12.07.2015 Views

The Continuum Hypothesis - Logic at Harvard

The Continuum Hypothesis - Logic at Harvard

The Continuum Hypothesis - Logic at Harvard

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Continuum</strong> <strong>Hypothesis</strong>Peter KoellnerSeptember 12, 2011<strong>The</strong> continuum hypotheses (CH) is one of the most central open problemsin set theory, one th<strong>at</strong> is important for both m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical and philosophicalreasons.<strong>The</strong> problem actually arose with the birth of set theory; indeed, in manyrespects it stimul<strong>at</strong>ed the birth of set theory. In 1874 Cantor had shownth<strong>at</strong> there is a one-to-one correspondence between the n<strong>at</strong>ural numbers andthe algebraic numbers. More surprisingly, he showed th<strong>at</strong> there is no oneto-onecorrespondence between the n<strong>at</strong>ural numbers and the real numbers.Taking the existence of a one-to-one correspondence as a criterion for whentwo sets have the same size (something he certainly did by 1878), this resultshows th<strong>at</strong> there is more than one level of infinity and thus gave birth tothe higher infinite in m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics. Cantor immedi<strong>at</strong>ely tried to determinewhether there were any infinite sets of real numbers th<strong>at</strong> were ofintermedi<strong>at</strong>esize, th<strong>at</strong> is, whether there was an infinite set of real numbers th<strong>at</strong> couldnot be put into one-to-one correspondence with the n<strong>at</strong>ural numbers andcould not be put into one-to-one correspondence with the real numbers. <strong>The</strong>continuum hypothesis (under one formul<strong>at</strong>ion) is simply the st<strong>at</strong>ement th<strong>at</strong>there is no such set of real numbers. It was through his <strong>at</strong>tempt to prove thishypothesis th<strong>at</strong> led Cantor do develop set theory into a sophistic<strong>at</strong>ed branchof m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics. 1Despite his efforts Cantor could not resolve CH. <strong>The</strong> problem persistedand was considered so important by Hilbert th<strong>at</strong> he placed it first on hisfamous list of open problems to be faced by the 20 th century. Hilbert alsostruggled to resolve CH, again without success. Ultim<strong>at</strong>ely, this lack ofprogress was explained by the combined results of Gödel and Cohen, which1 See Hallett (1984) for further historical inform<strong>at</strong>ion on the role of CH in the earlyfound<strong>at</strong>ions of set theory.1


together showed th<strong>at</strong> CH cannot be resolved on the basis of the axioms th<strong>at</strong>m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>icians were employing; in modern terms, CH is independent ofZFC.This independence result was quickly followed by many others. <strong>The</strong> independencetechniques were so powerful th<strong>at</strong> set theorists soon found themselvespreoccupied with the meta-theoretic enterprise of proving th<strong>at</strong> certainfundamental st<strong>at</strong>ements could not be proved or refuted within ZFC. <strong>The</strong>question then arose as to whether there were ways to settle the independentst<strong>at</strong>ements. <strong>The</strong> community of m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>icians and philosophers of m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>icswas largely divided on this question. <strong>The</strong> pluralists (like Cohen)maintained th<strong>at</strong> the independence results effectively settled the question byshowing th<strong>at</strong> it had no answer. On this view, one could adopt a system inwhich, say CH was an axiom and one could adopt a system in which ¬CHwas an axiom and th<strong>at</strong> was the end of the m<strong>at</strong>ter—there was no questionas to which of two incomp<strong>at</strong>ible extensions was the “correct” one. <strong>The</strong> nonpluralists(like Gödel) held th<strong>at</strong> the independence results merely indic<strong>at</strong>edthe paucity of our means for circumscribing m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical truth. On thisview, wh<strong>at</strong> was needed were new axioms, axioms th<strong>at</strong> are both justified andsufficient for the task. Gödel actually went further in proposing candid<strong>at</strong>esfor new axioms—large cardinal axioms—and he conjectured th<strong>at</strong> they wouldsettle CH.Gödel’s program for large cardinal axioms proved to be remarkably successful.Over the course of the next 30 years it was shown th<strong>at</strong> large cardinalaxioms settle many of the questions th<strong>at</strong> were shown to be independent duringthe era of independence. However, CH was left untouched. <strong>The</strong> situ<strong>at</strong>ionturned out to be r<strong>at</strong>her ironic since in the end it was shown (in a senseth<strong>at</strong> can be made precise) th<strong>at</strong> although the standard large cardinal axiomseffectively settle all question of complexity strictly below th<strong>at</strong> of CH, theycannot (by results of Levy and Solovay and others) settle CH itself. Thus,in choosing CH as a test case for his program, Gödel put his finger preciselyon the point where it fails. It is for this reason th<strong>at</strong> CH continues to play acentral role in the search for new axioms.In this entry we shall give an overview of the major approaches to settlingCH and we shall discuss some of the major found<strong>at</strong>ional frameworks whichmaintain th<strong>at</strong> CH does not have an answer. <strong>The</strong> subject is a large one andwe have had to sacrifice full comprehensiveness in two dimensions. First, wehave not been able to discuss the major philosophical issues th<strong>at</strong> are lying inthe background. For this the reader is directed to the entry “Large Cardinals2


and Determinacy”, which contains a general discussion of the independenceresults, the n<strong>at</strong>ure of axioms, the n<strong>at</strong>ure of justific<strong>at</strong>ion, and the successes oflarge cardinal axioms in the realm “below CH”. Second, we have not beenabletodiscuss everyapproachtoCHth<strong>at</strong>isintheliter<strong>at</strong>ure. Insteadwehaverestricted ourselves to those approaches th<strong>at</strong> appear most promising from aphilosophical point of view and where the m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics has been developedto a sufficiently advanced st<strong>at</strong>e. In the approaches we shall discuss—forcingaxioms, inner modeltheory, quasi-largecardinals—them<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>icshasbeenpressed to a very advanced stage over the course of 40 years. And this hasmade our task somewh<strong>at</strong> difficult. We have tried to keep the discussion asaccessible as possible and we have placed the more technical items in theendnotes. But the reader should bear in mind th<strong>at</strong> we are presenting a bird’seye view and th<strong>at</strong> for a higher resolution <strong>at</strong> any point the reader should dipinto the suggested readings th<strong>at</strong> appear <strong>at</strong> the end of each section. 2<strong>The</strong>re are really two kinds of approaches to new axioms—the local approachand the global approach. On the local approach one seeks axiomsth<strong>at</strong> answer questions concerning a specifiable fragment of the universe, suchas V ω+1 or V ω+2 , where CH lies. On the global approach one seeks axiomsth<strong>at</strong> <strong>at</strong>tempt to illumin<strong>at</strong>e the entire structure of the universe of sets. <strong>The</strong>global approach is clearly much more challenging. In this entry we shall startwith the local approach and toward the end we shall briefly touch upon theglobal approach.Here is an overview of the entry: Section 1 surveys the independenceresults in cardinal arithmetic, covering both the case of regular cardinals(where CH lies) and singular cardinals. Section 2 considers approaches toCH where one successively verifies a hierarchy of approxim<strong>at</strong>ions to CH, eachof which is an “effective” version of CH. This approach led to the remarkablediscovery of Woodin th<strong>at</strong> it is possible (in the presence of large cardinals)to have an effective failure of CH, thereby showing, th<strong>at</strong> the effective failureof CH is as intractable (with respect to large cardinal axioms) as CH itself.Section 3 continues with the developments th<strong>at</strong> stemmed from this discovery.<strong>The</strong> centerpiece of the discussion is the discovery of a “canonical” model inwhich CH fails. This formed the basis of a network of results th<strong>at</strong> wascollectively presented by Woodin as a case for the failure of CH. To present2 We have of necessity presupposed much in the way of set theory. <strong>The</strong> reader seekingadditional detail—for example, the definitions of regular and singular cardinals and otherfundamental notions—is directed to one of the many excellent texts in set theory, forexample Jech (2003).3


this case in the most streamlined form we introduce the strong logic Ω-logic.Section 4 takes up the competing found<strong>at</strong>ional view th<strong>at</strong> there is no solutionto CH. This view is sharpened in terms of the generic multiverse conceptionof truth and th<strong>at</strong> view is then scrutinized. Section 5 continues the assessmentof the case for ¬CH by investig<strong>at</strong>ing a parallel case for CH. In the remainingtwo sections we turn to the global approach to new axioms and here weshall be much briefer. Section 6 discusses the approach through inner modeltheory. Section7discusses theapproachthroughquasi-largecardinalaxioms.1 Independence in Cardinal ArithmeticIn this section we shall discuss the independence results in cardinal arithmetic.First, we shall tre<strong>at</strong> of the case of regular cardinals, where CH liesand where very little is determined in the context of ZFC. Second, for thesake of comprehensiveness, we shall discuss the case of singular cardinals,where much more can be established in the context of ZFC.1.1 Regular Cardinals<strong>The</strong> addition and multiplic<strong>at</strong>ion of infinite cardinal numbers is trivial: Forinfinite cardinals κ and λ,κ+λ = κ·λ = max{κ,λ}.<strong>The</strong> situ<strong>at</strong>ion becomes interesting when one turns to exponenti<strong>at</strong>ion and the<strong>at</strong>tempt to compute κ λ for infinite cardinals.During the dawn of set theory Cantor showed th<strong>at</strong> for every cardinal κ,2 κ > κ.<strong>The</strong>reisnomysteryaboutthesizeof2 n forfiniten. <strong>The</strong>firstn<strong>at</strong>uralquestionthen is where 2 ℵ 0is loc<strong>at</strong>ed in the aleph-hierarchy: Is it ℵ 1 ,ℵ 2 ,...,ℵ 17 orsomething much larger?<strong>The</strong> cardinal 2 ℵ 0is important since it is the size of the continuum (theset of real numbers). Cantor’s famous continuum hypothesis (CH) is thest<strong>at</strong>ement th<strong>at</strong> 2 ℵ 0= ℵ 1 . This is a special case of the generalized continuumhypothesis (GCH)which asserts th<strong>at</strong> forallα ω, 2 ℵα = ℵ α+1 . OnevirtueofGCH is th<strong>at</strong> it gives a complete solution to the problem of computing κ λ for4


infinite cardinals: Assuming GCH, if κ λ then κ λ = λ + ; if cf(κ) λ κthen κ λ = κ + ; and if λ < cf(κ) then κ λ = κ.Very little progress was made on CH and GCH. In fact, in the early eraof set theory the only other piece of progress beyond Cantor’s result th<strong>at</strong>2 κ > κ (and the trivial result th<strong>at</strong> if κ λ then 2 κ 2 λ ) was König’s resultth<strong>at</strong> cf(2 κ ) > κ. <strong>The</strong> explan<strong>at</strong>ion for the lack of progress was provided bythe independence results in set theory:<strong>The</strong>orem 1.1 (Gödel, 1938). Assume th<strong>at</strong> ZFC is consistent. <strong>The</strong>n ZFC+CH and ZFC+GCH are consistent.To prove this Gödel invented the method of inner models—he showed th<strong>at</strong>CH and GCH held in the minimal inner model L of ZFC. Cohen thencomplemented this result:<strong>The</strong>orem 1.2 (Cohen, 1963). Assume th<strong>at</strong> ZFC is consistent. <strong>The</strong>n ZFC+¬CH and ZFC+¬GCH are consistent.He did this by inventing the method of outer models and showing th<strong>at</strong> CHfailedin a generic extension V B ofV. <strong>The</strong> combined results ofGödel andCohenthus demonstr<strong>at</strong>e th<strong>at</strong> assuming the consistency of ZFC, it is in principleimpossible to settle either CH or GCH in ZFC.In the Fall of 1963 Easton completed the picture by showing th<strong>at</strong> forinfinite regular cardinals κ the only constraints on the function κ ↦→ 2 κ th<strong>at</strong>are provable in ZFC are the trivial constraint and the results of Cantor andKönig:<strong>The</strong>orem 1.3 (Easton, 1963). Assume th<strong>at</strong> ZFC is consistent. Suppose Fis a (definable class) function defined on infinite regular cardinals such th<strong>at</strong>(1) if κ λ then F(κ) F(λ),(2) F(κ) > κ, and(3) cf(F(κ)) > κ.<strong>The</strong>n ZFC+“For all infinite regular cardinals κ, 2 κ = F(κ)” is consistent.Thus, set theoristshadpushedthecardinalarithmeticofregularcardinalsas far as it could be pushed within the confines of ZFC.5


