part <strong>of</strong><br />

the settlement package. In some instances, the entire settlement may<br />

be about secrecy. Remove the option to bargain with secrecy, and one<br />

removes the ability to settle some disputes. But keeping secret settlements<br />

in the litigation system allows parties to use secrecy’s value in<br />

creative ways. For example, if one party values secrecy or if the control<br />

<strong>of</strong> information is important to both, the parties could add to the settlement<br />

a jointly drafted press release. That is a nonmonetary solution<br />

that has a monetary value for one or both parties. Part <strong>of</strong> a settlement<br />

could also include negotiations concerning the issuance <strong>of</strong> a warning<br />

about a defective product or a product recall in exchange for secrecy.<br />

Such a settlement solution would satisfy a litigant’s desire to ensure<br />

that harm does not happen to a future consumer, while still protecting<br />

the litigant’s privacy.<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> secrecy does not always have to be measured in dollars.<br />

Parties could also negotiate for a policy change in an organization<br />

or workplace in exchange for secrecy. Again, the ameliorative effect <strong>of</strong><br />

the settlement, so central to the public view <strong>of</strong> secret settlements, is<br />

not lost but is in fact enhanced by the addition <strong>of</strong> secrecy to settlement<br />

negotiations. The commodity <strong>of</strong> secrecy, unlike the commodity <strong>of</strong> money,<br />

prompts creative settlement discussions such as these. There is<br />

nothing stopping parties from negotiating confidentiality clauses in secret<br />

settlements that are tailored to the specific client’s future needs.<br />

Such needs could include therapy, the recognition <strong>of</strong> the therapeutic<br />

value <strong>of</strong> discussing some aspects <strong>of</strong> the results <strong>of</strong> the settlement, or the<br />

ability to disclose some information required to keep others safe while<br />

still respecting some private elements <strong>of</strong> the settlement. If secrecy is<br />

taken <strong>of</strong>f the bargaining table, negotiations are invariably limited to<br />

money alone. Surely the public interest benefits more from any one <strong>of</strong><br />

the above alternative settlement arrangements.<br />

For these types <strong>of</strong> standard private law disputes, the private view<br />

<strong>of</strong> the civil litigation system thus fosters a more complete dialogue<br />

about how to balance rights <strong>of</strong> parties with the public interest in operating<br />

a publicly funded and publicly available dispute resolution<br />

mechanism. However, because the public and private views operate<br />

on a nonexclusive, nonlinear continuum, the type <strong>of</strong> dispute may also<br />

control the perspective from which one views and reforms the system.<br />

A civil rights case or a class action may, by necessity, require some<br />

thinking more in line with the public end <strong>of</strong> the continuum.<br />

In the secret settlement context for typical private law disputes,<br />

the limits <strong>of</strong> bargaining with secrecy are thus the limits <strong>of</strong> partydriven<br />

imagination. If a party sees value in secrecy and the opposing


2010] KEEPING SETTLEMENTS SECRET 979<br />

party sees value in disclosure, there is suddenly opportunity for value-creation<br />

in compromise. The price <strong>of</strong> secrecy does not always have<br />

to depend solely on the willingness <strong>of</strong> a party to pay for secrecy but<br />

may also depend on the creativity <strong>of</strong> a party in trading on secrecy. In<br />

a party-driven adversary system, most disputants with nonaggregate<br />

private law claims are made worse <strong>of</strong>f by removing secret settlements<br />

from the landscape <strong>of</strong> civil litigation. Only the private view <strong>of</strong> the civil<br />

justice system equips one to evaluate procedural reforms on, ironically,<br />

both private and public criteria.<br />

By unpacking the criticisms <strong>of</strong> secret settlements, it becomes evident<br />

that the wholly public view arguments are problematic and reversible.<br />

This suggests that the public view, standing alone, may not<br />

be the best way to normatively design the civil justice system’s procedural<br />

mechanisms for standard private law disputes even if, in<br />

fact, one asserts that typical public values are <strong>of</strong> equal importance to<br />

private values. Perhaps, then, the public view is best thought <strong>of</strong> as<br />

operating on a nonexclusive continuum in conjunction with the private<br />

view. At the same time, the private view <strong>of</strong> secret settlements<br />

does a better job <strong>of</strong> accommodating many public view concerns while<br />

still preserving the party-driven civil justice system in which party<br />

autonomy is currently <strong>of</strong> some import. The relationship between<br />

these two standpoints is likely thus complementary and nonlinear. 101<br />

This conception may prove helpful in informing future scholarly debates<br />

about the procedural aspects <strong>of</strong> any kind <strong>of</strong> case, whether the<br />

bilateral private law dispute, the mass tort, or the class action. Scholars<br />

should recognize that concerns that were previously thought <strong>of</strong><br />

as belonging only to one camp <strong>of</strong> thinking are actually inversely <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

solved by the other perspective when the relationship between the<br />

public and private views is understood as something beyond oppositional.<br />

The public can indeed inform the private, and the private can<br />

inform the public. In the end, the utility <strong>of</strong> the difference is not one <strong>of</strong><br />

kind, but <strong>of</strong> degree.<br />

101. As opposed to bipolar, thus requiring a balancing or trade-<strong>of</strong>f exercise, as Lederman<br />

argues is necessary when discussing the benefits <strong>of</strong> legal precedent versus settlement<br />

<strong>of</strong> civil disputes. See Lederman, supra note 3 at 268.


980 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:945


AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET: THE NEXT<br />

REVOLUTION<br />

ALVAN BALENT *<br />

ABSTRACT<br />

The Internet is now a staple <strong>of</strong> modern society, and as a result, there is great interest in<br />

finding ways to further develop the Internet and expand its services. Recent literature has<br />

begun to focus on one particular aspect <strong>of</strong> the Internet that needs improvement: its energy<br />

usage. Accordingly, this Note examines the potential benefits <strong>of</strong> an energy-efficient Internet<br />

and explains how taxation based on energy usage can provide a constant impetus to improve<br />

not only the Internet’s energy efficiency but also that <strong>of</strong> other industries. Thus far, commentators<br />

have not published many works with regard to an Internet energy tax despite the<br />

longstanding debate over Internet taxation itself, which has largely centered upon the concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> a sales tax. This Note <strong>of</strong>fers new insights into the Internet tax policy debate and provides<br />

a rudimentary framework for structuring an Internet energy tax.<br />

I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................................ 981<br />

II. OVERVIEW OF THE INTERNET TAXATION DEBATE ........................................................... 982<br />

III. WHY AN ENERGY TAX ..................................................................................................... 984<br />

IV. WHY ACHIEVING ENERGY EFFICIENCY REQUIRES GOVERNMENT INTERVENTION .......... 991<br />

V. AN INTERNET ENERGY TAX PROPOSAL ........................................................................... 999<br />

VI. CONCLUSION ................................................................................................................... 1001<br />

I. INTRODUCTION<br />

Over the course <strong>of</strong> the last two decades, the Internet has revolutionized<br />

American society and humankind as a whole. 1 With the advent<br />

<strong>of</strong> email and instant messenger, the Internet changed the way<br />

we communicate; with the advent <strong>of</strong> search engines like Google and<br />

Yahoo, it changed the way we gather information; and now, with the<br />

advent <strong>of</strong> sites like Facebook and MySpace, the Internet is changing<br />

basic modes <strong>of</strong> social interactions. 2 The Internet has spurred economic<br />

growth by enabling the e-commerce phenomenon to develop. 3<br />

It has also created many high-tech jobs that help build, maintain,<br />

and improve the Internet’s vast technological infrastructure such as<br />

data centers, which are the buildings that hold the computer equipment<br />

supporting the information and communication systems. 4 This<br />

* Alvan Balent, a graduate <strong>of</strong> Vassar <strong>College</strong>, is a May 2010 J.D. graduate from<br />

FSU <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong>. He would like to thank his friends and family for their muchappreciated<br />

assistance with this paper, particularly FSU <strong>Law</strong> Review editors Nathan Hill,<br />

Nancy Pinzino, and Amanda Swindle, and FSU Pr<strong>of</strong>essor and Research Center Director,<br />

Faye Jones.<br />

1. See, e.g., MANUEL CASTELLS, THE RISE OF THE NETWORK SOCIETY: ECONOMY,<br />

SOCIETY AND CULTURE 387-88 (2000); CATHERINE L. MANN ET AL., GLOBAL ELECTRONIC<br />

COMMERCE:APOLICY PRIMER 16-18 (2000).<br />

2. See CASTELLS, supra note 1; see also PRESTON GRALLA ET AL., HOW THE INTERNET<br />

WORKS 133 (1998).<br />

3. Keith Regan, UN: E-Commerce Key to Global Economic Growth, E-COMMERCE<br />

TIMES, Nov. 21, 2001, available at http://www.ecommercetimes.com/story/14915.html;<br />

Mark W. Vigoroso, The Golden Age <strong>of</strong> E-Commerce Pr<strong>of</strong>its, E-COMMERCE TIMES, Mar. 19,<br />

2002, http://www.ecommercetimes.com/story/16805.html?wlc=1226258239.<br />

4. Jennifer D. Mitchell-Jackson, Energy Needs in an Internet Economy: A Closer


982 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981<br />

infrastructure requires a constant supply <strong>of</strong> energy—one that is more<br />

reliable than the United <strong>State</strong>s energy grid typically supplies—in order<br />

to operate. 5 Between the Internet’s constant expansion and the<br />

reluctance <strong>of</strong> data centers to share information for security reasons,<br />

it is difficult to determine exactly how much energy the Internet requires.<br />

6 Studies, though, have estimated the Internet’s net energy<br />

consumption, which includes all <strong>of</strong>fice equipment, to be anywhere between<br />

1-13% <strong>of</strong> the United <strong>State</strong>s’ total electrical usage, and demand<br />

is increasing constantly. 7 From 2000 to 2005, “energy use associated<br />

with servers doubled . . . representing an aggregate annual growth<br />

rate <strong>of</strong> 14% per year for the U.S. . . . .” 8 An energy-efficient Internet<br />

has desirable benefits—namely, the enabling <strong>of</strong> greater Internet deployment<br />

especially into the poorest regions <strong>of</strong> the world and improved<br />

Internet reliability in an emergency situation such as a natural disaster.<br />

This Note explores how the U.S. tax code could be used to<br />

achieve an energy-efficient Internet.<br />

II. OVERVIEW OF THE INTERNET TAXATION DEBATE<br />

Taxing the Internet is a subject <strong>of</strong> contentious debate. This debate<br />

most <strong>of</strong>ten focuses on whether a sales tax should be levied upon all<br />

cyberpurchases, i.e., the online “retail sales <strong>of</strong> products and services,<br />

advertising, and business-to-business commerce.” 9 Since its inception<br />

in the 1990s, e-commerce has been a pr<strong>of</strong>itable sector <strong>of</strong> the U.S.<br />

economy. For instance, government estimates showed that U.S. retail<br />

e-commerce sales were $5.3 billion in the fourth quarter <strong>of</strong> 1999<br />

alone. 10 While this number was a tiny fraction <strong>of</strong> the $821.2 billion in<br />

total retail sales for that quarter, it was clear that the e-commerce<br />

Look at Data Centers (July 10, 2001) (unpublished M.S. thesis, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> California,<br />

Berkeley), available at http://enduse.lbl.gov/Info/datacenterreport.pdf, at 3.<br />

5. Id.<br />

6. See generally Peter W. Huber, Dig More Coal—the PCs are Coming, FORBES<br />

MAGAZINE, May 31, 1999, available at http://www.forbes.com/forbes/1999/0531/6311070a_<br />

2.html.<br />

7. JONATHAN G. KOOMEY, ESTIMATING TOTAL POWER CONSUMPTION BY SERVERS IN<br />

THE U.S. AND THE WORLD 6 (2007), available at http://dl.klima2008.net/ccsl/koomey_<br />

long.pdf; see also Huber, supra note 6; Mitchell-Jackson, supra note 4, at 12. It may soon be<br />

possible to more accurately determine the energy usage <strong>of</strong> data centers because the Environmental<br />

Protection Agency has recently announced that it will soon provide Energy Star<br />

ratings for data centers. EPA to Begin Energy Star Ratings for Data Centers,<br />

ENVIRONMENTAL LEADER, Apr. 21, 2009, http://www.environmentalleader.com/2009/04/21/<br />

epa-to-release-energy-star-rating-for-data-centers/.<br />

8. KOOMEY, supra note 7, at 6 (emphasis added).<br />

9. Isabel M. Isidro, PowerHomeBiz.com, Internet Taxation: Which Side Are You On?,<br />

http://www.powerhomebiz.com/vol4/internet-taxation.htm (last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

10. Press Release, William M. Daley, Secretary <strong>of</strong> Commerce, Retail E-Commerce<br />

Sales for the Fourth Quarter 1999 Reach $5.3 Billion, Census Bureau Reports (Mar. 2,<br />

2000), available at http://www2.census.gov/retail/releases/historical/ecomm/99Q4.pdf).


2010] AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET 983<br />

sector <strong>of</strong> the economy would continue to grow. 11 The number <strong>of</strong> people<br />

shopping online increased between 1998 and 1999 and consumer ecommerce<br />

gained acceptance globally. 12 Statistics have proven early<br />

studies to be accurate. Between 2000-2009, the world’s Internet<br />

usage grew at a rate <strong>of</strong> 362.3%, and e-commerce is expected to become<br />

more than a $300 billion sector <strong>of</strong> the global economy between<br />

2008-2012. 13 This figure will likely continue to increase because, as <strong>of</strong><br />

September 2009, Internet service is only available to approximately<br />

25.6% <strong>of</strong> the world’s population. 14 As worldwide Internet use grows,<br />

e-commerce will expand with it.<br />

In light <strong>of</strong> the explosive growth <strong>of</strong> e-commerce, the revenues from<br />

a potential Internet sales tax became impossible to ignore, and soon<br />

there was much literature on the subject. Proponents <strong>of</strong> such a tax<br />

argue that tax-free e-commerce is like tax evasion in which states<br />

lose billions in annual sales tax revenue. 15 This massive revenue loss<br />

“impair[s] the ability <strong>of</strong> state and local governments to improve education,<br />

roads, public safety, health, low-income housing, and many<br />

other essential services[,]” and may ultimately lead to an increase in<br />

other taxes to recoup the lost revenue. 16 Proponents <strong>of</strong> an Internet<br />

sales tax also contend that it is fundamentally unfair not to tax ecommerce<br />

when other services that are important to economic growth<br />

are taxed and when studies indicate that the vast majority <strong>of</strong> online<br />

shoppers would not be deterred from shopping online by a sales tax. 17<br />

Opponents <strong>of</strong> Internet taxation, however, argue that the Internet<br />

is in the early and critical stages <strong>of</strong> development. Thus, any tax on e-<br />

11. Id.; Soyeon Shim et al., An Online Prepurchase Intentions Model: The Role <strong>of</strong> Intention<br />

to Search, 77 J. RETAILING 397, 397 (2001), available at http://itu.dk/<br />

~petermeldgaard/B12/lektion%203/An%20online%20prepurchase%20intentions%20model<br />

%20_The%20role%20<strong>of</strong>%20intention%20to%20search.pdf.<br />

12. Isidro, supra note 9; U.S. Consumers Remain Bullish on Online Shopping This<br />

Holiday Season, According to Ernst & Young Study; Holiday Online Volume Projected to<br />

Exceed $10 Billion, BUSINESS WIRE, Nov. 28, 2000, http://findarticles.com/p/articles/<br />

mi_m0EIN/is_2000_Nov_28/ai_67371621.<br />

13. InternetWorldStats.com, Internet Usage Statistics, http://<br />

www.internetworldstats.com/stats.htm (last visited Aug. 27, 2010); Sucharita Mulpuru et<br />

al., US eCommerce Forecast: 2008 To 2012, FORRESTER, Jan. 18, 2008, http://<br />

www.forrester.com/rb/Research/us_ecommerce_forecast_2008_to_2012/q/id/41592/t/2; Sucharita<br />

Mulpuru, Data Charts: US eCommerce: 2008 To 2012, FORRESTER, May 6, 2008,<br />

http://www.forrester.com/rb/Research/us_ecommerce_forecast_2008_to_2012/q/id/41592/t/2;<br />

Barbara M. Fraumeni, E-Commerce: Measurement and Measurement Issues, 91 AM. ECON.<br />

REV. 318, 319 (2001).<br />

14. AllAboutMarketResearch.com, Internet Growth and Stats: Today’s Road to<br />

eCommerce and Global Trade, http://www.allaboutmarketresearch.com/internet.htm (last<br />

visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

15. Neil Munro, If It Grows, Tax It, 40 COMM. OF THE ACM 11, 12 (1997), available at<br />

http://delivery.acm.org/10.1145/250000/242859/p11-munro.pdf?key1=242859&key2=<br />

4953504221&coll=GUIDE&dl=GUIDE&CFID=6516967&CFTOKEN=20177739.<br />

16. Isidro, supra note 9.<br />

17. Megan E. Groves, Tolling the <strong>Information</strong> Superhighway: <strong>State</strong> Sales and Use<br />

Taxation <strong>of</strong> Electronic Commerce, 13 HARV.J.L.&TECH. 619, 620 (2000).


