12.07.2015 Views

Is the Market a Test of Truth and Beauty?: Essays in Political Economy

Is the Market a Test of Truth and Beauty?: Essays in Political Economy

Is the Market a Test of Truth and Beauty?: Essays in Political Economy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> a <strong>Test</strong><strong>of</strong>TRUTH BEAUTY?<strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>byL B. YLudwig von Mises Institute


© 2011 by <strong>the</strong> Ludwig von Mises Institute <strong>and</strong> publishedunder <strong>the</strong> Creative Commons Attribution License 3.0.http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/Ludwig von Mises Institute518 West Magnolia AvenueAuburn, Alabama 36832mises.orgISBN: 978-1-61016-188-6


ContentsIntroduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . vii : Should Austrians Scorn General Equilibrium eory? . . . . Why Subjectivism? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics . . . . . . . . . . . e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> . . . e Debate over Calculation <strong>and</strong> Knowledge . . . . . . . . . Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong> . . . <strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> a <strong>Test</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Truth</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Beauty</strong>? . . . . . . . . . . Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation . . . . . . . . . . . . . e Keynesian Heritage <strong>in</strong> Economics . . . . . . . . . . . . Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . L<strong>and</strong>, Money, <strong>and</strong> Capital Formation . . . . . . . . . . . . Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d . . . . . . . . . . . . Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences . . . . . . : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Elementos del Economia Politic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? . . . . . . . . . . . Economics <strong>and</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . American Democracy Diagnosed . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Civic Religion Reasserted . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . A Libertarian Case for Monarchy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . v


viContents Uchronia, or Alternative History . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Hayek on <strong>the</strong> Psychology <strong>of</strong> Socialism <strong>and</strong> Freedom . . . . . Kirzner on <strong>the</strong> Morality <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Pr<strong>of</strong>it . . . . . . . . . Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law . . . . . . e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’s Human Action . . . . . . . . . Can a Liberal Be an Egalitarian? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal . . . . . . . Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .


Introductionis book’s title is <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> newly chosen title <strong>of</strong> chapter , “<strong>Is</strong><strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> a <strong>Test</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Truth</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Beauty</strong>?” at chapter, along with <strong>the</strong>one before it, questions a dangerously false argument for <strong>the</strong> free-marketeconomy sometimes made by its supposed friends. eir argument threatensto discredit, by association, <strong>the</strong> powerful <strong>and</strong> valid case for <strong>the</strong> market.Asked whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> market is a test <strong>of</strong> truth <strong>and</strong> beauty—<strong>of</strong> excellence—AynR<strong>and</strong> would presumably give <strong>the</strong> same answer as m<strong>in</strong>e: “No,<strong>of</strong> course not!” Consider her hero <strong>of</strong> e Founta<strong>in</strong>head, Howard Roark.<strong>Political</strong> economy is <strong>the</strong> area <strong>of</strong> overlap among economics, politicalscience, <strong>and</strong> philosophy. Beyond its positive content, political economydoes bear on policy but not only on policy; it is far from a hodge-podge <strong>of</strong>different people’s policy prejudices. Economics, when not disregarded, isobviously relevant to policy. So are philosophy <strong>and</strong> psychology, as when<strong>the</strong>y underlie doctr<strong>in</strong>es such as redistributionism <strong>and</strong> egalitarianism. Policycan affect economics. More exactly, a policy proposal may help clarifya str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> economic analysis even when, consider<strong>in</strong>g side-effects, <strong>the</strong>author does not actually recommend <strong>the</strong> policy; “L<strong>and</strong>, Money, <strong>and</strong> CapitalFormation,” chapter , provides an example. Regrettably, though,policy-driven economists do exist who start with <strong>the</strong>ir or <strong>the</strong>ir employers’preferred policies <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n twist <strong>the</strong>ir analysis <strong>in</strong>to support<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m.Writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> political economy, be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary, typically omit<strong>the</strong> deep technicalities <strong>of</strong> any specific field. Most <strong>of</strong> this book’s chaptersare semipopular pieces that <strong>the</strong> attentive “general reader” should underst<strong>and</strong>.ey deal with <strong>in</strong>tersect<strong>in</strong>g fields ra<strong>the</strong>r than with advanced details<strong>of</strong> any one field. Left out <strong>of</strong> this book, <strong>the</strong>n, are any <strong>of</strong> my relatively technicalwrit<strong>in</strong>gs, as on monetary <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational economics. A fewsemitechnical chapters, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g numbers <strong>and</strong> , come close to mak<strong>in</strong>gan exception. Chapter contributes to a field <strong>of</strong> particular <strong>in</strong>terestto Austrian economists, capital <strong>the</strong>ory. Yet it too strives for nontechnicallanguage.vii


