12.07.2015 Views

a theory of state formation and the origins of inequality

a theory of state formation and the origins of inequality

a theory of state formation and the origins of inequality

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

A THEORY OF STATE FORMATION AND THE ORIGINS OF INEQUALITY (*)Carles Boix (**)February 21, 2011(*) Previous versions <strong>of</strong> this paper were presented at <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Virginia, <strong>the</strong> New Yorkmeeting <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “September Group” Princeton University, Duke University, Yale University, StanfordUniversity, <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Chicago <strong>and</strong> Harvard University. I thank <strong>the</strong> comments <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong>irparticipants, in particular to those <strong>of</strong> Sam Bowles, Dan Gingerich, Stathis Kalyvas, Carol Mershon,Thomas Romer <strong>and</strong> Milan Svolik. I am especially grateful to <strong>the</strong> comments <strong>of</strong> Alícia Adserà <strong>and</strong> toTeppei Yamamoto for his research assistance.(**) Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Politics <strong>and</strong> Public Affairs, Princeton University. E-mail: cboix@princeton.edu.


AbstractTo explain <strong>the</strong> transition from <strong>state</strong>less, relatively equal communities to agrarian, unequal <strong>and</strong> <strong>state</strong>governedsocieties that has taken place since about 8,500 BC, this paper <strong>of</strong>fers a model with <strong>the</strong>following traits: income-maximizing agents, who may ei<strong>the</strong>r choose between a productive strategy<strong>and</strong> an expropriation strategy, coordinate on peace without permanent political institutions provided<strong>the</strong>ir economic conditions are relatively equal; however, as soon as <strong>inequality</strong> rises (due to a biasedtechnological shock), <strong>the</strong>ir spontaneous coordination around peace becomes unfeasible; agents sortout into different types; <strong>and</strong> <strong>state</strong>s are formed, ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> a monarchical type (where <strong>the</strong> moreproductive agents make a transfer to <strong>the</strong> less productive ones in exchange for permanent protection)or a republican system (where <strong>the</strong> former invest directly on some defensive structures to deter <strong>the</strong>latter from looting <strong>the</strong>m). Those two solutions, crucially determined by military technology <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>opportunity costs <strong>of</strong> not producing, lead to distinct distributional outcomes. The formal model isfollowed by a worldwide cross-sectional analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sources <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘exogenous’ nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>agricultural revolution, <strong>the</strong> latter’s effects on to <strong>the</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>state</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> impact <strong>of</strong> militarytechnologies on <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>and</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> different political regime. The paper concludeswith a brief exploration <strong>of</strong> empirical evidence (mostly related to <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> height patterns)relating <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong> political structure to <strong>the</strong> internal distribution <strong>of</strong> economic resources.1


Until about 10,000 years ago, mankind lived in small, relatively equal <strong>and</strong> <strong>state</strong>lesscommunities <strong>of</strong> foragers. From 8,500 B.C. onward, however, several regions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world transitedto agriculture <strong>and</strong> sedentary human communities. In turn, <strong>the</strong> domestication <strong>of</strong> plants <strong>and</strong> animalsspurred or at least was correlated with two momentous events: <strong>the</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>state</strong> (rangingfrom small urban polities to vast despotic monarchies) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> marked inequalities in<strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> wealth. Those changes had long-lasting political <strong>and</strong> economic consequences, atleast until <strong>the</strong> spread <strong>of</strong> industrial technologies compressed, with a few national exceptions <strong>and</strong>temporal reversions, <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> incomes within countries, <strong>and</strong> arguably triggered a process <strong>of</strong>democratization in <strong>the</strong> last 150 years or so.This article <strong>of</strong>fers a <strong><strong>the</strong>ory</strong> to account for those joint processes <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>origins</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong>. The first two sections <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> article develop a model in which incomemaximizingagents may pursue two kinds <strong>of</strong> strategies: ei<strong>the</strong>r a productive strategy, consisting in <strong>the</strong>allocation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir resources to <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> services, or an expropriatory orextractive strategy, which implies directing <strong>the</strong>ir resources to appropriate <strong>the</strong> assets or returns <strong>of</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r individuals. Even though those agents may engage in conflict in one-shot interactions, overtime <strong>the</strong>y may cooperate ‘spontaneously’, that is, without any permanent political institutions, if <strong>and</strong>only if <strong>the</strong>ir economic conditions are relatively equal. As soon as <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> rises above acertain threshold (generally following a biased technological shock in which some individualsbenefit differently from a similar innovation), <strong>the</strong> cooperation equilibrium breaks down. In such anunequal world, agents sort out into different types – with different pay<strong>of</strong>f functions <strong>and</strong> differentstrategies. Whereas <strong>the</strong> economically advantaged individuals or ‘natural producers’ have a strongpreference for production, those who do not benefit from <strong>the</strong> technological shock prefer looting.Hence, to deter <strong>the</strong> latter, <strong>the</strong> ‘natural producers’ ei<strong>the</strong>r invest on constructing <strong>and</strong> managing somedefensive structures (to stop <strong>the</strong> looters) or make some transfers to <strong>the</strong> ‘natural looters’ to appease<strong>the</strong>m (<strong>and</strong> to obtain some permanent protection from <strong>the</strong>m). Although both solutions give birth topermanent political institutions, i.e. <strong>the</strong> <strong>state</strong>, each strategy leads to different political regimes (self-2


governing or republican systems versus monarchical regimes). Each political outcome, which isstrongly affected by <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong> military technologies, has, in turn, distinctiveredistributive effects. Monarchical regimes tend to generate <strong>and</strong> sustain much higher levels <strong>of</strong><strong>inequality</strong> than republican institutions. Still, <strong>the</strong> overall distribution <strong>of</strong> income continues to dependon strictly economic (technological) variables too.The third part <strong>of</strong> this article explores <strong>the</strong> empirical validity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical model.Employing both anthropological <strong>and</strong> archaeological evidence, it first shows that foraging groupsboth have no permanent political authority (i.e. some kind <strong>of</strong> leadership stably holding <strong>the</strong> monopoly<strong>of</strong> coercion) <strong>and</strong> display very limited levels <strong>of</strong> social <strong>and</strong> economic stratification <strong>and</strong> similarinterpersonal patterns <strong>of</strong> consumption <strong>and</strong> individual wealth. Using systematic evidence across <strong>the</strong>world <strong>and</strong> over time, it demonstrates that <strong>the</strong> agricultural revolution that took place about 10,000years ago was triggered by exogenous factors, that is, <strong>the</strong> biogeographical conditions <strong>of</strong> each regionin <strong>the</strong> world. It <strong>the</strong>n relates <strong>the</strong> timing <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> birth <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> institutions to <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong>agriculture. It concludes by linking <strong>the</strong> prevailing type <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> institutions (in agricultural societies)to <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> military technologies.The fourth part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> article explores <strong>the</strong> determinants <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong>. After calibrating <strong>the</strong>model (showing how economic <strong>and</strong> military technologies as well as population <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> capacity <strong>of</strong><strong>state</strong>s shape <strong>the</strong> final distribution <strong>of</strong> income), it brings in some empirical evidence (mostly related to<strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> health patterns) relating <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong> political structure to <strong>the</strong> internal distribution <strong>of</strong>economic resources. Contrary to <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard research in political economy emphasizing ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>economic foundations (Marx 1848) or <strong>the</strong> political roots <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> (Rousseau 1755[1973],Andreski 1968), both exercises reveal that <strong>the</strong> patterns <strong>of</strong> wealth <strong>and</strong> income <strong>inequality</strong> are jointlydetermined by both technological <strong>and</strong> institutional parameters.This article makes several contributions to two areas <strong>of</strong> research in political economy: <strong>the</strong>process <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>origins</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong>. Broadly speaking, <strong>the</strong> literature on <strong>state</strong><strong>formation</strong> includes two main str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> thought. Institutionalist (including neomarxist) models3


interpret <strong>the</strong> construction <strong>of</strong> political institutions as <strong>the</strong> outcome <strong>of</strong> a (voluntary or forced) deal inwhich b<strong>and</strong>its <strong>of</strong>fer <strong>the</strong>ir protection to peasants in exchange for some payment or transfer (North1981; Olson 1993, 2000; Levi 1988; Bates 2001). Older, functionalist work sees <strong>state</strong>s forming as aresponse to collective action problems <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> breakdown <strong>of</strong> a cooperation equilibrium. Bothapproaches suffer from several glaring weaknesses. Institutionalist models do not entertain <strong>the</strong>possibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s forming as self-governing polities. Functionalist approaches cannot account for<strong>the</strong> distributive effects that accompany <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> political institutions. With <strong>the</strong> exception <strong>of</strong>some historical macrosociological accounts (McNeill 1982, Tilly 1990), both literatures bracket <strong>the</strong>effects <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>and</strong> military technologies on <strong>the</strong> overall process <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong>institutions upon which b<strong>and</strong>its <strong>and</strong> producers coordinate.Although <strong>the</strong>re is a burgeoning literature on <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> on growth (Atkinson<strong>and</strong> Bourguignon 2000, Lindert 2000, Piketty 2000, Kahhat 2007) <strong>and</strong> on political institutions <strong>and</strong>conflict (Boix 2003, Acemoglu <strong>and</strong> Robinson 2006, Geddes 2007, Boix 2008), much less work hasbeen done on <strong>the</strong> underlying causes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong>. From an empirical point <strong>of</strong> view<strong>the</strong>y have focused <strong>the</strong>ir attention to <strong>the</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong> income distribution in advanced countries in <strong>the</strong>last three decades (Gottschalk <strong>and</strong> Smeeding 1997), suggesting partial yet still heavily contestedexplanations (Wallerstein 1999, O’Rourke <strong>and</strong> Williamson 1999, Scheve <strong>and</strong> Stasavage 2007,Gordon <strong>and</strong> Dew-Becker 2008). From a <strong>the</strong>oretical point <strong>of</strong> view, most contributions are strictaccounting exercises or limit <strong>the</strong>mselves to economic variables such as imperfect credit marketswhich are in turn left unexplained. 1 Moreover, <strong>the</strong>re is little work on <strong>the</strong> choice <strong>of</strong> politicalinstitutions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> economic assets as jointly determined phenomena – even thoughthat question was a long-st<strong>and</strong>ing concern among classical political <strong>the</strong>orists such as Aristotle([1988], IV, 11), Machiavelli (1531 [1970], I, 55) or Rousseau (1755 [1973]).1 An exception is Rogowski <strong>and</strong> McRae (2008). For a review <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature, se Kahhat (2007) <strong>and</strong> Boix(2010).4


1. INITIAL CONDITIONSSet-upTo underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> dynamics that led from equal, primitive economies to complex, unequalhistorical societies, consider a world populated by two types <strong>of</strong> agents, 1 <strong>and</strong> 2, each one with sometechnological knowledge (for example, some natural abilities to hunt, fight, etc.). These two agentscan be thought <strong>of</strong> as individuals living toge<strong>the</strong>r or as individuals (or households) populating someterritory. They can also be thought <strong>of</strong> as representative individuals <strong>of</strong> homogeneous groups, that is,groups formed by agents who, because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir close ‘resemblance’ (in a sense to be made moreprecise shortly) to each o<strong>the</strong>r, can cooperate in a stable, permanent manner.All individuals have <strong>the</strong> same time L, which <strong>the</strong>y can employ in two different types <strong>of</strong>activities. On <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>y may allocate some fraction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir time L to some ‘productive’activity (such as hunting) that generates some income y i in a st<strong>and</strong>ard Cobb-Douglas productionfunction y i =A i T α 1-αi L i for i={1,2} <strong>and</strong> where A denotes <strong>the</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>of</strong> technology <strong>and</strong> T st<strong>and</strong>s for a fixedstock <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>. 2 On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>y may direct <strong>the</strong>ir time to predatory activities, that is, to stealo<strong>the</strong>r individuals’ production. In this latter instance, <strong>the</strong>y obtain (1-1/θ L )y j , where y j is <strong>the</strong> return from<strong>the</strong> productive activities <strong>of</strong> individual j (where j≠i) <strong>and</strong> θ L is a technology parameter (θ L >1) thatmeasures <strong>the</strong> effectiveness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> time allocated to extraction. Hence, <strong>the</strong> income <strong>of</strong> individual iwould be, in principle, that is, in a decision-<strong><strong>the</strong>ory</strong> setting:r i = (1-λ) A i T α 1-αi L i + λ(1-1/θ L ) A j T α 1-αj L jwhere λ (with 0 ≤λ ≤1) is <strong>the</strong> fraction <strong>of</strong> time i spends looting.Assume that T <strong>and</strong> L are identical across all agents <strong>and</strong> define  n = A n T α 1-αn L n / A j T α j L 1-α j sothat (A i T α 1-αi L i / A j T α j L 1-α j )=  i <strong>and</strong> (A j T α 1-αj L j / A j T α j L 1-α j )=1. Then we can rewrite r i as:r i = (1-λ)  i + λ(1-1/θ L ) (1)2 Later I explore more precisely <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> that productive or cooperative strategy, that is, <strong>the</strong> set <strong>of</strong>activities (<strong>and</strong> interpersonal activities) that go into it.5


Taking  i <strong>and</strong> θ L as given, agents i <strong>and</strong> j will choose λ that maximize <strong>the</strong>ir respectiveincomes in <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> strategic setting in which both agents choose between looting <strong>and</strong>producing. The pay<strong>of</strong>fs <strong>of</strong> that game will be as follows. If both agents simply produce (λ = 0), <strong>the</strong>irpay<strong>of</strong>f will be  i <strong>and</strong> 1 respectively. Under a condition <strong>of</strong> generalized looting (that is, with both i <strong>and</strong>j looting <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side), all output not directly consumed by each agent will be destroyed. Hence,agent i will be only able to obtain (in fact, keep) <strong>the</strong> portion she produces directly or (1-λ)  i . In turn,j will only keep (1-λ). Finally, if one agent loots while <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r does not, <strong>the</strong> income <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nonlooter(<strong>the</strong> part not expropriated by <strong>the</strong> looter) will be reduced by some proportion due to <strong>the</strong>destructive effects <strong>of</strong> pillaging. That is, if agent i loots while agent j does not loot, i receives <strong>the</strong>pay<strong>of</strong>fs in (1) while j gets (1-β)(1-λ). The parameter β (with 0≤β≤1) measures <strong>the</strong> destructiveness <strong>of</strong>predation. In turn, if j loots <strong>and</strong> i only produces, i keeps (1-β)(1-λ) i In that instance, j gets (1-λ) +λ(1-1/θ L )  i .Anarchy, Equality <strong>of</strong> Conditions, <strong>and</strong> Self-sustaining PeaceTo determine <strong>the</strong> conditions under which both agents will coordinate on a productionstrategy, suppose that <strong>the</strong>y play an infinite, repeated game, with some discount rate δ (identical forall players). To make <strong>the</strong> analysis simple (<strong>and</strong> focused on <strong>the</strong> problem at h<strong>and</strong>), assume that playershave two strategies available to <strong>the</strong>m. They can follow a trigger strategy PP, producing always untillooting occurs <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n responding with looting ever after. Or <strong>the</strong>y can adopt a constant lootingstrategy LL. 33 Since (1-β)(1-λ)