984 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981<br />

commerce would slow the internet’s growth before the tax gains acceptance<br />

among consumers. As evidence, opponents cite studies<br />

showing that e-commerce would decline if it were taxed. 18 They argue<br />

that e-commerce has increased regular retail purchases by citing a<br />

study showing that consumers only used the Internet to learn <strong>of</strong> an<br />

item before purchasing it in a store. 19 Tax opponents also argue that<br />

in addition to the Internet being a developing “medium whose full<br />

ramifications are not close to being understood[,]” the Internet’s very<br />

nature prevents it from being controlled or regulated. 20 Because it is<br />

“inherently non-geographic,” any tax on the Internet could lead to a<br />

reduction in the number <strong>of</strong> available jobs in the taxing nation as<br />

companies would relocate to places that do not tax them. 21 As illustrated<br />

by the passage and subsequent legislative extensions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Internet Tax Nondiscrimination Act (ITNA), which restricts the taxing<br />

authority <strong>of</strong> state and local government over the Internet, the anti-Internet<br />

tax camp is currently winning this debate. 22 Although the<br />

ITNA complicated efforts to tax the Internet, this Act would not prohibit<br />

a federal effort to tax the Internet based upon its net energy<br />

consumption. 23 A federal tax scheme focused on energy rather than ecommerce<br />

transactions would thus be outside the scope <strong>of</strong> the ITNA.<br />

III. WHY AN ENERGY TAX<br />

Regardless <strong>of</strong> the ITNA’s restrictions, the debate over Internet taxation<br />

has largely been focused around imposing sales and use taxes on<br />

Internet transactions. It is extremely difficult to locate publications<br />

that discuss the idea <strong>of</strong> an Internet energy tax. 24 Given the variety <strong>of</strong><br />

18. Austan Goolsbee, Internet Commerce, Tax Sensitivity, and the Generation Gap, 14<br />

TAX POL’Y &ECON. 45, 45 (2000).<br />

19. Isidro, supra note 9; Shim, supra note 11, at 398.<br />

20. David L. Forst, Old and New Issues in the Taxation <strong>of</strong> Electronic Commerce, 14<br />

BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 711, 711 (1999); see also Isidro, supra note 9.<br />

21. Isidro, supra note 9.<br />

22. The ITNA, originally known as the Internet Tax Freedom Act, and its impact on<br />

Internet taxation is beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> this Note. However, for more information on ITNA,<br />

see Austan Goolsbee & Jonathan Zittrain, Evaluating the Costs and Benefits <strong>of</strong> Taxing Internet<br />

Commerce, 52 NAT’L TAX J. 413 (1999); Burke T. Ward & Janice C. Sipior, To Tax or<br />

Not to Tax E-Commerce: A United Sates Perspective, 5 J. ELECTRONIC COMM. RES. 172<br />

(2004); K.C. Jones, President Bush Signs Internet Tax Freedom Act, INFORMATION WEEK,<br />

Nov. 7, 2007, http://www.informationweek.com/shared/printableArticle.jhtml?articleID=<br />

202801131; Xuan-Thao N. Nguyen, The Internet, E-Commerce and Tax Considerations, in<br />

ALI-ABA COURSE OF STUDY MATERIALS: INTERNET LAW FOR THE PRACTICAL LAWYER,<br />

SK102 (2005).<br />

23. See supra note 22, and accompanying text.<br />

24. In April 2000, the Advisory Commission on Electronic Commerce submitted its<br />

report to Congress on various ways to tax the Internet. While sales and use taxes were<br />

mentioned in this report, an energy tax was not. See ADVISORY COMMISSION OF<br />

ELECTRONIC COMMERCE, REPORT TO CONGRESS (2000), available at<br />

http://govinfo.library.unt.edu/ecommerce/report.htm. Energy taxes, however, do exist in


2010] AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET 985<br />

taxes in existence, this lack <strong>of</strong> diversity among the pro-Internet tax literature<br />

is surprising, especially when one <strong>of</strong> the primary arguments<br />

for an Internet sales tax is to recoup lost revenue. 25 The sales tax is not<br />

the only tax through which state and local governments raise revenue.<br />

Governments levy taxes on property and income. Governments also<br />

levy various excise taxes—taxes paid for the purchase <strong>of</strong> a specific<br />

good—such as those imposed on gas and tobacco sales. 26<br />

Of all these other taxes, an energy tax is one form <strong>of</strong> taxation that<br />

can definitively be imposed on the Internet. Studies examining Internet<br />

energy consumption illustrate that the Internet requires a sustained<br />

and reliable source <strong>of</strong> energy to operate. 27 Thus, while the Internet<br />

is “inherently non-geographic” in nature, its need for an energy<br />

source is the one grounding point through which it is vulnerable to national<br />

tax schemes. 28 Internet companies would have to submit to the<br />

tax in each country in which they wish to operate. In the case <strong>of</strong> the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s, which has an estimated 72.5% <strong>of</strong> its 300 million population<br />

connected to the Internet, an Internet company would sacrifice<br />

approximately 14.6% <strong>of</strong> the global Internet market if it avoided this<br />

tax; the rest <strong>of</strong> the world, with the exception <strong>of</strong> China, is still catching<br />

up to the United <strong>State</strong>s in terms <strong>of</strong> Internet usage. 29 It seems unlikely<br />

that a business would sacrifice the opportunity to operate in the large,<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>itable U.S. market; therefore, these companies would have to accept<br />

this tax as part <strong>of</strong> the cost <strong>of</strong> doing business.<br />

Internet tax opponents will nonetheless argue that this proposal<br />

will curtail Internet development when the Internet is still in the early<br />

stages <strong>of</strong> development. This argument, however, has been significantly<br />

undermined by the passage <strong>of</strong> time; consequently, it is difficult to say<br />

that the Internet is in the same early stage <strong>of</strong> development as it was in<br />

the 1990s, nearly twenty years ago. The fact that many technology<br />

companies survived the “dot-com” crash demonstrates that the Inter-<br />

other forums. See, e.g., FLA. STAT. § 203.01 (2006) (addressing taxes on gross receipts for<br />

utility and communications services).<br />

25. See Isidro, supra note 9.<br />

26. IRS.gov, Excise Tax, http://www.irs.gov/businesses/small/article/0,,id=99517,00.html<br />

(last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

27. See KOOMEY, supra note 7, at 1.<br />

28. Isidro, supra note 9.<br />

29. InternetWorldStats.com, United <strong>State</strong>s <strong>of</strong> America: Internet Usage and Broadband<br />

Usage Report, http://www.internetworldstats.com/am/us.htm (last visited Aug. 27,<br />

2010); INTERNATIONAL TELECOMMUNICATION UNION, WORLD TELECOMMUNICATION<br />

DEVELOPMENT REPORT: ACCESS INDICATORS FOR THE INFORMATION SOCIETY 22 Table 5.2<br />

(2003) (comparing the degrees <strong>of</strong> Internet access in different countries); Internet-<br />

WorldStats.com, Internet Usage and Population in North America,<br />

http://www.internetworldstats.com/stats14.htm#north (last visited Aug. 27, 2010); Yuli<br />

Yang, China Tops World in Internet Users, CNN, Jan. 14, 2009, http://www.cnn.com/<br />

2009/TECH/01/14/china.internet/index.html.


986 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981<br />

net is firmly established in the very threadwork <strong>of</strong> society. 30 Moreover,<br />

studies <strong>of</strong> the dot-com era, 1995-2001, found that Internet company attrition<br />

rates were roughly 20% a year, which is no different from other<br />

industries in their formative years. 31 Thus, the histories <strong>of</strong> how other<br />

industries grappled with the imposition <strong>of</strong> tax burdens should have<br />

substantive value to those designing an Internet energy tax by illuminating<br />

how best to integrate the tax burden into the new industry.<br />

Moreover, the fact that other industries, such as pharmaceuticals,<br />

have been able to pr<strong>of</strong>itably grow despite being taxed at reasonable levels<br />

strongly suggests that the Internet will not crumble once it assumes<br />

its share <strong>of</strong> societal tax burdens. 32<br />

Further weakening the argument that Internet growth would suffer<br />

if taxed is the fact that the Internet not only survived the dot-com<br />

crash, but it emerged stronger than before. As mentioned above, the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> global Internet users skyrocketed from 360 million people<br />

in 2000 to nearly 1.5 billion in 2008, and e-commerce also became a<br />

multi-billion dollar industry in the same time span. 33 This rapid increase<br />

and the fact that all indicators point to more growth make it<br />

highly doubtful that Internet usage will decrease. Spikes in gas prices<br />

also make the likelihood <strong>of</strong> decreased Internet usage more remote<br />

because businesses and consumers will likely turn to e-commerce<br />

shopping and delivery services in order to save money by reducing<br />

their gas costs. 34 In fact, the Internet is now so strong that it is an<br />

emerging threat to the livelihood <strong>of</strong> well-established business like<br />

newspapers, which are struggling to cope with massive losses in ad<br />

revenues as advertisers invest more heavily in online ads. 35 Online<br />

viewership has also aggravated the financial strain <strong>of</strong> newspapers by<br />

depressing sales <strong>of</strong> printed papers. 36<br />

Perhaps most emblematic <strong>of</strong> the Internet’s strong footing in society<br />

is its newfound centrality in American political campaigns. 37 For<br />

example, in 2004, the Internet helped propel Howard Dean from a<br />

30. See Lee Gomes, The Dot-Com Bubble Is Reconsidered–And Maybe Relived, WALL<br />

ST. J., Nov. 8, 2006, at B1.<br />

31. Id; Brent Goldfarb et al., Was There Too Little Entry During the Dot Com Era?, 86<br />

J. FIN.ECON. 100, 124 (2007).<br />

32. See, e.g., GARY GUENTHER, FEDERAL TAXATION OF THE DRUG INDUSTRY AND ITS<br />

EFFECTS ON NEW DRUG DEVELOPMENT 23-25 (2009), available at http://<br />

www.policyarchive.org/handle/10207/bitstreams/18823.pdf.<br />

33. InternetWorldStats.com, supra note 13.<br />

34. See generally Cool-Companies.org, Energy & the Internet: Internet, New Economy<br />

Technology Yield Dramatic Energy and Environmental Savings, http://www.coolcompanies.org/energy/debunk.cfm<br />

(last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

35. Richard Perez-Pena, Papers Facing Worst Year for Ad Revenue, N.Y. TIMES, June<br />

23, 2008, at C3; see also Kathy Shwiff, McClatchy to Cut Additional Jobs and Dividend,<br />

WALL ST. J., Sept. 17, 2008, at B7.<br />

36. Penez-Pena, supra note 35.<br />

37. See Aaron Smith, The Internet’s Role in Campaign 2008, PEW INTERNET, Apr. 15 2009,<br />

http://www.pewinternet.org/Reports/2009/6--The-Internets-Role-in-Campaign-2008.aspx.


2010] AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET 987<br />

dark horse candidate in the Democratic presidential primaries to<br />

front-runner status. 38 In 2006, the Internet helped give the Democrats<br />

control <strong>of</strong> the U.S. Senate by capturing and broadcasting the infamous<br />

“macaca moment” <strong>of</strong> former Senator George Allen <strong>of</strong> Virginia,<br />

a Republican who was previously considered “a sure bet for reelection”<br />

and a possible 2008 presidential contender. 39 That broadcast<br />

contributed to his defeat. 40 These events, though, were mere harbingers<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Internet’s political relevance in Barack Obama’s presidential<br />

campaign. One only needs to look at the 2008 U.S. presidential<br />

election cycle to see how central the Internet is in political campaigns.<br />

41 The Internet enabled Mr. Obama to amass a political organization<br />

so strong that he was able to defeat Hillary Clinton and consistently<br />

raise record-setting amounts <strong>of</strong> campaign cash—upwards <strong>of</strong><br />

$150 million in a month and about $600 million total. 42 It also allowed<br />

Mr. Obama to appeal to and engage younger voters at unprecedented<br />

levels, as they tend to be more Internet-savvy. 43 Mr. Obama,<br />

as a result, became the 44 th President <strong>of</strong> the United <strong>State</strong>s. 44<br />

Considering all <strong>of</strong> the above, it is clear that the Internet has a firm<br />

place in society. Thus, one can argue that it is time the Internet start<br />

shouldering its fair share <strong>of</strong> the societal tax burden. 45 It is highly unlikely<br />

that subjecting the Internet to some form <strong>of</strong> taxation would<br />

cripple it because it is so well accepted by younger generations. 46<br />

Thus, Internet companies have a guaranteed client-base that will naturally<br />

expand through the on-going process <strong>of</strong> generational change<br />

in society. The Internet taxation argument, therefore, boils down to<br />

one question: if the Internet is not taxed now, then when? In answering<br />

this question, one must remember that as time passes, the<br />

strength <strong>of</strong> the interest groups vested in the status quo <strong>of</strong> a tax-free<br />

Internet only increases, which makes implementing any new policy<br />

more difficult.<br />

38. Jodi Wilgoren & Jim Rutenberg, The 2004 Campaign: The Former Governor; Missteps<br />

Pulled A Surging Dean Back to Earth, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 1, 2004, at 11.<br />

39. Kate Zernike, Macaca, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 24, 2006, at 44.<br />

40. Id.<br />

41. Brian Stelter, The Facebooker Who Friended Obama, N.Y. TIMES, July 7, 2008, at C1.<br />

42. Id.; Jeff Zeleny et al., Donation Record as Colin Powell Endorses Obama, N.Y.<br />

TIMES, Oct. 20, 2008, at A1.<br />

43. See Stelter, supra note 41, at C1; Leslie Sanchez, Commentary: GOP Needs to<br />

Catch up to Obama’s Web Savvy, CNN, Nov. 9, 2008, http://www.cnn.com/2008/<br />

POLITICS/11/07/sanchez.technology/index.html.<br />

44. Sarah Lai Stirland, Propelled by Internet, Barack Obama Wins Presidency, WIRED,<br />

Nov. 4, 2008, http://www.wired.com/threatlevel/2008/11/propelled-by-in/.<br />

45. Ge<strong>of</strong>frey A. Fowler & Erica Alini, <strong>State</strong>s Plot New Path to Tax Online Retailers,<br />

WALL ST. J., July 3, 2009, at B1.<br />

46. See Sucharita Mulpuru et al., Why US B2C eCommerce Will Weather the Economic<br />

Downturn Well, FORRESTER, Apr. 30, 2008, http://www.forrester.com/rb/Research/<br />

why_us_b2c_ecommerce_will_weather_economic/q/id/45932/t/2.