1.2 Singular Cardinals<strong>The</strong> case of cardinal arithmetic on singular cardinals is much more subtle.Forthesakeofcompletenesswepausetobrieflydiscussthisbeforeproceedingwith the continuum hypothesis.It was generally believed th<strong>at</strong>, as in the case for regular cardinals, thebehaviour of the function κ ↦→ 2 κ would be rel<strong>at</strong>ively unconstrained withinthe setting of ZFC. But then Silver proved the following remarkable result: 3<strong>The</strong>orem 1.4 (Silver, 1974). If ℵ δ is a singular cardinal of uncountablecofinality, then, if GCH holds below ℵ δ , then GCH holds <strong>at</strong> ℵ δ .It turns out th<strong>at</strong> (by a deep result of Magidor, published in 1977) GCHcan first fail <strong>at</strong> ℵ ω (assuming the consistency of a supercompact cardinal).Silver’s theorem shows th<strong>at</strong> it cannot first fail <strong>at</strong> ℵ ω1 and this is provable inZFC.This raises the question of whether one can “control” the size of 2 ℵ δwith a weaker assumption than th<strong>at</strong> ℵ δ is a singular cardinal of uncountablecofinality such th<strong>at</strong> GCH holds below ℵ δ . <strong>The</strong> n<strong>at</strong>ural hypothesis to consideris th<strong>at</strong> ℵ δ is a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality which is a stronglimit cardinal, th<strong>at</strong> is, th<strong>at</strong> for all α < ℵ δ , 2 α < ℵ δ . In 1975 Galvin andHajnal proved (among other things) th<strong>at</strong> under this weaker assumption thereis indeed a bound:<strong>The</strong>orem 1.5 (Galvin and Hajnal, 1975). If ℵ δ is a singular strong limitcardinal of uncountable cofinality then2 ℵ δ< ℵ (|δ| cf(δ) ) +.It is possible th<strong>at</strong> there is a jump—in fact, Woodin showed (again assuminglarge cardinals) th<strong>at</strong> it is possible th<strong>at</strong> for all κ, 2 κ = κ ++ . Wh<strong>at</strong> the abovetheorem shows is th<strong>at</strong> in ZFC there is a provable bound on how big the jumpcan be.<strong>The</strong> next question is whether a similar situ<strong>at</strong>ion prevails with singularcardinals of countable cofinality. In 1978 Shelah showed th<strong>at</strong> this is indeedthe case. To fix ideas let us concentr<strong>at</strong>e on ℵ ω .3 To say th<strong>at</strong> GCH holds below δ is just to say th<strong>at</strong> 2 ℵα = ℵ α+1 for all ω α < δ andto say th<strong>at</strong> GCH holds <strong>at</strong> δ is just to say th<strong>at</strong> 2 ℵ δ= ℵ δ+1 ).6


<strong>The</strong>orem 1.6 (Shelah, 1978). If ℵ ω is a strong limit cardinal then2 ℵω < ℵ (2 ℵ 0) +.One drawback of this result is th<strong>at</strong> the bound is sensitive to the actual sizeof 2 ℵ 0, which can be anything below ℵ ω . Remarkably Shelah was l<strong>at</strong>er ableto remedy this with the development of his pcf (possible cofinalities) theory.One very quotable result from this theory is the following:<strong>The</strong>orem 1.7 (Shelah). If ℵ ω is a strong limit cardinal then (regardless ofthe size of 2 ℵ 0)2 ℵω < ℵ ω4 .In summary, although the continuum function <strong>at</strong> regular cardinals is rel<strong>at</strong>ivelyunconstrained in ZFC, the continuum function <strong>at</strong> singular cardinalsis (provably in ZFC) constrained in significant ways by the behaviour of thecontinuum function on the smaller cardinals.Further Reading: For more cardinal arithmetic see Jech (2003). For more onthe case of singular cardinals and pcf theory see Abraham & Magidor (2010)and Holz, Steffens & Weitz (1999).2 Definable Versions of the <strong>Continuum</strong> <strong>Hypothesis</strong>and its Neg<strong>at</strong>ionLet us return to the continuum function on regular cardinals and concentr<strong>at</strong>eon the simplest case, the size of 2 ℵ 0. One of Cantor’s original approaches toCH was by investig<strong>at</strong>ing “simple” sets of real numbers. 4 One of the firstresults in this direction is the Cantor-Bendixson theorem th<strong>at</strong> every infiniteclosed set is either countable or contains a perfect subset, in which case ithas the same cardinality as the set of reals. In other words, CH holds (inthis formul<strong>at</strong>ion) when one restricts one’s <strong>at</strong>tention to closed sets of reals.In general, questions about “definable” sets of reals are more tractable thanquestions about arbitrary sets of reals and this suggests looking <strong>at</strong> definableversions of the continuum hypothesis.4 See Hallett (1984), pp. 3-5 and §2.3(b).7


2.1 Three Versions<strong>The</strong>re are three different formul<strong>at</strong>ions of the continuum hypothesis—theinterpolant version, the well-ordering version, and the surjection version.<strong>The</strong>se versions are all equivalent to one another in ZFC but we shall beimposing a definability constraint and in this case there can be interestingdifferences. 5 <strong>The</strong>re is really a hierarchy of notions of definability—rangingup through the Borel hierarchy, the projective hierarchy, the hierarchy inL(R), and, more generally, the hierarchy of universally Baire sets—and soeach of these three general versions is really a hierarchy of versions, eachcorresponding to a given level of the hierarchy of definability. 62.1.1 Interpolant Version<strong>The</strong> first formul<strong>at</strong>ion of CH is th<strong>at</strong> there is no interpolant, th<strong>at</strong> is, there is noinfiniteset Aofrealnumbers suchth<strong>at</strong>thecardinalityofAisstrictlybetweenth<strong>at</strong> of the n<strong>at</strong>ural numbers and the real numbers. To obtain definableversions one simply asserts th<strong>at</strong> there is no “definable” interpolant and thisleads to a hierarchy of definable interpolant versions, depending on whichnotion of definability one employs. More precisely, for a given pointclassΓ in the hierarchy of definable sets of reals, the corresponding definableinterpolant version of CH asserts th<strong>at</strong> there is no interpolant in Γ.<strong>The</strong> Cantor-Bendixson theorem shows th<strong>at</strong> there is no interpolant in Γ inthe case where Γ is the pointclass of closed sets, thus verifying this version ofCH. This was improved by Suslin who showed th<strong>at</strong> this version of CH holds1for Γ where Γ is the class of Σ ∼1 sets. One cannot go much further withinZFC—to prove stronger versions one must bring in stronger assumptions. Itturns out th<strong>at</strong> axioms of definable determinacy and large cardinal axioms1achieve this. For example, results of Kechris and Martin show th<strong>at</strong> if ∆ ∼n -1determinacy holds then this version of CH holds for the pointclass of Σ ∼ n+1sets. Going further, if one assumes AD L(R) then this version of CH holds forall sets of real numbers appearing in L(R). Since these hypotheses followfrom large cardinal axioms one also has th<strong>at</strong> stronger and stronger largecardinal assumptions secure stronger and stronger versions of this version ofthe effective continuum hypothesis. Indeed large cardinal axioms imply th<strong>at</strong>5 Our discussion follows Martin (1976).6 For a discussion of the hierarchy of definability see §2.2.1 and §4.6 of the entry “LargeCardinals and Determinacy”.8


this version of CH holds for all sets of reals in the definability hierarchy weare considering; more precisely, if there is a proper class of Woodin cardinalsthen this version of CH holds for all universally Baire sets of reals.2.1.2 Well-ordering Version<strong>The</strong> second formul<strong>at</strong>ion of CH asserts th<strong>at</strong> every well-ordering of the realshas order type less than ℵ 2 . For a given pointclass Γ in the hierarchy, thecorresponding definable well-ordering version of CH asserts th<strong>at</strong> every wellordering(coded by a set) in Γ has order type less than ℵ 2 .Again, axioms of definable determinacy and large cardinal axioms implythis version of CH for richer notions of definability. For example, if AD L(R)holds then this version of CH holds for all sets of real numbers in L(R). Andif there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals then this version of CH holdsfor all universally Baire sets of reals.2.1.3 Surjection Version<strong>The</strong> third version formul<strong>at</strong>ion of CH asserts th<strong>at</strong> there is no surjection ρ :R → ℵ 2 , or, equivalently, th<strong>at</strong> there is no prewellordering of R of length ℵ 2 .For a given pointclass Γ in the hierarchy of definability, the correspondingsurjection version of CH asserts th<strong>at</strong> there is no surjection ρ : R → ℵ 2 suchth<strong>at</strong> (the code for) ρ is in Γ.Here the situ<strong>at</strong>ion is more interesting. Axioms of definable determinacyand large cardinal axioms have bearing on this version since they place1bounds on how long definable prewellorderings can be. Let ∼δ n be the supremumof the lengths of the Σ ∼n -prewellorderings of reals and let Θ L(R) be the1supremum of the lengths of prewellorderings of reals where the prewellorderingis definable in the sense of being in L(R). It is a classical result th<strong>at</strong>1δ∼ 1 = ℵ 11. Martin showed th<strong>at</strong> δ ∼2 ℵ 2 and th<strong>at</strong> if there is a measurable cardinalthen δ ∼3 ℵ 3 . Kunen and Martin also showed under PD, δ ∼4 ℵ 4 and1 11Jackson showed th<strong>at</strong> under PD, for each n < ω, ∼δ n < ℵ ω . Thus, assumingth<strong>at</strong> there are infinitely many Woodin cardinals, these bounds hold. Moreover,the bounds continue to hold regardless of the size of 2 ℵ 0. Of course,the question is whether these bounds can be improved to show th<strong>at</strong> theprewellorderings are shorter than ℵ 2 . In 1986 Foreman and Magidor initi<strong>at</strong>eda program to establish this. In the most general form they aimed toshow th<strong>at</strong> large cardinal axioms implied th<strong>at</strong> this version of CH held for all9