To have sustained peace, <strong>the</strong> following conditions should take place. For player i, <strong>the</strong> value<strong>of</strong> choosing a production strategy must be larger than looting a producer in <strong>the</strong> first period <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>nfacing a looting solution always ever after:Aˆi> (1 − λ)Â1 − δiLiRearranging terms:ˆA i1> (1 − δ )(1 − )(2)θLSimilarly, for player j <strong>the</strong> following <strong>inequality</strong> (where producing always is better than looting <strong>the</strong>producer <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n moving into a permanent situation <strong>of</strong> conflict) must hold:1 δ+ λ(1- ) + (1 − λ)Âθ 1 − δ11> (1 − λ)+ λ(1- )Â1 − δθLiδ+ (1 − λ)1 − δHence:1Aˆi1> (1 − δ )(1 − )(3)θLequilibrium if:Putting (2) <strong>and</strong> (3) toge<strong>the</strong>r, we can conclude that continuous production will be an1> Aˆi(1 − δ )(1 −1θ )L1> (1 − δ )(1 − )θL(4)Inequality (4) carries with it two main implications. In <strong>the</strong> first place, it shows that, even in aHobbesian world, that is, in a world where <strong>the</strong>re is no authority in place <strong>and</strong> players may haveincentives to raid o<strong>the</strong>rs, it is possible for individuals to sustain peace, avoid conflict <strong>and</strong> engage inproductive activities – again without having to resort to any centralized common mechanisms <strong>of</strong>authority. This is a result well known in <strong>the</strong> formal study <strong>of</strong> human cooperation (Axelrod 1984).In <strong>the</strong> second place, it also shows that <strong>the</strong> non-predatory equilibrium is only possible if <strong>the</strong>reis some fundamental equality <strong>of</strong> conditions among individuals or across human communities. If  ibecomes too large, that is, if agent i is much more productive (<strong>and</strong>, hence, better <strong>of</strong>f) than agent j,7


<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> left-h<strong>and</strong> side in (4) will not hold. Agent j has no incentive to cooperate <strong>and</strong> shifts to alooting strategy. Similarly, if  i becomes much lower than 1, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> right-h<strong>and</strong> side in (4) will nothold ei<strong>the</strong>r. In that instance, it is agent i that shifts away from <strong>the</strong> production strategy. In short, in <strong>the</strong>context <strong>of</strong> a primitive economy as <strong>the</strong> one described so far, peace is only possible if <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong>natural resources is uniformly distributed across <strong>the</strong> territory populated by i <strong>and</strong> j. 4 O<strong>the</strong>rwise, <strong>the</strong>production equilibrium collapses <strong>and</strong> conflict erupts. 5Open Conflict <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Exit ConditionThe bounds <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> within which cooperation is feasible vary with <strong>the</strong>discount rate <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> looting technology. First, <strong>the</strong> more players value <strong>the</strong> future (i.e. <strong>the</strong> closer <strong>the</strong>discount rate δ is to 0), <strong>the</strong> higher <strong>inequality</strong> can be without jeopardizing a production equilibrium.Second, a predatory outcome is less likely when looting is inefficient (that is, when θ L gets closest to1). The effectiveness <strong>of</strong> looting is directly related to <strong>the</strong> military technology in <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>predator. But it is also shaped by <strong>the</strong> strategies producers <strong>the</strong>mselves have to reduce <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong>what a looter can steal. The efficiency <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> looting technology declines (<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> occurrence <strong>of</strong> openpredation does too) if producers can easily exit or move away in response to any potentialaggression, that is, if <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> moving to a different territory are low. In fact, we know from <strong>the</strong>anthropological literature that ab<strong>and</strong>oning one’s own community <strong>and</strong> creating or joining ano<strong>the</strong>r is acommonly used mechanism in pre-<strong>state</strong> communities to lessen internal conflict (Leacock <strong>and</strong> Lee1982).4 In <strong>the</strong> model presented so far, <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> resources depends on <strong>the</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>of</strong> technology A. However, itcould also (<strong>and</strong> in fact it does) vary independently <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> tools <strong>and</strong> skills <strong>of</strong> humans as a result <strong>of</strong> climate,quality <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>, etc.5 Notice that <strong>the</strong> production equilibrium is compatible with higher levels <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> if <strong>the</strong> biased shockthat generates more <strong>inequality</strong> (that is, that increases <strong>the</strong> income differential across individuals) increases<strong>the</strong> income <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> poorer individual (in <strong>the</strong> production equilibrium) as well. [DEVELOP.]8


The feasibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> exit option is negatively related to population densities <strong>and</strong> positivelycorrelated with <strong>the</strong> marginal value <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>. The gradual territorial expansion <strong>of</strong> mankind across <strong>the</strong>globe in <strong>the</strong> late Pleistocene can be explained as a rational response to manage competition forresources. Migration was <strong>the</strong> automatic, less costly response to avoid a permanent <strong>state</strong> <strong>of</strong> open war.However, as l<strong>and</strong> filled up, <strong>the</strong> exit option became more costly <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> relative value <strong>of</strong> lootingincreases. According to <strong>the</strong> model, social conditions had to approximate strict equality to avoid apredatory equilibrium.The Nature <strong>of</strong> “Cooperation”So far I have defined <strong>the</strong> production equilibrium by exclusion: as a set <strong>of</strong> social interactionswith no systematic looting. However, a <strong>state</strong> <strong>of</strong> nature with no open war may take several forms. In<strong>the</strong> most stripped-down interpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> model, it may consist <strong>of</strong> a set <strong>of</strong> isolated individuals,w<strong>and</strong>ering alone in <strong>the</strong> forests, satisfying <strong>the</strong>ir needs on <strong>the</strong> spot, <strong>and</strong> clashing (or not) with eacho<strong>the</strong>r as a function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> parameters (<strong>the</strong>ir physical strength, roughly similar at <strong>the</strong> beginning <strong>of</strong>times, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> environmental distribution <strong>of</strong> resources, more or less concentrated) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> model. In amore elaborate application <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong><strong>the</strong>ory</strong>, it implies <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> some communities <strong>of</strong> men <strong>and</strong>women living toge<strong>the</strong>r under a condition <strong>of</strong> relative equality. The first type <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>of</strong> nature, akin toRousseau’s vision <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first men as a savage men, “solitary, idle <strong>and</strong> always near danger”, does notsquare well with <strong>the</strong> evidence produced by anthropological research <strong>and</strong>, more recently, byevolutionary biology <strong><strong>the</strong>ory</strong>. Human beings appear to have lived in families <strong>and</strong> b<strong>and</strong>s always (eventhough <strong>the</strong>se groups tend to exhibit some considerable level <strong>of</strong> fluidity in primitive societies). 6 Thosesocial units may be partly glued by biological as well as by emotional ties (Ingold 2000). But <strong>the</strong>yare <strong>the</strong> result, especially at <strong>the</strong> b<strong>and</strong> level, <strong>of</strong> optimizing individuals that join in groups to exploit6 On human sociality as a universal condition from an anthropological point <strong>of</strong> view, see Levi-Strauss(1961 [1955]), pp. 389-392, 397-398. For a review from <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> evolutionary biology, seeHanson (1992), Hawkes (1992) <strong>and</strong> Boone (1992).9


some economies <strong>of</strong> scale in production <strong>and</strong>/or to minimize <strong>the</strong> risks <strong>of</strong> foraging <strong>and</strong> harvestingthrough resource-sharing (Smith 1987, Boone 1992). In any case, that is, regardless <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>motivations that lead to <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> those cooperative structures, absent any force or authority,<strong>the</strong>y are only sustainable if <strong>the</strong>ir members are roughly equal.Notice <strong>the</strong>n that <strong>the</strong> model can be thought as a building block in what may be labeled a‘nested’ <strong><strong>the</strong>ory</strong> <strong>of</strong> cooperation. At <strong>the</strong> lowest (individual) level, peace is possible among a subset <strong>of</strong>actors provided <strong>the</strong>y enjoy sufficiently similar pay<strong>of</strong>fs: when <strong>the</strong>y do, <strong>the</strong>y can form a stable, orderlytribe, village or neighborhood. Similarly, this social unit can also sustain cooperative relations witho<strong>the</strong>r human b<strong>and</strong>s or tribes if <strong>the</strong> same degree <strong>of</strong> relative equality (<strong>and</strong> looting technologies) appliesat that level. Peace breaks down at <strong>the</strong> point (in <strong>the</strong> continuum <strong>of</strong> agents) where <strong>inequality</strong> <strong>of</strong>conditions becomes ‘excessive’, i.e., <strong>inequality</strong> (4) does not hold anymore. In short, <strong>the</strong> modelexplains why cooperation may exist at some but not o<strong>the</strong>r levels <strong>of</strong> social interactions.2. CONFLICT AND THE EMERGENCE OF STATE INSTITUTIONSInequality <strong>and</strong> Sorting <strong>of</strong> AgentsAs pointed above, <strong>inequality</strong> makes a cooperation equilibrium unfeasible because it alters<strong>the</strong> ranking <strong>of</strong> preferences (<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> corresponding optimal strategy) <strong>of</strong> each agent. The emergence <strong>of</strong><strong>inequality</strong> is <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> a process through which resources (or, more precisely, <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong>resources) become concentrated in dense <strong>and</strong> predictable patches <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>the</strong> returns toindividuals vary depending on <strong>the</strong> territory <strong>the</strong>y occupy. 7 This process can occur through at leastthree paths. First, <strong>the</strong> discovery <strong>of</strong> new resources (or, simply, <strong>the</strong> occupation <strong>of</strong> new areas that have amuch higher yield): this is <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gradual habitation by foraging communities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Northwest Pacific Coast, where fishing resources were concentrated in particular areas. Second, atechnological shock, such as <strong>the</strong> agricultural revolution that I describe <strong>and</strong> exploit empirically in <strong>the</strong>7 For a first analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> resource concentration among animal populations, see Wilson(1964). For its extension to humans, see Boone (1992).10


following section, that changes <strong>the</strong> marginal productivity for some but not all territories. Finally,population growth leading to <strong>the</strong> occupation <strong>of</strong> marginal territories <strong>and</strong> to a correspondingdifferentiation in incomes between <strong>the</strong> initial core <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> less valuable l<strong>and</strong>.Besides breaking <strong>the</strong> production equilibrium, <strong>inequality</strong> also sorts agents out into differenteconomic classes with different ‘political’ goals. Following a biased shock that increases <strong>the</strong> returnsto production <strong>of</strong> agent i relative to those <strong>of</strong> agent j, each individual pursues now very differentstrategies. Whereas agent j now prefers looting, <strong>the</strong> economically advantaged agent i still has an(even stronger) incentive to sustain a production equilibrium.From Anarchy to Political InstitutionsTo overcome a generalized situation <strong>of</strong> looting, those who are better <strong>of</strong>f under a productionequilibrium can pursue two alternative strategies. On <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>y can make a transfer (in <strong>the</strong>form <strong>of</strong> a tribute or lump-sum payment) to agents <strong>of</strong> type j such that <strong>the</strong> latter stop looting (<strong>and</strong>benefit from <strong>the</strong> production efforts <strong>of</strong> i). In this instance, <strong>the</strong> potential looters or b<strong>and</strong>its (those whohave not benefited from <strong>the</strong> economic shock) control (govern) <strong>and</strong> protect <strong>the</strong> natural producers from<strong>the</strong>ir own explicit violence <strong>and</strong> against o<strong>the</strong>r potential b<strong>and</strong>its. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> ‘natural’producers (or agents i) may decide to make looting a much less rewarding activity (for agents <strong>of</strong> typej) than just following a cooperative, non-violent path. They do so by setting up some institutions orstructures, such as a common army <strong>and</strong> some stable leadership, that would allow <strong>the</strong>m to defend<strong>the</strong>ir assets <strong>and</strong> lives against any potential b<strong>and</strong>its.Both solutions involve <strong>the</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> some organization or structure that controls <strong>the</strong>monopoly <strong>of</strong> violence over a given territory – that is, <strong>the</strong>y involve <strong>the</strong> construction <strong>of</strong> a “<strong>state</strong>”. But<strong>the</strong> mechanisms underpinning each solution are different. The first road to peace, which we may11


efer to as a “monarchical solution”, follows Olson’s insight on <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>state</strong> as “rovingb<strong>and</strong>its” become “stationary b<strong>and</strong>its” or l<strong>and</strong>lords (Olson 1993, 2000). 8The second strategy, which has received no attention in <strong>the</strong> modern institutionalist literatureon <strong>state</strong> <strong>formation</strong>, leads instead to <strong>the</strong> construction <strong>of</strong> a <strong>state</strong> in which <strong>the</strong> “natural” producers alsodouble as defenders <strong>and</strong> rulers. We may wish to call <strong>the</strong> second strategy an instance <strong>of</strong> a “selfgoverning”polity or <strong>of</strong> a republican settlement. 9 Notice that a system in which <strong>the</strong> community <strong>of</strong>producers sets aside some portion <strong>of</strong> its income to hire an army or a leader to protect its members(while governing <strong>the</strong>mselves through republican institutions) does not constitute a case <strong>of</strong> selfgovernmentor republicanism. Since <strong>the</strong> hired leader cannot credibly commit to preserve <strong>the</strong> terms <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> contract once he has been appointed <strong>and</strong> takes control <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> army, such a solution ends in (or isequivalent to) <strong>the</strong> subjection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> producers to a leader-monarch. In short, we should think <strong>of</strong> astable republican solution as one in which citizens have ultimate control over <strong>the</strong> means <strong>of</strong> defense. 10We do not need to think <strong>of</strong> b<strong>and</strong>its as ‘external’ enemies only. The term <strong>of</strong> looter refers aswell to individuals who live in a given community <strong>and</strong> may try to steal, free ride on o<strong>the</strong>rs, etc.8 Writing from an anthropological perspective, Carneiro (1970) also <strong>of</strong>fered a <strong><strong>the</strong>ory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>formation</strong>that emphasizes <strong>the</strong> interaction <strong>of</strong> violence <strong>and</strong> exit options (<strong>the</strong> latter in turn deriving from populationdensity). Exit strategies <strong>and</strong> density are, however, not endogenized in his paper. As in Olson, he focuseson <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> autocratic <strong>state</strong>s. See Wright (1977) for a review <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories inanthropology <strong>and</strong> archaeology.9 Olson’s (<strong>and</strong> in fact most neoinstitutionalist accounts’) unique solution explains why his explanationabout democratic transitions is ad hoc <strong>and</strong> unconvincing. He claims that democracy emerges when <strong>the</strong>reis a vacuum <strong>of</strong> power in an already-formed <strong>state</strong> in which a set <strong>of</strong> notables have roughly equal claims topower (see Olson 2000: 28 ff.). But this <strong>state</strong> <strong>of</strong> things (i.e. <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> balance <strong>of</strong> power) could beequally predicated for <strong>state</strong>less societies.10 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral hazard problems <strong>of</strong> hiring an external captain or condottiero in lateMedieval Italian cities, see McNeill (1982). The mechanisms through which citizens (or some subset <strong>of</strong>citizens) can control defense – <strong>and</strong> so limit exploitation – are multiple. For a formal analysis <strong>of</strong> howinstitutions may limit executive power, even in <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> non-democratic systems, see, for example,Boix <strong>and</strong> Svolik (2010).12


Individual(s) i will have <strong>the</strong>n an incentive to set up some policing mechanism to dissuadeindividual(s) j from misbehaving.Monarchical Settlement versus Self-Governing SolutionLet me now characterize each political solution separately <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n solve for <strong>the</strong> conditionsunder which one should prevail over <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. (All this discussion clears <strong>the</strong> way to examineanalytically (in <strong>the</strong> third part, after I explore <strong>the</strong> historical validity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> model) <strong>the</strong> ways in whichthose alternative paths <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>formation</strong> have different consequences for income distribution <strong>and</strong><strong>inequality</strong> – with <strong>the</strong> monarchical solution implying some redistribution from producers to <strong>the</strong> lord<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> eventual rearrangement <strong>of</strong> income rankings within society.)Monarchical Settlement. In a ‘monarchical’ settlement, where agents <strong>of</strong> type i make atransfer to agents j to buy <strong>the</strong>ir protection, agent i’s pay<strong>of</strong>f will be (1-ε) / (1-δ), where ε denotes <strong>the</strong>transfer extracted by agent j, with 0≤ε≤1, <strong>and</strong> all time is now devoted to production. In turn, agent jreceives, provided he follows a non-looting strategy (which now includes an effort to protectindividuals <strong>of</strong> type i against o<strong>the</strong>r potential b<strong>and</strong>its), a transfer from <strong>the</strong> producer in proportion to <strong>the</strong>time λ spent governing (as well as any pay<strong>of</strong>f from his own production, if any): [(1-λ)+(ε-γ)λ i ] / (1-δ), where γ is <strong>the</strong> portion that <strong>the</strong> b<strong>and</strong>it-lord spends in governing <strong>and</strong> protecting <strong>the</strong> producer <strong>and</strong>0