988 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981<br />

Taxing the Internet in a way that encourages energy efficiency<br />

will not curtail its future growth. In fact, the exact opposite will occur.<br />

Studies have shown that the Internet’s power needs restrict the<br />

areas where it can be deployed. This in turn restricts its ability to expand<br />

because electricity is a scarce resource in many parts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world. 47 By reducing the Internet’s energy consumption, companies<br />

will be able to deploy more Internet devices and services, and the<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its from these new deployments will likely <strong>of</strong>fset the costs <strong>of</strong> an<br />

energy tax. 48<br />

VNL, a Swedish mobile phone company, used this approach to<br />

economically expand its business into the world’s poorest and most<br />

remote areas. 49 Companies generally cannot afford to reach these<br />

areas, which in India alone amounts to writing <strong>of</strong>f approximately 700<br />

million potential customers. 50 In VNL’s case, the company was confronted<br />

with the high costs <strong>of</strong> installing, running, and maintaining<br />

transmission towers and recovering these costs from people who<br />

could only afford to pay about $2 per month for phone service. 51 VNL,<br />

however, managed to pr<strong>of</strong>itably expand into these rural areas by remodeling<br />

their transmission towers and making them energy efficient.<br />

52 These new towers are “roughly the size <strong>of</strong> a laser printer . . .<br />

[and] are powered by solar energy and use only as much energy as a<br />

100-watt lightbulb.” 53 These towers only cost $3500 to install, which<br />

is significantly lower than the $10,000 to $100,000 installation price<br />

range for standard transmission towers. 54 Overall, these rural base<br />

stations generate $15 billion in annual pr<strong>of</strong>its, and this number is<br />

expected to grow at a rate <strong>of</strong> 15% to 20% a year. 55<br />

In addition to increasing business revenues, it is common knowledge<br />

that Internet access benefits society by allowing for greater<br />

communication and distribution <strong>of</strong> information. The development <strong>of</strong> an<br />

energy-efficient Internet will expand Internet access, providing these<br />

benefits to presently underserved regions. Similarly, society will receive<br />

the environmental and national security benefits that are commonly<br />

associated with energy efficiency. An energy-efficient Internet,<br />

however, will uniquely benefit society in that it may help save lives in<br />

47. MARUTI GUPTA & SURESH SINGH, GREENING OF THE INTERNET 20 (2003),<br />

http://delivery.acm.org/10.1145/870000/863959/p19-gupta.pdf?key1=863959&key2=<br />

3731670221&coll=GUIDE&dl=GUIDE&CFID=1877967&CFTOKEN=84349380.<br />

48. See id.<br />

49. Jennifer L. Schenker, Making Mobile Networks Cheap and Green, BUS.WEEK ONLINE,<br />

Aug. 4, 2008, http://www.businessweek.com/globalbiz/content/aug2008/gb2008081_590263.htm.<br />

50. Id.<br />

51. Id.<br />

52. Id.<br />

53. Id.<br />

54. Id.<br />

55. Id.


2010] AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET 989<br />

the event <strong>of</strong> a disaster. 56 In disaster-hit areas, network equipment<br />

must largely rely on batteries in order to operate; therefore, by having<br />

communication devices that require less energy, these batteries will<br />

last longer. 57 Longer battery life will enable hospitals, police, rescue<br />

workers, and other agencies to have access to critical communication<br />

networks and resources they need for longer lengths <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

The importance <strong>of</strong> having energy-efficient equipment in disaster<br />

areas was keenly illustrated during the aftermath <strong>of</strong> Hurricane Katrina.<br />

After Katrina, communication between different emergency response<br />

agencies was essentially non-existent because many cell towers,<br />

emergency communication equipment, and 911 centers were<br />

rendered inoperable. 58 Communication was sporadic, and as a result,<br />

Washington <strong>of</strong>ficials had trouble gathering information about the<br />

area, impairing their ability to assist local <strong>of</strong>ficials in the recovery effort.<br />

59 These communication difficulties were surprising because since<br />

September 11, 2001, the government has spent millions <strong>of</strong> dollars<br />

upgrading emergency phone and radio communication systems, with<br />

states receiving $830 million in the 2004 fiscal year alone. 60 Although<br />

some state and local communities were slow to upgrade their communication<br />

systems, rescue efforts were not hampered because they<br />

were lacking modern or advanced technology, but because they<br />

lacked something far more basic—adequate power. 61 As a result, this<br />

high-tech, expensive radio and phone equipment became useless.<br />

“Field personnel are beginning to lose power on the radios because<br />

they don’t have any way to recharge them.” . . . Emergency generators<br />

powering some cell towers and underground phone switches,<br />

which route traditional phone calls, may also soon begin to go<br />

dark. “The issue is a power issue at its core.” 62<br />

This lack <strong>of</strong> power not only hindered the government’s rescue efforts,<br />

it also delayed the restoration <strong>of</strong> normal social services because<br />

the limited energy available was needed to keep emergency services<br />

operational. 63 The fact that energy inefficiency contributed to these<br />

post-Katrina power problems is particularly disturbing because energy<br />

efficiency can begin to be achieved through simple efforts. An energyefficient<br />

communication system may have saved lives during Katrina<br />

56. GUPTA &SINGH, supra note 47, at 20.<br />

57. Id.<br />

58. Christopher Rhoads & Amy Schatz, In Katrina’s Wake: Power Outages Hamstring<br />

Most Emergency Communications, WALL ST. J., Sept. 1, 2005, at A7.<br />

59. Id.<br />

60. Id.<br />

61. Id.<br />

62. Id. (quoting Courtney McCarron, spokeswoman for the Assoc. <strong>of</strong> Public-Safety<br />

Commc’ns Officials, and an unnamed FCC <strong>of</strong>ficial).<br />

63. Id.


990 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981<br />

and during other emergencies as well. It is, therefore, imperative that<br />

energy efficiency measures be taken to save lives in the future.<br />

Moreover, energy efficiency is a very safe area for routine corporate<br />

investments because such investments have quick, guaranteed,<br />

and continuing returns in terms <strong>of</strong> corporate savings. 64 Companies do<br />

not need to do much more than take small actions to save energy.<br />

These actions include “changing the light bulbs . . . installing . . .<br />

double-pane windows, or simply buying a new lamp,” and eventually,<br />

these “many small actions can add up to big savings[.]” 65 This point is<br />

best illustrated through Dow Chemical’s Louisiana division, whose<br />

energy department in 1982 began a yearly contest to discovery energy-saving<br />

projects. 66 Many <strong>of</strong> the discovered projects were simple,<br />

such as more efficient compressors and better insulation, yet this<br />

contest also yielded surprising results. 67<br />

The first year <strong>of</strong> the contest had 27 winners requiring a total<br />

capital investment <strong>of</strong> $1.7 million with an average annual return<br />

on investment <strong>of</strong> 173 percent. Many at Dow felt that there couldn’t<br />

be others with such high returns. The skeptics were wrong. The<br />

1983 contest had 32 winners requiring a total capital investment<br />

<strong>of</strong> $2.2 million and a 340 percent return�a savings <strong>of</strong> $7.5 million<br />

in the first year and every year after that. Even as fuel prices declined<br />

in the mid-1980s, the savings kept growing. The average return<br />

to the 1989 contest was the highest ever, an astounding 470<br />

percent in 1989—a payback <strong>of</strong> 11 weeks that saved the company<br />

$37 million a year. 68<br />

Ten years and 700 projects later, “the 2,000 Dow employees” are not<br />

yet “tapped out <strong>of</strong> ideas.” 69 The 1991-93 contests “each had in excess<br />

<strong>of</strong> 120 winners with an average return on investment <strong>of</strong> 300 percent.<br />

Total savings to Dow from just those projects exceeded $75 million a<br />

year.” 70 An energy tax is therefore nothing more than a tool to insure<br />

that these small actions are taken. Thus, so long as it is reasonable,<br />

an energy tax should not hamper growth as the anti-Internet tax<br />

camp argued with respect to an Internet sales tax. An Internet energy<br />

tax should therefore be examined.<br />

64. Joseph Romm, Why We Never Need to Build Another Polluting Power Plant,<br />

SALON, July 28, 2008, http://www.salon.com/news/feature/2008/07/28/energy_efficiency/<br />

print.html; see generally BOOSTING RESTAURANT PROFITS WITH ENERGY EFFICIENCY: AGUIDE<br />

FOR RESTAURANT OWNERS AND MANAGERS (2006), available at http://www.fypower.org/<br />

pdf/BPG_RestaurantEnergyEfficiency.pdf.<br />

65. Sarah Jane Tribble, Small Changes Can Yield Energy Savings in California,<br />

MERCURY NEWS, June 8, 2007, http://www.mercurynews.com/greenenergy/ ci_6086258.<br />

66. Romm, supra note 64.<br />

67. Id.<br />

68. Id.<br />

69. Id.<br />

70. Id.


2010] AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET 991<br />

IV. WHY ACHIEVING ENERGY EFFICIENCY REQUIRES GOVERNMENT<br />

INTERVENTION<br />

Given that energy efficiency is beneficial to corporate interests,<br />

opponents <strong>of</strong> government regulation will nevertheless claim that improvements<br />

in energy efficiency will occur without government involvement.<br />

71 Such opponents will also say that market forces have<br />

yet to address energy efficiency because the issue itself is relatively<br />

novel and only recently became an issue <strong>of</strong> serious consideration. The<br />

EPA’s voluntary “Energy Star” program, for example, has only existed<br />

since 1992. 72 Accordingly, these opponents will likely assert that<br />

the best role for the government is not to tax but to create educational<br />

programs on energy efficiency, which will then facilitate the development<br />

<strong>of</strong> market solutions. 73<br />

Educational programs would obviously be helpful, but they already<br />

exist. The United <strong>State</strong>s Department <strong>of</strong> Energy (DOE), for instance,<br />

has a separate <strong>of</strong>fice—the Office <strong>of</strong> Energy Efficiency and Renewable<br />

Energy—that has many programs to assist in delivering<br />

energy savings. 74 Private organizations, such as environmental<br />

groups, also provide similar information. For example, Greenpeace<br />

releases a guide to greener electronic products every three months. 75<br />

Because the Internet makes all this information easily accessible,<br />

additional education programs are unnecessary.<br />

The failure <strong>of</strong> corporate executives to utilize these programs shows<br />

that educational programs can be ignored and demonstrates the need<br />

for government involvement beyond the educational level. Education<br />

alone does nothing to insure that companies will seriously invest in<br />

energy efficiency on the consistent basis that meaningful energy efficiency<br />

requires, especially because new technologies continuously en-<br />

71. See Romm, supra note 64; see generally WILLIAM J. BAUMOL, THE FREE-MARKET<br />

INNOVATION MACHINE: ANALYZING THE GROWTH MIRACLE OF CAPITALISM (2002) (arguing<br />

that free-market pressures inherent in capitalism are constantly forcing firms to innovate,<br />

without need <strong>of</strong> government intervention).<br />

72. Marla C. Sanchez et al., Savings Estimates for the United <strong>State</strong>s Environmental<br />

Protection Agency’s ENERGY STAR Voluntary Product Labeling Program, 36 ENERGY<br />

POL’Y 2098, 2098 (2008).<br />

73. See generally Julie A. Caswell & Eliza M. Mojduszka, Using <strong>Information</strong>al Labeling<br />

to Influence the Market for Quality in Food Products 78 AM. J. OF AGRIC. ECON. 1248,<br />

1248 (1996) (arguing that “government policies and regulations” on labeling—i.e., facilitating<br />

the communication <strong>of</strong> information to consumers—greatly affects the development <strong>of</strong><br />

markets for food quality).<br />

74. United <strong>State</strong>s Department <strong>of</strong> Energy, Energy Efficiency and Renewable Energy,<br />

http://www.eere.energy.gov/ (last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

75. Simon Avery, New Tech Battleground: Who is the Greenest?, GLOBE & MAIL, Sept. 9,<br />

2008, at B6, available at http://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/technology/article708478.ece;<br />

Greenpeace, Guide to Greener Electronics, http://www.greenpeace.org/electronics (last visited<br />

Aug. 27, 2010).


992 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981<br />

able greater efficiency. 76 Further, as developments in the American<br />

and Japanese auto industries illustrates, leaving energy efficiency to<br />

market forces alone makes it difficult to determine which companies<br />

will pursue the matter. Thus, without government involvement,<br />

progress towards energy efficiency will likely occur in a piecemeal fashion<br />

with progress only occurring when the issue has the public’s interest.<br />

77 Piecemeal progress towards energy efficiency, however, is<br />

unacceptable given this issue’s national security implications. 78<br />

The current state <strong>of</strong> the American auto industry exemplifies how<br />

market forces alone do not induce companies to save energy. As seen<br />

by its need for congressional bailouts and GM’s and Chrysler’s subsequent<br />

bankruptcy filings, the U.S. auto industry is in dire straits. 79<br />

The industry, however, had been on the road to its current situation<br />

for many years as sales <strong>of</strong> SUVs and pick-up trucks declined because<br />

customers, due to rising oil prices, shifted to smaller, more fuelefficient<br />

passenger cars. 80 Such cars were not staples <strong>of</strong> the Big<br />

Three—Ford, GM, and Chrysler. The 2008 credit crisis merely magnified<br />

the financial strain that the Big Three faced.<br />

To be fair to the Big Three, SUV and pick-up truck sales were, until<br />

recently, a very pr<strong>of</strong>itable market. 81 Given that America’s loveaffair<br />

with such vehicles, which only began to wane in the past few<br />

years, it makes sense that these companies invested resources into<br />

these cars. 82 These cars accordingly became bigger and faster but not<br />

more fuel-efficient. 83 The Big Three’s failure to improve every aspect<br />

<strong>of</strong> these vehicles is odd because increasing fuel efficiency was clearly<br />

possible. Honda’s 2000 model vehicles, for example, had an average<br />

fuel efficiency that was six miles to the gallon higher than the aver-<br />

76. See Romm, supra note 64; see also Pam Frost Gorder, Materials May Help Autos<br />

Turn Heat into Electricity (July 25, 2008), http://www.renewableenergyworld.com/<br />

rea//news/article/ 2008/07/material-may-help-autos-turn-heat-into-electricity-53145.<br />

77. See generally Baumol, supra note 71.<br />

78. Daniel Yergin, Ensuring Energy Security, 85 FOREIGN AFF. 69, 69 (2006), available<br />

at http://www.un.org/ga/61/second/daniel_yergin_energysecurity.pdf.<br />

79. Aparajita Saha-Bubna, Corporate News: U.S. Auto Makers Seek Bailout for Bad<br />

Car Loans–Relief Plan, Part <strong>of</strong> Original Wall Street Rescue Package, Could Free Up Loans<br />

for Car Dealers as Well as Their Customers, WALL ST. J., Oct. 1, 2008, at B3; Jim Rutenberg<br />

& Bill Vlasic, Chrysler Files for Bankruptcy; U.A.W. and Fiat to Take Control, N.Y.<br />

TIMES, May 1, 2009, at A1; Neil King Jr. & Sharon Terlep, GM Collapses into Government’s<br />

Arms: Second-Largest Industrial Bankruptcy in History, WALL ST. J., June 2, 2009, at A1.<br />

80. Bill Vlasic & Nick Bunkley, The Struggles <strong>of</strong> Detroit Ensnare Its Workers, N.Y.<br />

TIMES, July 3, 2008, at C1; Bill Vlasic, As Gas Costs Soar, Buyers Are Flocking to Small<br />

Cars,N.Y.TIMES, May 2, 2008, at A1.<br />

81. Micheline Maynard, With $3 Gas, Detroit Pays for its Past, N.Y. TIMES, July 28,<br />

2006, at C1, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2006/07/28/business/worldbusiness/<br />

28auto.html.<br />

82. See id.; see also Bill Vlasic, Interest Fades in the Once-Mighty V-8, N.Y. TIMES,<br />

Jan. 16, 2008, at C1.<br />

83. Micheline Maynard, Downturn Will Test Obama’s Vision for an Energy-Efficient<br />

Auto Industry, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 21, 2008, at A38.


2010] AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET 993<br />

age American automobile. 84 Moreover, there were signs that consumers<br />

wanted greater fuel-efficient vehicles by the increased demand for<br />

hybrid vehicles. In 2004 for example, the demand for hybrids was so<br />

strong that there was a two year waiting list for the new Toyota<br />

Prius; meanwhile, Ford and GM needed to prop up their SUV and<br />

pick-up truck sales through discount <strong>of</strong>fers. 85 The Big Three were<br />

basically absent from the hybrid market until 2005 when Ford introduced<br />

the Escape Hybrid. 86 In contrast, the Toyota Prius debuted in<br />

Japan in 1997 and over 1 million vehicles had been sold in the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s by 2008, allowing Toyota to capitalize on this shift in consumer<br />

demand. 87 The Big Three’s past decisions complicated their recent<br />

efforts to be more fuel-efficient because these companies have the<br />

reputation <strong>of</strong> producing “gas-guzzlers.” 88 Consequently, they must<br />

overcome this reputation while playing “catch-up” with their competitors<br />

on the issue <strong>of</strong> fuel efficiency. 89<br />

While one can argue that the Big Three’s management decisions<br />

were rational at the time they were made, these automakers not only<br />

ignored fuel efficiency but actively campaigned against congressional<br />

efforts to raise federal fuel efficiency standards. 90 Their opposition to<br />

such efforts stemmed from the fact that it is costly to implement<br />

changes in fuel efficiency. 91 Congress’ 2007 increase in U.S. fuel standards<br />

was the first increase in these standards since 1984. 92 It, therefore,<br />

becomes easy to understand why the Big Three invested in other<br />

84. Danny Hakim, Honda Takes up Case in U.S. for Green Energy, N.Y. TIMES, June<br />

12, 2002, at C1.<br />

85. Jane Gross, From Guilt Trip to Hot Wheels, N.Y. TIMES, June 13, 2004, at 9; John D.<br />

Stoll & Joseph B. White, Moody’s Cuts GM, Ford Debt to Junk; Cost Concerns Gain Focus<br />

Ahead <strong>of</strong> UAW Negotiations; Downgrade Follows S&P’s, WALL ST. J., Aug. 25, 2005, at A3.<br />

86. Jerry Garrett, Around the Block: A Look at an Overlooked Hybrid, N.Y. TIMES, July<br />

30, 2006, at 12; Richard Truett, Big 3 Play Catch-up in the Hybrid Game, but Automakers<br />

Have Different Approaches (Apr. 11, 2005), http://www.autosafety.org/big-3-play-catchhybrid-game.<br />

87. Todd Kaho, Decade <strong>of</strong> the Toyota Prius Hybrid (Nov. 5, 2007),<br />

http://www.greencar.com/features/decade-<strong>of</strong>-the-toyota-prius; Chuck Squatriglia, Prius Sales<br />

Top 1 Million. Want One? Better Move Fast, WIRED, May 15, 2008, http://www.wired.com/<br />

autopia/2008/05/prius-sales-top.<br />

88. Mike Spector & Maya Jackson-Randall, Big Three Try to Rev Up Weakened Political<br />

Clout—Congress Is Asked to Ease its Plans on Fuel Standards, WALL ST. J., June 7,<br />

2007, at A4.<br />

89. Id.; Bill Vlasic, As Gas Costs Soar, Buyers Are Flocking to Small Cars, N.Y. TIMES,<br />

May 2, 2008, at A1.<br />

90. Maynard, supra note 81; Hakim, supra note 84 (2002 Senate proposal to raise fuel<br />

efficiency standards for the first time since the 1980s defeated). The documentary Who<br />

Killed the Electric Car even suggests that the Big Three conspired against more energyefficient<br />

vehicles. Who Killed the Electric Car? (June 9, 2006), http://www.pbs.org/now/<br />

shows/223/.<br />

91. Stephen Power & Christopher Conkey, U.S. Orders Stricter Fuel Goals for Autos,<br />

WALL ST. J., May 19, 2009, available at http://online.wsj.com/article/<br />

SB124266939482331283.html.<br />

92. Id.; see also John M. Broder & Micheline Maynard, Deal in Congress on Plan to<br />

Raise Fuel Efficiency, N. Y. TIMES, Dec. 1, 2007, at A1.