universally Baire sets of reals.2.1.4 Potential Bearing on CHNotice th<strong>at</strong> in the context of ZFC, these three hierarchies of versions of CHare all successive approxim<strong>at</strong>ions of CH and in the limit case, where Γ is thepointclass of all sets of reals, they are equivalent to CH. <strong>The</strong> question iswhether these approxim<strong>at</strong>ions can provide any insight into CH itself.<strong>The</strong>re is an asymmetry th<strong>at</strong> was pointed out by Martin, namely, th<strong>at</strong> adefinable counterexample to CH is a real counterexample, while no m<strong>at</strong>terhow far one proceeds in verifying definable versions of CH <strong>at</strong> no stage willone have touched CH itself. In other words, the definability approach couldrefute CH but it could not prove it.Still, one might argue th<strong>at</strong> although the definability approach could notprove CH it might provide some evidence for it. In the case of the first twoversions we now know th<strong>at</strong> CH holds for all definable sets. Does this provideevidence of CH? Martin pointed out (before the full results were known)th<strong>at</strong> this is highly doubtful since in each case one is dealing with sets th<strong>at</strong>are <strong>at</strong>ypical. For example, in the first version, <strong>at</strong> each stage one securesthe definable version of CH by showing th<strong>at</strong> all sets in the definability classhave the perfect set property; yet such sets are <strong>at</strong>ypical in th<strong>at</strong> assuming ACit is easy to show th<strong>at</strong> there are sets without this property. In the secondversion, <strong>at</strong> each stage one actually shows not only th<strong>at</strong> each well-ordering ofreals in the definability class has ordertype less than ℵ 2 , but also th<strong>at</strong> it hasordertype less than ℵ 1 . So neither of these versions really illumin<strong>at</strong>es CH.<strong>The</strong> third version actually has an advantage in this regard since not all ofthe sets it deals with are <strong>at</strong>ypical. For example, while all Σ ∼11 -sets have lengthless than ℵ 1 , there are Π ∼11 -sets of length ℵ 1 . Of course, it could turn out th<strong>at</strong>even if the Foreman-Magidor program were to succeed the sets could turnout to be <strong>at</strong>ypical in another sense, in which case it would shed little lighton CH. More interesting, however, is the possibility th<strong>at</strong> in contrast to thefirst two versions, it would actually provide an actual counterexample to CH.This, of course, would require the failure of the Foreman-Magidor program.2.2 <strong>The</strong> Foreman-Magidor Program<strong>The</strong> goal of the Foreman-Magidor program was to show th<strong>at</strong> large cardinalaxioms also implied th<strong>at</strong> the third version of CH held for all sets in L(R) and,10


more generally, all universally Baire sets. In other words, the goal was toshow th<strong>at</strong> largecardinal axioms implied th<strong>at</strong> Θ L(R) ℵ 2 and, more generally,th<strong>at</strong> Θ L(A,R) ℵ 2 for each universally Baire set A.<strong>The</strong> motiv<strong>at</strong>ion came from the celebr<strong>at</strong>ed results of Foreman, Magidorand Shelah on Martin’s Maximum (MM), which showed th<strong>at</strong> assuming largecardinal axioms one can always force to obtain a precipitous ideal on ℵ 2without collapsing ℵ 2 . 7 <strong>The</strong> program involved a two-part str<strong>at</strong>egy:(A) Strengthen this result to show th<strong>at</strong> assuming large cardinal axioms onecan always force to obtain a s<strong>at</strong>ur<strong>at</strong>ed ideal on ℵ 2 without collapsingℵ 2 .(B) Show th<strong>at</strong> the existence of such a s<strong>at</strong>ur<strong>at</strong>ed ideal implies th<strong>at</strong> Θ L(R) ℵ 2 and, more generally th<strong>at</strong> Θ L(A,R) ℵ 2 for every universally Baireset A.This would show th<strong>at</strong> show th<strong>at</strong> Θ L(R) ℵ 2 and, more generally th<strong>at</strong>Θ L(A,R) ℵ 2 for every universally Baire set A. 8In December 1991, the following result dashed the hopes of this program.<strong>The</strong>orem 2.1 (Woodin). Assume th<strong>at</strong> the non-st<strong>at</strong>ionary ideal on ℵ 1 iss<strong>at</strong>ur<strong>at</strong>ed and th<strong>at</strong> there is a measurable cardinal. <strong>The</strong>n δ ∼12 = ℵ 2 .<strong>The</strong> point is th<strong>at</strong> the hypothesis of this theorem can always be forced assuminglarge cardinals. Thus, it is possible to have Θ L(R) > ℵ 2 (in fact,1δ∼ 3 > ℵ 2 ).Where did the program go wrong? Foreman and Magidor had an approxim<strong>at</strong>ionto (B) and in the end it turned out th<strong>at</strong> (B) is true.<strong>The</strong>orem 2.2 (Woodin). Assume th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class of Woodincardinals and th<strong>at</strong> there is a s<strong>at</strong>ur<strong>at</strong>ed ideal on ℵ 2 . <strong>The</strong>n for every A ∈ Γ ∞ ,Θ L(A,R) ℵ 2 .7 See Foreman, Magidor & Shelah (1988).8 To see this argue as follows: Assume large cardinal axioms <strong>at</strong> the level involved in(A) and (B) and assume th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose forcontradiction th<strong>at</strong> there is a prewellordering in L(R) of length ℵ 2 . Now, using (A) forceto obtain a s<strong>at</strong>ur<strong>at</strong>ed ideal on ℵ 2 without collapsing ℵ 2 . In this forcing extension, theoriginal prewellordering is still a prewellordering in L(R) of length ℵ 2 , which contradicts(B). Thus, the original large cardinal axioms imply th<strong>at</strong> Θ L(R) ℵ 2 . <strong>The</strong> same argumentapplies in the more general case where the prewellordering is universally Baire.11


So the trouble is with (A).This illustr<strong>at</strong>es an interesting contrast between our three versions of theeffective continuum hypothesis, namely, th<strong>at</strong> they can come apart. For whilelarge cardinals rule out definable counterexamples of the first two kinds, theycannot rule out definable counterexamples of the third kind. But again wemust stress th<strong>at</strong> they cannot prove th<strong>at</strong> there are such counterexamples.But there is animportant point: Assuming largecardinal axioms (AD L(R)suffices), although one can produce outer models in which δ ∼13 > ℵ 2 it is notcurrently known how to produce outer models in which δ ∼13 > ℵ 3 or evenΘ L(R) > ℵ 3 . Thus it is an open possibility th<strong>at</strong> from ZFC+AD L(R) one canprove Θ L(R) ℵ 3 . Were this to be the case, it would follow th<strong>at</strong> althoughlarge cardinals cannot rule out the definable failure of CH they can rule outthe definable failure of 2 ℵ 0= ℵ 2 . This could provide some insight into thesize of the continuum, underscoring the centrality of ℵ 2 .Further Reading: For more on the three effective versions of CH see Martin(1976); for more on the Foreman-Magidor program see Foreman & Magidor(1995) and the introduction to Woodin (1999).3 <strong>The</strong> Case for ¬CH<strong>The</strong> above results led Woodin to the identific<strong>at</strong>ion of a “canonical” modelin which CH fails and this formed the basis of his an argument th<strong>at</strong> CH isfalse. In Section 3.1 we will describe the model and in the remainder of thesection we will present the case for the failure of CH. In Section 3.2 we willintroduce Ω-logic and the other notions needed to make the case. In Section3.3 we will present the case.3.1 P max<strong>The</strong> goal is to find a model in which CH is false and which is canonical in thesense th<strong>at</strong> its theory cannot be altered by set forcing in the presence of largecardinals. <strong>The</strong> background motiv<strong>at</strong>ion is this: First, we know th<strong>at</strong> in thepresence of large cardinal axioms the theory of second-order arithmetic andeven the entire theory of L(R) is invariant under set forcing. <strong>The</strong> importanceof this is th<strong>at</strong> it demonstr<strong>at</strong>es th<strong>at</strong> our main independence techniques cannotbe used to establish the independence of questions about second-order12


arithmetic (orabout L(R)) inthepresence of largecardinals. Second, experiencehas shown th<strong>at</strong> the large cardinal axioms in question seem to answer allof the major known open problems about second-order arithmetic and L(R)and the set forcing invariance theorems give precise content to the claim th<strong>at</strong>these axioms are “effectively complete”. 9It follows th<strong>at</strong> if P is any homogeneous partial order in L(R) then thegeneric extension L(R) P inherits the generic absoluteness of L(R). Woodindiscovered th<strong>at</strong> there isavery special partial order P max th<strong>at</strong>has thisfe<strong>at</strong>ure.Moreover, the model L(R) Pmax s<strong>at</strong>isfies ZFC+¬CH. <strong>The</strong> key fe<strong>at</strong>ure of thismodel is th<strong>at</strong> it is “maximal” (or “s<strong>at</strong>ur<strong>at</strong>ed”) with respect to sentences th<strong>at</strong>are of a certain complexity and which can be shown to be consistent via setforcing over the model; in other words, if these sentences can hold (by setforcing over the model) then they do hold in the model. To st<strong>at</strong>e this moreprecisely we are going to have to introduce a few r<strong>at</strong>her technical notions.<strong>The</strong>re are two ways of str<strong>at</strong>ifying the universe of sets. <strong>The</strong> first is interms of 〈V α | α ∈ On〉, the second is in terms of 〈H(κ) | κ ∈ Card〉, whereH(κ) is the set of all sets which have cardinality less than κ and whosemembers have cardinality less than κ, and whose members of members havecardinality less than κ, and so on. For example, H(ω) = V ω and the theoriesof the structures H(ω 1 ) and V ω+1 are mutually interpretable. This l<strong>at</strong>terstructureisthestructureofsecond-orderarithmeticand, asmentionedabove,large cardinal axioms give us an “effectively complete” understanding of thisstructure. We should like to be in the same position with regard to largerand larger fragments of the universe and the question is whether we shouldproceed in terms of the first or the second str<strong>at</strong>ific<strong>at</strong>ion.<strong>The</strong> second str<strong>at</strong>ific<strong>at</strong>ion is potentially more fine-grained. Assuming CHone has th<strong>at</strong> the theories of H(ω 2 ) and V ω+2 are mutually interpretable andassuming larger and larger fragments of GCH this correspondence continuesupward. But if CH is false then the structure H(ω 2 ) is less rich than thestructure V ω2 . In this event the l<strong>at</strong>ter structure captures full third-orderarithmetic, while the former captures only a small fragment of third-orderarithmetic but is nevertheless rich enough to express CH. Given this, in<strong>at</strong>tempting to understand the universe of sets by working up through it levelby level, it is sensible to use the potentially more fine-grained str<strong>at</strong>ific<strong>at</strong>ion.9 For more on the topic of invariance under set forcing and the extent to which this hasbeen established in the presence of large cardinal axioms, see §4.4 and §4.6 of the entry“Large Cardinals and Determinacy”.13


Our next step isthereforetounderstand H(ω 2 ). It actuallyturnsout th<strong>at</strong>we will be able to understand slightly more and this is somewh<strong>at</strong> technical.We will be concerned with the structure 〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A G 〉 |= ϕ, whereI NS is the non-st<strong>at</strong>ionary ideal on ω 1 and A G is the interpret<strong>at</strong>ion of (thecanonical represent<strong>at</strong>ion of) a set of reals A in L(R). <strong>The</strong> details will not beimportant and the reader is asked to just think of H(ω 2 ) along with some“extra stuff” and not worry about the details concerning the extra stuff. 10We are now in a position to st<strong>at</strong>e the main result:<strong>The</strong>orem 3.1 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> A ∈ P(R) ∩L(R) and ϕ is a Π 2 -sentence(in the extended language with two additional predic<strong>at</strong>es) and there is a setforcing extension V[G] such th<strong>at</strong>〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A G 〉 |= ϕ(where A G is the interpret<strong>at</strong>ion of A in V[G]). <strong>The</strong>nL(R) Pmax |= “〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A〉 |= ϕ”.<strong>The</strong>re are two key points: First, the theory of L(R) Pmax is “effectively complete”in the sense th<strong>at</strong> it is invariant under set forcing. Second, the modelL(R) Pmax is “maximal” (or “s<strong>at</strong>ur<strong>at</strong>ed”) in the sense th<strong>at</strong> it s<strong>at</strong>isfies all Π 2 -sentences (about the relevant structure) th<strong>at</strong> can possibly hold (in the senseth<strong>at</strong> they can be shown to be consistent by set forcing over the model).One would like to get a handle on the theory of this structure by axiom<strong>at</strong>izingit. <strong>The</strong> relevant axiom is the following:Definition 3.2 (Woodin). Axiom (∗): AD L(R) holds and L(P(ω 1 )) is a P max -generic extension of L(R).Finally, this axiom settles CH:<strong>The</strong>orem 3.3 (Woodin). Assume (∗). <strong>The</strong>n 2 ω = ℵ 2 .10 <strong>The</strong> non-st<strong>at</strong>ionary ideal I NS is a proper class from the point of view of H(ω 2 ) and itmanifests (throughSolovay’stheorem onsplitting st<strong>at</strong>ionarysets) a non-trivialapplic<strong>at</strong>ionof AC. For further details concerning A G see §4.6 of the entry “Large Cardinals andDeterminacy”.14