Self-Governing Institutions. In a self-governing system <strong>the</strong> producers <strong>the</strong>mselves takesteps to defend <strong>the</strong>ir assets <strong>and</strong> lives against b<strong>and</strong>its, that is, <strong>the</strong>y have to spend some fraction <strong>of</strong> hertime to set up a military or defense structure (such as building a wall or a watchtower to observe <strong>the</strong>horizon). That amount <strong>of</strong> time will depend on <strong>the</strong> efficiency with which it is employed to deter anylooter j from pillaging <strong>the</strong> producer. The level <strong>of</strong> efficiency will be a function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> militarytechnology in <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> producers (relative to <strong>the</strong> military technology <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> looters).Therefore, <strong>the</strong> pay<strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> those agents <strong>of</strong> type i (or a community with individuals i such that all havean incentive to cooperate) that decide to defend <strong>the</strong>mselves is [(1-(λ/θ D ))Â i ]/(1-δ)], where λ is <strong>the</strong>time spent in defense <strong>and</strong> θ D is <strong>the</strong> efficiency <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> technology with which producer i defendshimself against potential b<strong>and</strong>its – <strong>and</strong> where 0≤λ≤1 <strong>and</strong> θ D >λ. Agents i keep <strong>the</strong> fraction <strong>of</strong>production not spent in defense. As i’s defensive capabilities increase, <strong>the</strong> producer can spend moretime generating Y=YA α i L 1-α i .Looked at from <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> potential looter, <strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> creating a defensestructure is equivalent to <strong>the</strong> principle <strong>of</strong> inflicting some cost on j to push <strong>the</strong> latter into peacefulbehavior. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, agent i must choose a parameter <strong>of</strong> defense θ D such that j has no incentiveto exploit <strong>the</strong> producer. Hence, <strong>the</strong> j’s pay<strong>of</strong>f under a successful self-governing or republican regimewill be 1, that is, j will devote all his time to production <strong>and</strong> none to looting.Choice <strong>of</strong> Institutions. Once <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> disrupts <strong>the</strong> possibility od spontaneouscoordination around peace, <strong>the</strong> natural producers choose between establishing a self-governing <strong>state</strong>,giving up <strong>the</strong>ir rights to a tyrant (a ‘stationary b<strong>and</strong>it’) or engaging in a looting strategy. In turn,agents j must decide whe<strong>the</strong>r to abide by <strong>the</strong> political settlement or to loot.Under what conditions will each solution prevail?1. In <strong>the</strong> first place, a <strong>state</strong> will only emerge if <strong>the</strong> pay<strong>of</strong>fs under stable institutions (ei<strong>the</strong>r atyrant or a republican structure) exceed <strong>the</strong> pay<strong>of</strong>fs that come from looting <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side in <strong>the</strong> firstperiod <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n slipping into a situation <strong>of</strong> permanent conflict. Let me examine first (in points 1A14


<strong>and</strong> 1B) by examining each alternative separately, that is, <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a republican solution versusstraightforward looting <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> monarchy versus looting. Later (in point 2), I consider <strong>the</strong>conditions under which a republican solution prevails over a monarchical solution (or viceversa)provided order is preferred to conflict.1. A. The ‘natural’ producers (agents i) would ra<strong>the</strong>r have a republican structure than looting(provided <strong>the</strong>y prefer <strong>the</strong> republican solution over <strong>the</strong> monarchical settlement) if:(1 − λ θ ) AˆD1 − δi> (1 − λ)Aˆi1 δ+ λ(1− ) + (1 − λ)Aˆiθ 1 − δLRearranging <strong>the</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> this <strong>inequality</strong> gives us:ˆA i(1 −1θ L )> (1 − δ )(5)(1 −1θ )DThus, <strong>the</strong> incentives <strong>of</strong> any agent i to move to a republican solution increase when <strong>the</strong>alternative option <strong>of</strong> looting becomes less attractive – ei<strong>the</strong>r because <strong>the</strong> looting technology θ Ldeclines in efficiency, <strong>the</strong> defensive technology θ D improves, or <strong>the</strong> production technology  iincreases.In turn, agent j will accept <strong>the</strong> self-governing structure set up by i if just producing leaveshim better <strong>of</strong>f than trying <strong>the</strong> looting strategy:1> (1 − λ)+1 − δλθDÂiδ+ (1 − λ)1 − δRearranging this <strong>inequality</strong> <strong>the</strong>n:θ D> Âi1 − δ(6)In short, j is more likely to accept <strong>the</strong> production strategy when <strong>the</strong> strategy capabilities <strong>of</strong> iincreases <strong>and</strong> when <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> i’s production declines.Putting (5) <strong>and</strong> (6) toge<strong>the</strong>r, a republican settlement is feasible whenever:θ D ˆ (1 −1θ L )> Ai> (1 − δ )− δ(1 −1θ )(7)1 D15


In addition to (7), self-government will only be feasible if peace without transfers is not anequilibrium. 121. B. In <strong>the</strong> instance in which a monarchical solution is preferred over a republican one, <strong>the</strong>natural producers will only accept to transfer some resources to a tyrant if that makes <strong>the</strong>m better <strong>of</strong>fthan looting:(1 − ε ) Aˆ1 − δi> (1 − λ)Aˆi1 δ+ λ(1− ) + (1 − λ)Aˆiθ 1 − δLRearranging <strong>the</strong> <strong>inequality</strong>:(1 − δ )(1 −1/θ L ) λλ −> εÂi(8)A monarchical regime becomes more attractive to producers when <strong>the</strong> efficiency <strong>of</strong> looters(measures through θ L ) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> extraction rate ε decline <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> productivity <strong>of</strong> i increases.In turn, j will have an incentive to act as a monarch <strong>and</strong> not as a b<strong>and</strong>it if:(1 − λ)+ ( ε − γ ) λAˆ1 − δi1 δ> (1 − λ)+ (1 − ) λÂi + (1 − λ)θ 1 − δLHence:1ε > (1 − δ )(1 − ) + γθ L (9)Therefore, agents <strong>of</strong> type j will become monarchs when <strong>the</strong> extraction rate <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> lootingcosts increase <strong>and</strong> when <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> governing decline.Putting toge<strong>the</strong>r (8) <strong>and</strong> (9), a monarchical settlement will be possible whenever:1 11λ − λ(1−δ)(1 − ) > ε > (1 −δ)(1 − ) + γθ ˆL A θL(10)iAs in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> a republican settlement, in addition to (10), a monarchical settlement willonly be feasible if peace without transfers is not an equilibrium. 1312 This condition takes place, following (3), when  i >1/[(1-δ)(1-1/θ L )]. It is possible to show that <strong>the</strong>re isa broad range <strong>of</strong> values for which both <strong>the</strong> latter <strong>inequality</strong> <strong>and</strong> (7) hold at <strong>the</strong> same time.16


2. For <strong>the</strong> space in which a <strong>state</strong> (ei<strong>the</strong>r monarchical or republican) may take place(according to <strong>the</strong> conditions spelled out in 1.A <strong>and</strong> 1.B), <strong>the</strong> producer (agent i) will prefer arepublican over a monarchical solution whenever:1 − ( λ θ ˆD)) Ai1 − δ(1 − ε ) Aˆ>1 − δ(iSimplifying <strong>the</strong> expression:λε >θ D(11)According to <strong>inequality</strong> (11), <strong>the</strong> political solution depends, given a fixed time λ devoted tolooting, on <strong>the</strong> rate <strong>of</strong> extraction ε. The higher ε is, <strong>the</strong> higher <strong>the</strong> incentive to establish a republic.The political regime will be also a function <strong>of</strong> war technology. If producers are superior or evenrelatively equal to looters at war, <strong>the</strong> former will be able to deter any predator or set <strong>of</strong> predators <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>refore will associate in human communities where decisions are made in a consensual manner orwhere, at least, a broad section <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> population has some impact over politics. However, as soon asθ D falls, that is, as soon as looters acquire some strong comparative advantage in <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> force,monarchical regimes will become <strong>the</strong> prevalent form <strong>of</strong> government. That may happen for multiplereasons. Looters may control a particular type <strong>of</strong> weapon or develop a new set <strong>of</strong> military tactics thatare particularly effective at waging war. More <strong>of</strong>ten, <strong>the</strong> invention <strong>of</strong> new weapons (such as swordsor horse chariots) requiring considerable training <strong>and</strong> expertise foster <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> specialization<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essionalization <strong>of</strong> war-making. The opportunity costs <strong>of</strong> self-defense among producersescalate. By contrast, those individuals that engage in predatory activities gain in power <strong>and</strong>effectiveness. They form a separate caste <strong>of</strong> warriors that encroaches upon <strong>the</strong> self-governinginstitutions preferred by <strong>the</strong> producers <strong>and</strong> that establishes centralized <strong>state</strong>s with highly extractivefiscal systems.13 Again, <strong>the</strong>re is a wide range <strong>of</strong> values that make <strong>the</strong>se two conditions (<strong>and</strong> thus a monarchical regime)feasible.17


Notice that, if <strong>the</strong> producer sets up a republic, <strong>the</strong> potential looter j will abide by <strong>the</strong> solutionsince, by definition, a republic is only possible if producers have <strong>the</strong> actual military capacity to deterlooters from pillaging <strong>the</strong>m (<strong>and</strong>, again, this deterrence strategy still is preferable to any o<strong>the</strong>rsolution).If <strong>the</strong> producers are, instead, better <strong>of</strong>f under a monarchy, agents <strong>of</strong> type j will not accept <strong>the</strong>monarchical settlement if <strong>the</strong>ir pay<strong>of</strong>f under a republic is larger than <strong>the</strong> monarchical transfer (1-ε)A– with <strong>the</strong> looting alternative precluded by our assumption that <strong>inequality</strong> (7) holds. In that case, <strong>the</strong>producers will have to increase ε to <strong>the</strong> point that monarchy becomes attractive to j (provided that,even after that increase in <strong>the</strong> extraction rate, a republic would still leave agents i worse <strong>of</strong>f than <strong>the</strong>monarchical solution).An Extension: The Possibility <strong>of</strong> Imperial Republic. In addition to establishing a selfgoverningstructure to pursue a purely defensive strategy, producers i may decide to engage in an<strong>of</strong>fensive one, both geared toward defending <strong>the</strong>ir l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> attacking <strong>the</strong> looters. The <strong>of</strong>fensivestrategy costs an extra fraction <strong>of</strong> i’s production above <strong>the</strong> price paid to simply defend <strong>the</strong>ir ownterritory. Therefore, since it implies a lower direct output for i, we can denote <strong>the</strong> <strong>of</strong>fensivetechnology parameter as θ O with 0≤θ O ≤θ D . 14Since <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> an <strong>of</strong>fensive strategy implies that agents i will apply sufficient force to makeindividuals j spend <strong>the</strong>ir time producing even when <strong>the</strong>y experience some looting from i, <strong>the</strong> naturalproducers will follow that strategy (to establish an imperial republic) only if <strong>the</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> looting jare larger that <strong>the</strong> portion <strong>of</strong> output lost in upgrading <strong>the</strong> military strategy from a defensive into an14 It seems plausible to think that even when <strong>the</strong> main endeavor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se agents is production, <strong>the</strong>y stillneed to pay always some minimum costs <strong>of</strong> defense θ D to be ready to move to <strong>the</strong> fully militarizedstrategy. As a matter <strong>of</strong> fact, if θ D were equal to 0, <strong>the</strong>n government institutions would only appear whenindividuals <strong>of</strong> type j chose a looting strategy. O<strong>the</strong>rwise, if individuals <strong>of</strong> type j did not loot, everyonewould simply cooperate spontaneously with no permanent structure governing <strong>the</strong>m. This does not seemto be realistic.18


<strong>of</strong>fensive one. This will depend on two factors. First, <strong>the</strong> incentives to set up an imperial republicwill decline whenever <strong>the</strong> <strong>of</strong>fensive costs θ O increase with respect to <strong>the</strong> defensive costs θ D . Second,<strong>the</strong>y will also fall <strong>the</strong> more productive <strong>the</strong> agents <strong>of</strong> type i become with respect to <strong>the</strong> agents <strong>of</strong> typej. The latter proposition derives from <strong>the</strong> fact that, as <strong>the</strong> i’s become wealthier, <strong>the</strong> opportunity costs<strong>of</strong> any expansion become higher. Or, to put it in slightly different terms, <strong>the</strong> more marginal l<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong>persons (<strong>of</strong> type j) are, <strong>the</strong> less prone <strong>the</strong>ir (richer) neighbors i will be to attack <strong>and</strong> subject <strong>the</strong>m. 153. HISTORICAL DISCUSSIONEgalitarian, Pre-<strong>state</strong> CommunitiesUntil about 8,500 BC all mankind lived in b<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> hunters <strong>and</strong> ga<strong>the</strong>rers. Sincearchaeological research only <strong>of</strong>fers ra<strong>the</strong>r scant in<strong>formation</strong> about <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> patterns <strong>of</strong> socialinteractions in those pre-<strong>state</strong> communities, we are forced to rely on contemporary anthropologicalresearch, mostly on foraging communities, to assess <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> simple communities. 16With <strong>the</strong> exception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fishing communities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Northwest Pacific Coast, whichshowed considerable social differentiation, mostly related to a pattern <strong>of</strong> strong spatial concentration<strong>of</strong> resources in discrete areas, foraging communities are small in size (<strong>the</strong> sum, at most, <strong>of</strong> a fewextended families). 17 They are also internally equal. Economic differences within b<strong>and</strong>s are ei<strong>the</strong>r15 Ma<strong>the</strong>matically, i will choose to follow an <strong>of</strong>fensive strategy if:( 1 − λ θ ˆ + λ θ − λ θ ˆO ) Ai( / O ) (1 / D ) Ai>1 − δ1 − δSimplifying <strong>the</strong> expression shows that <strong>the</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> holds if:λ λ λ> ( − )Âiθ θ θThis will happen as ei<strong>the</strong>r  i becomes closer to ) or θ O approaches θ D (which in turns makes <strong>the</strong>expression in <strong>the</strong> paren<strong>the</strong>sis close to 0).16 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent to which current ethnographic evidence may be employed to makeinferences about past foraging communities, see Headl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Reid (1989) <strong>and</strong> O’Connell, Hwakes <strong>and</strong>Jones (1988).17 Northwest pacific communities were also characterized by <strong>the</strong> construction <strong>and</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong>sophisticated equipment, such as complex fish traps, which involved considerable labor (Rowley-Conwy2001).OOD19


absent or very limited. Food <strong>and</strong>, particularly, meat distribution is strictly egalitarian (except, insome communities, for very large preys) (Hawkes 2000). Differences in nutrition over <strong>the</strong> life cycleare minimal (at least within each gender) (Kelly 1995). Success in hunting is tracked by everyone(Hawkes 2000) <strong>and</strong> some social recognition is granted to <strong>the</strong> good hunter (Turnbull 1965; Kaplan &Hill 1985). But foraging communities have strict social norms that prevent <strong>the</strong> hunter from owning<strong>the</strong> meat he has hunted <strong>and</strong> status recognition is extremely transient (Weissner 1996, Erdal <strong>and</strong>Whitten 1994). Individual success seems to lead at most to easier access to a few goods such assexual partners. However, <strong>the</strong>re is too much variability in hunting performance over <strong>the</strong> medium runto lead to permanent social distinctions (Hawkes 2000). According to recent work comparing 21foraging, pastoralist <strong>and</strong> agricultural communities, <strong>inequality</strong> is extremely low among foragersexcept for embodied wealth (measured in terms <strong>of</strong> physical strength, hunting skills, etc.) (Smith et al.2010). The intergenerational transmission <strong>of</strong> wealth is also low except for traits that can be explainedin strict genetic terms. To <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong>re is some correlation in genetic endowment acrossgenerations, it does not come from more <strong>and</strong> better nutrition provided to <strong>the</strong> children <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> bestendowed parents but ra<strong>the</strong>r from matching between good hunters <strong>and</strong> more hardworking women(Hawkes 2000). The existing archaeological evidence for Paleolithic sites seems to confirm similarpatterns <strong>of</strong> nutritional equality <strong>and</strong> little material differentiation (Formicola 2007; Vanhaeren &D’Errico 2005).Simple foraging societies lack any clear, stable authority structure <strong>and</strong> certainly no stableorganization (or group <strong>of</strong> individuals) holding <strong>the</strong> monopoly <strong>of</strong> violence in a given territory.Decisions affecting <strong>the</strong> b<strong>and</strong> are arrived at through discussion in which all adults participate(Turney-High [1971]: 61-73; Silberbauer 1982). Even when <strong>the</strong>re are some patterns <strong>of</strong> leadership,leaders have no formal authority <strong>and</strong> act as mere referees among different individuals or families orspend substantial time negotiating with, cajoling or persuading o<strong>the</strong>r members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> tribe (Clastres1972; Lee <strong>and</strong> Leacock 1982; Lee 1982). And although threats <strong>and</strong> actual violence are certainlyemployed within <strong>the</strong> tribe, <strong>the</strong>y happen in a sporadic or at least non-institutionalized manner20