994 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> their cars but ignored fuel efficiency over this twenty-three<br />

year stretch <strong>of</strong> time. Small but continual investment over these twenty-three<br />

years would have lessened the financial burden now associated<br />

with improving fuel efficiency. Such systematic investment<br />

would also have been financially manageable and have enabled the<br />

Big Three to better compete in today’s market. For instance, the<br />

companies may have advanced the use <strong>of</strong> potential energy saving devices<br />

like thermoelectrics—materials that can possibly make cars<br />

more efficient by converting heat wasted through engine exhaust into<br />

electricity. 93 Instead, <strong>General</strong> Motors and Chrysler went bankrupt 94<br />

and must comply with the new federal fuel standards. These new<br />

cars, however, will not be ready until some future date when it is<br />

possible that technological advancements will already have outdated<br />

the 2007 standards.<br />

While the current state <strong>of</strong> the U.S. auto industry may be the result<br />

<strong>of</strong> market forces playing themselves out, it shows that market forces<br />

alone do not produce comprehensive progress in energy efficiency; they<br />

just award innovation. Additionally, the Big Three’s former pr<strong>of</strong>itability<br />

illustrates that energy inefficiency can at times be financially rewarding.<br />

However, wasting energy is socially undesirable given the<br />

aforementioned environmental and national security implications. The<br />

attacks <strong>of</strong> September 11, 2001, and oil’s rise to $147 a barrel in 2008<br />

have only served to reiterate this correlation. 95 Energy efficiency is too<br />

important an issue to be left to market forces. Government must be involved<br />

in some form. Regulations like fuel standards are helpful because<br />

they provide a comprehensive minimum that must be met. However,<br />

given technology’s ability to constantly open up new avenues for<br />

greater energy savings, government energy efficiency regulations<br />

would have to constantly be revised and updated. 96 The aforementioned<br />

lobbying efforts <strong>of</strong> the Big Three show how difficult it can be to<br />

update regulations. In contrast, a tax-based approach to energy efficiency<br />

would be able to inherently update itself because taxes can be<br />

established so that they are paid and reassessed annually.<br />

In addition to insuring that there would be continuous investments<br />

in energy efficiency, a tax-based approach has a proven record<br />

93. Gorder, supra note 76.<br />

94. Chris Woodyard, Ford Faces Competition; Bankruptcy Gives Rivals Benefits, USA<br />

TODAY, June 2, 2009, http://www.usatoday.com/money/autos/2009-06-01-bankruptcy-competitionford_N.htm.<br />

95. UNITED STATES ENERGY ASSOCIATION, NATIONAL ENERGY SECURITY POST 9/11 4-6<br />

(2002), http://www.usea.org/publications/documents/useareport.pdf; see also Kathryn<br />

Hopkins, Fuel Prices: Iran Missile Launches Send Oil to $147 a Barrel Record, THE<br />

GUARDIAN, July 12, 2008, http://www.guardian.co.uk/business/2008/jul/12/oil.commodities.<br />

96. See Romm, supra note 64; see also Broder & Maynard, supra note 92.


2010] AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET 995<br />

<strong>of</strong> effectively achieving energy efficiency. 97 For example, in 1973,<br />

Denmark imported 99% <strong>of</strong> its energy needs from the Middle East,<br />

and consequently, it was gravely affected by the 1973 oil embargo. 98<br />

To cope with the ensuring energy crisis, the Danish government had<br />

to take stringent measures, such as “bann[ing] all Sunday driving for<br />

a while” to curb energy demand. 99 Denmark also seriously engaged<br />

the issue <strong>of</strong> energy independence in a “focused and systematic<br />

way.” 100 As a result, Denmark now imports no oil from the Middle<br />

East and gets nearly 20% <strong>of</strong> its energy from wind. 101 Denmark<br />

achieved these results through a series <strong>of</strong> taxes, such as $10 gas taxes,<br />

and “green” building and appliance standards. 102 Contrary to popular<br />

belief, these taxes did not cripple the Danish economy. Instead,<br />

the economy grew while national energy consumption barely increased.<br />

103 Denmark has also developed one <strong>of</strong> the world’s most competitive<br />

clean-power industries, and energy-efficient technology has<br />

emerged as one <strong>of</strong> Denmark’s fastest-growing export areas. 104 The resulting<br />

energy revenues have prompted Denmark to look into reforming<br />

its tax code to include more emphasis on energy taxes and less on<br />

personal income taxes. 105<br />

Market forces alone, by comparison, do not produce similar results.<br />

For instance, the United <strong>State</strong>s has gone from importing 24%<br />

<strong>of</strong> its oil to 70%–roughly 12 million barrels a day–during the same<br />

thirty-five year time span and only gets about 1% <strong>of</strong> its energy from<br />

wind. 106 It is also absent from the clean-energy market. 107 Some companies,<br />

though, have begun making investments in this area. Google,<br />

for instance, recently patented a way to power its Internet data servers<br />

using tidal power. 108 Personal computer manufacturers have also<br />

begun “tackling the problem” <strong>of</strong> their products’ enormous energy<br />

use. 109 However, as seen in Denmark, meaningful progress in energy<br />

97. Thomas L. Friedman, Flush with Energy, N.Y. TIMES, Aug. 10, 2008, at WK,<br />

available at http://www.nytimes.com/2008/08/10/opinion/10friedman1.html?_r=1.<br />

98. Id.<br />

99. Id.<br />

100. Id.<br />

101. Id.<br />

102. Id.<br />

103. Id.<br />

104. Id.<br />

105. Id.<br />

106. Id.; Pickens Plan, Did You Know?, http://www.pickensplan.com/didyouknow (last<br />

visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

107. Friedman, supra note 97 (“We’ve had 35 new competitors coming out <strong>of</strong> China in<br />

the last 18 months . . . and not one out <strong>of</strong> the U.S.”).<br />

108. Thomas Claburn, Google Granted Floating Data Center Patent, INFORMATION WEEK,<br />

Apr. 30, 2009, http://www.informationweek.com/news/internet/google/showArticle.jhtml?<br />

articleID=217201005.<br />

109. Jim Carlton, The PC Goes on an Energy Diet, WALL ST. J., Sept. 8, 2009, at R8.


996 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981<br />

efficiency requires government involvement. 110 If left to market forces<br />

alone, Google may be the next Honda among a sea <strong>of</strong> Big Three-like<br />

companies that waste energy. 111 Although energy crises periodically<br />

occur, commentators have debated that the energy efficiency fervor<br />

may again subside with the passing <strong>of</strong> the 2008 energy crisis. 112 Given<br />

the centrality <strong>of</strong> energy resources to all parts <strong>of</strong> American society,<br />

there must be strong government measures to more comprehensively<br />

insure that energy resources are utilized efficiently.<br />

Some may argue that Denmark’s success with energy taxes cannot<br />

be equated to the United <strong>State</strong>s because <strong>of</strong> the many differences between<br />

the two countries, most notably geographical size. California,<br />

though, has successfully implemented measures similar to those <strong>of</strong><br />

Denmark, and the energy consumption differences between California<br />

and the rest <strong>of</strong> the United <strong>State</strong>s further illustrate how energy efficiency<br />

is best achieved through government involvement. 113 California<br />

began legislating energy efficiency in the 1970s, and its energy<br />

consumption has subsequently remained constant, in spite <strong>of</strong> the<br />

tech-boom and its growing population; meanwhile, over those same<br />

forty years, the rest <strong>of</strong> the nation’s per capita electricity consumption<br />

increased 60%. 114 If all Americans adopted California’s energy standards,<br />

U.S. electrical consumption would decrease by 40%. 115 According<br />

to a 2007 report from the international consulting firm McKinsey<br />

and Co., such energy savings could “<strong>of</strong>fset almost all <strong>of</strong> the projected<br />

demand for electricity in 2030 and largely negate the need for new . .<br />

. power plants.” 116 The magnitude <strong>of</strong> these savings should also allow<br />

for the quick recovery <strong>of</strong> any implementation costs. 117 The fact that<br />

companies can quickly recover their energy investments through savings<br />

consequently undermines the argument that a tax-based approach<br />

to energy efficiency would unduly burden business.<br />

Nevertheless, a tax proposal will likely be criticized as unnecessary<br />

government involvement in corporate affairs. Such criticisms, however,<br />

overlook the fact that while there may be some overlap, corporations<br />

exist to make money, not to further important social objectives.<br />

110. See generally Levine, supra note 77.<br />

111. See Hakim, supra note 84.<br />

112. See Vivienne Walt, Is Cheaper Oil a Good Thing?, TIME, Oct. 10, 2008,<br />

http://www.time.com/time/business/article/0,8599,1849215,00.html; Vivienne Walt, What’s<br />

Behind (and Ahead for) the Plunging Price <strong>of</strong> Oil, TIME, Oct. 24, 2008,<br />

http://www.time.com/time/printout/0,8816,1853775,00.html.<br />

113. Romm, supra note 64.<br />

114. Id. (providing an overview on California’s energy efficiency efforts); see also The<br />

California Energy Commission, http://www.energy.ca.gov/ (last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

115. Romm, supra note 64.<br />

116. Id. (citing McKinsey and Co., Reducing U.S. Greenhouse Gas Emissions: How<br />

Much at What Cost?, http://www.mckinsey.com/clientservice/ccsi/greenhousegas.asp (last<br />

visited Aug. 27, 2010)).<br />

117. Id.


2010] AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET 997<br />

This scenario was seen in 2006-2007 when U.S. beverage companies,<br />

in order to fend <strong>of</strong>f mounting public pressure and potential lawsuits or<br />

government regulations, voluntarily agreed to stop selling sugared sodas<br />

and limit the size and caloric content <strong>of</strong> their other drinks in<br />

schools. 118 Under this agreement, only “bottled water, unsweetened<br />

juices and lowfat or nonfat milk products” would be sold in elementary<br />

and middle schools, and only “diet s<strong>of</strong>t drinks . . . sports drinks, juices,<br />

milk and water” would be sold in high schools. 119 One year later,<br />

though, beverage makers were able to quietly amend the agreement so<br />

that “water” for high school sales included fortified waters, drinks that<br />

can have up to 100 calories per 12 ounce serving. 120 The beverage industry<br />

pushed for this change because enhanced water sales had skyrocketed<br />

from $20 million in 2000 to $884.7 million in 2006. 121 The<br />

original agreement was suddenly denounced by the beverage industry<br />

as draconian because it served only to limit the industry’s growth potential<br />

and ignored student needs. 122 Although this amendment did not<br />

fundamentally destroy the agreement, it weakened its effectiveness in<br />

combating student obesity because it provided students with access to<br />

another caloric drink, which was exactly what the voluntary agreement<br />

sought to restrict.<br />

The fact that this amendment passed without much notice also illustrates<br />

the superior position business leaders have in pursuing<br />

their own financial agendas when there is no public pressure to act<br />

as a watchdog. The Internet companies that would be affected by an<br />

energy tax have an even greater likelihood to vigorously pursue their<br />

financial interests because, unlike beverage companies, Internet<br />

companies essentially have a captive market. S<strong>of</strong>t drinks are widely<br />

available such that students can obtain these drinks without using a<br />

school vending machine. In contrast, everyone must pay his or her<br />

Internet provider’s fee in order to have legal access to the Internet.<br />

Thus, once public interest in energy efficiency fades, these Internet<br />

companies have little incentive to improve their energy efficiency because<br />

they have a guaranteed income from their customer base.<br />

However, too much government regulation or taxation can have a<br />

negative effect on economic growth. Mandating that corporations invest<br />

in energy efficiency, however, will most likely have a positive rather<br />

than negative economic impact. A 1993 DOE report showed that if<br />

one were to make the requisite investments to reduce American indus-<br />

118. Betsy McKay, Beverage Firms Yield to Pressure on School Sales, WALL ST. J.,May<br />

4, 2006, at D6.<br />

119. Id.<br />

120. Jane Zhang, Drink Makers Expand Offerings in Schools, WALL ST. J., Aug. 20,<br />

2007, at B2.<br />

121. Id.<br />

122. Id.


998 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981<br />

try waste by just ten to twenty percent, such investments would “generate<br />

a cumulative increase <strong>of</strong> $2 trillion in the gross domestic product<br />

from 1996 to 2010. By 2010, the improvements would be generating 2<br />

million new jobs.” 123 The aforementioned examples <strong>of</strong> Denmark and<br />

California demonstrate the accuracy <strong>of</strong> this report’s findings. Reasonable<br />

energy taxes can thus be a pro-growth economic policy.<br />

Also, because energy efficiency can be achieved through simple<br />

measures and can yield large pr<strong>of</strong>its, there should not be a need for<br />

government subsidies. Corporations should be able to self-finance the<br />

installation <strong>of</strong> these smaller measures without undue hardship. The<br />

savings that materialize should then enable a corporation to selffinance<br />

larger-scale energy efficiency projects, whose return savings<br />

will more than likely cover their investment costs and finance other<br />

energy savings projects. 124 Furthermore, with new technologies constantly<br />

allowing for greater energy savings, determining what to subsidize<br />

could become complicated. Subsidies may also stifle corporate<br />

innovation with respect to finding new ways to save energy by drawing<br />

attention to the subsidized item and focusing on its implementation.<br />

125 Such narrow focus diminishes the subsidy’s effectiveness,<br />

which is inherently better achieved when the corporation is broadly<br />

looking for ways to reduce its energy bill. Thus, an energy tax is<br />

merely a way to force corporations to constantly address the issue <strong>of</strong><br />

energy efficiency by making inefficiency more costly.<br />

An Internet energy tax alone may be criticized because it addresses<br />

the issue <strong>of</strong> energy efficiency in just one segment <strong>of</strong> our economy,<br />

rather than comprehensively addressing all industries. The Supreme<br />

Court, though, has repeatedly recognized that Congress has<br />

the authority to legislate in the manner it so chooses, thus rendering<br />

this argument meritless. 126 Moreover, unlike market forces, this tax<br />

will at least insure that an entire industry is pursuing energy efficiency<br />

rather than just a handful <strong>of</strong> innovative companies. However,<br />

the Internet companies may object to this proposal on fairness<br />

grounds and argue that it arbitrarily and capriciously singles them<br />

out when all industries waste energy and the Internet is far from the<br />

most wasteful. While it is true that an energy tax can, and ideally<br />

should, be applied to all industries, an energy source is the Internet’s<br />

123. Romm, supra note 64.<br />

124. See id.<br />

125. Id.<br />

126. Massachusetts v. EPA, 549 U.S. 497, 499 (2007) (“Agencies, like legislatures, do<br />

not generally resolve massive problems in one fell swoop . . . but instead whittle away over<br />

time, refining their approach as circumstances change and they develop a more nuanced understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> how best to proceed . . . .” (internal citations omitted)); Williamson v. Lee Optical<br />

<strong>of</strong> Okla., Inc., 348 U.S. 483, 489 (1955) (“[A] reform may take one step at a time, addressing<br />

itself to the phase <strong>of</strong> the problem which seems most acute to the legislative mind.”).


