13.07.2015 Views

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

Prices and knowledge: A market-process perspective

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

128 Notes39 See also Hahn (1984a:11) <strong>and</strong> Fisher (1983:4). According to Lavoie(1985a:35), ‘there are elements of disco-ordination diffused throughout any<strong>market</strong> economy…But there are also the well-known general regularities,such as those between prices <strong>and</strong> costs of production, that are reflected inboth the classical labor theory of value as well as the modern subjectivisttheories of marginal utility <strong>and</strong> imputation.’40 This view clearly underlies Mises’s writings: in a world with nounpredictability no ‘Misesian’ action would be necessary (an equilibriumwould, presumably, sooner or later, be achieved), <strong>and</strong> in a world withcompletely volatile <strong>and</strong> unpredictable change no such action could besuccessful or, therefore, worth while.41 As in other instances, the imperfection here referred to uses the questionablest<strong>and</strong>ard of an omniscient agent’s point of view.42 Schumpeter (1934:62) describes equilibrium as ‘never attained, continually“striven after” (of course not consciously) …’.43 In the world of price-taking agents of the st<strong>and</strong>ard version of this story, itis not clear who, aside from the makeshift device of a fictitiousauctioneer, is in charge of increasing the price of tin. This deficiency ofst<strong>and</strong>ard (‘competitive’) price theory leads Fisher (1970:195) to remarkthat ‘the Invisible H<strong>and</strong> is a little too invisible in this, the center of itsactivities’.44 This role includes the possibility of transmitting information (‘signalling’)through prices.4 ‘Bounded rationality’ <strong>and</strong> the price system1 For example, Simon (1981:41), Nelson <strong>and</strong> Winter (1982:361), <strong>and</strong>Williamson (1975:4–5) have interpreted Hayek as arguing against centralplanning from a bounded-rationality <strong>perspective</strong>. See also Langlois(1985:225–35). For an attempt to find common elements in these lines ofthought, see Langlois (1986: esp. 225–41).2 See, e.g., Radner (1968); Nelson <strong>and</strong> Winter (1982); Williamson (1975);Loasby (1976).3 Cf. Kirzner (1973:32–7). Simon, like the Austrians, also distinguishesbetween subjective <strong>and</strong> objective rationality, <strong>and</strong> mentions the need for anunderst<strong>and</strong>ing of how the means-ends framework is perceived by agents. Anearly distinction between objective <strong>and</strong> subjective rationality appears inHutchison (1938:109–14).4 Also see Ando (1979:86).5 The Austrian flavour resides in the content of the passage <strong>and</strong> not in itsreference to Schumpeter.6 For a strong criticism of Simon’s, <strong>and</strong> other researchers’, treatment of humanbeings as information <strong>process</strong>ors, see Dreyfus (1979) <strong>and</strong> Dreyfus <strong>and</strong>Dreyfus (1986).7 Williamson also includes within bounded rationality what he calls ‘languagelimits’, which ‘refer to the inability of individuals to articulate their<strong>knowledge</strong> or feelings by the use of words, numbers or graphics in ways

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!