03.12.2012 Views

Sartre's second century

Sartre's second century

Sartre's second century

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Autobiography, Ontology and Responsibility 29<br />

of das Volk: "The Volk that it designates knows neither unity or disunity,<br />

because in the transcendence of its historicising, it has always already<br />

reached beyond the isolation of individual subjects, as well as the isolation<br />

of an individual ethnic group." 29 When Heidegger claims that: "Authentic<br />

Being-one's-Self does not rest upon an exceptional condition of the<br />

subject, a condition that has been detached from the 'they'; it is rather an<br />

existentiell modification of the 'they'—of the 'they' as an essential<br />

existential 9 , 30 this modification of the "they" is interpreted by Phillips as<br />

referring to "destiny". The significance of Phillips's discussion resides in<br />

his attempt to identify destiny's defining characteristics, arguing that<br />

Heidegger's notions of destiny and Volk are both inconsistent with the<br />

language of the Nazi Party and ineluctably associated with it.<br />

For Phillips, the core of Heidegger's notions of destiny and das Volk is<br />

"decision". 31 Yet, in Phillips's analysis, ultimately nothing definite is in<br />

place for "decision" to act upon. The core of Destiny becomes an<br />

emphasis upon the pure uncertainty of the future and the "impenetrable<br />

idiocy of time". 32 Phillips has outlined the growing centrality of das Volk<br />

in Heidegger's writings and has pointed out its historical, futural/temporal<br />

nature. In the following discussion, I shall be less concerned to agree or<br />

disagree with Phillips's interpretation than I shall be to offer a complementary<br />

path to understanding Heidegger's post-1930s view of history in<br />

contrast to <strong>Sartre's</strong>.<br />

The opening sections of Being and Time celebrate the pragmatically<br />

oriented involvement of Dasein with the "world" understood as the totality<br />

of instrumental complexes. Dasein is what it does. Dasein 1 s ultimate aim<br />

in this, Heidegger tells us, is Dasein itself. Being and Time's account of<br />

the "world" is the world of work and pragmatic instrumentality.<br />

As early as the Basic Problems of Philosophy, written one year after<br />

Being and Time, we see an important modification of this somewhat<br />

earlier analysis of Dasein's relationship to the world. In Basic Problems,<br />

worldly things are no longer viewed exclusively in terms of their<br />

instrumentality, but are also to be understood in what I will term their<br />

"embodied presence". Things carry a specific ontological weight as things<br />

above and beyond their pure instrumentality. Heidegger writes: "The<br />

characters of thingness [...] were fixed for the first time in Greek ontology<br />

and later faded out and became formalized. [... the Greek meaning of] to<br />

pro-duce, place-here [...] means at the same time to bring into a narrower<br />

Heidegger's Volk, 13.<br />

30 Being and Time, 168.<br />

31 Heidegger's Volk, 199.<br />

32 Ibid., 204.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!