viiiIntroductionSome l<strong>in</strong>kages among <strong>the</strong> chosen articles may not be immediatelyobvious. But, for example, “Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics” <strong>and</strong> “Uchronia, orAlternative History” both illum<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong> chance aspects <strong>of</strong> life. So do<strong>in</strong>g,both bear on political philosophy (as on <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> luck <strong>in</strong> personal status).Both also underl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> difficulty <strong>of</strong> p<strong>in</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> supposed “deepparameters” <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy <strong>and</strong> so to mak<strong>in</strong>g quantitative predictions, asopposed to what F.A. Hayek (1967) called “pattern predictions.” (Far be itfrom me, however, to say that <strong>the</strong> necessary achievements <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> econometriciansare forever downright impossible.)About half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> articles deal with economics <strong>in</strong> particular. “eDebate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong>” <strong>and</strong> “e DebateOver Calculation <strong>and</strong> Knowledge” are among <strong>the</strong>m. e latter chaptersummarizes po<strong>in</strong>ts made more fully <strong>in</strong> my “Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek on Calculation<strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 7, no. 2, 1994, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> ensu<strong>in</strong>g debate with Joseph Salerno, Guido Hülsmann, Jeffrey Herbener,<strong>and</strong> Hans-Hermann Hoppe <strong>in</strong> 1996 <strong>and</strong> 1997 issues <strong>of</strong> that Review.at debate runs to too many pages for <strong>in</strong>clusion here (see <strong>the</strong> Review’sissues <strong>of</strong> 1994, 1996, <strong>and</strong> 1997, onl<strong>in</strong>e at <strong>the</strong> Mises Institute’s website).My “Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong>,” chapter, also provoked controversy, specifically from David Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> RobertTollison <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Quarterly Journal <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 3, no. 1, Spr<strong>in</strong>g2000. e reader should read <strong>the</strong>ir article (at <strong>the</strong> Mises Institute’s website)along with or before read<strong>in</strong>g my reply <strong>in</strong> chapter .Chapters on “Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation,” “e KeynesianHeritage <strong>in</strong> Economics,” “Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes,” <strong>and</strong> “e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard” deal with money-macro topics. e last two <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Economics chapters concern methodology or, ra<strong>the</strong>r, countermethodology:<strong>the</strong>y advise aga<strong>in</strong>st be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>timidated by narrow methodologicalpreach<strong>in</strong>g.Several chapters <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy section exam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong>merits <strong>and</strong> demerits <strong>of</strong> democratic government. Two <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m are bookreviews. One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> books treats <strong>the</strong> American political system realistically.e o<strong>the</strong>r takes <strong>the</strong> George Stigler/Earl ompson l<strong>in</strong>e that—if I mayexaggerate just a bit—whatever <strong>in</strong>stitution exists must be optimal or atleast satisfactory; o<strong>the</strong>rwise it would already have been replaced. O<strong>the</strong>rchapters <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> section deal with political philosophy.Most chapters are repr<strong>in</strong>ted with only slight edit<strong>in</strong>g, particularly tost<strong>and</strong>ardize <strong>the</strong> system <strong>of</strong> references. Chapter has been exp<strong>and</strong>ed (<strong>and</strong>renamed) to take account <strong>of</strong> developments <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> fifteen years s<strong>in</strong>ce it first