3.2 Ω-<strong>Logic</strong>We will now recast the above results in terms of a strong logic. We shallmake full use of large cardinal axioms and in this setting we are interested inlogics th<strong>at</strong> are “well-behaved” in the sense th<strong>at</strong> the question of wh<strong>at</strong> implieswh<strong>at</strong> is not radically independent. For example, it is well known th<strong>at</strong> CH isexpressible in full second-order logic. It follows th<strong>at</strong> in the presence of largecardinals one can always use set forcing to flip the truth-value of a purportedlogical validity of full second-order logic. However, there are strong logics—likeω-logicandβ-logic—th<strong>at</strong>donothavethisfe<strong>at</strong>ure—theyarewell-behavedin the sense th<strong>at</strong> in the presence of large cardinal axioms the question ofwh<strong>at</strong> implies wh<strong>at</strong> cannot be altered by set forcing. We shall introduce avery strong logic th<strong>at</strong> has this fe<strong>at</strong>ure—Ω-logic. In fact, the logic we shallintroduce can be characterized as the strongest logic with this fe<strong>at</strong>ure. 113.2.1 Ω-logicDefinition 3.4. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> T is a countable theory in the language of settheory and ϕ is a sentence. <strong>The</strong>nT |= Ω ϕif for all complete Boolean algebras B and for all ordinals α,if V B α |= T then V B α |= ϕ.We say th<strong>at</strong> a st<strong>at</strong>ement ϕ is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable if there exists an ordinal αand a complete Boolean algebra B such th<strong>at</strong> V B α |= ϕ, and we say th<strong>at</strong> ϕ isΩ-valid if ∅ |= Ω ϕ. So, the above theorem says th<strong>at</strong> (under our backgroundassumptions), the st<strong>at</strong>ement “ϕ is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable” is generically invariant andin terms of Ω-validity this is simply the following:<strong>The</strong>orem 3.5 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> T is a countable theory in the language ofset theory and ϕ is a sentence. <strong>The</strong>n for all complete Boolean algebras B,T |= Ω ϕ iff V B |= “T |= Ω ϕ.”Thus thislogicisrobust inth<strong>at</strong>thequestion ofwh<strong>at</strong> implieswh<strong>at</strong> isinvariantunder set forcing.11 See Koellner (2010) for further discussion of strong logics and for a precise st<strong>at</strong>ementof this result.15


3.2.2 <strong>The</strong> Ω ConjectureCorresponding to the semantic rel<strong>at</strong>ion |= Ω there is a quasi-syntactic proofrel<strong>at</strong>ion ⊢ Ω . <strong>The</strong> “proofs” are certain robust sets of reals (universally Bairesets of reals) and the test structures are models th<strong>at</strong> are “closed” under theseproofs. <strong>The</strong> precise notions of “closure” and “proof” are somewh<strong>at</strong> technicaland so we will pass over them in silence. 12Like the semantic rel<strong>at</strong>ion, this quasi-syntactic proof rel<strong>at</strong>ion is robustunder large cardinal assumptions:<strong>The</strong>orem 3.6 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. Suppose T is a countable theory in the language of settheory, ϕ is a sentence, and B is a complete Boolean algebra. <strong>The</strong>nT ⊢ Ω ϕ iff V B |= “T ⊢ Ω ϕ”.Thus, wehaveasemanticconsequencerel<strong>at</strong>ionandaquasi-syntacticproofrel<strong>at</strong>ion, both of which are robust under the assumption of large cardinal axioms.It is n<strong>at</strong>ural to ask whether the soundness and completeness theoremshold for these rel<strong>at</strong>ions. <strong>The</strong> soundness theorem is known to hold:<strong>The</strong>orem 3.7 (Woodin). Assume ZFC. Suppose T is a countable theory inthe language of set theory and ϕ is a sentence. If T ⊢ Ω ϕ then T |= Ω ϕ.It is open whether the corresponding completeness theorem holds. <strong>The</strong> ΩConjecture is simply the assertion th<strong>at</strong> it does:Conjecture 3.8 (Ω Conjecture). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a properclass of Woodin cardinals. <strong>The</strong>n for each sentence ϕ,∅ |= Ω ϕ iff ∅ ⊢ Ω ϕ.12 Here are the details: Let A ∈ Γ ∞ and M be a countable transitive model of ZFC. Wesay th<strong>at</strong> M is A-closed if for all set generic extensions M[G] of M, A∩M[G] ∈ M[G]. LetT be a set of sentences and ϕ be a sentence. We say th<strong>at</strong> T ⊢ Ω ϕ if there is a set A ⊆ Rsuch th<strong>at</strong>(1) L(A,R) |= AD + ,(2) P(R)∩L(A,R) ⊆ Γ ∞ , and(3) for all countable transitive A-closed M,M |= “T |= Ω ϕ”,where here AD + is a strengthening of AD.16


We will need a strong form of this conjecture which we shall call theStrong Ω Conjecture. It is somewh<strong>at</strong> technical and so we will pass over it insilence. 133.2.3 Ω-Complete <strong>The</strong>oriesRecall th<strong>at</strong> one key virtue of large cardinal axioms is th<strong>at</strong> they “effectivelysettle” the theory of second-order arithmetic (and, in fact, the theory ofL(R) and more) in the sense th<strong>at</strong> in the presence of large cardinals onecannot use the method of set forcing to establish independence with respectto st<strong>at</strong>ements about L(R). This notion of invariance under set forcing playedakey roleinSection 3.1. Wecannowrephrase thisnotionintermsofΩ-logic.Definition 3.9. A theory T is Ω-complete for a collection of sentences Γ iffor each ϕ ∈ Γ, T |= Ω ϕ or T |= Ω ¬ϕ.<strong>The</strong> invariance of the theory of L(R) under set forcing can now be rephrasedas follows:<strong>The</strong>orem 3.10 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. <strong>The</strong>n ZFC is Ω-complete for the collection of sentences ofthe form “L(R) |= ϕ”.Unfortun<strong>at</strong>ely, it follows from a series of results origin<strong>at</strong>ing with workof Levy and Solovay th<strong>at</strong> traditional large cardinal axioms do not yield Ω-complete theories <strong>at</strong> the level of Σ 2 1 since one can always use a “small” (andhence large cardinal preserving) forcing to alter the truth-value of CH.<strong>The</strong>orem 3.11. Assume L is a standard large cardinal axiom. <strong>The</strong>n ZFC+Lis not Ω-complete for Σ 2 1.13 Here are the details: First we need another conjecture: (<strong>The</strong> AD + Conjecture) Supposeth<strong>at</strong> A and B are sets of reals such th<strong>at</strong> L(A,R) and L(B,R) s<strong>at</strong>isfy AD + . Supposeevery setX ∈ P(R)∩ ( L(A,R)∪L(B,R) )is ω 1 -universally Baire. <strong>The</strong>n eitheror(∆ ∼21 ) L(A,R) ⊆ (∆ ∼21 ) L(B,R)(∆ ∼21 ) L(B,R) ⊆ (∆ ∼21 ) L(A,R) .(Strong Ω conjecture) Assume there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. <strong>The</strong>n the ΩConjecture holds and the AD + Conjecture is Ω-valid.17


3.3 <strong>The</strong> CaseNevertheless, if one supplements large cardinal axioms then Ω-complete theoriesare forthcoming. This is the centerpiece of the case against CH.<strong>The</strong>orem 3.12 (Woodin). Assume th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class of Woodincardinals and th<strong>at</strong> the Strong Ω Conjecture holds.(1) <strong>The</strong>re is an axiom A such th<strong>at</strong>(i) ZFC+A is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable and(ii) ZFC+A is Ω-complete for the structure H(ω 2 ).(2) Any such axiom A has the fe<strong>at</strong>ure th<strong>at</strong>ZFC+A |= Ω “H(ω 2 ) |= ¬CH”.Let us rephrase this as follows: For each A s<strong>at</strong>isfying (1), letT A = {ϕ | ZFC+A |= Ω “H(ω 2 ) |= ¬ϕ”}.<strong>The</strong> theorem says th<strong>at</strong> if there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and theΩ Conjecture holds, then there are (non-trivial) Ω-complete theories T A ofH(ω 2 ) and all such theories contain ¬CH.It is n<strong>at</strong>ural to ask whether there is gre<strong>at</strong>er agreement among the Ω-complete theories T A . Ideally, there would be just one. A recent result(building on <strong>The</strong>orem 5.5) shows th<strong>at</strong> if there is one such theory then thereare many such theories.<strong>The</strong>orem 3.13 (Koellner and Woodin). Assume th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper classof Woodin cardinals. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> A is an axiom such th<strong>at</strong>(i) ZFC+A is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable and(ii) ZFC+A is Ω-complete for the structure H(ω 2 ).<strong>The</strong>n there is an axiom B such th<strong>at</strong>(i ′ ) ZFC+B is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable and(ii ′ ) ZFC+B is Ω-complete for the structure H(ω 2 )18


and T A ≠ T B .How then shall one select from among these theories? Woodin’s work inthis area goes a good deal beyond <strong>The</strong>orem 5.1. In addition to isol<strong>at</strong>ing anaxiomth<strong>at</strong>s<strong>at</strong>isfies (1) of<strong>The</strong>orem 5.1(assuming Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiability), heisol<strong>at</strong>esa very special such axiom, namely, the axiom (∗) (“star”) mentioned earlier.This axiom can be phrased in terms of (the provability notion of) Ω-logic:<strong>The</strong>orem 3.14 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. <strong>The</strong>n the following are equivalent:(1) (∗).(2) For each Π 2 -sentence ϕ in the language for the structureif〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A | A ∈ P(R)∩L(R)〉ZFC+“〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A | A ∈ P(R)∩L(R)〉 |= ϕ”is Ω-consistent, then〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A | A ∈ P(R)∩L(R)〉 |= ϕ.It follows th<strong>at</strong> of the various theories T A involved in <strong>The</strong>orem 5.1, thereis one th<strong>at</strong> stands out: <strong>The</strong> theory T (∗) given by (∗). This theory maximizesthe Π 2 -theory of the structure 〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A | A ∈ P(R)∩L(R)〉.<strong>The</strong> continuum hypothesis fails in this theory. Moreover, in the maximaltheory T (∗) given by (∗) the size of the continuum is ℵ 2 . 14To summarize: Assuming the Strong Ω Conjecture, there is a “good”theory of H(ω 2 ) and all such theories imply th<strong>at</strong> CH fails. Moreover, (again,assuming the Strong Ω Conjecture) there is a maximal such theory and inth<strong>at</strong> theory 2 ℵ 0= ℵ 2 .Further Reading: For the m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics concerning P max see Woodin (1999).For an introduction to Ω-logic see Bagaria, Castells & Larson (2006). Formore on incomp<strong>at</strong>ible Ω-complete theories see Koellner & Woodin (2009).For more on the case against CH see Woodin (2001a), Woodin (2001b),Woodin (2005a), and Woodin (2005b).14 As mentioned <strong>at</strong> the end of Section 2.2 it could be the case (given our present knowledge)th<strong>at</strong> large cardinal axioms imply th<strong>at</strong> Θ L(R) < ℵ 3 and, more generally, rule out thedefinable failure of 2 ℵ0 = ℵ 2 . This would arguably further buttress the case for 2 ℵ0 = ℵ 2 .19