(Clastres 1972, 1974; Kelly 2000). In short, <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>and</strong> underlying dynamics <strong>of</strong> foragingsocieties match <strong>the</strong> model in section 1. A pattern <strong>of</strong> relative equality in foraging groups underpins<strong>the</strong> outcome <strong>of</strong> “spontaneous” social cooperation within each tribe or, to employ Clastres’ terms, <strong>the</strong>outcome <strong>of</strong> “non-<strong>state</strong> politics”.Equality is <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> a particular (uniform) distribution <strong>of</strong> resources in <strong>the</strong> environment(in conjunction with a specific technology <strong>of</strong> production). But <strong>the</strong> outcome <strong>of</strong> social cooperation is<strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> systematic, deliberate <strong>and</strong> painstaking efforts directed at maintaining peace amongindividuals. At <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> day, <strong>the</strong> production equilibrium is just one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two equilibria thatmay take place in <strong>the</strong> repeated PD game discussed in part 1. Violence, looting <strong>and</strong> exploitation canerupt at any time, with catastrophic consequences for everyone, especially given <strong>the</strong> constraintsimposed by a ra<strong>the</strong>r harsh ecological environment. Hence pre-<strong>state</strong> communities need to spendconsiderable efforts at equalizing material outcomes <strong>and</strong> social status across individuals.The “creation” (or maintenance) <strong>of</strong> equality in pre-<strong>state</strong> communities does not result fromhaving a shared ideology accepted <strong>and</strong> followed out <strong>of</strong> idealistic convictions. It has none <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>romantic qualities imagined by Marx <strong>and</strong> Engels in <strong>the</strong>ir depiction <strong>of</strong> primitive communism or laterattributed to foragers by a certain anthropological tradition. It is simply <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “behavior <strong>of</strong>sociable <strong>and</strong> self-interested individuals whose motivations include a strong desire to get enough for<strong>the</strong>mselves coupled with a strong desire to make sure that no one else gets more than <strong>the</strong>y do” (Erdal& Whiten 1994: 177). In fact, <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> food is <strong>of</strong>ten conflictual, involving arguments,yelling <strong>and</strong> clear signs <strong>of</strong> jealousy <strong>and</strong> envy. Any individual deviation from <strong>the</strong> mean is quicklynoticed <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n hammered out through mocking, pleading <strong>and</strong> shaming. Writing about <strong>the</strong> San,Wiessner notes that “[it cannot] be argued that !Kung have little interest in material possessions.Most possessions … are highly desired; <strong>and</strong> many !Kung are really torn between <strong>the</strong> desire toaccumulate goods <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> desire to remain within a secure system <strong>of</strong> mutual help.” Hence,individuals may work hard <strong>and</strong> even try to accumulate some material possessions only to “comeunder more <strong>and</strong> more pressure to give <strong>the</strong>m away in hxaro, <strong>and</strong> finally give in <strong>and</strong> redistribute <strong>the</strong>m”21


(1982: 81-82). Similarly, hunting parties are followed by an elaborate set <strong>of</strong> practices directed atleveling down <strong>the</strong> successful hunter. The latter rejoins <strong>the</strong> b<strong>and</strong> announcing <strong>the</strong> yield <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> huntmodestly, almost in a hush. His entry is <strong>the</strong>n followed by <strong>the</strong> systematic efforts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> b<strong>and</strong> to“downplay his merits” through teasing <strong>and</strong> mocking, to stress <strong>the</strong> r<strong>and</strong>omness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> success, <strong>and</strong> to“emphasize his duty to provide meat for o<strong>the</strong>rs” (Wiessner 1996: 179). 18 Across all simple societies,from <strong>the</strong> Inuit Eskimos to <strong>the</strong> !Kung in <strong>the</strong> Kalahari, <strong>the</strong> ideology <strong>and</strong> practice <strong>of</strong> equality turnsaround denouncing <strong>and</strong> avoiding two capital sins: stinginess, that is, “to hoard one’s goods jealously<strong>and</strong> secretively, guarding <strong>the</strong>m ‘like a hyena’” (Lee 1982: 52); <strong>and</strong> arrogance, which “is actuallydangerous, since according to <strong>the</strong> !Kung ‘[someone’s] pride will make him kill someone” (Lee 1982:54)Maintaining equality implies exercising an inordinate level <strong>of</strong> psychological repression uponeach <strong>and</strong> every member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> community. As stressed before, <strong>the</strong> suppression <strong>of</strong> individualdifferences is <strong>of</strong>ten done very openly: by <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> constant deprecation toward oneself, byemploying a piercing irony toward o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>and</strong> by constantly begging <strong>the</strong> more successful membersto engage in <strong>the</strong> proper behavior <strong>of</strong> sharing (or what someone has labeled “institutionalizedstealing”). But in some communities repression is above all about structuring <strong>the</strong> inner motivations<strong>of</strong> every member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> group: although relationships between parents <strong>and</strong> children are hardlyauthoritarian <strong>and</strong> although <strong>the</strong> latter normally enjoy a very playful infancy, children are brought upin <strong>the</strong> expectation that <strong>the</strong>y will uphold <strong>the</strong> tight social norms <strong>of</strong> equality <strong>and</strong> conformity in place.Accordingly, as Briggs writes about <strong>the</strong> Inuits, “in a society in which <strong>the</strong> expression <strong>of</strong> hostility isvery stringently controlled (…), it is more than likely that people project <strong>the</strong>ir own suppressedhostility onto o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>and</strong>, knowing that <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>mselves feel violent, will easily suspect o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>of</strong>murderous intents” (1982: 116).18 Similarly, Lee (1984) for <strong>the</strong> !Kung, Woodburn (1982: 440) on <strong>the</strong> Hadza, Hararo (1981: 536) on <strong>the</strong>Mbuti, Clastres (1972) on <strong>the</strong> Ache, Lothrop (1928: 422) on <strong>the</strong> Ona, Balicki (19xx: chapter 9) onEskimos.22


Those societies, characterized by repressed fear <strong>and</strong> constant suspicion, witness unexpectedexplosions <strong>of</strong> individual anger, resulting from ra<strong>the</strong>r trivial, almost childish disputes with a marked“noninstrumental manner” (Knaupf 1991: 400). According to <strong>the</strong> existing anthropological research,violence is unrelated to any struggle for material goods or political control. In turn, male competitionfor females only explains part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conflict <strong>and</strong> with different success across groups. In addition toindividual disputes <strong>and</strong> killings, <strong>the</strong>re is considerable collective violence: individuals deemed todeviate from <strong>the</strong> boundaries <strong>of</strong> appropriate behavior are prone to accusations <strong>of</strong> black magic <strong>and</strong>witchcraft <strong>and</strong> to some kind <strong>of</strong> socially sanctioned execution (Knauft 1987, 1991). Violent deathsare, as a result, extremely high in pre-<strong>state</strong> societies. The annual homicide rate, which st<strong>and</strong>s ataround 20 to 30 individuals per 100,000 in American inner cities, has been estimated to approacharound 300 individuals per 100,000 among Agta Pygmies <strong>and</strong> over 400 per 100,000 among <strong>the</strong>Copper Eskimo <strong>and</strong> Papua-New Guinea’s Gebusi (Knauft 1987; Headl<strong>and</strong> 1989; Gat 1999). About25 percent <strong>of</strong> adult males die from a violent death on average in foraging societies. That proportionmatches <strong>the</strong> percentage <strong>of</strong> buried skeletal remains from <strong>the</strong> Paleolithic showing traces <strong>of</strong> violence(Kelly 2000; 155).None<strong>the</strong>less, that level <strong>of</strong> lethal conflict does not jeopardize social stability. Homicidescommitted by a single individual remain largely constrained. They never escalate into a generalconflict pitting one family against <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r in <strong>the</strong> social group. 19 As Balikci (1970: 182) points outin his study on <strong>the</strong> Netsilik Eskimos, because “every murder signified <strong>the</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> a highly neededseal hunter”, <strong>the</strong> community always intervened to stop any revenge that could lead to a chain19 Homicides (committed to revenge a previous crime) are hardly interpreted as an injury to a wholegroup <strong>and</strong> do not generally lead to <strong>the</strong> collapse <strong>of</strong> social interaction within a given human b<strong>and</strong>. Inforaging communities, “when felt anger or ill-feeling is expressed in interpersonal violence, <strong>the</strong>expressive action typically runs its course (…) <strong>and</strong> may actually culminate in murder. However, <strong>the</strong>violence that occurs is specific, not generalized, <strong>and</strong> it does not escalate beyond a sequence <strong>of</strong> events thatencompasses homicide followed by execution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> killer. Typically, a murder is an isolated event withno sequel” (Kelly 2000: 42-43).23


eaction. If generalized violence becomes unavoidable, most foraging b<strong>and</strong>s manage it through aprocess <strong>of</strong> fission: a section <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> group secedes <strong>and</strong> migrates to a new location, where it selforganizesagain along <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard patterns <strong>of</strong> relative equality <strong>and</strong> non-institutionalized politics. 20Transition to AgricultureThe domestication <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>and</strong> plants about 11,000 years ago put an end to a world solelypopulated with foraging communities. The invention <strong>of</strong> agriculture had two effects. It increased l<strong>and</strong>productivity: whereas a family <strong>of</strong> hunters <strong>and</strong> ga<strong>the</strong>rers may need several square miles to survive, ahousehold <strong>of</strong> irrigation agriculturalists may live with less than one hectare (Bellwood 2005: 14-19).It raised l<strong>and</strong> productivity in a non-uniform manner across territories, generating a pattern <strong>of</strong><strong>inequality</strong> across individuals <strong>and</strong> human communities (<strong>and</strong> probably within human groups also): asagriculture spread out, initially homogeneous regions (enjoying <strong>the</strong> same marginal productivity ashunting areas) acquired a differentiated resource gradient ranging from a ‘core’ <strong>of</strong> rich l<strong>and</strong>s to a‘periphery’ <strong>of</strong> very marginal quality.The causes behind <strong>the</strong> adoption <strong>of</strong> agriculture have been thoroughly debated amongscholars. A first str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature explains <strong>the</strong> domestication <strong>of</strong> plants <strong>and</strong> animals as aresponse to <strong>the</strong> declining marginal productivity <strong>of</strong> hunting <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> related Malthusian constraintsfaced by growing populations <strong>of</strong> hunters <strong>and</strong> ga<strong>the</strong>rers (Flannery 1965; Binford 1968; Cohen 1977).A second set <strong>of</strong> researchers interprets agriculture as a technological improvement that happened as aresult <strong>of</strong> a long process <strong>of</strong> learning (Rindos 1980). A third line <strong>of</strong> research traces it back to amomentous change in cultural norms among foraging societies (Bender 1978). 21 Regardless <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ultimate causes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> agricultural revolution, it is obvious that <strong>the</strong> transition to agriculture could20 For an analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> exit option in <strong>the</strong> hortoculturalist society <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Yanomanos, see Chagnon (1997).For a broader conceptual analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> strong exit options on income distribution <strong>and</strong> politicalstructures, see Hirschman (1981), chapter 10.21 For general reviews, see Watson (1995), Bar-Yosef <strong>and</strong> Meadow (1995), Bellwood (2005), Barker(2006).24


have only taken place in those areas that were characterized by quite precise geographical,environmental <strong>and</strong> climatic conditions. As pointed out by Diamond (1997), <strong>the</strong> agriculturalrevolution materialized in those regions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world that had enough plants <strong>and</strong> animals suitable fordomestication <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> proper climate to exploit those species.Partly building upon seminal empirical work by Hibbs <strong>and</strong> Olsson (2004) <strong>and</strong> Olsson <strong>and</strong>Hibbs (2005), Table 1 shows that most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> variation in <strong>the</strong> time at which different parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>world transited to agriculture was indeed related to <strong>the</strong> set <strong>of</strong> biological <strong>and</strong> geographical conditions<strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> those areas. That result implies that <strong>the</strong> causes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> transition that led to <strong>the</strong> social <strong>and</strong>political consequences (<strong>inequality</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>formation</strong>) formalized in Section 1 were exogenous tothose outcomes.The estimations in Table 1 are <strong>of</strong> two kinds. Models 1 through 3 examine <strong>the</strong> impact <strong>of</strong> strictgeographical conditions on <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> domesticable plants <strong>and</strong> animals across <strong>the</strong> world. Models4 <strong>and</strong> 5 estimate <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> those same geographical conditions on <strong>the</strong> years it took eachgeographical unit to transit to agriculture. The units <strong>of</strong> analysis are <strong>the</strong> geographical quadrantsdefined by 10 degrees in latitude <strong>and</strong> longitude (starting at <strong>the</strong> intersection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Equator with <strong>the</strong>Greenwhich meridian) for which <strong>the</strong>re is some l<strong>and</strong> mass. There are 234 such observations – 203 ifwe exclude <strong>the</strong> Antarctica. 22 The number <strong>of</strong> species suitable for domestication are taken from Olsson<strong>and</strong> Hibbs (2005) <strong>and</strong> come for ten separate regions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. 23 The number <strong>of</strong> domesticableanimals ranges from 9 in <strong>the</strong> Middle East to 0 in Icel<strong>and</strong>. The number <strong>of</strong> plants goes from 33 to 0.The years to agriculture are <strong>the</strong> years it took agriculture to appear since <strong>the</strong> beginning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Holocene (9,500 BC). 24 The data is built employing <strong>the</strong> in<strong>formation</strong> ga<strong>the</strong>red in <strong>the</strong> surveys written22 In <strong>the</strong> Olsson-Hibbs work, <strong>the</strong> unit <strong>of</strong> observation is <strong>the</strong> contemporary <strong>state</strong>.23 Those regions are: Near East-Europe-North Africa, East Asia, Sou<strong>the</strong>ast Asia, Sub-Saharan Africa,North America, Central America, South America, Australia, Pacific Isl<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Icel<strong>and</strong>.24 For a discussion on whe<strong>the</strong>r to code <strong>the</strong> <strong>origins</strong> <strong>of</strong> agriculture following ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> first evidence <strong>of</strong>plant (<strong>and</strong> animal) domestication or <strong>the</strong> moment at which horticultural practices give way to intensiveagriculture, see Shenk et al. (2010) <strong>and</strong> Thurston <strong>and</strong> Fischer (2007).25