Acknowledgmentsixappeared, <strong>and</strong> chapter (also renamed) has been modified at its beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gto read less like an <strong>in</strong>vited <strong>in</strong>troduction to o<strong>the</strong>rs’ articles. Several pages <strong>of</strong>chapter have been cut out because <strong>the</strong>y rebut a stra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong>Mises’s work that is hardly worth attention. Chapter , “e Debate about<strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong>,” although <strong>and</strong> perhaps especiallybecause it dates from 1949, is pr<strong>in</strong>ted unchanged.e selection process has just happened to give <strong>the</strong> book an Austrianflavor not orig<strong>in</strong>ally <strong>in</strong>tended. e bulk <strong>of</strong> my work is not particularlyAustrian. On whe<strong>the</strong>r I count as an Austrian economist, see <strong>the</strong> open<strong>in</strong>gl<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> chapter .For enjoyable <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>structive discussions over many years, I am <strong>in</strong>debtedto dozens, even hundreds, <strong>of</strong> students <strong>in</strong> my graduate Sem<strong>in</strong>ar <strong>in</strong> <strong>Political</strong><strong>Economy</strong> at <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia <strong>and</strong> at Auburn University.(at sem<strong>in</strong>ar covered its topics <strong>in</strong> more scope, detail, <strong>and</strong> technicalitiesthan <strong>the</strong> articles <strong>in</strong>cluded here.) Many persons, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g ones both mentioned<strong>and</strong> unmentioned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual papers, have given me valuable<strong>in</strong>struction, encouragement, provocation, <strong>and</strong> warn<strong>in</strong>gs. I hesitate tolist names because any such list would be <strong>in</strong>complete <strong>and</strong> would sufferfrom my lapses <strong>of</strong> memory; but it would <strong>in</strong>clude Roger Garrison, LuisDopico, Daniel Edwards, Robert Greenfield, Roger Koppl, Juergen Backhaus,Steven Caudill, Warren Nutter, Edgar Brown<strong>in</strong>g, William Breit,Northrup Buechner, Murray Rothbard, James Buchanan, Gordon Tullock,<strong>and</strong>, to go back many years, Aurelius Morgner, James Waller, <strong>and</strong>Clarence Philbrook.e Ludwig von Mises Institute made no suggestion that I moderateany views contrary to its own. For this <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r reasons I am<strong>in</strong>debted to Llewellyn Rockwell, <strong>the</strong> Institute’s chairman, <strong>and</strong> DouglasFrench, its president. Jeffrey Tucker, editorial vice president, encouraged<strong>and</strong> patiently supported this book project from <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g. Perhaps<strong>the</strong> Institute’s greatest support has been <strong>the</strong> services <strong>of</strong> Miss Lauren Barlow.She helped select <strong>the</strong> papers to repr<strong>in</strong>t; st<strong>and</strong>ardized <strong>the</strong> system <strong>of</strong>citations (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g placement <strong>of</strong> notes where <strong>the</strong>y belong, at <strong>the</strong> bottom<strong>of</strong> each page); questioned errors, undue repetition, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>felicitous formulations;coped with many drafts; <strong>and</strong> gave <strong>in</strong>valuable support on <strong>the</strong>many arduous chores scarcely imag<strong>in</strong>able by someone who has not triedto assemble diverse articles <strong>in</strong>to a coherent (I hope) book.


xIntroductionFor <strong>the</strong>se reasons I extend my special admiration <strong>and</strong> thanks to LaurenBarlow.Hayek, F.A. “Degrees <strong>of</strong> Explanation” <strong>and</strong> “e eory <strong>of</strong> Complex Phenomena.”In Studies <strong>in</strong> Philosophy, Politics <strong>and</strong> Economics, 3–21, <strong>and</strong> 22–42. Chicago:University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, .


