12.07.2015 Views

Moral Relativism

Moral Relativism

Moral Relativism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

2areas. I shall be concerned with finding the right amount, and the right kind, ofobjectivity for moral judgements within the framework. Thus the ultimate aim of thepaper is to sketch an account of judgement which (a) allows an answer to the question“Are moral judgements objective, and if so to what extent?” and (b) explains why moraljudgements in particular present an especially difficult and controversial case. I shall startby summarising my approach to the general problem, then I shall develop and refine thatapproach and apply it to moral judgements.The general problem of non-objectivityI shall start by outlining my view about the general problem of objectivity by consideringcases that are much easier and clearer than the case of moral judgement. Consider(1) Chewing tobacco is rich in vitamins.(2) Chewing tobacco is enjoyable.In important respects, (1) and (2) are similar: they have the same grammatical and logicalform. They both express propositions that can be called “true”. There are certainstandards of correctness for both: one could err in believing the propositions they express.Both have negations, and their negations are incompatible with them. However, manypeople, including myself, differentiate between (1) and (2) in terms of the objectivity oftheir subject matter: (2) does not concern an objective matter while (1) does. (The reasonsfor saying that evaluative propositions lack objectivity are ultimately epistemological: ifwe are to say that there are objective facts of the matter, to which our judgements onthese matters are answerable, then we also need some account of how thinkers can accessthese very facts independently of one another.)I follow Crispin Wright (1992) in thinking that objectivity or lack thereof isindependent of truth-aptness. A proposition can be truth-apt yet lack objectivity. But whatis objectivity if not aptitude for truth? According to the definition I shall be using, aproposition is objective just if we know in an a priori manner that if there is adisagreement on that proposition then at least one party is mistaken. Conversely, aproposition is not objective if a disagreement on it, for all we know, may not involve anymistake. Let’s consider the example again. The idea is that a disagreement on (1)conclusively shows that one of the parties has made a mistake, while a disagreement on(2) does not. In other words, if you think chewing tobacco is rich in vitamins and I thinkit’s not, then one of us is wrong, and we know this in an a priori manner (more on thislater). By contrast, if you think chewing tobacco is delicious and I think it’s not, then thatalone does not show that one of us is wrong. The matter is less clear for moralpropositions, like the one expressed by:(3) It is morally wrong to use chewing tobacco.Here it is controversial whether (3) should be grouped with (1) or with (2) when it comesto objectivity. It is the uultimate aim of this paper to describe the kind of objectivityexhibited by judgements like the one expressed by (3) compared to those expressed by(1) and (2). But before I get to that, I will need to do a lot of stagesetting.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!