y Bellwood (2005) <strong>and</strong> Parker (2006). For those areas where agriculture has yet to develop I assigna value <strong>of</strong> 11,500 years (9,500 plus 2,000 years).The geographical conditions are measured through four variables:1. Climate, measured following Köppen’s system <strong>of</strong> climatic classification <strong>and</strong> ranging from1 (worst climate for agriculture) to 4 (Mediterranean <strong>and</strong> West Coast climate). I code each unit <strong>of</strong>observation by looking at <strong>the</strong> geometrical center <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> quadrant. 252. Latitude <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> geometrical center <strong>of</strong> each observation. I also add <strong>the</strong> square <strong>of</strong> latitude tocapture any potential non-linearities in <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> latitude.3. Major axis <strong>of</strong> continent, that is, longitudinal degrees between <strong>the</strong> extreme eastern <strong>and</strong>western points <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> continent divided by <strong>the</strong> distance in latitudinal degrees between <strong>the</strong> extremenor<strong>the</strong>rn <strong>and</strong> sou<strong>the</strong>rn points <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> continent. The axis ratio goes from 0.1 (in <strong>the</strong> Pacific Ocean) to3 (for Asia).4. Isl<strong>and</strong>, that is, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> unit <strong>of</strong> observation (or most <strong>of</strong> it) belongs to an isl<strong>and</strong> or not.Both climate <strong>and</strong> latitude approximate <strong>the</strong> environmental conditions most favorable toagriculture. The axis ratio measures <strong>the</strong> fact that, as emphasized in Diamond (1997), a predominantEast-West orientation speeds up <strong>the</strong> diffusion <strong>of</strong> agricultural techniques within continents since newagriculturalists do not need to modify <strong>the</strong> received plants to new climatic conditions. The dummyisl<strong>and</strong> is a second proxy to tap <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> oceans as barriers to <strong>the</strong> adoption <strong>of</strong> agriculture.[Table 1 about here]The geographical variables <strong>of</strong> climate, axis <strong>and</strong> isl<strong>and</strong> are statistically significant, behave in<strong>the</strong> expected direction <strong>and</strong> toge<strong>the</strong>r explain about 55 percent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> variance in <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong>animals (Model 1), plants (Model 2) <strong>and</strong> a composite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two (Model 3). A one-point shift in <strong>the</strong>25 The coding is as follows: 1 for tundra <strong>and</strong> ice (climates <strong>of</strong> type E in Köppen’s classification), drytropical climates (climates <strong>of</strong> type B) <strong>and</strong> subarctic climates (Dc <strong>and</strong> Dd in Köppen’s); 2 for wet tropical(climates <strong>of</strong> type A); 3 for temperate humid subtropical <strong>and</strong> continental areas (types Caf, Caw, Da <strong>and</strong> Dbin Köppen’s system); <strong>and</strong> 4 for dry hot summers <strong>and</strong> wet winters (types Cb, Cc <strong>and</strong> Cs).26


climate variable changes <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> animals by 0.5 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> total <strong>of</strong> plants by 1.5. The axis ratiohas a strong impact on <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> species that can be domesticated: <strong>the</strong> maximum value <strong>of</strong> 3implies about 11 animals <strong>and</strong> 24 plants. Being an isl<strong>and</strong> reduces <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> domesticable plants<strong>and</strong> animals by 3 <strong>and</strong> 10 respectively. Finally, latitude has some effect on <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> plants.Models 4 <strong>and</strong> 5 report <strong>the</strong> impact <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> environmental conditions on <strong>the</strong> time to agriculture– with Model 5 excluding <strong>the</strong> cases <strong>of</strong> Antarctica. All <strong>the</strong> variables are strongly significant <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> r-squared is 0.54. A shift in <strong>the</strong> climate index from <strong>the</strong> worst to <strong>the</strong> best conditions leads to <strong>the</strong>introduction <strong>of</strong> agriculture 2,800 years earlier. The size <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> coefficients for axis ratio <strong>and</strong> isl<strong>and</strong>underscore, in turn, <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> geographical barriers to explain <strong>the</strong> agricultural revolution. Allo<strong>the</strong>r thing equal, agriculture spread 2,000 to 2,500 years earlier in Asia than in America. The seadelayed <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> diffusion by 1,500 to 2,250 years. Figure 1 displays <strong>the</strong> correlation between<strong>the</strong> time at each agriculture was introduced <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> composite index <strong>of</strong> biogeographical conditions(<strong>the</strong> abbreviations correspond to <strong>the</strong> contemporary country that matches <strong>the</strong> geometrical median <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> area <strong>and</strong> so <strong>the</strong>re could be more than one observation represented by <strong>the</strong> same abbreviation). 26[Figure 1 about here]State FormationThe process <strong>of</strong> economic differentiation <strong>of</strong> individuals <strong>and</strong> territories (due to a biasedtechnological shock such as <strong>the</strong> agricultural revolution or <strong>the</strong> occupation <strong>of</strong> new l<strong>and</strong>s) is a necessarybut not sufficient condition for <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s. The introduction <strong>of</strong> political institutionsdepends on <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> some permanent military structures, ei<strong>the</strong>r directly by <strong>the</strong> ‘naturalproducers’ or provided by a ‘condottiero’ or pacified b<strong>and</strong>it. In turn, to set up those structures, thatis, to establish some kind <strong>of</strong> political hierarchy, <strong>the</strong> technologies <strong>of</strong> war must grow in <strong>the</strong>ir degree <strong>of</strong>sophistication: if all individuals have equal access to very simple weapons (such as rocks <strong>and</strong> sticks),26 The index is an equally weighted average <strong>of</strong> climate, latitude, axis <strong>and</strong> isl<strong>and</strong> (set at <strong>the</strong>ir relativevalues with respect to <strong>the</strong> maximum value in each variable).27


<strong>the</strong>y have no incentives ei<strong>the</strong>r to associate toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> spend some time in military training or toaccept <strong>the</strong> tyranny <strong>of</strong> a b<strong>and</strong>it.According to <strong>the</strong> existing archaeological research, political institutions emerged after (<strong>and</strong>never before) <strong>the</strong> transition to agriculture (cf. Thurston <strong>and</strong> Fischer, ed. 2007, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> chapters<strong>the</strong>rein). In <strong>the</strong> most investigated region where agriculture appeared independently, <strong>the</strong> Middle East,<strong>the</strong>re were several villages with an estimated population in each one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m <strong>of</strong> three to fourthous<strong>and</strong> inhabitants in <strong>the</strong> sou<strong>the</strong>rn Levant already in <strong>the</strong> seventh millennium before Christ (Kuijt2000). Although <strong>the</strong>re are some traces <strong>of</strong> labor specialization, most studies agree that householdswere <strong>the</strong> basic economic units in <strong>the</strong> agricultural Neolithic <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y were “homogeneous withregard to wealth <strong>and</strong> status” (Voigt 1990: 7). The existing non-domestic structures, such as <strong>the</strong>defensive walls <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> temple shrine <strong>of</strong> Jericho, from about 6,500 BC (Yadin 1963, Finer 1997),point to <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> some collective authority. But <strong>the</strong>y do not appear to embody any statusdifferentiation (Monahan 2007).The first <strong>and</strong> more systematic historical records attesting <strong>the</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s (<strong>and</strong> a muchmore hierarchical political structure) only appeared later in time, at around 3,200 BC, that is, a fewthous<strong>and</strong> years after <strong>the</strong> domestication <strong>of</strong> plants <strong>and</strong> animals, mainly because writing was onlyinvented at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fourth millennium before Christ. As discussed later, it is not coincidentalthat <strong>the</strong>y appear with <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> metals to build weapons. All <strong>the</strong> first documented <strong>state</strong>s invariablyformed in areas that had first transited to agriculture. At <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fourth millennium BC <strong>the</strong>rewere a few city <strong>state</strong>s, with several thous<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> inhabitants, a centralized political authority <strong>and</strong>fortified walls, in sou<strong>the</strong>rn Mesopotamia. Egypt became unified under a single monarch at around3,000 BC. By <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third millennium several palaces were built in Crete, spawning <strong>the</strong>Minoan civilization. A few hundred years later continental Greece witnessed <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong>several monarchies within what has been called <strong>the</strong> Mycenaean civilization. The Harrapan culture,with large urban agglomerations <strong>and</strong> fortified structures, flourished in <strong>the</strong> Indus valley in <strong>the</strong> middle<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third millennium BC. The first firm evidence <strong>of</strong> a <strong>state</strong> structure in East Asia has been put at28


around 1,850 BC with <strong>the</strong> Shang dynasty governing nor<strong>the</strong>astern China. In America, urbansettlements <strong>and</strong> <strong>state</strong> structures developed in <strong>the</strong> two main cradles <strong>of</strong> agriculture: in Mesoamericaabout two thous<strong>and</strong> years ago <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Andean area around AD 500-700 or perhaps earlier.[Figure 2 here]More systematically, Figure 2 explores <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong> spread <strong>of</strong> agriculture(horizontal axis) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> institutions (vertical axis) in all <strong>the</strong> geographicalquadrants <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world (as defined earlier). A <strong>state</strong> is defined by <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> a specializedorganization with <strong>the</strong> quasi-monopoly <strong>of</strong> coercion over a well defined territory. I code an area ashaving a <strong>state</strong> if <strong>the</strong>re are contemporary writing materials that report <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> those structuresor if, absent writing records, <strong>the</strong>re are sufficiently large fortified structures that point to <strong>the</strong> existence<strong>of</strong> armies <strong>and</strong> <strong>state</strong>s. I employ <strong>the</strong> in<strong>formation</strong> provided in Kinder <strong>and</strong> Hilgeman (1974), Mann(1986) <strong>and</strong> Finer (1997) <strong>and</strong> several regional histories to date <strong>the</strong> approximate century at whichpolitical institutions formed. In coding <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s I take a conservative approach: forexample I date <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s at around 3,000 BC in Mesopotamia <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Near East (whenwriting records appear for <strong>the</strong> first time) even though Jericho seemed to have had some fortifiedstructures a few thous<strong>and</strong> years earlier. Pacific isl<strong>and</strong>s are not coded because it is unclear whe<strong>the</strong>r(<strong>and</strong> when) complex tribal chiefdoms were born before Europeans explored that area.Figure 2 reveals two main empirical patterns. First, <strong>the</strong> transition to agriculture alwayspreceded ra<strong>the</strong>r than followed <strong>the</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s. Second, <strong>state</strong>s came into being with a temporallag with respect to agriculture. This temporal gap, which shrank over time, must be related to tw<strong>of</strong>acts: first, <strong>the</strong> dissemination <strong>of</strong> intensive agriculture (at around 4,100-4,000 BC according to[Barker 2006]); second, a shift in military technology. Until <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fourth millennium, menemployed stone, a material that was too cheap <strong>and</strong> easily available to give any strong advantage toany <strong>of</strong> its users, to build weapons. The introduction <strong>of</strong> copper helmets <strong>and</strong> swords revolutionized <strong>the</strong>dynamics <strong>of</strong> war – it certainly coincided with <strong>the</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first Mesopotamian city-<strong>state</strong>s. Afew hundred years later, <strong>the</strong> invention <strong>of</strong> bronze, an alloy <strong>of</strong> common copper <strong>and</strong> tin, exacerbated29


those trends toward more military specialization (<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> creation <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s) for two reasons: <strong>the</strong>hardiness <strong>of</strong> bronze gave a considerable military advantage to its users; <strong>the</strong> scarcity <strong>of</strong> tin <strong>and</strong> itsvery localized sources “made it a substance on which it was easy to levy high market prices <strong>and</strong>heavy transport tolls <strong>and</strong> taxes at <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong> delivery” (Keegan 2004: 238), fur<strong>the</strong>r fostering thatprocess <strong>of</strong> concentration <strong>of</strong> military might among certain strata.[Table 2 here]Table 2, which estimates <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong> transition to agriculture <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s, confirms <strong>the</strong> previous discussion. Models 1 <strong>and</strong> 2 estimate <strong>the</strong> impact <strong>of</strong>biogeographical conditions on <strong>the</strong> birth <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s, with <strong>and</strong> without Antarctica respectively. All <strong>the</strong>variables are strongly significant <strong>and</strong> operate as expected. Models 3 <strong>and</strong> 4 examine <strong>the</strong> relationshipbetween year <strong>of</strong> transition to agriculture <strong>and</strong> year <strong>of</strong> birth <strong>of</strong> political institutions (again with <strong>and</strong>without Antarctica). The relationship is extremely strong with <strong>and</strong> r 2 around 0.6. Since one can claimthat diffusion effects may be important <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> <strong>formation</strong>, Model 5 simply looks at thosecases where political institutions formed ‘originally’ in each area. The explained variance is about<strong>the</strong> same.Violence <strong>and</strong> Population MigrationsBesides linking <strong>the</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s to <strong>the</strong> agricultural revolution (<strong>and</strong> militarytechnologies), <strong>the</strong> model in Section 1 sheds light on <strong>the</strong> <strong>origins</strong> <strong>and</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> violence, with <strong>the</strong>poor, non-agricultural populations looting <strong>the</strong> technologically advanced, sedentary societies thatemerged after <strong>the</strong> domestication <strong>of</strong> plants <strong>and</strong> animals. That prediction turns out to be a very strongregularity in human history. Populations in peripheral, less rich l<strong>and</strong>s have tended to breed muchmore war-prone populations than fertile l<strong>and</strong>s. Ancient Mesopotamia <strong>and</strong> Egypt, <strong>the</strong> first centers <strong>of</strong>agriculture in <strong>the</strong> Middle East, withstood successive waves <strong>of</strong> invaders originating in <strong>the</strong> Caucasus<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Asian steppes such as <strong>the</strong> Hurrians in <strong>the</strong> third millennium <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Hyksos in <strong>the</strong> late secondmillennium. The Roman Empire fell under <strong>the</strong> pressure <strong>of</strong> Germanic tribes. Medieval Europe30


endured <strong>the</strong> attacks <strong>of</strong> periphery populations such as <strong>the</strong> Vikings, Slavs, Turks <strong>and</strong> Mongols.Similarly, China was raided <strong>and</strong> at times governed by several steppe tribes. In Mexico <strong>and</strong> CentralAmerica, once-periphery groups such as <strong>the</strong> Aztecs came to dominate <strong>the</strong> core l<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> region.Military Technology <strong>and</strong> Type <strong>of</strong> Political InstitutionsAs discussed in Section 1, <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>, ranging from a ‘self-governing’ or republicanconstitution to a monarchical or dictatorial regime, depends crucially on <strong>the</strong> efficiency θ D with which<strong>the</strong> producers can defend <strong>the</strong>mselves against potential looters. 27 To examine <strong>the</strong> impact <strong>of</strong> warmaking on <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong> institutions, I now look at <strong>the</strong> political consequences <strong>of</strong> what have beenconsidered five key technological innovations in military weaponry: bronze weapons, <strong>the</strong> horsechariot, <strong>the</strong> invention <strong>of</strong> iron, <strong>the</strong> stirrup <strong>and</strong> firepower arms. 28As already mentioned before, <strong>the</strong> introduction <strong>of</strong> bronze helmets, swords <strong>and</strong> ax sockets at<strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third millennium B.C. led to <strong>the</strong> collapse <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Mesopotamian city-<strong>state</strong>s <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong><strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first big monarchical <strong>state</strong>s in <strong>the</strong> Middle East – Sargon <strong>of</strong> Akkad, for example,27 In addition to <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong> war technology, <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> self-defense for producers may be affected by <strong>the</strong>levels <strong>of</strong> competition among looters. A b<strong>and</strong>it-lord who has to fend <strong>of</strong>f <strong>the</strong> assault <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r agents <strong>of</strong> hissame type will have fewer resources left to enslave o<strong>the</strong>r communities <strong>of</strong> producers. As emphasized byHansen (2000), many (if not most) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thirty city-<strong>state</strong> systems that he has identified emerged in <strong>the</strong>margins <strong>of</strong> empires or kingdoms with insufficient means to exercise complete control over <strong>the</strong>ir nominalterritories. For example, after <strong>the</strong> collapse <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Carolingian empire, <strong>the</strong> exercise <strong>of</strong> political authoritywas substantially weak in <strong>the</strong> decentralized areas <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Lotharingia: that may explain why Europeancities emerged mostly in <strong>the</strong> axis Fl<strong>and</strong>ers-North Italy already in <strong>the</strong> early Middle Ages (Dhondt 1976).28 Although <strong>the</strong>se technological innovations do not exhaust <strong>the</strong> list <strong>of</strong> invented weapons (since <strong>the</strong>re areo<strong>the</strong>r tools such as <strong>the</strong> bow, fortifications, etc.), <strong>the</strong>y are arguably <strong>the</strong> most important in military history(Andreski 1968, Keegan 2004). Besides any strictly technological innovations, <strong>the</strong>re have beenconsiderable organizational <strong>and</strong> strategic changes in war making. I do not consider <strong>the</strong>m directly forseveral reasons: <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>of</strong>ten linked to technological changes (for example, <strong>the</strong> hegemony <strong>of</strong> cavalry isdirectly related to <strong>the</strong> introduction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> stirrup); <strong>the</strong>y are harder to trace <strong>and</strong> more volatile in nature(with some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m related to <strong>the</strong> military creativity <strong>of</strong> a particular general); <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y are arguably lessexogenous to politics than pure technological changes.31