Economics


Should Austrians ScornGeneral Equilibrium eory? *Austrian economists try to expla<strong>in</strong> how a whole economic system functions.ey do not focus narrowly on <strong>the</strong> circumstances <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualhousehold or <strong>the</strong> geometry <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual firm. ey <strong>in</strong>vestigate <strong>the</strong>coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mutually <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>g yet separately decided activities<strong>of</strong> many millions <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual units; <strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong>vestigate general <strong>in</strong>terdependence.General equilibrium is a somewhat narrower concept. (“GE” is aconvenient abbreviation for both “general equilibrium” <strong>and</strong>, as contextrequires, general-equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory or approach.) By GE I mean work by<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> tradition <strong>of</strong> Léon Walras, Vilfredo Pareto, Gustav Cassel, GerardDebreu (1959), Robert Kuenne (1963, 1968), Kenneth Arrow <strong>and</strong> FrankHahn (1971), <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. Distaste for GE among Austrian economistsis familiar, as it was among Chicago economists such as Milton Friedman<strong>and</strong> George Stigler (who thought that it somehow stood <strong>in</strong> rivalrywith Marshallian partial-equilibrium analysis). Austrians sometimes stateexplicit reasons for <strong>the</strong>ir scorn, but <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>the</strong>y take <strong>the</strong> reasons as too wellknown to need repeat<strong>in</strong>g. I myself have been accused <strong>of</strong> a GE m<strong>in</strong>dset<strong>in</strong> a context that takes such a m<strong>in</strong>dset for granted as a bad th<strong>in</strong>g (Salerno1994, pp. 115–120).*From Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 11, nos. 1–2 (1999): 19–30. Austrians pursue a l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> research marked out by Adam Smith, try<strong>in</strong>g “to expla<strong>in</strong>how a system <strong>of</strong> ‘Natural Liberty’, a market economy based upon private ownership <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> self-<strong>in</strong>terested pursuit <strong>of</strong> utility <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its, could become coord<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> such a waythat it generates ever-exp<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g circles <strong>of</strong> productivity, efficiency <strong>and</strong> growth” (Boettke<strong>and</strong> Prychitko 1998, p. x). Reasons are reviewed by Boettke <strong>and</strong> Prychitko 1998 <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> several <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> articlesrepr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> volumes that <strong>the</strong>y edited. eir Introduction, those articles, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>present article re<strong>in</strong>force <strong>and</strong> supplement each o<strong>the</strong>r.3


4 Part I: Economics Jesús Huerta de Soto provides an example <strong>of</strong> scorn <strong>in</strong> his 1992 Spanishbook on socialism, economic calculation, <strong>and</strong> entrepreneurship. It is anexcellent <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>sightful book, apart from some methodological preach<strong>in</strong>g.Huerta de Soto regrets<strong>the</strong> negative effects that ma<strong>the</strong>matical formalism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> perniciousobsession with analyses based on full <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> on equilibriumhave had on <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> our science. It is likewise necessary toab<strong>and</strong>on <strong>the</strong> functional <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> price determ<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong> replace it witha <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> prices that expla<strong>in</strong>s how <strong>the</strong>se are established dynamically as<strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> a sequential <strong>and</strong> evolv<strong>in</strong>g process driven by <strong>the</strong> force <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> entrepreneurial function, that is, by <strong>the</strong> human actions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> actors<strong>in</strong>volved, <strong>and</strong> not by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tersection <strong>of</strong> mysterious curves or functionslack<strong>in</strong>g any real existence, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation necessary to formulate<strong>the</strong>m does not exist even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> actors <strong>in</strong>volved. (Huerta deSoto 1992, pp. 34–35)Jack High (1994) provides ano<strong>the</strong>r example. Especially s<strong>in</strong>ce WorldWar II, he says, ma<strong>in</strong>stream economists shifted <strong>the</strong>ir attention from actualmarket prices ma<strong>in</strong>ly to <strong>the</strong>ir hypo<strong>the</strong>tical counterparts <strong>in</strong> equilibrium.ose economists could say much about how producers <strong>and</strong> consumerswould react to given prices but little about how prices were formed <strong>and</strong>adjusted. GE existence pro<strong>of</strong>s supposed that producers <strong>and</strong> consumerswere maximiz<strong>in</strong>g with respect to “given” prices. To dodge <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong>how prices reach <strong>the</strong>ir equilibrium values, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory brought <strong>in</strong> a deus exmach<strong>in</strong>a, a fictional economywide auctioneer who somehow achieves thisresult. “e fundamental motivat<strong>in</strong>g force <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory was absentfrom <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> price formation” (High 1994, pp. 151–152, quotationfrom p. 152).High <strong>in</strong>vokes <strong>the</strong> authority <strong>of</strong> Robert Clower (1975/1986) for a fur<strong>the</strong>rverdict on GE. Although Clower does not classify himself as an Austrian,overlaps between his <strong>and</strong> Austrian views justify quot<strong>in</strong>g him also.To argue that neo-Walrasian <strong>the</strong>ory has any bear<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> observablebehavior <strong>of</strong> an economy actually <strong>in</strong> motion, we should have to regard it I cannot f<strong>in</strong>d mention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> auctioneer <strong>in</strong> Walras’s own writ<strong>in</strong>gs; <strong>and</strong> Donald Walker,<strong>the</strong> lead<strong>in</strong>g liv<strong>in</strong>g U.S. expert on Walras, assured me (<strong>in</strong> conversation) that <strong>the</strong> auctioneer<strong>in</strong>deed does not appear <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. at prodigious figure is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>vention <strong>of</strong> later <strong>the</strong>oriststry<strong>in</strong>g to make <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory tighter.