4 <strong>The</strong> Multiverse<strong>The</strong> above case for the failure of CH is the strongest known local case foraxioms th<strong>at</strong> settle CH. In this section and the next we will switch sidesand consider the pluralist arguments to the effect th<strong>at</strong> CH does not havean answer (in this section) and to the effect th<strong>at</strong> there is an equally goodcase for CH (in the next section). In the final two section we will investig<strong>at</strong>eoptimistic global scenarios th<strong>at</strong> provide hope of settling the issue.<strong>The</strong> pluralist maintains th<strong>at</strong> the independence results effectively settlethe undecided questions by showing th<strong>at</strong> they have no answer. One wayof providing a found<strong>at</strong>ional framework for such a view is in terms of themultiverse. On this view there is not a single universe of set theory butr<strong>at</strong>heramultiverse oflegitim<strong>at</strong>ecandid<strong>at</strong>es, someofwhich may bepreferableto others for certain purposes but none of which can be said to be the “true”universe. <strong>The</strong> multiverse conception of truth is the view th<strong>at</strong> a st<strong>at</strong>ement ofset theory can only be said to be true simpliciter if it is true in all universesof the multiverse. For the purposes of this discussion we shall say th<strong>at</strong> ast<strong>at</strong>ement is indetermin<strong>at</strong>e according to the multiverse conception if it isneither true nor false according to the multiverse conception. How radicalsuch a view is depends on the breadth of the conception of the multiverse.4.1 Broad Multiverse Views<strong>The</strong> pluralist is generally a non-pluralist about certain domains of m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics.For example, a strict finitist might be a non-pluralist about PA buta pluralist about set theory and one might be a non-pluralist about ZFC anda pluralist about large cardinal axioms and st<strong>at</strong>ements like CH.<strong>The</strong>re is a form of radical pluralism which advoc<strong>at</strong>es pluralism concerningall domains of m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics. On this view any consistent theory is alegitim<strong>at</strong>e candid<strong>at</strong>e and the corresponding models of such theories are legitim<strong>at</strong>ecandid<strong>at</strong>es for the the domain of m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics. Let us call this thebroadest multiverse view. <strong>The</strong>re is a difficulty inarticul<strong>at</strong>ing this view, whichmay be brought out as follows: To begin with, one must pick a backgroundtheory in which to discuss the various models and this leads to a difficult.For example, according to the broad multiverse conception, since PA cannotprove Con(PA) (by the second incompleteness theorem, assuming th<strong>at</strong> PAis consistent) there are models of PA+¬Con(PA) and these models are legitim<strong>at</strong>ecandid<strong>at</strong>es, th<strong>at</strong> is, they are universes within the broad multiverse.20


Now to arrive <strong>at</strong> this conclusion one must (in the background theory) bein a position to prove Con(PA) (since this assumption is required to applythe second incompleteness theorem in this particular case). Thus, from theperspective of the background theory used to argue th<strong>at</strong> the above modelsare legitim<strong>at</strong>e candid<strong>at</strong>es, the models in question s<strong>at</strong>isfy a false Σ 0 1 -sentence,namely, ¬Con(PA). In short, there is a lack of harmony between wh<strong>at</strong> isheld <strong>at</strong> the meta-level and wh<strong>at</strong> is held <strong>at</strong> the object-level.<strong>The</strong> only way out of this difficulty would seem to be to regard eachviewpoint—each articul<strong>at</strong>ion of the multiverse conception—as provisionaland, when pressed, embrace pluralism concerning the background theory.In other words, one would have to adopt a multiverse conception of themultiverse, a multiverse conception of the multiverse conception of the multiverse,and so on, off to infinity. It follows th<strong>at</strong> such a position can never befully articul<strong>at</strong>ed—each time one <strong>at</strong>tempts to articul<strong>at</strong>e the broad multiverseconception one must employ a background theory but since one is a pluralistabout th<strong>at</strong> background theory this pass <strong>at</strong> using the broad multiverse to articul<strong>at</strong>ethe conception does not do the conception full justice. <strong>The</strong> positionis thus difficult to articul<strong>at</strong>e. One can certainly take the pluralist stance andtry to gesture toward or exhibit the view th<strong>at</strong> one intends by provisionallysettling on a particular background theory but then advoc<strong>at</strong>e pluralism regardingth<strong>at</strong> when pressed. <strong>The</strong> view is thus something of a “moving target”.We shall pass over this view in silence and concentr<strong>at</strong>e on views th<strong>at</strong> can bearticul<strong>at</strong>ed within a found<strong>at</strong>ional framework.We will accordingly look <strong>at</strong> views which embrace non-pluralism with regardto a given stretch of m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics and for reasons of space and becausethis is an entry on set theory we will pass over the long deb<strong>at</strong>es concerningstrict finitism, finitism, predic<strong>at</strong>ivism, and start with views th<strong>at</strong> embracenon-pluralism regarding ZFC.Let the broad multiverse (based on ZFC) be the collection of all modelsof ZFC. <strong>The</strong> broad multiverse conception of truth (based on ZFC) is thensimply the view th<strong>at</strong> a st<strong>at</strong>ement of set theory is true simpliciter if it isprovable in ZFC. On this view the st<strong>at</strong>ement Con(ZFC) and other undecidedΠ 0 1-st<strong>at</strong>ements are classified as indetermin<strong>at</strong>e. This view thus faces adifficulty parallel to the one mentioned above concerning radical pluralism.This motiv<strong>at</strong>es the shift to views th<strong>at</strong> narrow the class of universes inthe multiverse by employing a strong logic. For example, one can restrictto universes th<strong>at</strong> are ω-models, β-models (i.e. wellfounded), etc. On theview where one takes ω-models, the st<strong>at</strong>ement Con(ZFC) is classified as true21


(though this is sensitive to the background theory) but the st<strong>at</strong>ement PM(all projective sets are Lebesgue measurable) is classified as indetermin<strong>at</strong>e.For those who are convinced by the arguments (surveyed in the entry“Large Cardinals and Determinacy”) for large cardinal axioms and axiomsofdefinable determinacy, even thesemultiverse conceptions aretooweak. Wewill followthis route. Fortherest of thisentry we will embrace non-pluralismconcerning large cardinal axioms and axioms of definable determinacy andfocus on the question of CH.4.2 <strong>The</strong> Generic Multiverse<strong>The</strong> motiv<strong>at</strong>ion behind the generic multiverse is to grant the case for largecardinal axioms and definable determinacy but deny th<strong>at</strong> st<strong>at</strong>ements such asCHhave a determin<strong>at</strong>e truthvalue. Tobespecific aboutthe background theorylet us take ZFC+“<strong>The</strong>re is a proper class of Woodincardinals” and recallth<strong>at</strong> this large cardinal assumption secures axioms of definable determinacysuch as PD and AD L(R) .Let the generic multiverse V be the result of closing V under genericextensions and generic refinements. One way to formalize this is by takingan external vantage point and start with a countable transitive model M.<strong>The</strong> generic multiverse based on M is then the smallest set V M such th<strong>at</strong>M ∈ V M and, for each pair of countable transitive models (N,N[G]) suchth<strong>at</strong> N |= ZFC and G ⊆ P is N-generic for some partial order in P ∈ N, ifeither N or N[G] is in V M then both N and N[G] are in V M .Let the generic multiverse conception of truth be the view th<strong>at</strong> a st<strong>at</strong>ementis true simpliciter iff it is true in all universes of the generic multiverse.We will call such a st<strong>at</strong>ement a generic multiverse truth. A st<strong>at</strong>ement is saidto be indetermin<strong>at</strong>e according to the generic multiverse conception iff it isneither true nor false according to the generic multiverse conception. Forexample, granting our large cardinal assumptions, such a view deems PM(and PD and AD L(R) ) true but deems CH indetermin<strong>at</strong>e.4.3 <strong>The</strong> Ω Conjecture and the Generic MultiverseIs the generic multiverse conception of truth tenable? <strong>The</strong> answer to thisquestion is closely rel<strong>at</strong>ed to the subject of Ω-logic. <strong>The</strong> basic connectionbetween generic multiverse truth and Ω-logic is embodied in the followingtheorem:22


<strong>The</strong>orem 4.1 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. <strong>The</strong>n, for each Π 2 -st<strong>at</strong>ement ϕ the following are equivalent:(1) ϕ is a generic multiverse truth.(2) ϕ is Ω-valid.Now, recall th<strong>at</strong> by <strong>The</strong>orem 3.5, under our background assumptions, Ω-validity is generically invariant. It follows th<strong>at</strong> given our background theory,thenotionofgenericmultiversetruthisrobustwithrespecttoΠ 2 -st<strong>at</strong>ements.In particular, for Π 2 -st<strong>at</strong>ements, the st<strong>at</strong>ement “ϕ is indetermin<strong>at</strong>e” is itselfdetermin<strong>at</strong>e according to the generic multiverse conception. In this sensethe conception of truth is not “self-undermining” and one is not sent in adownward spiral where one has to countenance multiverses of multiverses.So it passes the first test. Whether it passes a more challenging test dependson the Ω Conjecture.<strong>The</strong> Ω Conjecture has profound consequences for the generic multiverseconception of truth. Letand, for any specifiable cardinal κ, letV Ω = {ϕ | ∅ |= Ω ϕ}V Ω (H(κ + )) = {ϕ | ZFC |= Ω “H(κ + ) |= ϕ”},where recall th<strong>at</strong> H(κ + ) is the collection of sets of hereditary cardinality lessthan κ + . Thus, assuming ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class of Woodincardinals, the set V Ω is Turing equivalent to the set of Π 2 generic multiversetruths and the set V Ω (H(κ + )) is precisely the set of generic multiverse truthsof H(κ + ).To describe the bearing of the Ω Conjecture on the generic-multiverseconception of truth, we introduce two Transcendence Principles which serveas constraints on any tenable conception of truth in set theory—a truth constraintand a definability constraint.Definition 4.2 (Truth Constraint). Any tenable multiverse conception oftruth in set theory must be such th<strong>at</strong> the Π 2 -truths (according to th<strong>at</strong> conception)in the universe of sets are not recursive in the truths about H(κ)(according to th<strong>at</strong> conception), for any specifiable cardinal.23