controlled an empire <strong>of</strong> roughly <strong>the</strong> size <strong>of</strong> modern Iraq. The predominant use <strong>of</strong> bronze weaponswas associated with a sharp division between a warrior aristocracy <strong>and</strong> a peasant class in AncientGreece (Andreski 1968: 43-44).The introduction <strong>of</strong> two-wheeled horse chariots probably had an even stronger impact on <strong>the</strong>kind <strong>of</strong> political institutions. The invention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> spoked wheel <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> light chariot bodies combinedwith <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> fast horses (in place <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> former onagers) radically altered war making at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> second millennium B.C. The speed <strong>of</strong> transportation was multiplied by ten to about 20 miles perhour. Military effectiveness at <strong>the</strong> battle camp also increased extraordinarily. Since a single chariotcrew (one driver <strong>and</strong> one archer) could kill about six men a minute circling at a distance <strong>of</strong> 100 to200 yards, ten chariots (or twenty men) could cause over half a thous<strong>and</strong> casualties in about tenminutes. The pastoralist peoples in <strong>the</strong> margins <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Eurasian steppes were <strong>the</strong> first to employ <strong>the</strong>horse chariot – <strong>the</strong>y could easily apply all <strong>the</strong>ir riding <strong>and</strong> hunting skills to <strong>the</strong>se new technologies <strong>of</strong>war (Keegan 2004: 159-66). Attracted by <strong>the</strong> much richer agricultural l<strong>and</strong>s to <strong>the</strong> South (<strong>and</strong> East),<strong>the</strong>y launched successive waves <strong>of</strong> attack: <strong>the</strong> Hyksos penetrated Egypt, <strong>the</strong> Hurrians <strong>and</strong> Kassitesentered Mesopotamia, <strong>the</strong> Aryans conquered India <strong>and</strong> certain tribes originating in <strong>the</strong> proto-Iranianheartl<strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Altai established China’s Shang dynasty. The success <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> chariot peoples wasgenerally short-lived: <strong>the</strong> Assyrian <strong>and</strong> Egyptian elites copied <strong>the</strong>ir war strategies <strong>and</strong> restored <strong>the</strong>ircontrol over <strong>the</strong>ir own l<strong>and</strong>s. But <strong>the</strong> horse chariot led to <strong>the</strong> consolidation <strong>of</strong> a set <strong>of</strong> ‘feudal’ <strong>state</strong>swith a narrow aristocracy <strong>of</strong> warriors exercising full control over <strong>the</strong>ir subjects (McNeill 1982). TheOld Testament provides us with direct, written in<strong>formation</strong> on this trans<strong>formation</strong> in Israel. During<strong>the</strong> period <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Judges, Israel’s army was essentially a militia “made up <strong>of</strong> warriors from individualtribes who were summoned to battle only in emergency” (Yadin 1963: 255) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> internalorganization <strong>and</strong> equipment <strong>of</strong> each tribal unit remained in <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> each clan. In response to <strong>the</strong>attacks <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> peoples <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sea, David <strong>and</strong> his descendants pr<strong>of</strong>essionalized its army, introducing aregular army <strong>and</strong> a body <strong>of</strong> heavily armed charioteers, <strong>and</strong> effectively constructing a centralizedmonarchy in <strong>the</strong> process.32


Whereas <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> bronze weapons <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> horse chariot reduced θ D or <strong>the</strong> militaryeffectiveness <strong>of</strong> producers, <strong>the</strong> discovery <strong>of</strong> how to make weapons out <strong>of</strong> iron allowed a “relativelylarge proportion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> male population [to] acquire metal arms <strong>and</strong> armor” (McNeill 1982:12),mostly because <strong>the</strong>re is a large supply <strong>of</strong> iron ores in <strong>the</strong> world (about 4 percent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> earth mass isiron ores). Although with some lag, this led to relatively more egalitarian political <strong>and</strong> socialstructures. After <strong>the</strong> expulsion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Etruscan kings, iron cheapened <strong>the</strong> access to arms, madeinfantry central in war <strong>and</strong> secured <strong>the</strong> political ascendancy <strong>of</strong> Roman rural strata – to <strong>the</strong> point thatonly those who were too poor to equip <strong>the</strong>mselves for military service were practically deprived <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> vote” (Andreski 1968: 54). 29 In Greece, where <strong>the</strong> irregularity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> terrain (<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong>crops) made <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> chariots ra<strong>the</strong>r ineffective [check Victor Hanson], <strong>the</strong> spread <strong>of</strong> iron weaponsbroke <strong>the</strong> hegemony <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> bronze-wielding aristocracy <strong>and</strong> equalized conditions. As pointed byAristotle in his Politics, “where <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> country can admit a great number <strong>of</strong> horse, <strong>the</strong>re apowerful oligarchy may be easily established”, “where <strong>the</strong> troops are chiefly heavy-armed, <strong>the</strong>re anoligarchy, inferior in power to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r [<strong>the</strong> calvary-dominated one] may be established” <strong>and</strong>,finally, “<strong>the</strong> light-armed <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> sailors always contribute to support a democracy” (Book 6, Part 7).Thus, whereas A<strong>the</strong>ns was a maritime republic, Thessaly, where <strong>the</strong> cavalry was always <strong>the</strong> mainarmy, remained wholly unaffected by democratic movements (Andreski 1968: 45).Widely employed in China by <strong>the</strong> fifth century AD, <strong>the</strong> stirrup reached Japan during <strong>the</strong>following century <strong>and</strong> Eastern Europe by <strong>the</strong> seventh century. By <strong>the</strong> ninth century <strong>the</strong> stirrup <strong>and</strong>,with it, heavy cavalry were fully widespread in Europe. Given <strong>the</strong> high cost <strong>of</strong> equipping one knight,<strong>the</strong> rise <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> armored horseman had to tip <strong>the</strong> balance again in favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> specialized warrior.Under <strong>the</strong> Sassanid dynasty <strong>and</strong> after <strong>the</strong> introduction <strong>of</strong> heavy protective armor, peasants werereduced to harsh servitude. Under <strong>the</strong> T’ang dynasty <strong>the</strong> situation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Chinese peasant alsoworsened considerably (Andreski 1968: 46-49).29 Even when <strong>the</strong> armed men had <strong>the</strong> right to participate in politics, <strong>the</strong> vote was weighted according to<strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> armament, that is, it was biased in favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cavalry <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> heavy infantry.33


Whereas <strong>the</strong> impact <strong>of</strong> heavy cavalrymen operated through cohesive armies <strong>and</strong> stableimperial bureaucracies in China, in Europe it took place in a ra<strong>the</strong>r fragmented <strong>and</strong> conflict-riddencontinent. The geographical diversity <strong>of</strong> Europe <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> effectiveness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> stirrup <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> heavy cavalry are heavily dependent on ground conditions afford us an excellent opportunity totest <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> war technologies on <strong>state</strong> structures. In <strong>the</strong> broad plains <strong>of</strong> continental Europe,where heavy cavalry became <strong>the</strong> dominant type <strong>of</strong> military force, feudalism replaced previous forms<strong>of</strong> social <strong>and</strong> political organization: that transition was completed after Charlemagne in France <strong>and</strong>Germany; in Catalonia by <strong>the</strong> tenth century; in Engl<strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> Norman invasion; 30 in Pol<strong>and</strong> after<strong>the</strong> gradual clearance <strong>of</strong> forests <strong>and</strong> morasses facilitated <strong>the</strong> movement <strong>of</strong> horses; in <strong>the</strong> lowl<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> Balkans with <strong>the</strong> invasions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Avars, Bulgars, Magyars <strong>and</strong> Petchnegs; in Denmark by <strong>the</strong>beginning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> lower Middle Ages (Andreski 1968: 59-61, 66-67; Rogowski <strong>and</strong> McRae 2008). Bycontrast, feudalism did not succeed in those terrains where heavy cavalry was ineffective. Infantryprevailed in Sweden due to <strong>the</strong> density <strong>of</strong> forests <strong>and</strong> in Norway, Switzerl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> highl<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> Balkans due to <strong>the</strong>ir mountainous nature. There was never serfdom in Sweden, <strong>the</strong> only countryin Europe where representatives <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> peasantry sat in parliament. The inhabitants <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> high Swisscantons always governed <strong>the</strong>mselves through communal assemblies. And in <strong>the</strong> highl<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Serbia,Bosnia <strong>and</strong> Montenegro “<strong>the</strong> semi-nomadic mountaineers [lived] under <strong>the</strong> tribal democracytempered by patriarchy” without any ruling nobles (Andreski 1968: 67). 31 According to Ferejohn<strong>and</strong> Rosenbluth (2010), medieval Japan presented <strong>the</strong> same pattern: mountain villagers <strong>and</strong> isl<strong>and</strong>erscould defend <strong>the</strong>mselves well against <strong>the</strong> encroachment <strong>of</strong> horsemen <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> central <strong>state</strong> untillate in time.30 English feudalism declined after 1300 – arguably after <strong>the</strong> English learned <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> long bow in<strong>the</strong>ir wars against <strong>the</strong> Welsh (Andreski 1968: 64-65).31 In Japan feudalism crystallized with <strong>the</strong> expansion <strong>of</strong> heavy cavalry – but faced too pockets <strong>of</strong>resistance in mountainous areas (Ferejohn <strong>and</strong> Rosenbluth 2009).34


The cannon triggered ano<strong>the</strong>r shift in <strong>the</strong> internal distribution <strong>of</strong> political power. The need togenerate economies <strong>of</strong> scale encouraged <strong>the</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> large <strong>state</strong>s with a strong, absolutist crown<strong>and</strong> led to <strong>the</strong> demise <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> old class <strong>of</strong> feudal lords (Anderson 1979, Tilly 1990). ItalianRenaissance cities only resisted after <strong>the</strong>ir engineers discovered how to build wide earth-based wallsthat could absorb <strong>the</strong> impact <strong>of</strong> cannonballs. Such a process <strong>of</strong> power concentration was onlyreversed by <strong>the</strong> industrial production <strong>of</strong> light, one-man, cheap guns <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> corresponding creation<strong>of</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ing armies. 324. DISTRIBUTIONAL CONSEQUENCES OF POLITICAL SETTINGSIn <strong>the</strong> model <strong>the</strong> final distribution <strong>of</strong> income is a function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> following factors: <strong>the</strong> nature<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> technological shock (which could in itself lead to more or less variance in income), <strong>the</strong> finalregime in place, <strong>the</strong> extraction rate <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> size <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ruling class.Technological Shock <strong>and</strong> Population StructureTo examine <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> different political institutions on <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> income, let usfirst consider <strong>the</strong> impact <strong>of</strong> any technological shock on population. Following <strong>the</strong> literature on preindustrialeconomies, assume that net population growth (ΔL) tracks <strong>the</strong> rate <strong>of</strong> technological change32 I am not suggesting that <strong>the</strong> discovery <strong>of</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ing armies mechanically triggered <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong>political liberalization that has taken place in <strong>the</strong> last two hundred years. All absolutist <strong>state</strong>s blocked <strong>the</strong>introduction <strong>of</strong> national armies for as long as it was feasible because <strong>the</strong>y contributed to undermine <strong>the</strong>position <strong>of</strong> monarchs <strong>and</strong> aristocracies. The French revolution broke down an implicit oligopolisticagreement among absolutist kings to block a new technology <strong>of</strong> war. In fact, after <strong>the</strong> defeat <strong>of</strong> Napoleon,<strong>the</strong> Austrian Prime Minister Metternich insisted on an explicit pact to abolish conscription at <strong>the</strong>Congress <strong>of</strong> Vienna. However, once <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong> battle <strong>of</strong> Valmy (1793) <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong> Napoleonic campaigns haddemonstrated <strong>the</strong> superiority <strong>of</strong> universal conscription, most <strong>state</strong>s ended up adopting some kind <strong>of</strong>st<strong>and</strong>ing army over time: Prussia immediately after <strong>the</strong> defeat at <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Napoleon, Russia after <strong>the</strong>Crimean war <strong>and</strong> Austria after its defeat at <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Germany. For recent analysis suggesting thatmodern war contributed to extension <strong>of</strong> political rights <strong>and</strong>/or to higher levels <strong>of</strong> taxation, see Levi(1997), Peacock <strong>and</strong> Wiseman (1961) ans Scheve <strong>and</strong> Stasavage (2010).35


(ΔA). That assumption implies that population adjusts so that output per person equals somesubsistence income ŷ = Y/L. This fits two key features <strong>of</strong> pre-industrial societies. First, <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong>material welfare in pre-industrial societies is not very different, at least in terms <strong>of</strong> vital statistics:food consumption per capita, life expectancies <strong>and</strong> health pr<strong>of</strong>iles have been found to be similaracross foraging <strong>and</strong> agricultural societies (Clark 2007: 40-70, 91-111). Second, population densitiesare much higher in technologically ‘advanced’ (agrarian) societies than in hunting-ga<strong>the</strong>ringterritories. In <strong>the</strong> latter, population densities fluctuate, mostly depending on climate <strong>and</strong> l<strong>and</strong>conditions, between 2 (in a few cases) to less than 0.5 persons per square kilometer (Kelly 1995). Bycontrast, recent archaeological studies suggest a density <strong>of</strong> about 90 persons per square kilometer in<strong>the</strong> first Neolithic villages in <strong>the</strong> Levant about 8,000 to 9,000 years ago (Kuijt 2000).To calculate <strong>the</strong> population growth rate (<strong>and</strong> hence <strong>the</strong> size <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> population) given <strong>the</strong> level<strong>of</strong> technology, take <strong>the</strong> previous function <strong>of</strong> ŷ, substitute <strong>the</strong> production function introduced inSection 1 for Y <strong>and</strong> solve for L:1−α1 1/ αL = ( ) AαT(12)yˆSince T <strong>and</strong> ŷ are constant, <strong>the</strong> growth rate <strong>of</strong> L is (1-α)/α times <strong>the</strong> growth rate <strong>of</strong> A.Given (12) <strong>and</strong> assuming that <strong>the</strong> share <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong> factor in total output (with no o<strong>the</strong>routput than <strong>the</strong> one from agricultural activities) was about 2/5 (α=0.4) (Clark 2007: 138), Figure 3.Adisplays <strong>the</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> population (in relative terms) in both foraging <strong>and</strong> agrariancommunities as <strong>the</strong> technology changes for <strong>the</strong> latter one. As soon as <strong>the</strong> technical know-howdoubles, <strong>the</strong> agricultural population becomes two <strong>and</strong> half times larger than <strong>the</strong> foraging population.For a technology ten times more advanced, <strong>the</strong> agricultural population becomes over thirty timeslarger than <strong>the</strong> hunting one (for <strong>the</strong> same unit <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>).[Figure 3 here]The Consequences <strong>of</strong> Regime Type36