2010] AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET 999<br />

primary requirement. 127 An energy-efficient Internet provides unique<br />

benefits. These benefits are then strong grounds to argue that steps<br />

must be taken to ensure that the Internet is at the forefront <strong>of</strong> this<br />

energy reform movement.<br />

The Internet is at least partially responsible for helping reduce<br />

U.S. energy needs in the 1990s during a booming economy, which is<br />

usually associated with greater energy consumption. 128 One way in<br />

which it helped reduce U.S. energy consumption was through ematerialization,<br />

the process by which things are handled online rather<br />

than in hardcopy. 129 This process thereby reduces paper manufacturing,<br />

one <strong>of</strong> the most energy and resource intensive processes in<br />

the economy. 130 While the Internet’s current contributions to greater<br />

energy-efficiency are commendable, there are always new ways to invest<br />

in greater energy efficiency. Energy resources, after all, are finite<br />

in supply and therefore must be conserved. Furthermore, the Internet,<br />

as the epitome <strong>of</strong> technological creations, should be the industry<br />

with the greatest capacity to adapt to energy-saving technological<br />

changes. Thus, Internet companies appear to be the perfect “guinea<br />

pig” to test this tax proposal before it is expanded to businesses in<br />

general, especially when this industry is currently protected from<br />

other tax burdens. 131<br />

V. AN INTERNET ENERGY TAX PROPOSAL<br />

In order to achieve Internet energy efficiency, this energy tax<br />

could be structured as follows. The federal government should impose<br />

a gasoline-like excise tax upon all Internet service providers and<br />

network companies such as AT&T, Comcast Cable, and others. This<br />

tax shall be an additional expense that these companies will pay on<br />

their overall energy bill. This charge will reflect the amount <strong>of</strong> energy<br />

the company uses to run the equipment that powers and maintains<br />

the Internet. This tax structure should ideally insure that the tax<br />

does not unduly burden small businesses because they use less energy<br />

and thus will pay less tax. Calculating how much this additional<br />

fee will be is difficult because, as mentioned above, there is uncer-<br />

127. See KOOMEY, supra note 7, at 6.<br />

128. Cool-Companies.org, Energy & the Internet: Internet, New Economy Technology<br />

Yield Dramatic Energy and Environmental Savings, http://www.cool-companies.org/energy/<br />

debunk.cfm (last visited Aug. 27, 2010).<br />

129. JOSEPH ROMM ET AL., THE INTERNET ECONOMY AND GLOBAL WARMING: A<br />

SCENARIO OF THE IMPACT OF E-COMMERCE ON ENERGY AND THE ENVIRONMENT 38 (1999),<br />

available at http://www.p2pays.org/ref%5C04%5C03784/0378401.pdf; but see Gerry Bayne,<br />

Cyberinfrastructure in a Carbon-Constrained World (Nov. 25 2009), http://<br />

www.educause.edu/blog/gbayne/SessionCyberinfrastructureinaC/191981.<br />

130. Id.<br />

131. See Jones, supra note 22.


1000 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981<br />

tainty as to how much energy the Internet consumes. 132 Thus, in order<br />

to better assess the tax, these companies would first have to install<br />

monitoring devices, like those recording how much electricity,<br />

water, and gas individual homes consume, that measure their Internet<br />

equipment’s energy consumption. 133<br />

While there may be some difficulty in determining an appropriate<br />

tax rate, this determination is not central to the tax because its intent<br />

is not to raise revenue, but to make the Internet energy efficient. The<br />

number just needs to be enough to make corporations seriously examine<br />

ways to improve energy efficiency. This objective could possibly<br />

be reached by establishing the tax so that it also self-credits, up to the<br />

entire amount <strong>of</strong> the tax, any investments a corporation makes towards<br />

energy efficiency. This self-credit will ideally foster corporate<br />

innovation and flexibility in meeting its annual energy efficiency<br />

mandate. 134 The company would accordingly have to provide the government<br />

with a long term plan, in which its Internet energy efficiency<br />

is ultimately improved, in order to qualify for this self-credit. The corporation<br />

should then be able to structure the investments so that they<br />

are not burdensome and provide the highest return to the company.<br />

Such flexibility is particularly important for Internet companies<br />

because improving the Internet’s energy efficiency involves much<br />

more than changing light bulbs. 135 For example, in their article<br />

Greening the Internet, Maruti Gupta and Suresh Singh argue that<br />

greater use <strong>of</strong> sleep modes for Internet components not in use can<br />

significantly improve the Internet’s energy efficiency. 136 While this<br />

approach seems promising, the authors do not mention how much its<br />

implementation costs would be in terms <strong>of</strong> both time and money, but<br />

these costs are likely high given the number <strong>of</strong> variables in this ap-<br />

132. See generally KOOMEY, supra note 7, at 1 (discussing the common speculation that<br />

occurs in discussions concerning how much energy the Internet uses). While an estimated<br />

energy consumption range does exist, the consensus among studies is towards the lower<br />

end <strong>of</strong> the spectrum. The study that reached the 13% figure is widely seen as an inflated<br />

value. However, this study—the Mills and Huber project—was heavily cited by the media,<br />

which then lent credibility, in the general public’s mind, to the idea that the Internet is a<br />

mammoth power consumer. Mitchell-Jackson, supra note 4, at 12-15.<br />

133. As mentioned above, the EPA’s forthcoming Energy Star ratings for data centers<br />

may make such assessments easier and possibly make the installation <strong>of</strong> such monitoring<br />

devices unnecessary. EPA to Begin Energy Star Ratings for Data Centers, supra note 7.<br />

134. Though beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> this paper, it must be mentioned here that the inclusion<br />

<strong>of</strong> this self-credit provision would also differentiate this energy tax from already existing<br />

energy taxes such as <strong>Florida</strong>’s sales tax on non-residential sales <strong>of</strong> electricity and its grossreceipt<br />

tax on all sales <strong>of</strong> electricity. See generally supra note 22 and accompanying text.<br />

135. See Gupta & Singh, supra note 47; USF Energy-efficient Internet Project,<br />

http://www.csee.usf.edu/~christen/energy/main.html (last visited Aug. 27, 2010); Enrico<br />

Rantala et al., Modeling Energy Efficiency in Wireless Internet Communication (Aug. 17,<br />

2009), http://conferences.sigcomm.org/sigcomm/2009/workshops/mobiheld/papers/p67.pdf.<br />

136. Gupta & Singh, supra note 47, at 20-25.


2010] AN ENERGY-EFFICIENT INTERNET 1001<br />

proach. 137 If an energy tax proposal were to force Internet companies<br />

to immediately begin implementing Gupta and Singh’s proposal, the<br />

companies would probably elect to pay the tax and pass its cost <strong>of</strong>f to<br />

consumers because paying the tax would likely be cheaper. However,<br />

under the aforementioned self-credit provision, the company could<br />

take various “small actions [that] can add up to big savings,” which<br />

could then fund the more costly energy saving projects.” 138<br />

Again, the goal <strong>of</strong> this tax is not to raise revenue for the government,<br />

but it is likely that some revenue will be collected should an Internet<br />

company decide to annually pay this tax rather than invest in energy efficiency.<br />

Any revenue that is raised could then be placed into an energy<br />

fund similar to the Universal Service Fund that was established by the<br />

US Telecommunications Act <strong>of</strong> 1996 to try to expand Internet access into<br />

rural and underserved areas by subsidizing access rates. 139 Another<br />

possible use <strong>of</strong> any generated revenue is to earmark it for financing improvements<br />

on the nation’s electrical grid making it similar to California’s<br />

because such changes are an expensive but integral part <strong>of</strong> making<br />

meaningful progress towards energy efficiency. 140<br />

VI. CONCLUSION<br />

The importance <strong>of</strong> energy efficiency is common knowledge, and thus<br />

any and all measures that can help lead to greater energy efficiency<br />

should be explored. As shown above, the tax code is one measure that<br />

can help the United <strong>State</strong>s make meaningful and consistent progress<br />

towards this objective, and it is perhaps the most effective. The tax<br />

code, however, is under-utilized with regard to penalizing inefficient<br />

energy usage. This under-utilization must change. Given the dangers<br />

posed by climate change, the potential for another energy crisis, and<br />

the current state <strong>of</strong> the U.S. economy, this under-utilization should<br />

change now. The results could rival the societal and economic revolutions<br />

that the Internet itself sparked in the 1990s.<br />

137. Id. at 22 (describing the difficulties involved in maximizing the energy savings <strong>of</strong><br />

this approach such as insuring that an Internet component can sleep long enough so the additional<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> energy it takes to reawaken the component is <strong>of</strong>fset by the amount saved).<br />

138. Tribble, supra note 65.<br />

139. Heather E. Hudson, Universal Access: What Have We Learned from the E-rate?,<br />

TELECOMM. POL’Y, Apr. 1, 2004, at 309, available at http://intel.si.umich.edu/tprc/papers/<br />

2002/119/tprc02eratehudson.htm.<br />

140. Though the process <strong>of</strong> nationalizing California’s energy standards is beyond the<br />

scope <strong>of</strong> this paper, the federal government would obviously be heavily involved in such a<br />

large-scale project. The legislative process, however, is notoriously cumbersome, and given<br />

the evident complexity that changing the nation’s energy grid entails, passing the necessary<br />

legislation for this project will be difficult. This difficulty is, in itself, another reason to<br />

pass an energy tax because it is a much simpler approach and thus potentially easier to<br />

enact. The process towards energy efficiency can then at least begin while the more complex<br />

issues are hammered out.


1002 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:981


BUSINESS INSURANCE: FIRST-PARTY<br />

COMMERCIAL PROPERTY INSURANCE AND THE<br />

PHYSICAL DAMAGE REQUIREMENT IN A<br />

COMPUTER-DOMINATED WORLD<br />

AMY R. WILLIS *<br />

I. INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................. 1003<br />

II. CYBERSPACE ..................................................................................................... 1006<br />

A. The New Form <strong>of</strong> Property ......................................................................... 1006<br />

B. E-Businesses ............................................................................................... 1007<br />

C. E-Commerce Insurance .............................................................................. 1008<br />

1. E-Commerce Insurance and Conflicts <strong>of</strong> Interest ................................ 1010<br />

III. THE PHYSICAL DAMAGE REQUIREMENT ............................................................ 1010<br />

A. The Physical Damage Requirement and Computers ................................. 1011<br />

B. The Physical Damage Requirement in Other Contexts .............................. 1014<br />

IV. BOILERPLATE LANGUAGE .................................................................................. 1015<br />

A. Insurance Services Office ........................................................................... 1016<br />

V. CONCLUSION ..................................................................................................... 1020<br />

I. INTRODUCTION<br />

We live in an intangible world—a world where computers dominate<br />

business operations at a level that would have been unheard <strong>of</strong><br />

twenty years ago. Vital ingredients <strong>of</strong> a business, such as customer<br />

and proprietary information, product design data, and accounting information,<br />

are now stored on computers. 1 This intangible information<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten constitutes a large portion <strong>of</strong> a company’s assets. 2 If this information<br />

is lost or computers malfunction during some fortuit-<br />

ous event, the affected businesses may suffer devastating losses, and<br />

operations may be interrupted for an extended period <strong>of</strong> time. 3 When<br />

this occurs, businesses will turn to their insurance companies<br />

for coverage.<br />

* J.D., <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>College</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Law</strong>, with honors. With special thanks to<br />

my family and friends for their love, support, and encouragement. I would also like to<br />

thank the <strong>Florida</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>Law</strong> Review’s editorial staff for all <strong>of</strong> their assistance<br />

with this Article.<br />

1. See Hazel Glenn Beh, Physical Losses in Cyberspace, 8 CONN.INS. L.J. 55, 55-56 (2001).<br />

2. Id. at 57.<br />

3. See, e.g., Robert L. Carter, Jr. & Donald O. Johnson, Power to Policyholders: Court<br />

Supports Insurance Recoveries for Loss <strong>of</strong> Electronic Data, 86 A.B.A.J. 66, 66 (2000); Paula<br />

M. Yost, Paul E.B. Glad & William T. Barker, In Search <strong>of</strong> Coverage in Cyberspace: Why<br />

the Commercial <strong>General</strong> Liability Policy Fails to Insure Lost or Corrupted Computer Data,<br />

54 SMU L. REV. 2055, 2061 (2001) (noting that large economic losses can result from “the<br />

deletion or corruption <strong>of</strong> valuable business data,” and “[i]n a digital economy in which information<br />

is the new currency, businesses are increasingly dependent upon their ability to<br />

access, store, and transmit computerized data . . . . Any interference with that ability can,<br />

and does, translate into titanic financial losses”).


1004 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:1003<br />

First-party commercial property policies provide insurance benefits<br />

directly to the affected business when there is a loss. 4 Business<br />

interruption insurance, also known as business income insurance, is<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten purchased as part <strong>of</strong> a first-party commercial property business<br />

insurance package to protect against lost earnings that a policyholder<br />

would have earned absent the interruption in business. 5 Virtually all<br />

first-party property coverage, including business interruption insurance,<br />

will not provide coverage unless a covered peril causes actual<br />

physical damage resulting in loss or interruption. 6 For decades this<br />

coverage was sufficient because businesses typically faced physical<br />

perils that caused tangible damage. 7 Today, this coverage is insufficient<br />

because it <strong>of</strong>ten fails to cover significant intangible assets, such<br />

as electronic data. 8<br />

To determine whether a policy covers losses that result from loss<br />

<strong>of</strong> electronic data, a court will first look at the language <strong>of</strong> the insurance<br />

policy. 9 Insurance companies <strong>of</strong>ten use boilerplate language<br />

from standard insurance forms created by the Insurance Services Office<br />

(ISO) to draft policies. 10 Thus, the policies and practices adopted<br />

by the ISO encourage insurance companies to follow suit. The current<br />

ISO language in first-party policies excludes or limits electronic data<br />

from coverage. 11 Despite the ISO’s position, the issue <strong>of</strong> coverage for<br />

electronic data and other intangibles remains widely discussed and<br />

litigated, and not all insurance companies strictly follow ISO forms.<br />

In today’s business world, coverage that excludes electronic data is<br />

unworkable because property forms have changed. 12 Many businesses<br />

4. Anna Lee, Note, Why Traditional Insurance Policies Are Not Enough: The Nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> Potential E-Commerce Losses & Liabilities, 3 VAND.J.ENT.L.&PRAC. 84, 85 (2001).<br />

5. See, e.g., Robert J. Brennan & Laura C. Conway, Business Income Insurance Coverage,<br />

32 THE BRIEF 65, 65 (2003). To recover under business interruption insurance, the<br />

business must actually show a loss <strong>of</strong> income. Id. at 69. Business interruption policies may<br />

also contain extra expense coverage, which covers extra costs incurred as a result <strong>of</strong> the<br />

event, such as rental or transportation expenses. Id. at 66.<br />

6. See, e.g., Beh, supra note 1, at 67. Individual policy language will determine what<br />

perils are covered; however, common losses covered in business interruption policies include<br />

“fire; explosions; power failures; earthquakes; closure by order <strong>of</strong> civil authority . . .<br />

hail; floods; riots and civil commotions.” Brennan & Conway, supra note 5, at 67.<br />

7. See Beh, supra note 1, at 64-68.<br />

8. See id. at 64.<br />

9. Under standard contract law, the plain and unambiguous meaning <strong>of</strong> policy provisions<br />

will be given effect. See, e.g., Ward Gen. Ins. Servs., Inc. v. Employers Fire Ins. Co., 7<br />

Cal. Rptr. 3d 844, 852 (Cal. Ct. App. 4th Dist. 2003).<br />

10. Michelle E. Boardman, Contra Pr<strong>of</strong>erentem: The Allure <strong>of</strong> Ambiguous Boilerplate,<br />

104 MICH.L.REV. 1105, 1113 (2006).<br />

11. See Insurance Services Office, Building and Personal Property Coverage Form,<br />

2007, at § (A)(2)(n), available at LEXIS ISO Policy Forms No. 00 10 06 07; Insurance Services<br />

Office, Business Income (and Extra Expense) Coverage Form, 2007, at § (A)(5)(d),<br />

available at LEXIS ISO Policy Forms No. 00 30 06 07; William K. Austin, Cyber Risk—<br />

Data Damage and Destruction Beyond the Naked Eye, IRMI ONLINE, July 2009,<br />

http://www.irmi.com/expert/articles/2009/austin07-commercial-property-insurance.aspx.<br />

12. See Beh, supra note 1, at 55.


2010] BUSINESS INSURANCE 1005<br />

have abandoned physical storefronts and the familiarity <strong>of</strong> face-t<strong>of</strong>ace<br />

transactions and operate exclusively on the Internet as electronic<br />

businesses (e-businesses). 13 Bricks and mortar businesses that once<br />

stored valuable data in <strong>of</strong>fice filing cabinets now store most data electronically.<br />