Thisconstraint isinthespirit ofthoseprinciples ofset theory—most notably,reflection principles—which aim to capture the pretheoretic idea th<strong>at</strong> theuniverse of sets is so rich th<strong>at</strong> it cannot “be described from below”; moreprecisely, itassertsth<strong>at</strong>anytenableconception oftruthmust respect theide<strong>at</strong>h<strong>at</strong> the universe of sets is so rich th<strong>at</strong> truth (or even just Π 2 -truth) cannotbe described in some specifiable fragment. (Notice th<strong>at</strong> by Tarski’s theoremon the undefinability of truth, the truth constraint is trivially s<strong>at</strong>isfied bythe standard conception of truth in set theory which takes the multiverse tocontain a single element, namely, V.)<strong>The</strong>re is also a rel<strong>at</strong>ed constraint concerning the definability of truth. Foraspecifiable cardinal κ, set Y ⊆ ω isdefinable in H(κ + ) across the multiverseif Y is definable in the structure H(κ + ) of each universe of the multiverse(possibly by formulas which depend on the parent universe).Definition 4.3 (DefinabilityConstraint). Anytenablemultiverseconceptionof truth in set theory must be such th<strong>at</strong> the Π 2 -truths (according to th<strong>at</strong>conception) in the universe of sets are definable in H(κ) across the multiverseuniverse, for any specifiable cardinal κ.Notice again th<strong>at</strong> by Tarski’s theorem on the undefinability of truth, the definabilityconstraint is trivially s<strong>at</strong>isfied by the degener<strong>at</strong>e multiverse conceptionth<strong>at</strong> takes the multiverse to contain the single element V. (Notice alsoth<strong>at</strong>ifonemodifiesthedefinabilityconstraintbyaddingtherequirement th<strong>at</strong>the definition be uniform across the multiverse, then the constraint wouldautom<strong>at</strong>ically be met.)<strong>The</strong> bearing of the Ω Conjecture on the tenability of the genericmultiverseconception of truth is contained in the following two theorems:<strong>The</strong>orem 4.4 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> the Ω Conjecture holds. <strong>The</strong>n V Ω is recursivein V Ω (H(δ + 0 )), where δ 0 is the least Woodin cardinal.<strong>The</strong>orem 4.5 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> the Ω Conjecture holds. <strong>The</strong>n V Ω is definablein H(δ + 0 ), where δ 0 is the least Woodin cardinal.In other words, if there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and if the ΩConjecture holds then the generic multiverse conception of truth viol<strong>at</strong>esboth the Truth Constraint (<strong>at</strong> δ 0 ) and the Definability Constraint (<strong>at</strong> δ 0 ).<strong>The</strong>reareactuallysharperversionsoftheaboveresultsth<strong>at</strong>involveH(c + )in place of H(δ + 0 ). 24


<strong>The</strong>orem 4.6 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> the Ω Conjecture holds. <strong>The</strong>n V Ω is recursivein V Ω (H(c + )).<strong>The</strong>orem 4.7 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> the Ω Conjecture holds and th<strong>at</strong> the AD +Conjecture holds. <strong>The</strong>n V Ω is definable in H(c + ).In other words, if there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and if the ΩConjecture holds then the generic-multiverse conception of truth viol<strong>at</strong>es theTruth Constraint <strong>at</strong> the level of third-order arithmetic, and if, in addition,the AD + Conjecture holds, then the generic-multiverse conception of truthviol<strong>at</strong>es the Definability Constraint <strong>at</strong> the level of third-order arithmetic.4.4 Is <strong>The</strong>re a Way Out?<strong>The</strong>re appear to be four ways th<strong>at</strong> the advoc<strong>at</strong>e of the generic multiversemight resist the above criticism.First, one could maintain th<strong>at</strong> the Ω Conjecture is just as problem<strong>at</strong>ic asCH and hence like CH it is to be regarded as indetermin<strong>at</strong>e according to thegeneric-multiverse conception of truth. <strong>The</strong> difficulty with this approach isthe following:<strong>The</strong>orem 4.8 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. <strong>The</strong>n, for any complete Boolean algebra B,V |= Ω-conjecture iff V B |= Ω-conjecture.Thus, in contrast to CH, the Ω Conjecture cannot be shown to be independentof ZFC+“<strong>The</strong>re is a proper class of Woodin cardinals” via set forcing.In terms of the generic multiverse conception of truth, we can put the pointthis way: While the generic-multiverse conception of truth deems CH to beindetermin<strong>at</strong>e, it does not deem the Ω Conjecture to be indetermin<strong>at</strong>e. Sothe above response is not available to the advoc<strong>at</strong>e of the generic-multiverseconception of truth. <strong>The</strong> advoc<strong>at</strong>e of th<strong>at</strong> conception already deems the ΩConjecture to be determin<strong>at</strong>e.Second, one could grant th<strong>at</strong> the Ω Conjecture is determin<strong>at</strong>e but maintainth<strong>at</strong> it is false. <strong>The</strong>re are ways in which one might do this but th<strong>at</strong>does not undercut the above argument. <strong>The</strong> reason is the following: To beginwith there is a closely rel<strong>at</strong>ed Σ 2 -st<strong>at</strong>ement th<strong>at</strong> one can substitute for25


the Ω Conjecture in the above arguments. This is the st<strong>at</strong>ement th<strong>at</strong> theΩ Conjecture is (non-trivially) Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable, th<strong>at</strong> is, the st<strong>at</strong>ement: <strong>The</strong>reexists an ordinal α and a universe V ′ of the multiverse such th<strong>at</strong>andV ′ α |= ZFC+“<strong>The</strong>re is a proper class of Woodin cardinals”V ′ α |= “<strong>The</strong> Ω Conjecture”.This Σ 2 -st<strong>at</strong>ement is invariant under set forcing and hence is one adherentsto the generic multiverse view of truth must deem determin<strong>at</strong>e. Moreover,the key arguments above go through with this Σ 2 -st<strong>at</strong>ement instead of theΩ Conjecture. <strong>The</strong> person taking this second line of response would thusalso have to maintain th<strong>at</strong> this st<strong>at</strong>ement is false. But there is substantialevidence th<strong>at</strong> this st<strong>at</strong>ement is true. <strong>The</strong> reason is th<strong>at</strong> there is no knownexample of a Σ 2 -st<strong>at</strong>ement th<strong>at</strong> is invariant under set forcing rel<strong>at</strong>ive to largecardinal axioms and which cannot be settled by large cardinal axioms. (Sucha st<strong>at</strong>ement would be a candid<strong>at</strong>e for an absolutely undecidable st<strong>at</strong>ement.)So it is reasonable to expect th<strong>at</strong> this st<strong>at</strong>ement is resolved by large cardinalaxioms. However, recent advances in inner model theory—in particular,those in Woodin (2011b)—provide evidence th<strong>at</strong> no large cardinal axiom canrefute this st<strong>at</strong>ement. Putting everything together: It is very likely th<strong>at</strong> thisst<strong>at</strong>ement is in fact true; so this line of response is not promising.Third, one could reject either the Truth Constraint or the DefinabilityConstraint. <strong>The</strong> trouble is th<strong>at</strong> if one rejects the Truth Constraint then onthis view (assuming the Ω Conjecture) Π 2 truth in set theory is reducible inthe sense of Turing reducibility to truth in H(δ 0 ) (or, assuming the StrongΩ Conjecture, H(c + )). And if one rejects the Definability Constraint thenon this view (assuming the Ω Conjecture) Π 2 truth in set theory is reduciblein the sense of definability to truth in H(δ 0 ) (or, assuming the Strong ΩConjecture, H(c + )). On either view, the reduction is in tension with theacceptance of non-pluralism regarding the background theory ZFC+“<strong>The</strong>reis a proper class of Woodin cardinals”.Fourth, onecouldembracethecriticism, rejectthegenericmultiverse conceptionof truth, and admit th<strong>at</strong> there are some st<strong>at</strong>ements about H(δ + 0 ) (orH(c + ), granting, in addition, the AD + Conjecture) th<strong>at</strong> are true simpliciterbut not true in the sense of the generic-multiverse, and yet nevertheless continueto maintain th<strong>at</strong> CH is indetermin<strong>at</strong>e. <strong>The</strong> difficulty is th<strong>at</strong> any suchsentence ϕ is qualit<strong>at</strong>ively just like CH in th<strong>at</strong> it can be forced to hold and26


forced to fail. <strong>The</strong> challenge for the advoc<strong>at</strong>e of this approach is to modifythe generic-multiverse conception of truth in such a way th<strong>at</strong> it counts ϕ asdetermin<strong>at</strong>e and yet counts CH as indetermin<strong>at</strong>e.In summary: <strong>The</strong>re is evidence th<strong>at</strong> the only way out is the fourth wayoutandthisplaces theburden back onthepluralist—the pluralist must comeup with a modified version of the generic multiverse.Further Reading: FormoreontheconnectionbetweenΩ-logicandthegenericmultiverse and the above criticism of the generic multiverse see Woodin(2011a). For the bearing of recent results in inner model theory on thest<strong>at</strong>us of the Ω Conjecture see Woodin (2011b).5 <strong>The</strong> Local Case RevisitedLet us now turn to a second way in which one might resist the local case forthe failure of CH. This involves a parallel case for CH. In Section 5.1 we willreview the main fe<strong>at</strong>ures of the case for ¬CH in order to compare it with theparallel case for CH. In Section 5.2 we will present the parallel case for CH.In Section 5.3 we will assess the comparison.5.1 <strong>The</strong> Case for ¬CHRecall th<strong>at</strong> there are two basic steps in the case presented in Section 3.3.<strong>The</strong> first step involves Ω-completeness (and this gives ¬CH) and the secondstep involves maximality (and this gives the stronger 2 ℵ 0= ℵ 2 ). For ease ofcomparison we shall repe<strong>at</strong> these fe<strong>at</strong>ures here:<strong>The</strong> first step is based on the following result:<strong>The</strong>orem 5.1 (Woodin). Assume th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class of Woodincardinals and th<strong>at</strong> the Strong Ω Conjecture holds.(1) <strong>The</strong>re is an axiom A such th<strong>at</strong>(i) ZFC+A is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable and(ii) ZFC+A is Ω-complete for the structure H(ω 2 ).(2) Any such axiom A has the fe<strong>at</strong>ure th<strong>at</strong>ZFC+A |= Ω “H(ω 2 ) |= ¬CH”.27


Let us rephrase this as follows: For each A s<strong>at</strong>isfying (1), letT A = {ϕ | ZFC+A |= Ω “H(ω 2 ) |= ¬ϕ”}.<strong>The</strong> theorem says th<strong>at</strong> if there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and theStrong Ω Conjecture holds, then there are (non-trivial) Ω-complete theoriesT A of H(ω 2 ) and all such theories contain ¬CH. In other words, under theseassumptions, there is a “good” theory and all “good” theories imply ¬CH.<strong>The</strong> second step begins with the question of whether there is gre<strong>at</strong>eragreement among the Ω-complete theories T A . Ideally, there would be justone. However, this is not the case.<strong>The</strong>orem 5.2 (Koellner and Woodin). Assume th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper classof Woodin cardinals. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> A is an axiom such th<strong>at</strong>(i) ZFC+A is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable and(ii) ZFC+A is Ω-complete for the structure H(ω 2 ).<strong>The</strong>n there is an axiom B such th<strong>at</strong>(i ′ ) ZFC+B is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable and(ii ′ ) ZFC+B is Ω-complete for the structure H(ω 2 )and T A ≠ T B .This raises the issue as to how one is to select from among these theories?It turns out th<strong>at</strong> there is a maximal theory among the T A and this is givenby the axiom (∗).<strong>The</strong>orem 5.3 (Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class ofWoodin cardinals. <strong>The</strong>n the following are equivalent:(1) (∗).(2) For each Π 2 -sentence ϕ in the language for the structureif〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A | A ∈ P(R)∩L(R)〉ZFC+“〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A | A ∈ P(R)∩L(R)〉 |= ϕ”is Ω-consistent, then〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A | A ∈ P(R)∩L(R)〉 |= ϕ.28