Before <strong>the</strong> <strong>state</strong> is established (<strong>and</strong> institutionalized peace is in place), each individualreceives an income y i <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re is no <strong>inequality</strong> beyond <strong>the</strong> (relatively bounded) one determined by<strong>the</strong> productivity A i <strong>of</strong> each individual. In a monarchical system, instead, <strong>the</strong> ruler siphons <strong>of</strong>f a shareε <strong>of</strong> every individual to himself (<strong>and</strong> his servants <strong>and</strong> allies) <strong>and</strong> hence gets (ε-γ)λy i N with N denoting<strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> subjects while each subject keeps (1-ε)y i in each period. (For any minimal number <strong>of</strong>subjects, this process <strong>of</strong> redistribution always increases <strong>inequality</strong>.) By contrast, in a republican orself-governing polity every citizen keeps (1-1/θ D )y i <strong>and</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> does not vary with respect to <strong>the</strong>pre-shock world. (For <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> simplicity I will assume λ=1 throughout this section).[Figure 4 here]Productivity Shock <strong>and</strong> Income Distribution. Employing <strong>the</strong> parameters <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> model,Figures 4 <strong>and</strong> 5 simulate <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> income under different economic <strong>and</strong> politicalconditions. Figure 4.A displays <strong>the</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong> material conditions for i <strong>and</strong> j individuals as <strong>the</strong> iindividuals benefit from a growing productivity shock (represented in <strong>the</strong> horizontal axis). Figure4.A assumes that, once <strong>the</strong> shock makes <strong>the</strong> spontaneous peace equilibrium across communitiesunfeasible, <strong>the</strong> j-individuals organize <strong>and</strong> have a better military technology than producers, impose amonarchy <strong>and</strong> extract some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> producers’ income (at <strong>the</strong> highest feasible extraction rate). 33 As<strong>the</strong> productive shock increases <strong>and</strong> provided <strong>the</strong> monarchical regime is in place, <strong>the</strong> position <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ruling class improves to <strong>the</strong> point that for A=10 is eighteen times higher than <strong>the</strong> producers’ percapita income. The Gini index goes up to around 0.29 if <strong>the</strong> productive individuals double <strong>the</strong>iroutput <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ruling class in a monarchical system imposes <strong>the</strong> corresponding highest feasibleextraction rate, that is, 48 per cent, to about 0.34 percent.Size <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ruling Group. As noted before, holding <strong>the</strong> feasible rate <strong>of</strong> extraction constant,<strong>the</strong> distribution becomes <strong>the</strong> more unequal, <strong>the</strong> smaller <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> rulers relative to <strong>the</strong>population <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> country. Figure 4.B examines <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> reducing <strong>the</strong> size <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ruling groupwhile holding <strong>the</strong> extraction rate fixed (at 0.6). The Gini index goes from less than 0.1 to around 0.6.33 The parameters assumed are δ=0.7, θ D =0.6, λ=0.5.37


Variable Extraction Rate. Figure 4.C explores <strong>the</strong> impact <strong>of</strong> a changing extraction rate on<strong>the</strong> final distribution <strong>of</strong> income. For <strong>the</strong> same proportion <strong>of</strong> rulers, <strong>the</strong> Gini index increases from 0.17to 0.44 as <strong>the</strong> extraction rate climbs up to 70 percent.[Figure 5 here]Monarchies versus Republics. Figure 5 compares <strong>the</strong> income distribution under amonarchical <strong>and</strong> republican regime. To make <strong>the</strong> analysis richer, <strong>the</strong> baseline distribution <strong>of</strong> incomeis different than in Figures 4.A to 4.C. Instead <strong>of</strong> two types, <strong>the</strong> shock differentiates <strong>the</strong> populationinto ten segments or deciles. 34 The tenth decile does not experience any shock (y 10 = 1) – itcorresponds to <strong>the</strong> type-j individuals <strong>of</strong> Figure 4. The o<strong>the</strong>r deciles experience an increase inproductivity – but <strong>the</strong> extent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> raise varies across <strong>the</strong>m. However, <strong>the</strong> increase is bounded sothat <strong>the</strong>y have an incentive to cooperate among <strong>the</strong>m. (The lowest increase, <strong>the</strong> one experienced by<strong>the</strong> first decile, is big enough to make it impossible for those individuals that do not get any increase(those in <strong>the</strong> 10th decile) to maintain a cooperative relationship with <strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> population.) InFigure 5 <strong>the</strong> post-shock income ranges from 2 for <strong>the</strong> first decile to 3.58 for <strong>the</strong> ninth decile (<strong>the</strong>tenth decile keeps receiving 1). A monarchical system leads to a strong redistribution <strong>of</strong> income. Thetenth decile becomes <strong>the</strong> richest one: it has a per capita income that is about nine times larger than<strong>the</strong> poorest decile’s <strong>and</strong> it controls almost 39 percent <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> wealth. The Gini index more th<strong>and</strong>oubles to 0.35 under a monarchy. By contrast, a republican system reduces <strong>the</strong> initial distributionslightly – as a result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> tax burden to defend <strong>the</strong> human settlement. Under an “imperial republic”(where <strong>the</strong> tenth decile is expropriated by <strong>the</strong> majority), <strong>inequality</strong> does not increase by much: evenwith <strong>the</strong> highest extraction rate, <strong>the</strong> Gini index inches up from 0.14 to 0.19.34 This differentiation is done by assumption. The assumption can be justified as follows: consider <strong>the</strong>case in which different segments experience different technology shocks <strong>and</strong> choose <strong>the</strong> same populationgrowth rate, unlinked to <strong>the</strong> technological growth rate (in contrast to expression (12) where both werefunctionally related).38


Although I do not consider <strong>the</strong> following point in <strong>the</strong> simulation, <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> incomemay be also shaped by <strong>the</strong> way in which rulers extract <strong>the</strong>ir resources or, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, what kinds<strong>of</strong> alliances <strong>the</strong>y form with different strata <strong>of</strong> producers. The distribution <strong>of</strong> income becomes highlyskewed when <strong>the</strong> rulers ally with <strong>the</strong> richest fraction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> population (this would be equal toimposing a lower extraction rate ε on <strong>the</strong>m than on o<strong>the</strong>r groups) or where <strong>the</strong> ruling elite simplyreplace <strong>the</strong> existing segment <strong>of</strong> wealthy individuals. By contrast, <strong>the</strong> ruling elite may favor a moreequalized structure <strong>of</strong> income within <strong>the</strong> producers’ population. These different outcomes, resultingfrom different institutional (<strong>and</strong> taxation) choices, are particularly apparent in processes <strong>of</strong>repopulation <strong>and</strong> colonization. After <strong>the</strong> Christian kingdoms <strong>of</strong> Nor<strong>the</strong>rn Spain took over most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Sou<strong>the</strong>rn half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Iberian Peninsula in <strong>the</strong> 13th century, <strong>the</strong>y differed markedly in <strong>the</strong>ir strategies<strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> redistribution. Castile <strong>and</strong> Portugal favored <strong>the</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> large l<strong>and</strong>holdings. Catalanssettled in Valencia through small farms (Vicens Vives 1957). Similarly, <strong>the</strong> conquest <strong>of</strong> Americafollowed very divergent paths: farming communities settled in <strong>the</strong> Nor<strong>the</strong>astern seaboard <strong>and</strong> inQuebec; <strong>the</strong> Caribbean basin <strong>and</strong> Central <strong>and</strong> South America were dominated by l<strong>and</strong>owners. In allthose cases <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> partly responded to economic considerations, such as <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong>natural endowments <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> supply <strong>of</strong> labor (Engerman <strong>and</strong> Sokol<strong>of</strong>f 2002). But it was stronglyaffected by <strong>the</strong> way in which <strong>the</strong> ruling elites decided to structure <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> assets. That wasin turn related to <strong>the</strong> prevailing political institutions <strong>and</strong> societal conditions back in <strong>the</strong> conqueringcountries: <strong>the</strong> Castilian monarch relied upon <strong>the</strong> high nobility <strong>and</strong> military orders to conquerAndalusia in <strong>the</strong> thirteenth century.Some EmpiricsThe simulated extraction rates <strong>and</strong> Gini indexes fall in line with <strong>the</strong> available historicalevidence. According to data ga<strong>the</strong>red by Milanovic et al. (2007) <strong>and</strong> reproduced in Table 3, inalmost all pre-industrial regimes <strong>the</strong> Gini index fluctuated around 0.40 <strong>and</strong> in most cases <strong>the</strong> top 1039


percent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> distribution controlled more than two fifths <strong>of</strong> total income. Bourguignon <strong>and</strong>Morrisson (2002) <strong>of</strong>fer similar data across <strong>the</strong> world in 1820, at <strong>the</strong> dawn <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> industrialrevolution.[Table 3 here]Given <strong>the</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> reliable data on income distribution before <strong>the</strong> 19 th century, one possiblestrategy to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> income consequences <strong>of</strong> regimes is to employ height as a proxy for accessto resources, health status <strong>and</strong> general welfare. As discussed in Steckel (1995), height <strong>and</strong> individualincome seem to be strongly correlated <strong>and</strong>, as a result, <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> heights should provide uswith clues about how that society distributed its resources, at least in human communities livingunder conditions <strong>of</strong> scarcity. 35 In fact, we know that insufficient nutrition was widespread <strong>and</strong> that<strong>the</strong> access to food was biased across social strata in pre-industrial economies: for example, inEngl<strong>and</strong> in 1790 whereas <strong>the</strong> top decile consumed 4,329 kg cal per day; <strong>the</strong> bottom decile consumed1,545 kg cal per day (Fogel 1994).Table 4 summarizes a more extensive discussion <strong>of</strong> data reported in Boix <strong>and</strong> Rosenbluth(2006) on <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> variance in height across times <strong>and</strong> within different societies. Inequality is lowwithin tribal, pre-agrarian groups. With <strong>the</strong> transition to a fully agricultural society with complexpolitical institutions, heights vary strongly with <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong> political regime. In ancient kingdoms <strong>and</strong>absolute monarchies, <strong>the</strong>re is considerable differentiation among individuals: <strong>the</strong> height gap betweennobles <strong>and</strong> peasants goes from 7 to 9 cm. Using fitted models between log income (in constantdollars <strong>of</strong> 1985) <strong>and</strong> height (Steckel 1995), this difference translates into an income ratio <strong>of</strong> 5 or 6 to1 between both groups.36By contrast, more democratic settings (although still predominantlyagrarian such as Ohio in middle <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 19 th century) show a much more compressed height structure.35 For a critique, mostly directed at crude cross-country or cross-ethnic group comparisons, see Eaton(2007).36 This ratio matches <strong>the</strong> ratio <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 95 th centile/50 th centile in <strong>the</strong> data Bourguignon <strong>and</strong> Morrisson(2002) <strong>of</strong>fer for several (46) world areas in 1820.40


[Table 4 here]5. CONCLUSIONSBroadly speaking, <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> income in human societies has been characterized by<strong>the</strong> following pattern. First, primitive (<strong>state</strong>less, pre-agrarian) societies displayed (<strong>and</strong> still displaywherever <strong>the</strong>y exist) relatively equal distributions <strong>of</strong> income <strong>and</strong> certainly very low level <strong>of</strong>intergenerational transmissions <strong>of</strong> wealth. Second, <strong>the</strong> agricultural revolution came h<strong>and</strong> in h<strong>and</strong>with <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> marked inequalities <strong>of</strong> income (across individuals <strong>and</strong> over generations) <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> <strong>formation</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>state</strong>. Third, <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong> political institutions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> hasvaried considerably across historical communities since <strong>the</strong> invention <strong>of</strong> agriculture.This paper develops a <strong>the</strong>oretical model to explain <strong>the</strong> transition away from relatively equalpre-agrarian societies. After <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> last glacial period, a process <strong>of</strong> learning <strong>and</strong>experimentation resulted in territorially differentiated technological shocks that generated <strong>inequality</strong>(within but mostly across human b<strong>and</strong>s). That <strong>inequality</strong> made spontaneous cooperation unfeasible.That opened <strong>the</strong> way to both political institutions <strong>and</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r shifts in income distribution. Inresponse to <strong>the</strong> productivity growth, <strong>the</strong> more productive individuals responded by accepting (even ifreluctantly) <strong>the</strong> protection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir potential looters in exchange for some systematic payments.Alternatively, <strong>the</strong>y could choose to devote part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir time <strong>and</strong> income to defend <strong>the</strong>mselvesagainst those b<strong>and</strong>its. Both outcomes (‘monarchical’ <strong>and</strong> ‘republican’), strongly driven by <strong>the</strong>evolution <strong>of</strong> military technologies, had distinctive effects on <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> resources – withmonarchical regimes generating <strong>and</strong> sustaining much higher levels <strong>of</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> than republicansystems. The <strong>the</strong>oretical results match <strong>the</strong> existing descriptive work as well as broader empiricalwork compiled in Boix <strong>and</strong> Rosenbluth (2006).Underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> sources <strong>of</strong> <strong>state</strong>s institutions <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> income <strong>inequality</strong> is in fact importantto explain economic development <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> contemporary process <strong>of</strong> democratization. The emergence<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>state</strong> had a considerable stabilizing effect on <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> income over time. As41


discussed in Boix (2010), authoritarianism, economic stagnation <strong>and</strong> <strong>inequality</strong> came toge<strong>the</strong>r in anoverwhelming majority <strong>of</strong> Ancien Régime polities -- income <strong>inequality</strong> only started to trenddownward in a systematic fashion after <strong>the</strong> industrial revolution. That was a direct outcome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>incentive structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir ruling elites. The latter’s final income depended, directly, on <strong>the</strong> returnsto <strong>the</strong>ir assets <strong>and</strong>, indirectly, on <strong>the</strong> extraction rate embodied on <strong>the</strong> existing political institutions,<strong>the</strong>mselves endogenous to <strong>the</strong> prevailing income distribution. Hence, those governing had a directinterest in protecting <strong>the</strong> status quo <strong>and</strong> in blocking any process <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>and</strong> politicalliberalization.42


BIBLIOGRAPHYAcemoglu, Daron <strong>and</strong> James A. Robinson. 2006. Economic Origins <strong>of</strong> Dictatorship <strong>and</strong> Democracy.New York: Cambridge University Press.Andreski. 1968.Aristotle. [1988] The Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press.Atkinson, A.B. <strong>and</strong> F. Bourguignon. 2000. “Introduction: Income Distribution <strong>and</strong> Economics.” In A.B.Atkinson <strong>and</strong> F. Bourguignon, eds. H<strong>and</strong>book <strong>of</strong> Income Distribution. Elsevier Science. Pages 1-58.Bar-Yosef, Ofer <strong>and</strong> Richard H. Meadow. 1995. “The Origins <strong>of</strong> Agriculture in <strong>the</strong> Near East,” in T.Douglas Price <strong>and</strong> Anne B. Gebauer, eds. Last Hunters, First Farmers. Santa Fe, NM: School <strong>of</strong>American Research Press. Pages 39-94.Bates, Robert. 2001. Prosperity <strong>and</strong> Violence. The Political Economy <strong>of</strong> Development. New York:Norton.Bellwood, Peter. First Farmers. The Origins <strong>of</strong> Agricultural Societies. Malden MA: BlackwellBender. 1978.Binford. 1968.Boix, Carles. 2003. Democracy <strong>and</strong> Redistribution. New York: Cambridge University Press.Boix, Carles. 2008. “Economic Roots <strong>of</strong> Civil Wars <strong>and</strong> Revolutions in <strong>the</strong> Contemporary World,” WorldPolitics 60 (April): 390-437.Boix, Carles. 2010. “Origins <strong>and</strong> Perisistence <strong>of</strong> Inequality.” Annual Review <strong>of</strong> Political Science.Boix, Carles <strong>and</strong> Francis Rosenbluth. 2006. "Bones <strong>of</strong> Contention: The Political Economy <strong>of</strong> HeightInequality." Unpublished manuscript.Boix, Carles <strong>and</strong> Milan Svolik. 2010. “The Foundations <strong>of</strong> Limited Authoritarian Government.Institutions <strong>and</strong> Power-Sharing in Dictatorships.” Unpublished manuscript.Bollen, Kenneth A. <strong>and</strong> Pamela Paxton. 1997. “Democracy before A<strong>the</strong>ns.” in Democracy <strong>and</strong>Inequality, edited by Manus Midlarsky. New York: Cambridge University Press.Borgerh<strong>of</strong>f-Mulder, Sam Bowles et al. 2008. “The Inheritance <strong>of</strong> Inequality in Pre-Modern Societies.”43