Businesses are evolving, but the insurance industry has<br />

intentionally lagged behind, ensuring businesses will have inadequate<br />

coverage for electronic assets.<br />

ISO standard forms, insurance policies, and case law contain inconsistencies<br />

that further confuse and leave policyholders uncertain<br />

as to property and business interruption coverage involving electronic<br />

data. Drafters <strong>of</strong> ISO policy language should take a step back and<br />

reconsider their positions on electronic data exclusions. Some insurance<br />

companies are providing endorsements to policies notwithstanding<br />

the language, 14 and courts have recognized the physicality <strong>of</strong> electronic<br />

data. 15 Additionally, courts and scholars failing to recognize<br />

electronic data loss as physical damage <strong>of</strong>ten cite third-party commercial<br />

general liability policies (CGL) as support, which is inappropriate<br />

due to first- and third-party coverage differences. 16<br />

As we move ahead in the twenty-first century and become increasingly<br />

more dependent on computer-run businesses, the number <strong>of</strong><br />

possible events that may not meet the physical damage requirement<br />

continues to grow. Why has the insurance industry failed to make<br />

changes to standard first-party commercial property policies that reflect<br />

the modern realities <strong>of</strong> our computer-dominated world?<br />

I will address this question and argue that the physical damage requirement<br />

in standard first-party policies is outdated or unsuitable for<br />

the evolving insurance needs <strong>of</strong> modern businesses because it excludes<br />

electronic data from coverage. First, I will discuss the impact cyberspace<br />

has had on property forms, business operations, and insurance<br />

needs, and I will explore current problems many businesses face when<br />

obtaining cyber-related coverage. Second, I will provide an analysis <strong>of</strong><br />

the issues and case law surrounding the physical damage requirement<br />

13. E-businesses transact business over the Internet instead <strong>of</strong> at a physical location.<br />

Id. at 56.<br />

14. See Lambrecht & Assocs., Inc. v. <strong>State</strong> Farm Lloyds, 119 S.W.3d 16, 22 (Tex. App.<br />

12th Dist. 2003).<br />

15. See Am. Guar. & Liab. Ins. Co. v. Ingram Micro, Inc., No. 99-185 TUC ACM, 2000<br />

U.S. Dist. LEXIS 7299, at *6 (D. Ariz. Apr. 18, 2000).<br />

16. Courts should not use third-party liability policies as a guide in interpreting firstparty<br />

property policies because, from an insurer’s perspective, coverage risks in each policy<br />

are very different. See Erik S. Knutsen, Confusion About Causation in Insurance: Solutions<br />

for Catastrophic Losses, 61 ALA. L.REV. (forthcoming 2009) (manuscript at 11, on file with<br />

author). In a liability policy, an insurer’s scope <strong>of</strong> coverage is as broad as tort law, and in a<br />

property case insurers have greater control over underwritten risks. Id. Although courts<br />

and scholars have argued for the different treatment <strong>of</strong> first and third-party policies, comparisons<br />

continue to be made. See id. at 70; see also Ward Gen. Ins. Servs., Inc. v. Employers<br />

Fire Ins. Co., 7 Cal. Rptr. 3d 844, 852 (Cal. Ct. App. 4th Dist. 2003).


1006 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:1003<br />

in a computer-related context, and I will briefly introduce problems the<br />

requirement creates in other insurance contexts. Lastly, I will discuss<br />

the implications <strong>of</strong> boilerplate language in insurance contracts, dissect<br />

current ISO forms, present theories on why the industry has not<br />

evolved, and make recommendations for the future.<br />

II. CYBERSPACE<br />

Computers have taken the world by storm. Many businesses’ most<br />

valuable assets now exist in cyberspace. 17 Businesses are changing,<br />

and traditional insurance products should be updated to reflect these<br />

changes. The rise in e-businesses and specialized cyber insurance<br />

products evidence the need for change. Businesses that once cautiously<br />

flirted with cyberspace now trust the cyberworld with some <strong>of</strong><br />

their most precious information.<br />

A. The New Form <strong>of</strong> Property<br />

Electronic data has become a significant form <strong>of</strong> commercial property.<br />

18 Many businesses have purged familiar steel filing cabinets, opting<br />

instead to transfer paper data into an electronic form. Other than the<br />

occasional post-it note, people today rarely use handwritten materials to<br />

communicate information, and typewriters are practically extinct. Businesses<br />

likely believe they are keeping up with technology by engaging in<br />

these practices and may not realize the insurance implications.<br />

Much <strong>of</strong> the electronic data stored by businesses is the same data<br />

previously stored in filing cabinets and, thus, has simply changed<br />

forms. The ability to store data in an electronic form has enabled<br />

companies to go “green” by reducing their environmental impact. 19<br />

Storing data electronically may also provide additional safeguards<br />

because paper can be more easily destroyed by fires, floods, and other<br />

natural disasters. While this kind <strong>of</strong> damage is easily seen with the<br />

naked eye, damage to data stored on computer systems is intangible<br />

and cannot be seen. 20 Property forms have changed so drastically that<br />

if a natural disaster destroys all <strong>of</strong> a company’s computers, the company<br />

will probably be more concerned about the intangible information<br />

the computer held than the loss <strong>of</strong> the physical system.<br />

The emergence <strong>of</strong> electronic data as a major property form is a<br />

significant reason why the current physical damage requirement is<br />

17. See Beh, supra note 1, at 55.<br />

18. See id.<br />

19. The paper production process comes with significant costs to the environment.<br />

Many companies are finding that reducing paper consumption saves money, is more efficient,<br />

and may bolster their reputations for being “environmentally conscious.” Heather<br />

Sarantis, Business Guide to Paper Reduction, September 2002, pp. 1-4, available at<br />

http://www.environmentalpaper.org/documents/REDUCE-BUSINESS-GUIDE.pdf.<br />

20. See id. at 56.


2010] BUSINESS INSURANCE 1007<br />

outdated. Businesses are simply choosing to store data in a different<br />

way. Their choice is an optimal one for the environment, and wording<br />

in standard insurance policies should not incentivize businesses to<br />

regress. For insurance purposes, it should not matter what form a<br />

company uses to store data. Insurance companies themselves likely<br />

use computers as their major source <strong>of</strong> data storage.<br />

B. E-businesses<br />

Cyberspace has changed conventional business operations. Ebusinesses<br />

are on the rise. Without having to maintain a physical location,<br />

e-businesses are important for the economy because they can<br />

expand and break into markets faster than conventional businesses,<br />

thus maximizing pr<strong>of</strong>its. 21 E-businesses can potentially reach an unlimited<br />

number <strong>of</strong> customers through the Internet, and conducting<br />

business online reduces transaction costs. 22 These business forms<br />

have no use for an insurance policy that covers only physical losses<br />

and physical perils even though they desperately need business interruption<br />

and property protection. If a policyholder’s entire business<br />

is conducted online, any interruption that keeps the business <strong>of</strong>fline<br />

could result in huge losses. 23 Further, any data loss or s<strong>of</strong>tware corruption<br />

could also result in substantial interruptions. 24<br />

One reason traditional first-party policies are inadequate is that ebusinesses<br />

face different risks and damages in the cyberworld than<br />

those that threaten the traditional business. 25 The risks that affect ebusinesses<br />

are different than the physical risks once contemplated by<br />

traditional commercial property policies. 26 E-perils, such as computer<br />

viruses 27 and computer hacking, 28 threaten to harm e-businesses more<br />

21. See id. at 57.<br />

22. See id.<br />

23. See id. at 59-60.<br />

24. Yost, Glad & Barker, supra note 3, at 2061.<br />

25. See id. Modern traditional bricks and mortar businesses face many <strong>of</strong> the same<br />

risks as e-businesses. Viruses and worms may be the most serious threat facing corporations<br />

today. Robert W. Hahn & Anne Layne-Farrar, The <strong>Law</strong> and Economics <strong>of</strong> S<strong>of</strong>tware<br />

Security, 30 HARV.J.L.&PUB.POL’Y 283, 289-90 (2006).<br />

26. See Beh, supra note 1, at 55-56 (“The perils that face these new business forms are<br />

not the traditional perils <strong>of</strong> fires, floods, and other physical forces <strong>of</strong> man and nature, but<br />

perils that exert no apparent physical force and leave no sign <strong>of</strong> physical damage behind.”).<br />

27. Worms and computer viruses are self-replicating programs that usually arrive via<br />

email and corrupt data and programs on computers. One infamous worm, the Love Bug,<br />

spread from Asia in 2000 and even reached government computers at Congress, the White<br />

House, and the Pentagon. The Love Bug may have caused up to $10 billion in damages.<br />

Hahn & Layne-Farrar, supra note 25, at 289.<br />

28. Computer hackers <strong>of</strong>ten use social engineering tactics to invade secure networks.<br />

They may send fraudulent emails to customers to trick them into divulging confidential information,<br />

or they may gain access to networks when employees and consumers select unoriginal<br />

passwords or fail to keep passwords private. In these cases they are posing as legitimate<br />

users when they hack into sites. Id. at 290-91.


1008 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:1003<br />

than any physical peril. 29 E-perils include the risks <strong>of</strong> “information<br />

theft, insertion <strong>of</strong> malicious codes, denial <strong>of</strong> service attacks, 30 access violations,<br />

failure <strong>of</strong> computer security, programming errors, and misuse<br />

or misappropriation <strong>of</strong> intangible assets.” 31 Because e-businesses face<br />

more danger in the cyberworld, they need business interruption and<br />

property coverage for e-perils instead <strong>of</strong> physical perils. 32<br />

Similar to the way fires and floods interrupt the business <strong>of</strong> a<br />

shopkeeper, e-perils interrupt the operations <strong>of</strong> an e-business. Surprisingly,<br />

even the slightest website interruption can have devastating<br />

consequences on pr<strong>of</strong>its due to the impatient nature <strong>of</strong> e-customers. 33 If<br />

Amazon.com and Overstock.com are both selling the same product at<br />

the same price, a customer will naturally prefer the site that is working<br />

properly. A prudent e-business owner will seek to insure for these<br />

interruptions, particularly because they could last for extended periods<br />

<strong>of</strong> time. 34 E-businesses today should shy away from traditional firstparty<br />

commercial property policies and look for an e-commerce policy<br />

with some kind <strong>of</strong> business interruption coverage. 35<br />

C. E-Commerce Insurance<br />

Despite the radical changes cyberspace has brought to modern<br />

businesses, many traditional insurance products have remained the<br />

same. Both first-party commercial property policies and CGL 36 policies<br />

require the incurrence <strong>of</strong> some kind <strong>of</strong> physical damage. 37 Instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> modifying traditional products, some insurance companies<br />

29. See Beh, supra note 1, at 56.<br />

30. A denial <strong>of</strong> service attack is when a network is overwhelmed with traffic that<br />

shuts down and prevents customers from accessing the network. Hahn & Layne-Farrar,<br />

supra note 25, at 288.<br />

31. See Beh, supra note 1, at 58-59.<br />

32. See id.<br />

33. See id. at 60 (noting that the average web surfer will only wait approximately<br />

eight seconds for a website to load before moving on to a different site).<br />

34. Claims for web interruptions may be more successful when interruptions last for<br />

extended periods <strong>of</strong> time. The majority <strong>of</strong> courts require business operations to be completely<br />

suspended and will not provide coverage for slowdowns. See Clark Schirle, Time<br />

Element Coverages in Business Interruption Insurance, 37 THE BRIEF 32, 34 (2007). This<br />

requirement is problematic because e-commerce-related losses <strong>of</strong>ten involve brief interruptions<br />

or network slowdowns.<br />

35. See Robert H. Jerry, II & Michele L. Mekel, Cybercoverage for Cyber-Risks: An<br />

Overview <strong>of</strong> Insurers’ Responses to the Perils <strong>of</strong> E-Commerce, 8 CONN.INS. L.J. 7, 13 (2001).<br />

36. CGL policies will be referred to in this Note because courts and scholars <strong>of</strong>ten use<br />

these cases as a guide in interpreting physical damage under first-party property cases due<br />

to the requirement in CGL policies <strong>of</strong> damage to tangible property. See, e.g., Ward Gen. Ins.<br />

Servs., Inc. v. Employers Fire Ins. Co., 7 Cal. Rptr. 3d 844, 852 (Cal. Ct. App. 4th Dist.<br />

2003); Kendall Bodden, Note, Tangible Cash for an Intangible Loss? Insurance Coverage for<br />

Damage or Loss <strong>of</strong> Third-Party Data, 1 SHIDLER J.L. COM. &TECH. 6, *2 (2005), available<br />

at http://www.lctjournal.washington.edu/Vol1/a006Bodden.html.<br />

37. See Jerry & Mekel, supra note 35, at 10, 15-16.


2010] BUSINESS INSURANCE 1009<br />

have created new products that are specifically tailored to e-perils. 38<br />

These e-commerce or cyber policies are specialized and aim to cover<br />

intangible assets. 39 For example, insurance giant AIG recently<br />

created a new cyber-breach package that covers many risks including<br />

network interruptions, cyber extortion, and network security. 40 Businesses<br />

that want insurance for electronic data can purchase ecommerce<br />

policies designed to cover cyber risks. These policies provide<br />

coverage for e-perils and will <strong>of</strong>ten compensate the insured for<br />

loss <strong>of</strong> income when a website becomes inoperable during a cyber<br />

event. 41 Although these products sound desirable, many believe the<br />

cyber insurance market is under used because <strong>of</strong> expensive premiums.<br />

42 Many <strong>of</strong> these products were created at the beginning <strong>of</strong> the<br />

decade and because <strong>of</strong> their relatively short history, there may be uncertainty<br />

regarding their scope <strong>of</strong> coverage. 43<br />

Cyber products may be effective for some businesses, but they do<br />

not appeal to all clients. 44 Fortune 1000 companies may not want to<br />

negotiate and administer these stand-alone policies. 45 These companies<br />

have the clout to induce insurance companies into drafting endorsements<br />

or individualized policies, but smaller companies may<br />

find that standardized cyber policies are their only option. 46 Many cyber<br />

insurers require businesses to implement certain IT security<br />

standards before providing coverage, and these security measures<br />

may be too costly for smaller businesses. 47 Modern brick and mortar<br />

businesses that have significant intangible assets but are not involved<br />

in e-commerce may be stuck between a rock and a hard place.<br />

Traditional first-party policies will not provide electronic data coverage,<br />

and standardized e-commerce policies may not cover businesses<br />

that are not engaged in e-commerce. 48 Business owners may believe<br />

their standard first-party policy is enough, they may fail to appre-<br />

38. See Beh, supra note 1, at 56-57.<br />

39. It is important to distinguish between commonly used cyber insurance terminology<br />

for first-party policies (<strong>of</strong>ten called e-business or e-commerce insurance) and third-party<br />

policies (<strong>of</strong>ten called cyber-risk insurance). These terms are <strong>of</strong>ten used interchangeably in<br />

material and due to this trend both terms will be used in this Note. See F. LAWRENCE<br />

STREET,LAW OF THE INTERNET § 13.02 (2009).<br />

40. Pete Brush, Ailing AIG Rolls out New Cyber-Breach Product, LAW 360, Jan. 27,<br />

2009, http://www.law360.com/print_article/84826. AIG’s cyber-breach product is a thirdparty<br />

policy and is only for businesses with annual revenue <strong>of</strong> over $500 million. Id.<br />

41. See Jerry & Mekel, supra note 35, at 13.<br />

42. Ross Anderson & Tyler Moore, The Economics <strong>of</strong> <strong>Information</strong> Security, SCIENCE,<br />

Oct. 27, 2006, at 610, 612.<br />

43. See Jerry & Mekel, supra note 35, at 13.<br />

44. See id. at 28.<br />

45. Id.<br />

46. Id. at 28-29.<br />

47. See Bodden, supra note 36, at *5.<br />

48. See Insurance Services Office, Electronic Commerce (E-Commerce), 2007, available<br />

at LEXIS ISO Policy Forms No. CP 00 30 06 07.