So, of the various theories T A involved in <strong>The</strong>orem 5.1, there is one th<strong>at</strong>stands out: <strong>The</strong> theory T (∗) given by (∗). This theory maximizes the Π 2 -theory of the structure 〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A | A ∈ P(R) ∩ L(R)〉. <strong>The</strong> fundamentalresult is th<strong>at</strong> in this maximal theory2 ℵ 0= ℵ 2 .5.2 <strong>The</strong> Parallel Case for CH<strong>The</strong>parallelcaseforCHalsohastwosteps, thefirstinvolving Ω-completenessand the second involving maximality.<strong>The</strong> first result in the first step is the following:<strong>The</strong>orem 5.4 (Woodin, 1985). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper classof measurable Woodin cardinals. <strong>The</strong>n ZFC+CH is Ω-complete for Σ 2 1 .Moreover, up to Ω-equivalence, CH is the unique Σ 2 1-st<strong>at</strong>ement th<strong>at</strong> is Ω-complete for Σ 2 1 ; th<strong>at</strong> is, letting T A be the Ω-complete theory given by ZFC+A where A is Σ 2 1 , all such T A are Ω-equivalent to T CH and hence (trivially)all such T A contain CH. In other words, there is a “good” theory and all“good” theories imply CH.To complete the first step we have to determine whether this result isrobust. For it could be the case th<strong>at</strong> when one considers the next level,Σ 2 2 (or further levels, like third-order arithmetic) CH is no longer part ofthe picture, th<strong>at</strong> is, perhaps large cardinals imply th<strong>at</strong> there is an axiom Asuch th<strong>at</strong> ZFC+A is Ω-complete for Σ 2 2 (or, going further, all of third orderarithmetic) and yet not all such A have an associ<strong>at</strong>ed T A which contains CH.We must rule this out if we are to secure the first step.<strong>The</strong> most optimistic scenario along these lines is this: <strong>The</strong> scenario isth<strong>at</strong> there is a large cardinal axiom L and axioms A ⃗ such th<strong>at</strong> ZFC+L+⃗A is Ω-complete for all of third-order arithmetic and all such theories areΩ-equivalent and imply CH. Going further, perhaps for each specifiablefragment V λ of the universe of sets there is a large cardinal axiom L andaxioms A ⃗ such th<strong>at</strong> ZFC+L+ A ⃗ is Ω-complete for the entire theory of V λand, moreover, th<strong>at</strong> such theories are Ω-equivalent and imply CH. Werethis to be the case it would mean th<strong>at</strong> for each such λ there is a unique Ω-completepictureofV λ andwewouldhaveauniqueΩ-completeunderstandingof arbitrarily large fragments of the universe of sets. This would make for a29


strong case for new axioms completing the axioms of ZFC and large cardinalaxioms.Unfortun<strong>at</strong>ely, this optimistic scenario fails: Assuming the existence ofone such theory one can construct another which differs on CH:<strong>The</strong>orem 5.5 (Koellner and Woodin). Assume ZFC and th<strong>at</strong> there is aproper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose V λ is a specifiable fragment of theuniverse (th<strong>at</strong> is sufficiently large) and suppose th<strong>at</strong> there is a large cardinalaxiom L and axioms ⃗ A such th<strong>at</strong><strong>The</strong>n there are axioms ⃗ B such th<strong>at</strong>ZFC+L+ ⃗ A is Ω-complete for Th(V λ ).ZFC+L+ ⃗ B is Ω-complete for Th(V λ )and the first theory Ω-implies CH if and only if the second theory Ω-implies¬CH.This still leaves us with the question of existence and the answer to thisquestion is sensitive to the Ω Conjecture and the AD + Conjecture:<strong>The</strong>orem 5.6 (Woodin). Assume th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class of Woodincardinals and th<strong>at</strong> the Ω Conjecture holds. <strong>The</strong>n there is no recursive theory⃗A such th<strong>at</strong> ZFC+ ⃗ A is Ω-complete for the theory of V δ0 +1, where δ 0 is theleast Woodin cardinal.In fact, under a stronger assumption, the scenario must fail <strong>at</strong> a much earlierlevel.<strong>The</strong>orem 5.7 (Woodin). Assume th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper class of Woodincardinals and th<strong>at</strong> the Ω Conjecture holds. Assume th<strong>at</strong> the AD + Conjectureholds. <strong>The</strong>n there is no recursive theory ⃗ A such th<strong>at</strong> ZFC+ ⃗ A is Ω-completefor the theory of Σ 2 3 .It is open whether there can be such a theory <strong>at</strong> the level of Σ 2 2. It isconjectured th<strong>at</strong> ZFC + ♦ is Ω-complete (assuming large cardinal axioms)for Σ 2 2.Let us assume th<strong>at</strong> it is answered positively and return to the questionof uniqueness. For each such axiom A, let T A be the Σ 2 2 theory computed byZFC+A in Ω-logic. <strong>The</strong> question of uniqueness simply asks whether T A isunique.30


<strong>The</strong>orem 5.8 (Koellner and Woodin). Assume th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper classof Woodin cardinals. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> A is an axiom such th<strong>at</strong>(i) ZFC+A is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable and(ii) ZFC+A is Ω-complete for Σ 2 2 .<strong>The</strong>n there is an axiom B such th<strong>at</strong>(i ′ ) ZFC+B is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable and(ii ′ ) ZFC+B is Ω-complete for Σ 2 2and T A ≠ T B .This is the parallel of <strong>The</strong>orem 5.2.To complete the parallel one would need th<strong>at</strong> CH is among all of the T A .This is not known. But it is a reasonable conjecture.Conjecture 5.9. Assume large cardinal axioms.(1) <strong>The</strong>re is an Σ 2 2 axiom A such th<strong>at</strong>(i) ZFC+A is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable and(ii) ZFC+A is Ω-complete for the Σ 2 2 .(2) Any such Σ 2 2axiom A has the fe<strong>at</strong>ure th<strong>at</strong>ZFC+A |= Ω CH.Should this conjecture hold it would provide a true analogue of <strong>The</strong>orem 5.1.This would complete the parallel with the first step.<strong>The</strong>re is also a parallel with the second step. Recall th<strong>at</strong> for the secondstep in the previous subsection we had th<strong>at</strong> although the various T A did notagree, they all contained ¬CH and, moreover, from among them there is oneth<strong>at</strong> stands out, namely the theory given by (∗), since this theory maximizesthe Π 2 -theory of the structure 〈H(ω 2 ),∈,I NS ,A | A ∈ P(R)∩L(R)〉. In thepresent context of CHwe again(assuming theconjecture) have th<strong>at</strong> althoughthe T A do not agree, they all contain CH. It turns out th<strong>at</strong> once again, fromamong them there is one th<strong>at</strong> stands out, namely, the maximum one. Forit is known (by a result of Woodin in 1985) th<strong>at</strong> if there is a proper class31


of measurable Woodin cardinals then there is a forcing extension s<strong>at</strong>isfyingall Σ 2 2 sentences ϕ such th<strong>at</strong> ZFC + CH + ϕ is Ω-s<strong>at</strong>isfiable. (See Larson,Ketchersid & Zapletal (2008).) It follows th<strong>at</strong> if the question of existenceis answered positively with an A th<strong>at</strong> is Σ 2 2 then T A must be this maximumΣ 2 2 theory and, consequently, all T A agree when A is Σ 2 2 . So, assuming th<strong>at</strong>there is a T A where A is Σ 2 2, then, although not all T A agree (when A isarbitrary) there is one th<strong>at</strong> stands out, namely, the one th<strong>at</strong> is maximum forΣ 2 2 sentences.Thus, if the above conjecture holds, then the case of CH parallels th<strong>at</strong>of ¬CH, only now Σ 2 2 takes the place of the theory of H(ω 2).5.3 AssessmentAssuming th<strong>at</strong> the conjecture holds the case of CH parallels th<strong>at</strong> of ¬CH,only now Σ 2 2 takes the place of the theory of H(ω 2): Under the backgroundassumptions we have:(1) (a) there are A such th<strong>at</strong> ZFC+A is Ω-complete for H(ω 2 )(b) for every such A the associ<strong>at</strong>ed T A contains ¬CH, and(c) there is a T A which is maximal, namely, T (∗) and this theory contains2 ℵ 0= ℵ 2 .(2) (a) there are Σ 2 2-axioms A such th<strong>at</strong> ZFC+A is Ω-complete for Σ 2 2(b) for every such A the associ<strong>at</strong>ed T A contains CH, and(c) there is a T A which is maximal.<strong>The</strong> two situ<strong>at</strong>ions are parallel with regard to maximality but in termsof the level of Ω-completeness the first is stronger. For in the first case weare not just getting Ω-completeness with regard to the Π 2 theory of H(ω 2 )(with the additional predic<strong>at</strong>es), r<strong>at</strong>her we are getting Ω-completeness withregard to all of H(ω 2 ). This is arguably an argument in favour of the casefor ¬CH, even granting the conjecture.But there is a stronger point. <strong>The</strong>re is evidence coming from inner modeltheory (which we shall discuss in the next section) to the effect th<strong>at</strong> theconjecture is in fact false. Should this turn out to be the case it would breakthe parallel, strengthening the case for ¬CH.However, one might counter this as follows: <strong>The</strong> higher degree of Ω-completeness in the case for ¬CH is really illusory since it is an artifact of32


the fact th<strong>at</strong> under (∗) the theory of H(ω 2 ) is in fact mutually interpretablewith th<strong>at</strong> of H(ω 1 ) (by a deep result of Woodin). Moreover, this l<strong>at</strong>ter factis in conflict with the spirit of the Transcendence Principles discussed inSection 4.3. Those principles were invoked in an argument to the effect th<strong>at</strong>CH does not have an answer. Thus, when all the dust settles the real importof Woodin’s work on CH (so the argument goes) is not th<strong>at</strong> CH is false butr<strong>at</strong>her th<strong>at</strong> CH very likely has an answer.It seems fair to say th<strong>at</strong> <strong>at</strong> this stage the st<strong>at</strong>us of the local approachesto resolving CH is somewh<strong>at</strong> unsettled. For this reason, in the remainder ofthis entry we shall focus on global approaches to settling CH. We shall verybriefly discuss two such approaches—the approach via inner model theoryand the approach via quasi-large cardinal axioms.6 <strong>The</strong> Ultim<strong>at</strong>e Inner ModelInner model theory aims to produce “L-like” models th<strong>at</strong> contain large cardinalaxioms. For each large cardinal axiom Φ th<strong>at</strong> has been reached by innermodel theory, one has an axiom of the form V=L Φ . This axiom has thevirtue th<strong>at</strong> (just as in the simplest case of V=L) it provides an “effectivelycomplete” solution regarding questions about L Φ (which, by assumption, isV). Unfortun<strong>at</strong>ely, it turns out th<strong>at</strong> the axiom V=L Φ is incomp<strong>at</strong>ible withstronger large cardinal axioms Φ ′ . For this reason, axioms of this form havenever been considered as plausible candid<strong>at</strong>es for new axioms.But recent developments in inner model theory (due to Woodin) showth<strong>at</strong> everything changes <strong>at</strong> the level of a supercompact cardinal. <strong>The</strong>se developmentsshow th<strong>at</strong> if there is an inner model N which “inherits” a supercompactcardinal from V (in the manner in which one would expect, giventhe trajectory of inner model theory), then there are two remarkable consequences:First, N is close to V (in, for example, the sense th<strong>at</strong> for sufficientlylarge singular cardinals λ, N correctly computes λ + ). Second, N inherits allknown large cardinals th<strong>at</strong> exist in V. Thus, in contrast to the inner modelsth<strong>at</strong> have been developed thus far, an inner model <strong>at</strong> the level of a supercompactwould provide one with an axiom th<strong>at</strong> could not be refuted by strongerlarge cardinal assumptions.<strong>The</strong> issue, of course, is whether one can have an “L-like” model (oneth<strong>at</strong> yields an “effectively complete” axiom) <strong>at</strong> this level. <strong>The</strong>re is reasonto believe th<strong>at</strong> one can. <strong>The</strong>re is now a candid<strong>at</strong>e model L Ω th<strong>at</strong> yields33