Chapter : Should Austrians Scorn General Equilibrium eory? 5as provid<strong>in</strong>g a complete description <strong>of</strong> actual behavior ra<strong>the</strong>r than a partialdescription <strong>of</strong> virtual behavior—<strong>and</strong> that we surely cannot do. Strictly<strong>in</strong>terpreted, neo-Walrasian <strong>the</strong>ory is descriptive only <strong>of</strong> a fairy-tale world<strong>of</strong> notional economic activities that bears not <strong>the</strong> slightest resemblance toany economy <strong>of</strong> record, past, present, or future. It is science fiction, pure<strong>and</strong> simple—clever <strong>and</strong> elegant science fiction, no doubt, but sciencefiction all <strong>the</strong> same. (Clower 1975/1986, p. 195)More recently Clower noted<strong>the</strong> meretriciousness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economist’s notion <strong>of</strong> “equilibrium.” In everybranch <strong>of</strong> physical science, “equilibrium” refers to a “balance <strong>of</strong> forces”[citations omitted] such as might be associated with an olive rest<strong>in</strong>gat <strong>the</strong> bottom <strong>of</strong> a cone-shaped mart<strong>in</strong>i glass; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> word mislead<strong>in</strong>glyconjures up analogous images when it is used by economic <strong>the</strong>orists.Strictly speak<strong>in</strong>g, however, <strong>the</strong> “equilibria” that neowalrasian <strong>the</strong>oryshows to exist are more correctly called solutions [to a system <strong>of</strong>implicitly-def<strong>in</strong>ed algebraic equations]. So understood, <strong>the</strong> importantachievements <strong>of</strong> neowalrasian equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory lose much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>irapparent lustre, which should <strong>in</strong> any case adhere to <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>maticalgeniuses Gauss <strong>and</strong> Brouwer whose work underlies all modern existencepro<strong>of</strong>s. (Clower 1995, p. 317; <strong>the</strong> eight words <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second pair <strong>of</strong> bracketsare Clower’s.)Clower justly objects to how some economists have stretched <strong>the</strong>concept <strong>of</strong> equilibrium. Robert Lucas <strong>and</strong> omas Sargent (1978, p. 58)appeared to congratulate <strong>the</strong>mselves on <strong>the</strong> “dramatic development” that<strong>the</strong> very mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term “equilibrium” had undergone. Sargent (<strong>in</strong>terviewed<strong>in</strong> Klamer 1983, pp. 67–68) expressed satisfaction with “fancier”notions <strong>of</strong> equilibrium, “much more complicated” notions <strong>of</strong> marketclear<strong>in</strong>g,<strong>and</strong> “fancy new k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> equilibrium models.” Well, to recommenddestabiliz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> words, subvert<strong>in</strong>g communication,is <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> methodologiz<strong>in</strong>g that needs to be dragged <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> open<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>spected. If what economists “with proper sensitivity tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g” call<strong>the</strong> “computable dynamic general equilibrium model” really is <strong>the</strong> realbus<strong>in</strong>esscycle model, as Bernard Saffran (1995, p. 231) suggests, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>Is</strong>hare contempt for it. Some str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> GE do perhaps deserve scorn or neglect. But let uskeep our scorn well focused. e problem lies not with <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory’s


