13.07.2015 Views

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

132 Notes3 Economists, Nelson <strong>and</strong> Winter (1982:358) say, are aware of the fact thatnot all firms act as price-takers, that there are public goods <strong>and</strong>‘externalities are pervasive’, that economic agents may lack perfectinformation, <strong>and</strong> so on.4 Nelson (1981:95) credits Simon for the ‘most forceful articulation of themeaning <strong>and</strong> significance of bounded rationality…’.5 Nelson (1977:136) points out the failure of economists—whom he does notidentify— ‘to recognize the contradiction between those arguments for<strong>market</strong> structure which are based on the premise that behavior of acompetitive regime will be Pareto optimal, <strong>and</strong> those arguments for real<strong>market</strong>s which are focused on the alleged flexibility <strong>and</strong> responsiveness ofsuch a regime…’.6 Nelson (1981:95) notices that both Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek, ‘the two advocates ofprivate enterprise in this debate, pose their arguments in a form much moredistant from that of contemporary welfare economics than does Lange, theadvocate of Socialism’.7 The other exception to the ‘static <strong>perspective</strong>,’ in his view, is ‘the earlySchumpeter’. Because of his questionable differentiation of Mises’s <strong>and</strong>Hayek’s argument, Nelson seems to believe that Lange’s was an appropriateresponse to Mises’s challenge.8 In the light of the economic analysis of regulation <strong>and</strong> the theory of publicchoice, Nelson may have been too hasty in attributing such altruistic motivesto these government interventions. However, it should be noticed, he ends bynot advocating any particular regime because he does not ‘have any strongnotions about the answers’ to these organizational questions (Nelson1981:110).9 See the quotation of Gordon <strong>and</strong> Hynes (1970) in chapter 2.10 For a survey of this literature, see Fisher (1983).11 The tone of this statement is cautious because a <strong>market</strong> economy need notactually achieve equilibrium even under imaginary unchanging conditions.However, as long as this equilibrium state was not reached, a <strong>market</strong> systemwould still stimulate entrepreneurial activity, whereas no equivalentdiscovery <strong>process</strong> would be at work in a planned regime.12 Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek used a similar assumption, although Mises (1936: 142)correctly pointed out that to do so ‘we need only avoid asking how thisstationary condition is achieved’. See, e.g., Mises (1920: 109–10), <strong>and</strong>Hayek (1940:188).13 In Nelson’s book with Winter, consideration of these possibilities appears tohave been deliberately suppressed (Nelson <strong>and</strong> Winter 1982:38).14 The terms ‘hierarchy’ <strong>and</strong> ‘organization’ will be used interchangeably.15 The term ‘non-<strong>market</strong> hierarchies’ is used because although it will most oftenrefer to government-generated organizations, what is meant, more generally,is organizations created by individuals whose decisions are not motivated byprofits in the <strong>market</strong> <strong>and</strong> who are significantly immune from its competitivepressures (in the sense that they do not have to compete for the acquisition ofresources <strong>and</strong> may not be overly concerned about pecuniary losses caused bytheir decisions). In the case of government, this independence from the<strong>market</strong> is due to the possibility of obtaining resources through non-voluntarymeans.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!