03.12.2012 Views

Sartre's second century

Sartre's second century

Sartre's second century

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

78 Chapter Six<br />

Nevertheless, Simone de Beauvoir was clearly unhappy with critics'<br />

understanding of Ufctre et le neant, particularly in connection with<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> use of the term "useless passion" to describe the pour-soi: the<br />

knowingly futile attempt of self-consciousness to become its own<br />

foundation. One of the principal aims of her 1947 essay, Pour une Morale<br />

de Vambiguite (The Ethics of Ambiguity), is precisely to re-examine the<br />

term "useful", opening it up to the fundamental ambiguity of existential<br />

meaning: "[A]t the level of description where Being and Nothingness is<br />

situated, the word useful has not yet been given any meaning [...]. In the<br />

original abandonment where man rises up, nothing is useful, nothing is<br />

useless." 14 In a parallel trajectory to <strong>Sartre's</strong> lecture, then, the aim of<br />

Beauvoir's essay was to give a lively defence of certain allegations made<br />

against existentialism, in particular that it was a philosophy of the absurd,<br />

that it gave rise to a "sterile anguish" and an "empty subjectivity". These<br />

charges are, in Beauvoir's typically brusque manner, publicly rebuffed.<br />

Although <strong>Sartre's</strong> relationship to the Cartesian tradition has long been<br />

the object of much critical scrutiny, it is <strong>Sartre's</strong> relationship to Heidegger<br />

which, over the course of the last sixty years or so, has arguably caused the<br />

most controversy. Sartre places himself squarely in the tradition of<br />

atheistic existentialist thinkers, and further implicates Heidegger in his<br />

"humanist" project. Levy rightly asserts that "Sartre is not a French<br />

Heidegger". 15 However, <strong>Sartre's</strong> relationship to Heidegger is fundamentally<br />

problematic. It begins with his implicit acceptance of Henri Corbin's<br />

translation of Dasein (meaning literally "There-being") as "human<br />

reality". Jacques Derrida famously denounced "human reality" as a<br />

"monstrous translation" of Dasein in his essay "Les Fins de l'homme"<br />

("The Ends of Man"), and a symptom of a false anthropological reading of<br />

Heidegger's Being and Time. 16 Heidegger would, of course, refute any<br />

suggestion that the ontology contained in his Sein und Zeit (Being and<br />

Time) is humanistic: his well-known "Letter on Humanism", published in<br />

1947, was his reply to <strong>Sartre's</strong> UExistentialisme est un humanisme: "[...]<br />

—isms", writes Heidegger, "have for a long time now been suspect". 17<br />

Non-metaphysical, non subject-based, post-structuralist theorists throughout<br />

the 1960s and 70s—Barthes, Foucault and Derrida, amongst others—<br />

have taken this aspect of Heidegger's thought through to its logical<br />

14 "[A]u niveau de description ou se situe Ufctre et le Neant, le mot utile n'a pas<br />

encore regu de sens [...]. Dans le delaissement originel ou l'homme surgit, rien<br />

n'est utile, rien n'est inutile" (Beauvoir, Pour une Morale de Vambiguite, 17).<br />

15 "Sartre n'est pas le Heidegger frangais" (B.-H. Le\y, Le Siecle de Sartre, 171).<br />

16 Derrida, "Les Fins de rhomme", in Marges de la philosophic 131-64.<br />

17 Heidegger, Basic Writings, 219.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!