12.07.2015 Views

Heller M, Woodin W.H. (eds.) Infinity. New research frontiers (CUP, 2011)(ISBN 1107003873)(O)(327s)_MAml_

Heller M, Woodin W.H. (eds.) Infinity. New research frontiers (CUP, 2011)(ISBN 1107003873)(O)(327s)_MAml_

Heller M, Woodin W.H. (eds.) Infinity. New research frontiers (CUP, 2011)(ISBN 1107003873)(O)(327s)_MAml_

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

260 notes on the concept of the infinitetruth: the diffusiveness of the good is sustained only by the absolute inexpressivenessof its ultimate principle. At the last, the “infinite” in Plotinus is still a concept governedby the α-privative.7. There was no reason for any of the classical pagan schools of thought to movebeyond this concept of the infinite; no principle indigenous to pagan thought demandedthat they do so.12.3 The “Christian Infinite”1. In the intellectual world of the first three centuries before the Council of Nicaea,especially in the eastern half of the empire, something like a “Logos metaphysics”was a crucial part of the philosophical lingua franca of almost the entire educatedclass, pagan, Jewish, Christian, and even Gnostic (even though the term generallypreferred was rarely “logos”). Certainly, this was the case in Alexandria: the idea ofa “derivative” or “secondary” divine principle was an indispensable premise in thecity’s native schools of Trinitarian reflection and in the thought of either “Hellenized”Jews like Philo or of the Platonists, middle or late. Furthermore, one could describeall of these systems, without any significant exception, pagan and Jewish no less thanChristian, as “subordinationist” in structure. All of them attempted, with greater orlesser complexity, and with more or less vivid mythical adornments, to connect theworld here below to its highest principle by populating the interval between them withvarious intermediate degrees of spiritual reality. All of them, that is, were shaped by thesame basic metaphysical impulse, one sometimes described as the “pleonastic fallacy”:the notion that, in order to overcome the infinite disproportion between the immanentand the transcendent, it is enough to conceive of some sort of tertium quid –orofanumber of successively more accommodating quiddities – between, on the one hand,the One or the Father or oJ QeoV” and, on the other, the world of finite and mutablethings.2. In all such systems, the second “moment” of the real – that which proce<strong>eds</strong>directly from the supreme principle of all things (logos, ornous, or what have you) –was understood as a kind of economic limitation of its source, so reduced in “scale”and nature as to be capable of entering into contact with the realm of discrete beings, oftranslating the power of the supreme principle into various finite effects, and of unitingthis world to the wellspring of all things. This derivative principle, therefore, may notas a rule properly be called oJ QeoV”, but it definitely is qeoV”: God with respect toall lower reality. (This, of course, is why Augustine, in Confessions VII.9, credits thePlatonists with having taught him the truths revealed in John 1:1–3.) Moreover, thisinevitably meant that this secondary moment of the real was understood as mediatingthis supreme principle in only a partial and distorted way, for such a Logos (let us settleon this as our term) can appear within the totality of things that are only as a restrictionand diffusion of – even perhaps a deviation or alienation from – that which is “mostreal,” the Father who, in the purity of his transcendence, can never directly touch thisworld. For Christians who thought in such terms, this almost inevitably implied that theLogos had been, in some sense, generated with respect to the created order, as its mostexalted expression, certainly, but as inseparably involved in its existence nonetheless.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!