1010 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:1003<br />

ciate their coverage needs, or their insurance agent may misrepresent<br />

the extent <strong>of</strong> coverage. 49<br />

1. E-Commerce Insurance and Conflicts <strong>of</strong> Interest<br />

One reason obtaining insurance can be a hazard to businesses seeking<br />

e-commerce-related coverage is that there is an inherent conflict <strong>of</strong><br />

interest between insurance agents and the insured. 50 Both experienced<br />

and rookie insurance agents are faced with ethical dilemmas when<br />

clients ask coverage questions. 51 Both agents want to make the sale<br />

and may be tempted to lead clients to believe policies will provide coverage.<br />

52 An experienced insurance agent knows he cannot accurately<br />

predict coverage. 53 Businesses spend thousands—even millions <strong>of</strong> dollars<br />

on premiums and they want to be assured <strong>of</strong> coverage. 54<br />

When selling a policy, insurance agents may be tempted to suggest<br />

that traditional policies will cover e-commerce-related losses. Insurance<br />

agents may also misinform policyholders <strong>of</strong> coverage available<br />

under specialized products and may not spend enough time accurately<br />

assessing businesses’ coverage needs. It may be particularly<br />

problematic for insurance agents to accurately predict coverage scenarios<br />

under specialized e-commerce or cyber products because they<br />

are relatively recent editions to insurance companies’ inventories.<br />

An insurance agent’s temptation to misinform or inability to accurately<br />

predict coverage is nothing new and is certainly not limited to ecommerce-related<br />

coverage; however, businesses should be aware <strong>of</strong> the<br />

uncertainty that may accompany e-commerce policies. Until nuances in<br />

these policies have been litigated, it is impossible for the conscientious<br />

agent to accurately estimate coverage, and it may be easier for the rookie<br />

agent to engage in insincere sales tactics. Clients may expect some<br />

degree <strong>of</strong> “puffing” by any salesperson, but they will likely expect their<br />

insurance agents to provide clear answers regarding coverage.<br />

III. THE PHYSICAL DAMAGE REQUIREMENT<br />

What is physical damage? This seems to be the million dollar<br />

question when it comes to cyber-related commercial property and<br />

49. See Lee Roy Pierce, Jr., The Ethical Dilemma Insurance Agents Face Which May<br />

Tempt Some to Mislead Their Clients Regarding Coverage, and What to Do to Protect Your<br />

Business from the Consequences <strong>of</strong> Such Conduct, 19 W. ST. U.L.REV. 507, 507-08 (1992)<br />

(providing general information on the problems that may arise as a result <strong>of</strong> the conflict <strong>of</strong><br />

interest between insurance agents and their clients).<br />

50. See id.<br />

51. See id. at 508.<br />

52. See id.<br />

53. Id. at 509-10.<br />

54. Id. at 511.


2010] BUSINESS INSURANCE 1011<br />

business interruption litigation. Can the concept <strong>of</strong> physical damage<br />

change with advances in technology, or is it a static concept?<br />

<strong>General</strong>ly, to meet the physical damage requirement, the insured<br />

must prove there was a “material or substantive physical change to<br />

the insured property;” 55 however, policy definitions may differ. If the<br />

term physical damage is undefined in the contract between the parties,<br />

courts <strong>of</strong>ten differ in interpretations <strong>of</strong> what constitutes physical<br />

damage. 56 These inconsistencies threaten to leave policyholders uncertain<br />

about what property will be covered. If insurance companies<br />

and courts strictly construe the concept <strong>of</strong> physical damage, many<br />

businesses could be left without electronic data coverage.<br />

A. The Physical Damage Requirement and Computers<br />

Insurance companies and policyholders disagree over what constitutes<br />

physical damage. 57 Policyholders argue that physical damage<br />

occurs when magnetic changes occur within the computer’s memory.<br />

58 Policyholders can also analogize computer-related losses to other<br />

invisible forms <strong>of</strong> damage like mold spores, odors, and gasses. 59 Insurance<br />

companies will likely consistently oppose these arguments<br />

and contend that changes in electronic information are intangible<br />

and do not constitute physical damage. 60<br />

E-commerce-related losses could be covered in first-party commercial<br />

property policies that are written on an all-risk basis. 61 All-risk policies<br />

typically provide coverage when a fortuitous event causes physical loss<br />

or damage. 62 There is some confusion over whether the word “physical”<br />

applies merely to losses or applies to damages as well. 63<br />

Businesses may have more luck with e-commerce-related losses in<br />

all-risk business interruption policies. A leading case on the subject,<br />

American Guarantee & Liability Insurance Co. v. Ingram Micro,<br />

Inc., 64 demonstrates that some courts will stretch traditional business<br />

55. Peter E. Kanaris, Analytical Approach to Business Interruption, Extra Expense,<br />

and Civil Authority Coverage Issues, 43 TORT TRIAL &INS.PRAC. L.J. 113, 114 (2007).<br />

56. See, e.g., Am. Guar. & Liab. Ins. Co. v. Ingram Micro, Inc., No. 99-185 TUC ACM,<br />

2000 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 7299, at *10 (D. Ariz. Apr. 18, 2000) (holding that physical damage<br />

included loss <strong>of</strong> use or functioning <strong>of</strong> computer); Ward Gen. Ins. Servs., Inc. v. Employers<br />

Fire Ins. Co., 7 Cal. Rptr. 3d 844, 850 (Cal. Ct. App. 2003) (holding that loss <strong>of</strong> electronic<br />

database did not constitute physical damage).<br />

57. See Beh, supra note 1, at 66.<br />

58. See id.<br />

59. Id. at 66-67.<br />

60. Id. at 66.<br />

61. Lee, supra note 4, at 86.<br />

62. Id.<br />

63. Id.<br />

64. See generally No. 99-185 TUC ACM, 2000 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 7299 (D. Ariz. Apr. 18,<br />

2000) (holding that damage to a computer system resulting from a power outage constituted<br />

“physical damage”).


1012 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:1003<br />

interruption policies to find coverage. 65 Ingram, “a wholesale distributer<br />

<strong>of</strong> microcomputer products,” purchased an all-risk property policy<br />

from American to insure against business interruption losses. 66<br />

The policy insured against “[a]ll [r]isks <strong>of</strong> direct physical loss or damage<br />

from any cause.” 67 Ingram’s business operations depended solely<br />

on the functioning <strong>of</strong> a computer network used to conduct daily business.<br />

68 As a result <strong>of</strong> a power outage, Ingram’s computer lost all programming<br />

information from the random access memory, and it took<br />

almost eight hours for Ingram to return to full operation due to a<br />

malfunctioning matrix switch. 69 American argued that there was no<br />

physical damage because the matrix switch and the computer had<br />

not lost the ability to accept data. 70 Ingram argued that physical<br />

damage includes loss <strong>of</strong> use and functionality. 71<br />

The court referenced language in penal statutes that defined computer<br />

damage and held in favor <strong>of</strong> Ingram, stating the following:<br />

At a time when computer technology dominates our pr<strong>of</strong>essional as<br />

well as personal lives, the Court must side with Ingram’s broader<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> “physical damage.” The Court finds that “physical<br />

damage” is not restricted to the physical destruction or harm <strong>of</strong><br />

computer circuitry but includes loss <strong>of</strong> access, loss <strong>of</strong> use, and loss<br />

<strong>of</strong> functionality. 72<br />

The court found language in penal statutes to be relevant to insurance<br />

because “[l]awmakers around the country have determined that<br />

when a computer’s data is unavailable, there is damage; when a<br />

computer’s services are interrupted, there is damage; and when a<br />

computer’s s<strong>of</strong>tware or network is altered, there is damage.” 73<br />

Ingram served as a warning to the insurance industry, and some<br />

companies drafted electronic data exclusions. 74 Notwithstanding<br />

possible exclusions, the Ingram case is evidence that businesses may<br />

be covered under all-risk policies for business interruption losses that<br />

result from corruption or loss <strong>of</strong> electronic data. 75 Although Ingram<br />

has not been widely accepted, 76 some courts still follow the Ingram<br />

65. See, e.g., Beh, supra note 1, at 68-69; Lee, supra note 4, at 86.<br />

66. Ingram, 2000 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 7299, at *2-*3.<br />

67. Id. at *3.<br />

68. Id. at *3.<br />

69. Id. at *4-*5.<br />

70. See id. at *5.<br />

71. Id. at *6.<br />

72. Id.<br />

73. Id. at *7.<br />

74. See, e.g., Beh, supra note 1, at 68-69; Felix’s Rest., Inc. v. Aspen Specialty Ins. Co.,<br />

No. 07-4290, 2008 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 82815, at *15 (E.D. La. Oct. 17, 2008) (interpreting<br />

policy containing endorsement that excluded electronic data from coverage unless damage<br />

was caused by a covered peril).<br />

75. STREET, supra note 39, at §13.02.<br />

76. Id.


2010] BUSINESS INSURANCE 1013<br />

holding. 77 In Southeast Mental Health Center, Inc., v. Pacific Insurance<br />

Co., Ltd., the plaintiff’s operations were interrupted after a<br />

storm and a power outage caused data loss to the pharmacy computer.<br />

78 Although the storm did not physically damage plaintiff’s real<br />

property, plaintiff sought recovery for business income losses that resulted<br />

from its inability to fill customer prescriptions on the pharmacy<br />

computer. 79 The court, noting that the Ingram court’s reasoning<br />

was persuasive, held that “the corruption <strong>of</strong> the pharmacy computer<br />

constitutes ‘direct physical loss <strong>of</strong> or damage to property’ under the<br />

business interruption policy.” 80<br />

Despite Ingram’s persuasiveness, the recent trend in CGL cases is<br />

to find that electronic data is not tangible property. 81 Although there<br />

are vast differences between third-party and first-party policies that<br />

should not be ignored, some courts follow the reasoning in thirdparty<br />

cases. 82 In Ward <strong>General</strong> Insurance Services, Inc., v. Employers<br />

Fire Insurance Co., the court held that loss <strong>of</strong> electronically stored<br />

data was not a physical loss without any “loss or damage to the storage<br />

media or to any other property.” 83 The court used dictionary definitions<br />

<strong>of</strong> the term physical and followed holdings in third-party<br />

cases, including a widely-cited case, America Online, Inc., v. St. Paul<br />

Mercury Insurance Co. 84 In the America Online case, the court held<br />

that “computer data, s<strong>of</strong>tware and systems are not ‘tangible’ property<br />

in the common sense understanding <strong>of</strong> the word.” 85 The court declined<br />

to follow Ingram, stating the following:<br />

The court in Ingram Micro did not apply the plain meaning <strong>of</strong> the<br />

word “physical.” Rather, the court relied on the increased importance<br />

<strong>of</strong> computers in our lives and the reflection <strong>of</strong> this level <strong>of</strong><br />

importance in various state and federal statutes qualifying loss <strong>of</strong><br />

computer data as physical damage. Although the importance <strong>of</strong><br />

computers in our personal and pr<strong>of</strong>essional lives cannot be overstated,<br />

this Court is bound by the terms <strong>of</strong> the insurance policy. 86<br />

Both the Ingram and the America Online courts recognized the importance<br />

<strong>of</strong> computers in today’s society; however, the America On-<br />

77. See Se. Mental Health Ctr., Inc. v. Pac. Ins. Co., 439 F. Supp. 2d 831, 837-38 (W.D.<br />

Tenn. 2006).<br />

78. Id. at 833.<br />

79. Id. at 834, 836.<br />

80. Id. at 837.<br />

81. STREET, supra note 39, at §13.02.<br />

82. See Ward Gen. Ins. Servs., Inc. v. Employers Fire Ins. Co., 7 Cal. Rptr. 3d 844, 852<br />

(Cal. Ct. App. 4th Dist. 2003) (“We see no reason to attribute different meanings to ‘direct<br />

physical loss,’ as used in first-party coverage provisions, and ‘physical damage to tangible<br />

property,’ as used in third-party coverage provisions.”).<br />

83. Id. at 851.<br />

84. 207 F. Supp. 2d 459 (E.D. Va. 2002).<br />

85. Id. at 462.<br />

86. Id. at 469-70.


1014 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:1003<br />

line court was unwilling to use public policy in its decision. Also, the<br />

America Online court failed to recognize that property forms have<br />

changed, while in Ingram the court recognized that strict construction<br />

<strong>of</strong> the definition <strong>of</strong> physical damage would be “archaic.” 87<br />

The physical damage requirement should be modified because<br />

electronic data can be damaged and is merely a different form <strong>of</strong> data<br />

storage. Electronic data can be manipulated, altered, and changed 88<br />

and is used as a substitute for paper records. These changes should<br />

be considered to constitute physical damage. Further, there are important<br />

public policy reasons to change the way we view physical<br />

damage. Computers have changed our lives and the way we do business.<br />

Computers are important for the economy and have aided businesses<br />

in maximizing pr<strong>of</strong>its by lowering transaction costs. Computers<br />

have become the premier storage device utilized by businesses,<br />

and electronic data is a vital asset that should be covered in firstparty<br />

policies. As discussed in Ingram, legislators have already recognized<br />

that electronic data can be damaged. Businesses today already<br />

face a precarious existence. Leaving modern businesses without<br />

adequate coverage <strong>of</strong> intangibles will only further the problem.<br />

B. The Physical Damage Requirement in Other Contexts<br />

The cyberworld is not the only context in which the physical damage<br />

requirement has started controversy. 89 Litigation over the definition<br />

<strong>of</strong> physical damage still ensues and is anticipated in other situations.<br />

A power grid stops functioning—physical damage? Swine flu<br />

contaminates a work place—is the contamination physical damage?<br />

These are just a few <strong>of</strong> the many issues that arise in litigation involving<br />

business interruption insurance.<br />

The recent swine flu pandemic has alarmed many businesses and<br />

encouraged them to reexamine their insurance coverage. 90 The number<br />

<strong>of</strong> swine flu cases has continued to grow, and businesses are worried<br />

about coverage when business operations shut down. 91 Attorneys<br />

expect insurance companies will contend that swine flu losses do not<br />

constitute property damage. 92 These disagreements will likely lead to<br />

litigation. Under applicable law, some contamination is considered<br />

87. Am. Guar. & Liab. Ins. Co. v. Ingram Micro, Inc., No. 99-185 TUC ACM, 2000 U.S.<br />

Dist. LEXIS 7299, at *7 (D. Ariz. Apr. 18, 2000).<br />

88. See Beh, supra note 1, at 66.<br />

89. This Note focuses on the physical damage requirement and electronic data; however,<br />

it is useful to examine other areas in which the requirement has created confusion<br />

regarding scope <strong>of</strong> coverage.<br />

90. See Christie Smythe, Swine Flu Prompts Cos. to Examine Insurance, LAW 360,<br />

May 1, 2009, http://www.law360.com/print_article/99373.<br />

91. See id.<br />

92. Id.


2010] BUSINESS INSURANCE 1015<br />

physical damage to property. 93 Businesses should be covered for<br />

losses sustained during the time they were decontaminating the<br />

property, but only time will tell. 94<br />

Power outages can wreak havoc on business operations, and there<br />

is controversy regarding whether outages constitute physical damage.<br />

In a recent case, Wakefern Food Corp. v. Liberty Mutual Fire Insurance<br />

Co., a New Jersey appellate court found that an electrical<br />

grid was physically damaged when it was unable to provide electricity.<br />

95 As a result <strong>of</strong> this case, Liberty Mutual was ordered to cover a<br />

group <strong>of</strong> supermarkets for losses they suffered during a power outage<br />

that lasted four days. 96 The trial court had found there was no physical<br />

damage to the power grid because it was able to function after the<br />

interruption. 97 The appellate court found that “the trial court construed<br />

the term [physical damage] too narrowly, in a manner favoring<br />

the insurer and inconsistent with the reasonable expectations <strong>of</strong><br />

the insured.” 98 The plaintiffs in this case had paid a $5.5 million dollar<br />

premium for a policy that included coverage for power outages. 99<br />

Many <strong>of</strong> these concepts are obvious, and perhaps drafters <strong>of</strong> traditional<br />

business interruption insurance policies anticipated these<br />

risks and chose not to provide coverage. Notwithstanding policy language,<br />

many businesses urge courts to stretch the term physical<br />

damage, and sometimes courts agree. The power outage case and the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> swine flu litigation provide additional support for the<br />

modification <strong>of</strong> the physical damage requirement. Not all physical<br />

damage can be easily seen with the naked eye, but this does not<br />

mean damage does not exist. Businesses spend fortunes in premiums<br />

and are being denied coverage on technicalities. Although insurance<br />

litigation in our society will continue, some courts are construing the<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> physical damage broadly, and insurance companies and<br />

the ISO should take note.<br />

IV. BOILERPLATE LANGUAGE<br />

Boilerplate language can make even the most attentive reader’s<br />

eyes glaze over with confusion. Like many contract drafters, the insurance<br />

industry is no stranger to ambiguous boilerplate language. 100<br />

93. Richard P. Lewis, Securing Business Income Coverage in a Pandemic, LAW360,<br />

May 1, 2009, http://www.law360.com/print_article/99440.<br />

94. Id.<br />

95. 968 A.2d 724, 734 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div. 2009); Tina Peng, Liberty Must Cover<br />

Markets for Power Outages: Court, LAW 360, Apr. 23, 2009,<br />

http://www.law360.com/print_article/98222.<br />

96. Wakefern Food Corp., 968 A.2d at 739.<br />

97. Id. at 734.<br />

98. Id.<br />

99. See Peng, supra note 95.<br />

100. See Boardman, supra note 10, at 1111.


1016 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:1003<br />

Insurers likely use boilerplate language not because clients understand<br />

it, but because courts have already interpreted the language.<br />

Insurers continue to use ambiguous language even though courts <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

construe such language against them. 101<br />

In her article, Contra Pr<strong>of</strong>erentem: The Allure <strong>of</strong> Ambiguous Boilerplate,<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Michelle E. Boardman evaluates the insurance industry’s<br />

attraction to boilerplate language despite incentives to draft<br />

clearer policies. 102 Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Boardman makes the following observation<br />

about courts’ attempts to incentivize insurance companies:<br />

“Courts try to improve the language <strong>of</strong> insurance policies, as a parent<br />

tries to improve a child’s behavior, both by punishment and by encouragement.<br />