6 Part I: Economicscentral ideas but with some abuses committed <strong>in</strong> its name. ese <strong>in</strong>cludeparades <strong>of</strong> sham rigor <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical games that make no contactwith reality (cf. Buchanan 1983/1988, Allais 1989). More specifically, <strong>the</strong>yarguably <strong>in</strong>clude obsession with <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical requirements for existence,uniqueness, <strong>and</strong> stability <strong>of</strong> GE to <strong>the</strong> extent <strong>of</strong> crowd<strong>in</strong>g out attentionto economic substance. (On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, let <strong>the</strong> would-be ma<strong>the</strong>maticiansamuse <strong>the</strong>mselves as <strong>the</strong>y like, provided <strong>the</strong>y not deceive o<strong>the</strong>rpeople about <strong>the</strong> significance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir efforts.) A related abuse is push<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> strongest-l<strong>in</strong>k pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, <strong>the</strong> tacit idea that a <strong>the</strong>ory is as strong not asits weakest but as its logically most rigorous l<strong>in</strong>k (cf. Mayer 1993, pp. x,57–63, 80, 127–130, <strong>and</strong> passim). Still o<strong>the</strong>rs are frontiersmanship <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rvarieties <strong>of</strong> tacit methodological preach<strong>in</strong>g (cf. chapter below).e correct response to abuses is to p<strong>in</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>the</strong>m. If we appraise adoctr<strong>in</strong>e or approach or technique by whe<strong>the</strong>r or not it might be abused,mis<strong>in</strong>terpreted, distorted, set aside, or taught with unduly narrow <strong>and</strong>exclusive emphasis, we are putt<strong>in</strong>g it to a test that no doctr<strong>in</strong>e can pass.GE is <strong>of</strong>ten charged with be<strong>in</strong>g static <strong>and</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g preoccupied withan all-around equilibrium <strong>in</strong> which all plans mesh <strong>and</strong> all prices, be<strong>in</strong>gat <strong>the</strong>ir market-clear<strong>in</strong>g levels, convey exact <strong>in</strong>formation. e services <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> mysterious auctioneer leave no scope for entrepreneurial activity <strong>and</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r actual market processes. e <strong>the</strong>ory ignores complexity, uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty,judgment, creativity, <strong>and</strong> enterprise. In a sense <strong>the</strong>se compla<strong>in</strong>ts are correct. Of course formalized equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory does not teach us everyth<strong>in</strong>g about economics, <strong>and</strong> perhaps noteven <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> ideas. No one known to me claims that it is <strong>the</strong> whole story.Of course GE leaves room for <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> processes at work <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>real world <strong>of</strong> disequilibrium. We cannot learn everyth<strong>in</strong>g at once, but wecan learn someth<strong>in</strong>g from a static view <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n go on to dynamics <strong>and</strong>process. e two str<strong>and</strong>s complement each o<strong>the</strong>r; GE affords <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>togeneral <strong>in</strong>terdependence. We can better underst<strong>and</strong> market pressures <strong>and</strong>processes if we have an idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> state toward which <strong>the</strong>y are work<strong>in</strong>g(if <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>the</strong>y are equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g ra<strong>the</strong>r than disequilibrat<strong>in</strong>g) <strong>and</strong> if thisstate helps us, by contrast, to contemplate disequilibrium, <strong>the</strong> nonmesh<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> plans. Ludwig von Mises recognized <strong>the</strong> usefulness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “evenlyrotat<strong>in</strong>g economy” as an analytical benchmark (1949/1966, pp. 244–250<strong>and</strong> passim). We need not suppose that <strong>the</strong> world ever actually reaches


