13.07.2015 Views

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Equilibrium prices <strong>and</strong> information 35This only situation capable of sustaining an equilibrium,Grossman <strong>and</strong> Stiglitz argue, violates Hayek’s description of theprice system because these prices are not fully informative: someindividuals make economic decisions without being fully informed.(And Hayek is believed to be arguing that in a competitive <strong>market</strong>individuals achieve allocations identical to those that could beachieved by an invisible h<strong>and</strong> with all the information in theeconomy.) 13Grossman <strong>and</strong> Stiglitz’s argument applies not only to thetransmission of information through prices. They also make asimilar point for the aggregation of information by prices in <strong>market</strong>situations in which individuals have different information: theyshow that, if the price aggregated their information perfectly, theindividuals would no longer base their dem<strong>and</strong>s on their privateinformation but only on the price. But then a paradox occurs: ‘If alltraders ignore their own information how does the information getinto the price?’ (Grossman 1976:582). Again, Grossman <strong>and</strong>Stiglitz show, the paradox might not appear if the price systemwere ‘noisy,’ i.e., if it failed to aggregate information perfectly.However, this condition for the existence of an equilibrium would(once more) violate Hayek’s description of the achievements of theprice system.The case of ‘costless’ informationAlthough Grossman <strong>and</strong> Stiglitz devote very little space to it, they domention the case of what they describe as costless information. It ismentioned here because it might seem to contradict the description ofthese authors as information-as-a-commodity economists: this latterapproach tends to suggest that, without costly information, therewould be no informational problem. It turns out that what Grossmanmeans by situations of costless information are situations in whichthere is information that is costly for any arbitrary individual toacquire but that was costless to its possessor. (This is not, then, a purecase of costless information.) He gives the example of a shoe sellerwho, in the course of his business, ‘learns a little about the dem<strong>and</strong> forshoes, for free, from his customers’. This would be one of thosefrequent cases in which information is ‘produced complementary withthe production, <strong>and</strong> distribution of other commodities’. According toGrossman (1981:556),

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!