The frustration <strong>of</strong> courts in this endeavor suggests that<br />

they realize their efforts are being wasted.” 103 When courts construe<br />

ambiguous boilerplate language against insurance companies, the result<br />

is less than optimal. 104 Instead <strong>of</strong> redrafting language to increase<br />

policy clarity, insurance companies use ambiguous language to their<br />

advantage. They retain language that is unreadable, but has been interpreted<br />

by courts because they know courts will use precedent in<br />

the future to interpret the provisions. 105 They may retain language<br />

that has been construed in their favor but is confusing to policyholders,<br />

or they may even retain language that has been construed<br />

against them but will mislead policyholders into believing they have<br />

no meritable claim. 106 Boilerplate language takes on a private meaning<br />

between courts and insurers, but policyholders are left out in the<br />

cold. 107 The result only perpetuates path dependency. 108<br />

A. Insurance Services Office<br />

As discussed in the Introduction, the ISO drafts standard insurance<br />

forms that many insurance companies use as models for their<br />

own first- or third-party policies. The ISO copyrights these forms and<br />

sells them to insurance companies. 109 The ISO also seeks approval <strong>of</strong><br />

policy language from state insurance commissioners, and after courts<br />

interpret policies and data on losses is received, the ISO may begin<br />

redrafting forms. 110 The ISO maintains that this process increases<br />

clarity in standard language. 111 However, redrafts usually only in-<br />

101. Id. at 1106.<br />

102. Id.<br />

103. Id. at 1107.<br />

104. See id. at 1111.<br />

105. See id.<br />

106. See id.<br />

107. See id.<br />

108. See id. at 1113.<br />

109. Id.<br />

110. Id.<br />

111. Id.


2010] BUSINESS INSURANCE 1017<br />

crease clarity for courts and insurers. 112 Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Boardman contends<br />

that “[i]t should be questioned both whether language does indeed<br />

evolve from less to more clear and who benefits from the language<br />

changes that are made.” 113 ISO forms are ideally supposed to<br />

represent current changes in the law, the insurance industry, and<br />

market conditions. 114 Despite sweeping changes in technology and<br />

new markets for cyber-related coverage, current ISO forms primarily<br />

exclude or limit electronic data coverage. 115<br />

Under the ISO form for first-party coverage, electronic data is<br />

listed as one <strong>of</strong> the items that is not covered. 116 The form does contain<br />

a $2,500 extension <strong>of</strong> coverage for the cost to replace electronic data,<br />

but not for the data itself. 117 This limit is too small for most businesses,<br />

118 and the form further provides that “the loss will be valued at<br />

the cost <strong>of</strong> replacement <strong>of</strong> the media on which the electronic data was<br />

stored.” 119 The ISO form for business interruption coverage also contains<br />

a $2,500 limit and will only provide coverage for electronic data<br />

related interruptions that are caused by covered perils. 120 The ISO ecommerce<br />

form provides business interruption coverage, but only for<br />

businesses engaged in e-commerce. 121 This specification means modern<br />

brick and mortar businesses will not be eligible for e-commerce<br />

policies modeled after ISO forms. These forms essentially provide no<br />

workable solutions for brick and mortar businesses that do not engage<br />

in e-commerce. 122<br />

Because courts may look to third-party policy language as a guide,<br />

it is useful to examine ISO forms for CGL policies. Businesses <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

rely on these third-party policies when they lose or damage their customers’<br />

data. 123 In 2001, the ISO changed the standard CGL form to<br />

exclude electronic data from property coverage. 124 The definition <strong>of</strong><br />

property damage in the ISO form contains the following language:<br />

For the purposes <strong>of</strong> this insurance, electronic data is not tangible<br />

property. As used in this definition, electronic data means infor-<br />

112. Id.<br />

113. Id.<br />

114. See id.<br />

115. Austin, supra note 11.<br />

116. Insurance Services Office, Building and Personal Property Coverage Form, 2007,<br />

at § (A)(2)(n), available at LEXIS ISO Policy Forms No. 00 10 06 07.<br />

117. Austin, supra note 11.<br />

118. Id.<br />

119. Insurance Services Office, Building and Personal Property Coverage Form, 2007,<br />

at § (A)(4)(f), available at LEXIS ISO Policy Forms No. 00 10 06 07.<br />

120. See Insurance Services Office, Business Income (and Extra Expense) Coverage<br />

Form, § (A)(5)(d), available at LEXIS ISO Policy Forms No. 00 30 06 07.<br />

121. See Id.<br />

122. Austin, supra note 11.<br />

123. Bodden, supra note 36, at *1.<br />

124. Id. at *2.


1018 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:1003<br />

mation, facts or programs stored as or on, created or used on, or<br />

transmitted to or from computer s<strong>of</strong>tware, including systems and<br />

applications s<strong>of</strong>tware, hard or floppy disks, CD-ROMS, tapes,<br />

drives, cells, data processing devices, or any other media which are<br />

used with electronically controlled equipment. 125<br />

This language ensures that data loss will not be covered under CGL<br />

policies that adopt ISO language. However, “the new language does<br />

not exclude the third party’s loss <strong>of</strong> use <strong>of</strong> undamaged hardware (i.e.<br />

tangible property) caused by data loss (i.e. intangible property).” 126<br />

If insurance companies follow ISO forms, businesses will be forced to<br />

try to obtain e-commerce policies or litigate their claims. 127<br />

The current ISO forms present a significant obstacle to reform <strong>of</strong><br />

the physical damage requirement. ISO forms greatly influence insurance<br />

companies. Ideally, these forms should be modified to reflect<br />

modern realities. The ISO is setting an unworkable example, and<br />

some insurance companies have recognized this and have added endorsements<br />

providing for e-commerce-related losses. 128 Restricting ecommerce<br />

policies to businesses engaged in e-commerce prevents<br />

modern brick and mortar businesses from obtaining sufficient electronic<br />

data coverage. If insurance companies follow these standard<br />

forms, modern brick and mortar businesses will not be covered under<br />

traditional first-party policies and will not be eligible to obtain ecommerce<br />

insurance.<br />

While the ISO reports that its standardized policy forms are actually<br />

drafted to benefit consumers, it seems that electronic data exclusions<br />

were drafted to shield insurers from taking on risks in a relatively<br />

novel area. This behavior makes sense, and insurers are not<br />

expected to serve as saviors to modern businesses. Property forms<br />

have drastically changed in a relatively short period <strong>of</strong> time. The insurance<br />

industry may be cautious because they are alarmed by the<br />

rapidity <strong>of</strong> the changes, or they may be using changes in technology<br />

as an excuse to withhold coverage under traditional policies, thus<br />

creating an insurance market for expensive cyber products.<br />

The industry is getting its feet wet by <strong>of</strong>fering limited e-commerce<br />

coverage and seems to have no immediate plans to broaden coverage<br />

under traditional first-party policies. Insurance companies may be<br />

worried about accurately assessing risks presented by insuring electronic<br />

data. There may be concern about how to accurately measure<br />

electronic data damages. Insurance companies could also be worried<br />

125. Id. at *4.<br />

126. Id. at *5.<br />

127. See id.<br />

128. Policy endorsements issued by some companies do not contain the e-commerce requirement.<br />

See Lambrecht & Assoc., Inc., v. <strong>State</strong> Farm Lloyds, 110 S.W.3d 16, 22 (Tex.<br />

App. 12th Dist. 2003).


2010] BUSINESS INSURANCE 1019<br />

about pro<strong>of</strong>—if filing cabinets go up in smoke, the extent <strong>of</strong> the damage<br />

can be easily seen, but there is no obvious sign <strong>of</strong> damage to electronic<br />

data. If insurance companies are worried about pro<strong>of</strong>, they<br />

should consider that, as a practical reality, pro<strong>of</strong> is an issue when it<br />

comes to insuring any kind <strong>of</strong> data. If a business’s filing cabinet goes<br />

up in smoke, it will be difficult to ascertain the extent <strong>of</strong> damage even<br />

though it can be easily seen. The cabinet could have been filled with<br />

blank sheets <strong>of</strong> paper. If a business is going to commit insurance<br />

fraud, they will likely be motivated to do this whether or not electronic<br />

data is involved.<br />

By maintaining forms that exclude or limit electronic data from<br />

coverage, the ISO is doing the insurance industry a disservice. Under<br />

current ISO extension forms, paper is insurable. The provision provides<br />

that: “You may extend the insurance . . . to apply to the cost to<br />

replace or restore the lost information on valuable papers and records<br />

for which duplicates do not exist. But this Extension does not apply<br />

to valuable papers and records which exist as electronic data.” 129<br />

Many businesses are likely seeking insurance for the same data that<br />

was previously stored on paper. Insurance companies can cover electronic<br />

data and still restrict covered perils. Many insurance companies<br />

are missing out on pr<strong>of</strong>its because they are following ISO forms.<br />

Although other model forms exist, smaller insurance companies cannot<br />

afford to use non-ISO forms or to draft individualized forms.<br />

These smaller companies are missing out on a productive market<br />

while pr<strong>of</strong>its are being siphoned by specialty carriers <strong>of</strong>fering ecommerce<br />

coverage. 130<br />

There could be additional motivations for following ISO forms that<br />

have nothing to do with insurance. For example, “an insurance executive<br />

may be able to keep her job and steadily advance, all the<br />

while endorsing ISO-drafted language that all other insurers are using,<br />

even if that language causes millions or billions <strong>of</strong> dollars in litigation.”<br />

131 An executive may be held accountable for a bad decision if<br />

she makes an individual decision to depart from ISO forms, but she<br />

will not be held accountable for following industry standards. 132<br />

President Barack Obama has stressed the importance <strong>of</strong> cyberspace<br />

in our lives, 133 and based on the government’s recent trend <strong>of</strong><br />

becoming involved in many industries, it is possible that someday the<br />

government could <strong>of</strong>fer cyber insurance subsidies. If this happens, in-<br />

129. Insurance Services Office, Building and Personal Property Coverage Form, 2007,<br />

at § (A)(5)(c)(1), available at LEXIS ISO Policy Forms No. 00 10 06 07.<br />

130. Telephone Interview with William K. Austin, Partner, Austin & Stanovich Risk<br />

Managers, LLC (Nov. 23, 2009).<br />

131. Boardman, supra note 10, at 1128.<br />

132. See id.<br />

133. Austin, supra note 11.


1020 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:1003<br />

surers will lose money. Insurers are undoubtedly taking on some risk<br />

by insuring for electronic data loss; however, due to changing property<br />

forms, the benefits likely outweigh the risks. In ten or twenty<br />

years, businesses will have little to no use for a first-party policy that<br />

does not cover electronic data. The ISO should recognize the direction<br />

the world is heading and should change the physical damage requirement<br />

and protect itself by limiting covered perils or requiring<br />

the implementation <strong>of</strong> affordable security measures prior to underwriting<br />

the policy.<br />

V. CONCLUSION<br />

The Internet has seduced the world and changed the way we do<br />

business. People have become so accustomed to communicating<br />

through the World Wide Web that Twitter messages have even been<br />

sent from outer space. 134 Advances in technology have changed the<br />

way businesses operate, what they value most, and most importantly,<br />

how their most valuable data is stored. Businesses now operate in<br />

a computer-dependent world; however, the majority <strong>of</strong> the insurance<br />

industry is refusing to take the bait. The ISO is continuing to design<br />

cyber-excluding forms, and current e-commerce products are illsuited<br />

for bricks and mortar businesses that have substantial intangible<br />

assets but are not engaged in e-commerce. If technology has<br />

changed, it only makes sense to redraft standard insurance forms.<br />

An insurance policy is only as good as its drafter. Although the majority<br />

<strong>of</strong> insurance companies follow ISO boilerplate language that excludes<br />

electronic data from coverage, some policies may still have loopholes<br />

or remain ambiguous. When faced with an ambiguous policy,<br />

insurers will be dragged into court by businesses attempting to convince<br />

courts to stretch the physical damage requirement. Because<br />

these situations exist and litigation on these coverage issues will likely<br />

only increase, insurance companies would be wise to modify existing<br />

products instead <strong>of</strong> creating more specialized products. Adding newfangled<br />

products that have not stood the test <strong>of</strong> time and have not been<br />

litigated enough creates risks for the insurer and the insured.<br />

Modern brick and mortar businesses now face the worst <strong>of</strong> both<br />

worlds. They face the traditional perils <strong>of</strong> floods and fires that<br />

threaten to destroy their business sites, and they face perils that<br />

threaten to destroy valuable intangible assets. Under standard ISO<br />

forms, businesses are likely not even covered for intangible damage<br />

that results from physical perils. A hurricane may strike and cause<br />

computers to lose important electronic data and s<strong>of</strong>tware programs.<br />

Although this data has been manipulated, altered, or changed under<br />

134. Clara Moskowitz, First Twitter Message from Space Sent, May 15, 2009,<br />

FOXNEWS.COM, http://www.foxnews.com/story/0,2933,520225,00.html.


2010] BUSINESS INSURANCE 1021<br />

standard forms, policyholders are not adequately covered and, even<br />

in an all-risk policy, courts could find that the physical damage requirement<br />

has not been met.<br />

The physical damage requirement in first-party commercial policies<br />

is inadequate because property forms have changed. Property<br />

has become a much more intangible concept. Until the insurance industry<br />

recognizes that keeping traditional first-party policies the<br />

same is unpr<strong>of</strong>itable, businesses must be cautious when assessing<br />

coverage needs. If insurance companies do not provide sufficient coverage<br />

solutions to meet the needs <strong>of</strong> modern businesses, the government<br />

could provide a public option for e-commerce-related coverage.<br />

Although this is an unlikely possibility, if the economy fails to recover<br />

and businesses are left uninsured for some <strong>of</strong> their most valuable<br />

assets, it is likely that demand for insurance reforms will arise.<br />

Failing to update the physical damage requirement is like keeping<br />

archaic language in a statute—inefficient and confusing. Cyberspace<br />

is not the only area in which the physical damage requirement causes<br />

problems. Insurers may draft exclusions regarding electronic data<br />

but may still lose when it comes to litigation involving black-outs or<br />

property contamination. Case law reflects that courts <strong>of</strong>ten look at<br />

the reasonable expectations <strong>of</strong> the insured, and in ambiguous situations<br />

insurers could lose the physical damage battle. To prevent future<br />

litigation in the cyber context, it would be prudent to adopt a<br />

broader definition <strong>of</strong> physical damage that includes deletion or corruption<br />

<strong>of</strong> electronic data. Adopting this definition would be also be<br />

financially advantageous to insurers.<br />

Until the ISO redrafts standard forms, insurance companies<br />

should decline to follow forms that contain electronic data exclusions<br />

because the insured is not the only loser when these forms are used.<br />

Insurers using these forms are missing out on a valuable insurance<br />

market. Brick and mortar businesses that have merely transferred<br />

data into an electronic form are willing to pay a premium to protect<br />

this data. These businesses are not engaged in e-commerce and do<br />

not need (or cannot afford) specialized cyber policies. They also may<br />

not have the complex security measures in place that many cyber policies<br />

require. While it may be prudent to set reasonable limits on<br />

electronic data losses, by excluding these losses altogether, insurers<br />

are shooting themselves in the foot. Insurers should discount for any<br />

perceived risks <strong>of</strong> providing coverage and should price premiums in<br />

accordance with these risks.<br />

Insurers should consider petitioning the ISO to develop rates and<br />

forms for first-party electronic data coverage. This will enable companies<br />

to collect pr<strong>of</strong>its currently going to specialty carriers. The first<br />

step in the right direction for the ISO could be to design electronic<br />

policy endorsements. Coverage limits and certain exclusions could be


1022 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 37:1003<br />

in place while still providing brick and mortar businesses with electronic<br />

data coverage. After these endorsements stand the test <strong>of</strong> time<br />

and insurers receive back statistics on policy claims, the ISO can incorporate<br />

coverage into standard first-party forms.<br />

As technology progresses and the world becomes even more computer-dominated,<br />

the insurance industry should modify traditional<br />

policies to update coverage concepts. It is likely the standard business<br />

insurance package will soon be wholly inadequate to cover business<br />

assets. Businesses will not want to insure against paper losses<br />

when their valuable data exists in electronic form. Changes in technology<br />

should not provide a basis for insurers to change the essential<br />

function <strong>of</strong> first-party policies by failing to provide coverage for a<br />

business’s most valuable assets. Insurance companies can dive into<br />

this new market by modifying existing products, assessing the costs<br />

<strong>of</strong> the risks <strong>of</strong> these modifications, and charging premiums accordingly.<br />

If insurance companies fail to take advantage <strong>of</strong> this lucrative<br />

market, they will have to watch large, specialized carriers rake in the<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its they could have been making.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!