Chapter : Should Austrians Scorn General Equilibrium eory? 7equilibrium; we can rema<strong>in</strong> duly scornful <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories (like a recently fashionablebr<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> macroeconomics) that treat equilibrium-always as a substantiveproposition.I taught a course <strong>in</strong> GE at <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia for several yearsflank<strong>in</strong>g 1960. e pr<strong>of</strong>essors who had named <strong>the</strong> course, years earlier,apparently thought that GE was a fancy name for macroeconomics, but Itook <strong>the</strong> course title at face value. Large doses <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Mises’s <strong>and</strong> Hayek’s <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to socialist calculation, werehelpful, I th<strong>in</strong>k, <strong>in</strong> rescu<strong>in</strong>g GE from <strong>the</strong> sterility <strong>of</strong> its worst versions.I never saw any necessary tension between GE <strong>and</strong> Austrian economics. . GE gives us a view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic system as a whole. Analysis<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> behavior <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual firms <strong>and</strong> households has little po<strong>in</strong>t unlessit fits <strong>in</strong>to underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> system (cf. Eucken 1954, pp. 220–221). Forexample, <strong>the</strong> charge that a monopoly firm’s output is too small has littlemean<strong>in</strong>g unless it is related to <strong>the</strong> economywide allocation <strong>of</strong> resources.. Especially when bolstered by contemplation <strong>of</strong> a centrally adm<strong>in</strong>isteredeconomy, GE illum<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>the</strong> complexity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> task performedby entrepreneurs <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r agents, guided by <strong>the</strong> price system. It illum<strong>in</strong>ates<strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> decentralized decisions for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> a fuller use <strong>of</strong>knowledge, with prices communicat<strong>in</strong>g signals <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives.. Contemplat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> immense task ideally performed by economywidecoord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g processes underl<strong>in</strong>es <strong>the</strong> attendant scope for th<strong>in</strong>gsto go wrong. (Compare medical students’ attention to <strong>the</strong> physiology <strong>of</strong>a healthy body.) e surpris<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>g is not so much that coord<strong>in</strong>ationsometimes fails as that <strong>the</strong> processes work at all. Failure is most evident <strong>in</strong>depression, when people keenly desire to trade with one ano<strong>the</strong>r (althoughmore through multilateral than bilateral exchanges), yet run <strong>in</strong>to frustration.Alerted to <strong>the</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation problem, we can better look for disruptiveconditions or events.. GE illum<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>the</strong> real significance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> money prices, costs,<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>comes confront<strong>in</strong>g households, firms, <strong>and</strong> governments. It expla<strong>in</strong>sopportunity cost <strong>in</strong> a way not possible with partial analysis alone. All toocommonly, opportunity cost is def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> choices madeby a particular decisionmaker: <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> his chosen course <strong>of</strong> action is<strong>the</strong> next-best course that he <strong>the</strong>reby forgoes. at def<strong>in</strong>ition, br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g tom<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> considerations <strong>and</strong> even agonies <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g decisions,


8 Part I: Economicsseems familiar to <strong>the</strong> layman. is deceptive familiarity trivializes <strong>the</strong> concept.What requires <strong>the</strong> economist’s expertise <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> student’s alertness tolearn<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g new is opportunity cost <strong>in</strong> a deeper sense—<strong>the</strong> widersocial significance <strong>of</strong> money cost. Misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g still abounds. How<strong>of</strong>ten do we hear compla<strong>in</strong>ts about desired production <strong>and</strong> services be<strong>in</strong>gcurtailed or worthwhile projects shelved out <strong>of</strong> grubby concern with meremoney cost? (Even <strong>the</strong> epi<strong>the</strong>t “greed” gets tossed around.) What needsrepeated explanation is how money costs reflect <strong>the</strong> subjectively appraisedvalues <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r outputs <strong>and</strong> activities necessarily forgone if resourcesare withheld from <strong>the</strong>m for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular output or activity <strong>in</strong>question. What fur<strong>the</strong>r needs explanation is how money costs <strong>and</strong> pricestransmit <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives to decisionmakers. (is is not tosay that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation conveyed about opportunity cost is completelyaccurate; for one th<strong>in</strong>g, real-world prices are not GE prices. However,<strong>the</strong> market process, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g entrepreneurial activity, works to weed outgross <strong>in</strong>accuracies.)Expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g opportunity cost <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> nontrivial sense is not easy. EvenIrv<strong>in</strong>g Fisher (1930/1970, pp. 485–487, 534–541) astonish<strong>in</strong>gly denied thatone particular price, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate, measures any genu<strong>in</strong>e opportunitycost. Precisely because <strong>the</strong> expository task is such a dem<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g one, itis important to beware <strong>of</strong> deceptively simple <strong>and</strong> familiar formulations<strong>and</strong> examples. is is what a GE framework helps to do. It helps portray<strong>the</strong> variety <strong>and</strong> diffusion <strong>of</strong> sacrifices <strong>of</strong> alternative goods, <strong>in</strong>tangible orsubjective as well as tangible, that <strong>the</strong> money cost <strong>of</strong> a particular goodmeasures.. e GE framework is a necessary background for special str<strong>and</strong>s<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. Monetary <strong>the</strong>ory is closely bound up with concepts <strong>of</strong> general<strong>in</strong>terdependence, s<strong>in</strong>ce money is <strong>the</strong> one good traded on all markets. GEhelps show how price-level determ<strong>in</strong>acy presupposes a nom<strong>in</strong>al anchor,provided ei<strong>the</strong>r by a commodity st<strong>and</strong>ard (or foreign-exchange st<strong>and</strong>ard)or by quantitative regulation <strong>of</strong> a fiat currency. In <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g,capital, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest, GE helps us underst<strong>and</strong> conceptual dist<strong>in</strong>ctions evenbetween magnitudes that are <strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong> equilibrium (apart from differences<strong>in</strong> risk, liquidity, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like), such as <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate on loans,rates <strong>of</strong> return on capital goods <strong>and</strong> l<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> agio <strong>of</strong> present over futuregoods, subjective marg<strong>in</strong>al rates <strong>of</strong> time preference, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> technologicalmarg<strong>in</strong>al productivity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> capital goods. It shows <strong>the</strong>error <strong>of</strong> quarrel<strong>in</strong>g over supposedly rival partial-equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terest.


