13.07.2015 Views

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

50 <strong>Prices</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>knowledge</strong>It is probably more realistic to say, with Mises (1949:252), that ‘inany real <strong>and</strong> living economy every actor is always an entrepreneur’.The idea of prices as sufficient statistics has to be used, if at all, in amore limited sense, as in a recent statement by Hayek where he saysthe price mechanism operates as a medium of communicating<strong>knowledge</strong> which brings it about that the facts which becomeknown to some, through the effects of their actions on prices, aremade to influence the decision of others.(1979:125)The point then is not that it is enough (sufficient) for an individual toknow prices, in addition to his preferences, resources, <strong>and</strong>technologies, to act correctly—the target of Grossman <strong>and</strong> Stiglitz’scriticism. Instead, it is that prices reduce the amount of detail that heneeds to know to do so. 30 As O’Driscoll <strong>and</strong> Rizzo (1985:39) put it,‘the crucial point is that, overall, more information is conveyedthrough a <strong>market</strong> price system than without one.’ The effectiveness ofprices in this role will depend crucially on the existence of a rivalrouscompetitive <strong>process</strong>, an issue considered below.There is another interpretation of Hayek to consider which at firstappears also to treat prices as sufficient statistics. Vernon L. Smith(1982a) has conducted experimental tests regarding ‘the institutional<strong>and</strong> technical conditions necessary to achieve a competitiveequilibrium (C.E.)’. 31 He says:one view, which has comm<strong>and</strong>ed a modest following since theclassic work of Adam Smith, suggests that the attainment of C.E.allocations do [sic] not require any individual participant to have<strong>knowledge</strong> of the circumstances of other agents, or to have anunderst<strong>and</strong>ing either of the <strong>market</strong> as an allocation system or of his/her role in promoting ‘an end which was no part of his intention’.(1982a:166; emphasis added)Smith singles out Hayek as the economist who has presented thisposition ‘more strongly <strong>and</strong> more influentially in recent decades’(1982a:166). Smith decides to test what he therefore terms the ‘Hayekhypothesis’, which affirms that ‘strict privacy together with thetrading rules of a <strong>market</strong> institution are sufficient to producecompetitive <strong>market</strong> outcomes at or near 100% efficiency’ (167). By‘strict privacy’ he means ‘each buyer in a <strong>market</strong> knows only his/her

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!