Bourguignon <strong>and</strong> Morrisson. 2002.Carneiro, Robert L. 1970. “A Theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Origin <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> State,” Science 169 (August): 733-738.Chagnon, Pierre. 1997. Yanomamö: Case Studies in Cultural Anthropology. Wadsworth Publishing.Clark, Gregory. 2007. A Farewell to Alms: A Brief Economic History <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> World. Princeton UniversityPress.Clastres, Pierre. 1972. Chronique des Indiens Guayaki. Paris: Editions Plon.Clastres, Pierre. 1974. La société contre l’État. Recherches d’anthropologie politique. Paris: Les Ëditionsde Minuit.Cohen. 1977.Dal Bo <strong>and</strong> Fréchette. 2009.Deaton, Angus. 2007. “Height, health, <strong>and</strong> development,” Proceedings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> National Academy <strong>of</strong>Sciences 104 (33):13232-7Diamond, Jared. 1997. 1999. Guns, Germs <strong>and</strong> Steel. New York: Norton.Dixit, Avinash. 2008. “Elite-Led <strong>and</strong> Majoritarian Institutional Reforms.” Princeton: Unpublishedmanuscript.Dhondt, Jan. 1976. Le haut Moyen Age : VIIIe-XIe siècles. Paris: Bordas.Engerman, Stanley L. <strong>and</strong> Sokol<strong>of</strong>f, Kenneth L. 2002. “Factor Endowments, Inequality, <strong>and</strong> Paths <strong>of</strong>Development among New World Economies,” Economia 3: 41-102.Finer. 1997.Flannery 1965.Fogel, R.W. 1994. “Economic growth, population <strong><strong>the</strong>ory</strong>, <strong>and</strong> physiology: The bearing <strong>of</strong> long-termprocesses on <strong>the</strong> making <strong>of</strong> economic policy,” American Economic Review 84: 369-395.Gat, Azar. 2000. “The Human Motivational Complex.” Anthropological Quarterly.Geddes, Barbara. 2007. “Democratization.” In Carles Boix <strong>and</strong> Susan Stokes, eds. Oxford H<strong>and</strong>book <strong>of</strong>Comparative Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.Gordon <strong>and</strong> Dew-Becker. 2008.Gottschalk <strong>and</strong> Smeeding. 1997.44


Hansen, Mogens H., ed. 2002. A Comparative Study <strong>of</strong> Six City-State Cultures. Copenhagen: The DanishRoyal Academy.Hibbs, Douglass <strong>and</strong> Ola Olsson. 2004. “Geography, Biogeography <strong>and</strong> Why Some Countries Are Rich<strong>and</strong> O<strong>the</strong>rs Poor,” Proceedings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> National Academy <strong>of</strong> Sciences <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States 101(10): 3715-3740.Hirschman, Albert O. 1981. Essays in Trespassing. Economics to Politics <strong>and</strong> Beyond. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Kahhat. 2007.Keegan. 2004.Kelly, Robert. 1995. The Foraging Spectrum: Diversity in Hunter-Ga<strong>the</strong>rer Lifeways. SmithsonianInstitution Press.Kinder, Hermann <strong>and</strong> Werner Hilgemann. 1974. The Anchor atlas <strong>of</strong> world history from <strong>the</strong> Stone Age to<strong>the</strong> eve <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> French Revolution. Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor Books.Kuijt, Ian. 2000. “People <strong>and</strong> Space in Early Agricultural Villages: Exploring Daily Lives, CommunitySize, <strong>and</strong> Architecture in <strong>the</strong> Late Pre-Pottery Neolithic,” Journal <strong>of</strong> AnthropologicalArchaeology 19: 75–102.LeBlanc, Steven. 2003. Constant Battles: The Myth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Peaceful, Noble Savage. St. Martins.Levi, Margaret. 1988. Of Rule <strong>and</strong> Revenue. Berkeley, CA: The University <strong>of</strong> California Press.Levi, Margaret. 1997. Consent, Dissent, <strong>and</strong> Patriotism. New York: Cambridge University Press.Lindert. 2000.Machiavelli, Niccolò. 1531 [1970]. The Discourses. London: Penguin.Mann. 1986.McNeill, William H. 1982. The Pursuit <strong>of</strong> Power. Chicago: The University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.Milanovic, Branko, Peter H. Lindert <strong>and</strong> Jeffrey G. Williamson. 2007. “Measuring Ancient Inequality,”NBER Working Papers # 13550.North, Douglass. 1981. Structure <strong>and</strong> Change in Economic History. New York: Norton.45


Olson, Mancur. 1993. "Dictatorship, Democracy, <strong>and</strong> Development," American Political Science Review87: 567-576.Olson, Mancur. 2000. Power <strong>and</strong> Prosperity. New York: Basic Books.Olsson, Ola <strong>and</strong> Douglas Hibbs. 2005.O’Rourke, Kevin H. <strong>and</strong> Jeffrey G. Williamson. 1999. Globalization <strong>and</strong> History: The Evolution <strong>of</strong> aNineteenth-Century Atlantic Economy. Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press.Panter-Brick, Ca<strong>the</strong>rine, Robert H. Layton <strong>and</strong> Peter Rowley-Conwy, eds. 2001. Hunter-ga<strong>the</strong>rers: aninterdisciplinary perspective. New York: Cambridge University Press.Peacock <strong>and</strong> Wisemann. 1961.Piketty, Thomas. 2000. “Theories <strong>of</strong> Persistent Inequality <strong>and</strong> Intergenerational Mobility.” In A.B.Atkinson <strong>and</strong> F. Bourguignon, eds. H<strong>and</strong>book <strong>of</strong> Income Distribution. Chapter 8. ElsevierScience. Pages 429-476.Price, T. Douglas <strong>and</strong> Anne B. Gebauer. 1995. Last Hunters-First Farmers: New Perspectives on <strong>the</strong>Prehistoric Transition to Agriculture. Santa Fe, New Mexico: School <strong>of</strong> American ResearchPress.Rindos. 1978.Rogowski, Ronald <strong>and</strong> Duncan McRae. 2008. “Inequality <strong>and</strong> Institutions: What Theory, History <strong>and</strong>(Some) Data Tell Us.” In P. Beramendi <strong>and</strong> Christopher J Anderson, eds., Democracy, Inequality<strong>and</strong> Representation. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.Rowley-Conwy, P. 2001. “Time, change, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> archaeology <strong>of</strong> hunter-ga<strong>the</strong>rers: how original is <strong>the</strong>‘Original Affluent Society’?” In C. Panter-Brick, R. H. Layton, <strong>and</strong> P. Rowley-Conwy (eds.)Hunter-Ga<strong>the</strong>rers: An Inter-Disciplinary Perspective. Pages 39-72. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1755 [1973]. A Discourse on <strong>the</strong> Origin <strong>of</strong> Inequality. In The Social Contract<strong>and</strong> Discourses. London: Everyman’s Lybrary.Scheve, Kenneth <strong>and</strong> David Stasavage. 2007. “Political Institutions <strong>and</strong> Income Inequality, 1900-2000.”World Politics.46


Scheve, Ken <strong>and</strong> David Stasavage. 2010.Steckel, Richard H. 1995. “Stature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> St<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> Living,” Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic Literature 33(December): 1903-1940.Tilly, Charles. 1990. Coercion, Capital <strong>and</strong> European States, AD 990-1992. Blackwell.Turney-High. 19xx.Vicens Vives, Jaume. 1957. Historia económica y social de España y América. Barcelona: Teide.Wallerstein, Michael. 1999.Watson, Patty Jo. 1995. “Explaining <strong>the</strong> Transition to Agriculture,” in T. Douglas Price <strong>and</strong> Anne B.Gebauer, eds. Last Hunter, First Farmers. Santa Fe, NM: School <strong>of</strong> American Research Press.Pages 21-38.Wright, Henry T. 1977. “Recent Research on <strong>the</strong> Origin <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> State,” Annual Review <strong>of</strong> Anthropology 6:379-397.Yadin. 1963.47


TABLE 1. ESTIMATING THE CAUSES OF THE AGRICULTURAL REVOLUTIONModel 1 Model 2 Model 3 Model 4 Model 5Dependent Variable Animals Plants Animals Years to YearsAnd Plants Agriculture to AgricultureConstant -3.023*** -5.214** -24.474*** 11,252.226*** 11,140.786***(0.683) (2.506) (7.273) (455.150) (461.598)Climate 0.492*** 1.540** 5.148*** -830.410*** -959.365***(0.181) (0.665) (1.9292) (120.751) (125.037)Latitude 0.008 0.0781*** 0.169*** 8.056** -27.554***(0.005) (0.020) (0.058) (3.614) (7.992)(Latitude) 2 -0.017 0.0080 -0.061 73.574*** 131.756***(0.011) (0.042) (0.120) (7.531) (13.869)EW Axis / NS Axis 3.778*** 8.690*** 33.461*** -1,479.413*** -1,169.922***(0.350) (1.283) (3.723) (233.010) (243.907)Isl<strong>and</strong> -3.329*** -9.946*** -33.035*** 2,299.943*** 1,688.177***(0.502) (1.842) (5.345) (334.573) (360.257)Observations 234 234 234 234 203R-squared 0.5580 0.4693 0.5303 0.5477 0.5485St<strong>and</strong>ard errors in paren<strong>the</strong>ses. *** p


TABLE 2. ESTIMATING THE EMERGENCE OF STATESDependent Variable Emergence <strong>of</strong> State ------------------------------------------------ Emergence <strong>of</strong> State(Original & Derivative)(Only Original)Model 1 Model 2 Model 3 Model 4 Model 5Constant 2,540.131*** 2,474.894*** 1,263.651*** 1,255.726*** 1,266.825***(211.439) (218.471) (43.309) (51.029) (173.048)Climate -260.769*** -311.078***(54.822) (57.753)Latitude 4.693*** -9.436**(1.682) (3.758)(Latitude) 2 22.853*** 45.736***(3.443) (6.455)EW Axis / NS Axis -928.002*** -792.815***(112.164) (119.894)Isl<strong>and</strong> 706.341*** 448.982***(155.587) (171.475)Year <strong>of</strong> Transition 0.327*** 0.324*** 0.446***To Agriculture (0.016) (0.019) (0.046)Observations 229 198 229 198 46R 2 0.449 0.454 0.638 0.607 0.684St<strong>and</strong>ard errors in paren<strong>the</strong>ses*** p


TABLE 3. SOME INEQUALITY STATISTICSGiniTop 10 percentRoman Empire ca. 14 AD (a) 0.36 0.44Byzantium 1000 (a) 0.41 0.46Engl<strong>and</strong>/Wales 1688 (a) 0.45 0.38Moghul India 1750 (a) 0.39 0.35Mexico 1790 (a) 0.64 0.61Naples 1811 (a) 0.28 0.35Brazil 1872 (a) 0.39France 1780 (b) 0.56(a) Milanovic et al. (2007).(b) Morrisson 200050


TABLE 4. POLITICAL SETTINGS AND DIFFERENCES IN MALE HEIGHTSINSTITUTIONS, PLACE MEAN DIFFERENCE(IN CM.) (IN CM.)Pre-State SocietiesZuni Pueblos (before 1680 AD.)Height at 90 th centile 165.8Height at 50 th centile 161.1 4.7Monarchical/AuthoritarianAncient Egypt (New Kingdom)Royal family 174Commoners 166 8.0MycenaeRoyal 172.5Commoners 166.1 6.4Pol<strong>and</strong> – 17 th cent.Noble 170.6Rural Non-Jewish 165.2Jewish 162.9 7.7DemocraticOhio Recruits, Mid 19 th CenturyLaborers 173.3Skilled Workers 174.0Farmer 174.7Pr<strong>of</strong>essional 175.5 2.2Source: Boix <strong>and</strong> Rosenbluth (2006).51


Years to <strong>the</strong> Introduction <strong>of</strong> Agriculture0 5000 10000 15000Figure 1. Transition to Agriculture <strong>and</strong> Biogeographical ConditionsAULAUL AULJPNLIBAUL AUL SAU UAE ALGRUSRUSRUSARGUSACANUSACANARG ARG ICECAN USACHLRUSCANHAI CUB NEW SURINEWMAG MAGNAM BOT MZMUSAFCANANG ZAM MAWZAI TAZFINVEN NIG CAO CENSENCHNRUSKZKMON CHNNMARI PHI PNGINSOMNIRCHA MLIBRA COLBRA BRAIVO MAA BOL CHL HON PAR THI ALGBRU INSARGURUALGUSA MORPER PERMEXETIUSAJPNSUDINDINDIND MYACHNUSAROK LITRUS NOR SWDDENUKMEXNTHEGYCHN SUDCHNYEMRUS SPNFRNAFG IND RUM CRORUSCHN GRCIRNIRQSYR.2 .4 .6 .8 1Biogeographical Conditions (Climate, Latitude, Ratio Axis, Continental L<strong>and</strong>)Year <strong>of</strong> Emergence <strong>of</strong> State Institutions-8000 -6000 -4000 -2000 0 2000Figure 2. Transition to Agriculture <strong>and</strong> Birth <strong>of</strong> State InstitutionsSUD ALGPNGINSCENALGLIBRUSRUSRUSZAIETI CAOZAIANG ZAMMAW NAM BOT MZMMAG SAFNEWAULBRAPARBRA ARG URUARGARG CHLMEXUSAUSAUSACHL IVO COL VEN USA CANSURIDOM HAI BAH CUBCANUSACANSOMNIRNIG RUSKZKMONJPNSWDFIN TAZRUS PHI CHAYEMNOR MLI PERBOLCHNSENICEMAASAUMEX MYA JPN HONRUSNTHUKDENINS INS INSCHNCHN IND THICHNIRN AFG CHNSPNRUS RUSSUDALGFRNUAEMORSYRCRORUM CHN IND IND ROKGRC CHNCHNIND PAKIRQEGY-8000 -6000 -4000 -2000 0 2000Aprroximate transition year to agriculture. Based on Bellwood <strong>and</strong> on Parker52


35Figure 3.Technological Change <strong>and</strong> Population Growth3025Number <strong>of</strong> individuals201510501 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10Level <strong>of</strong> Technology (Value <strong>of</strong> A)Population <strong>of</strong> ProducersPopulation <strong>of</strong> B<strong>and</strong>its0.9Figure 4.A. Monarchical Rule <strong>and</strong> Productivity Shock200.8180.716Proportion / Gini Index0.60.50.40.314121086Per Capita Income0.240.1201 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10Level <strong>of</strong> Technology (Value <strong>of</strong> A)0Percentage <strong>of</strong> Income Controlled by Monarchical ClassPer Capita Income <strong>of</strong> Monarchical ClassGini IndexPer Capita Income <strong>of</strong> Producer53


0.9Figure 4.B. Monarchical Regime <strong>and</strong> Change in Size <strong>of</strong> Ruling Group200.8180.716Proportion / Gini Index0.60.50.40.314121086Per Capita Income0.240.12000 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5Proportion <strong>of</strong> Monarchical ClassPercentage <strong>of</strong> Income Controlled by Monarchical ClassPer Capita Income <strong>of</strong> Ruling GroupGini IndexPer Capita Income <strong>of</strong> Producers0.9Figure 4.C. Monarchical Rule <strong>and</strong> Varying Extraction Rate200.8180.716Proportion / Gini Index0.60.50.40.314121086Per Capita Income0.240.12000.25 0.30 0.35 0.40 0.45 0.50 0.55 0.60 0.65 0.70Extraction RatePercentage <strong>of</strong> Income Controlled by Monarchical ClassPer Capita Income <strong>of</strong> Ruling GroupGini IndexPer Capita Income <strong>of</strong> Producers54


10Figure 5. Income Distribution Under Monarchical <strong>and</strong> Republican Regimes98Per Capita Income for Each Decile765432101 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10DecileIncome after shock without <strong>state</strong> Income under Monarchy Income under Republic Income under Imperial Republic55

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!