03.12.2012 Views

Sartre's second century

Sartre's second century

Sartre's second century

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

1945-2005: Existentialism and Humanism Sixty Years On 77<br />

However, Sartre is never content merely to follow. As Nik Farrell Fox<br />

states in his excellent book, The New Sartre, "<strong>Sartre's</strong> attachment to the<br />

Cartesian cogito in his early work is never a complete or exhaustive<br />

one". 12 The later Sartre tries to distance himself from an overtly Cartesian<br />

emphasis on his early work, and his comments made during the 1960s<br />

seemed to resonate with the times when he said it was never his intention<br />

to reiterate Cartesianism. But what exactly do we understand by this term<br />

"Cartesianism", specifically from a humanistic perspective? Sartre avoids<br />

the substantiality of the subject by creating the pre-reflective cogito as the<br />

foundation to its Cartesian counterpart. As he puts it very succinctly in<br />

VEtre et le neant: "[T]here is a pre-reflective cogito which is the<br />

condition of the Cartesian cogito." 13<br />

First described in La Transcendance de VEgo {The Transcendence of<br />

the Ego, 1936), the pre-reflective cogito challenges some fundamental<br />

assumptions made by Descartes. For Sartre, Descartes assumes the<br />

subjective, isolated presence of the cogito which exists at a specific<br />

moment in time: the instant or now. And it is this aspect of the Cartesian<br />

cogito which Sartre is, of course, anxious to challenge. He does this in two<br />

main ways. Firstly, in order to get outside this problem of instantaneity,<br />

the pour-soi (for-itself) is constructed as a non-material, temporal being. It<br />

is itself this process of temporalisation by which the past and present<br />

ecstasies are continually transcended towards an "open" future. Secondly,<br />

to refute the charge of subjectivity, while at the same time distancing<br />

himself somewhat from his erstwhile mentor, Husserl, the ego is made<br />

transcendent to consciousness. It does not "inhabit" the pour-soi. Then, in<br />

a further radical move for phenomenology, the Sartrean cogito is called<br />

into question by the presence of the Other. The existence of the Other is as<br />

certain as our own existence, and a condition of it. In this way, the charge<br />

of subjective "isolation" implied in the Cartesian cogito is counterbalanced<br />

by Sartre with Hegel's intuition of the Other. In other words, it is<br />

counterbalanced by the ontological significance of alterity. Only the Other<br />

has power to confer value to my own subjectivity. I may consider myself<br />

to be good, bad, cunning, out-going, generous, etc., but I cannot confer<br />

these values on myself outside of the presence of others.<br />

absolue de la conscience s'atteignant elle-m§me. [...] cette thdorie est la seule a<br />

donner une dignitd a rhomme, c'est la seule qui n'en fasse pas un objet" (Sartre,<br />

VExistentialisme est un humanisme, 63-64, 65).<br />

12 Farrell Fox, The New Sartre, 14.<br />

13 "[I]l y a un cogito prgrgflexif qui est la condition du cogito carte'sien" (Sartre,<br />

L'fore et le neant, 19).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!