an axiom V=L Ω with the following fe<strong>at</strong>ures: First, V=L Ω is “effectivelycomplete.” Second, V=L Ω is comp<strong>at</strong>ible with all large cardinal axioms.Thus, on this scenario, the ultim<strong>at</strong>e theory would be the (open-ended) theoryZFC+V=LΩ +LCA, where LCAis a schema standing for“largecardinalaxioms.” <strong>The</strong> large cardinal axioms will c<strong>at</strong>ch instances of Gödelian independenceand the axiom V=L Ω will capture the remaining instances of independence.This theory would imply CH and settle the remaining undecidedst<strong>at</strong>ements. Independence would cease to be an issue.It turns out, however, th<strong>at</strong> there are other candid<strong>at</strong>e axioms th<strong>at</strong> sharethese fe<strong>at</strong>ures, and so the spectre of pluralism reappears. For example, thereare axioms V=L Ω S and V=LΩ (∗). <strong>The</strong>se axioms would also be “effectivelycomplete” and comp<strong>at</strong>ible with all large cardinal axioms. Yet they wouldresolve various questions differently than the axiom V=L Ω . For example,the axiom, V=L Ω (∗)would imply ¬CH. How, then, is one to adjudic<strong>at</strong>ebetween them?Further Reading: For an introduction to inner model theory see Mitchell(2010) and Steel (2010). For more on the recent developments <strong>at</strong> the level ofone supercompact and beyond see Woodin (2011b).7 <strong>The</strong> Structure <strong>The</strong>ory of L(V λ+1 )This brings us to the second global approach, one th<strong>at</strong> promises to select thecorrect axiom from among V=L Ω , V=L Ω S , V=LΩ (∗), and their variants. Thisapproach is based on the remarkable analogy between the structure theoryof L(R) under the assumption of AD L(R) and the structure theory of L(V λ+1 )under the assumption th<strong>at</strong> there is an elementary embedding from L(V λ+1 )into itself with critical point below λ. This embedding assumption is thestrongest large cardinal axiom th<strong>at</strong> appears in the liter<strong>at</strong>ure.<strong>The</strong> analogy between L(R) and L(V λ+1 ) is based on the observ<strong>at</strong>ion th<strong>at</strong>L(R) is simply L(V ω+1 ). Thus, λ is the analogue of ω, λ + is the analogueof ω 1 , and so on. As an example of the parallel between the structure theoryof L(R) under AD L(R) and the structure theory of L(V λ+1 ) under theembedding axiom, let us mention th<strong>at</strong> in the first case, ω 1 is a measurablecardinal in L(R) and, in the second case, the analogue of ω 1 —namely, λ + —isa measurable cardinal in L(V λ+1 ). This result is due to Woodin and is justone instance from among many examples of the parallel th<strong>at</strong> are contained34


in his work.Now, we have a gre<strong>at</strong> deal of inform<strong>at</strong>ion about the structure theory ofL(R) under AD L(R) . Indeed, as we noted above, this axiom is “effectivelycomplete” with regard to questions about L(R). In contrast, the embeddingaxiom on its own is not sufficient to imply th<strong>at</strong> L(V λ+1 ) has a structure theoryth<strong>at</strong> fully parallels th<strong>at</strong> of L(R) under AD L(R) . However, the existence ofan already rich parallel is evidence th<strong>at</strong> the parallel extends, and we can supplementthe embedding axiom by adding some key components. When onedoes so, something remarkable happens: the supplementary axioms becomeforcing fragile. This means th<strong>at</strong> they have the potential to erase independenceand provide non-trivial inform<strong>at</strong>ion about V λ+1 . For example, thesesupplementary axioms might settle CH and much more.<strong>The</strong> difficulty in investig<strong>at</strong>ing the possibilities for the structure theory ofL(V λ+1 ) is th<strong>at</strong> we have not had the proper lenses through which to view it.<strong>The</strong>troubleis th<strong>at</strong>themodel L(V λ+1 )contains alargepiece oftheuniverse—namely, L(V λ+1 )—and the theory of this structure is radically underdetermined.<strong>The</strong> results discussed above provide us with the proper lenses. Forone can examine the structure theory of L(V λ+1 ) in the context of ultim<strong>at</strong>einner models like L Ω , L Ω S , LΩ (∗), and their variants. <strong>The</strong> point is th<strong>at</strong> thesemodels can accommod<strong>at</strong>e the embedding axiom and, within each, one willbe able to compute the structure theory of L(V λ+1 ).This provides a means to select the correct axiom from among V=L Ω ,V=L Ω S , V=LΩ (∗) , and their variants. One simply looks <strong>at</strong> the L(V λ+1) ofeach model (where the embedding axiom holds) and checks to see which hasthe true analogue of the structure theory of L(R) under the assumption ofAD L(R) . Itisalreadyknownth<strong>at</strong>certainpieces ofthestructuretheorycannothold in L Ω . But it is open whether they can hold in L Ω S .Let us consider one such (very optimistic) scenario: <strong>The</strong> true analogueof the structure theory of L(R) under AD L(R) holds of the L(V λ+1 ) of L Ω Sbut not of any of its variants. Moreover, this structure theory is “effectivelycomplete” for the theory of V λ+1 . Assuming th<strong>at</strong> there is a proper classof λ where the embedding axiom holds, this gives an “effectively complete”theory of V. And, remarkably, part of th<strong>at</strong> theory is th<strong>at</strong> V must be L Ω S .This (admittedly very optimistic) scenario would constitute a very strongcase for axioms th<strong>at</strong> resolve all of the undecided st<strong>at</strong>ements.One should not place too much weight on this particular scenario. It isjust one of many. <strong>The</strong> point is th<strong>at</strong> we are now in a position to write down a35


list of definite questions with the following fe<strong>at</strong>ures: First, the questions onthis list will have answers—independence is not an issue. Second, if the answersconverge then one will have strong evidence for new axioms settling theundecided st<strong>at</strong>ements (and hence non-pluralism about the universe of sets);whileiftheanswers oscill<strong>at</strong>e, onewill haveevidence th<strong>at</strong>these st<strong>at</strong>ements are“absolutely undecidable” and this will strengthen the case for pluralism. Inthis way the questions of “absolute undecidability” and pluralism are givenm<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical traction.Further Reading: For more on the structure theory of L(V λ+1 ) and the parallelwith determinacy see Woodin (Forthcoming).ReferencesAbraham, U. & Magidor, M. (2010). Cardinal arithmetic, (Foreman &Kanamori 2010), Springer.Bagaria,J., Castells, N.&Larson, P.(2006). AnΩ-logicprimer, inJ.Bagaria& S. Todorcevic (eds), Set theory, Trends in M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics, Birkhäuser,Basel, pp. 1–28.Foreman, M. & Kanamori, A. (2010). Handbook of Set <strong>The</strong>ory, Springer-Verlag.Foreman, M. & Magidor, M. (1995). Large cardinals and definable counterexamplesto the continuum hypothesis, Annals of Pure and Applied<strong>Logic</strong> 76: 47–97.Foreman, M., Magidor, M. & Shelah, S. (1988). Martin’s Maximum, s<strong>at</strong>ur<strong>at</strong>edideals, and non-regular ultrafilters. Part i, Annals of M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics127: 1–47.Hallett, M. (1984). Cantorian Set <strong>The</strong>ory and Limit<strong>at</strong>ion of Size, Vol. 10 ofOxford <strong>Logic</strong> Guides, Oxford University Press.Holz, M., Steffens, K. & Weitz, E. (1999). Introduction to Cardinal Arithmetic,Birkhäuser Advanced Texts, Birkhäuser Verlag, Basel.Jech, T. J. (2003). Set <strong>The</strong>ory: Third Millennium Edition, Revised andExpanded, Springer-Verlag, Berlin.36


Koellner, P. (2010). Strong logics of first and second order, Bulletin of Symbolic<strong>Logic</strong> 16(1): 1–36.Koellner, P. & Woodin, W. H. (2009). Incomp<strong>at</strong>ible Ω-complete theories,<strong>The</strong> Journal of Symbolic <strong>Logic</strong> 74(4).Larson, P., Ketchersid, R. & Zapletal, J. (2008). Regular embeddings of thest<strong>at</strong>ionary tower and Woodin’s Σ 2 2 maximality theorem. Preprint.Martin, D. A. (1976). Hilbert’s first problem: <strong>The</strong> <strong>Continuum</strong> <strong>Hypothesis</strong>,in F. Browder (ed.), M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical Developments Arising from Hilbert’sProblems, Vol. 28 of Proceedings of Symposia in Pure M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics,American M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical Society, Providence, pp. 81–92.Mitchell, W. (2010). Beginning inner model theory, (Foreman & Kanamori2010), Springer.Steel, J. R. (2010). An outline of inner model theory, (Foreman & Kanamori2010), Springer.Woodin, W. H. (1999). <strong>The</strong> Axiom of Determinacy, Forcing Axioms, andthe Nonst<strong>at</strong>ionary Ideal, Vol. 1 of de Gruyter Series in <strong>Logic</strong> and itsApplic<strong>at</strong>ions, de Gruyter, Berlin.Woodin, W. H. (2001a). <strong>The</strong> continuum hypothesis, part I, Notices of theAmerican M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical Society 48(6): 567–576.Woodin, W. H. (2001b). <strong>The</strong> continuum hypothesis, part II, Notices of theAmerican M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical Society 48(7): 681–690.Woodin, W. H. (2005a). <strong>The</strong> continuum hypothesis, in R.Cori, A. Razborov,S. Todorĉević & C. Wood (eds), <strong>Logic</strong> Colloquium 2000, Vol. 19 of LectureNotes in <strong>Logic</strong>, Associ<strong>at</strong>ion of Symbolic <strong>Logic</strong>, pp. 143–197.Woodin, W. H. (2005b). Set theory after Russell: the journey back to Eden,in G. Link (ed.), One Hundred Years Of Russell’s Paradox: M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics,<strong>Logic</strong>, Philosophy, Vol. 6 of de Gruyter Series in <strong>Logic</strong> and ItsApplic<strong>at</strong>ions, Walter De Gruyter Inc, pp. 29–47.37


Woodin, W. H. (2011a). <strong>The</strong> <strong>Continuum</strong> <strong>Hypothesis</strong>, the generic-multiverseofsets, andtheΩ-conjecture, inJ. Kennedy &R.Kossak(eds), Set <strong>The</strong>ory,Arithmetic, and Found<strong>at</strong>ions of M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ics: <strong>The</strong>orems, Philosophies,Vol. 36 of Lecture Notes in <strong>Logic</strong>, Cambridge University Press.Woodin, W. H.(2011b). Suitableextender models I,Journal of M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical<strong>Logic</strong> 11(1–2): 101–339.Woodin, W.H.(Forthcoming). Suitableextender modelsII,Journal of M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical<strong>Logic</strong> .38

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!