Chapter : Should Austrians Scorn General Equilibrium eory? 9. GE triggers alertness to consequences <strong>of</strong> particular actions, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>gones remote <strong>in</strong> space <strong>and</strong> time; it alerts one to <strong>the</strong> Law <strong>of</strong> Un<strong>in</strong>tendedConsequences (cf. Meade’s primary, secondary, <strong>and</strong> tertiary effects <strong>in</strong> his1955, esp. chaps. XIII, XXXI, XXXII).Here are some examples <strong>of</strong> repercussions that GE helps illum<strong>in</strong>ate:Why monetary expansion lowers <strong>in</strong>terest rates only transitionally; howmonetary expansion affects <strong>the</strong> price level; why survey results on <strong>the</strong>supposed <strong>in</strong>terest-<strong>in</strong>sensitivity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment decisions do not prove thatmonetary policy is <strong>in</strong>effective (cf. Wicksell’s cumulative process). GEhelps us underst<strong>and</strong> how <strong>the</strong> strength <strong>of</strong> some relation about which wehave <strong>in</strong>adequate direct empirical evidence may be judged <strong>in</strong>directly byempirical evidence on someth<strong>in</strong>g else that is related to <strong>the</strong> first, even ifnot <strong>in</strong> an obvious way. One example <strong>in</strong>volves import <strong>and</strong> export supply<strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> elasticities <strong>and</strong> purchas<strong>in</strong>g-power parity. My next three claims, numbers 7, 8 <strong>and</strong> 9, are <strong>in</strong>terrelated <strong>and</strong>, unfortunately,lengthy. ey concern avoid<strong>in</strong>g fallacies.. GE analysis helps clarify <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between data <strong>and</strong> variables<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic system. (More exactly, <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction perta<strong>in</strong>s notso much to objectively exist<strong>in</strong>g reality itself as to analysis <strong>of</strong> a particularaspect <strong>of</strong> it, or to a particular str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> analysis. For example, populationmay count among <strong>the</strong> givens <strong>in</strong> a particular str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> analysis yet countamong <strong>the</strong> variables to be expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r str<strong>and</strong>.) GE emphasizes,<strong>in</strong> particular, <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between variables that get determ<strong>in</strong>ed, on<strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> “wants, resources, <strong>and</strong> technology,” on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>.(“WR&T” also <strong>in</strong>cludes social <strong>and</strong> legal organizations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir rules;cf. Eucken 1950, pp. 81, 202–203, <strong>and</strong> V<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g 1984.) GE shows <strong>the</strong> error <strong>of</strong>ask<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> a change <strong>in</strong> a particular magnitude when thatmagnitude is a determ<strong>in</strong>ed variable <strong>and</strong> not a given. It is a mistake, forexample, to ask how a change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate will affect <strong>in</strong>vestmentor total spend<strong>in</strong>g. e question should be rephrased to ask about fur<strong>the</strong>rconsequences <strong>of</strong> whatever change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> data underlies <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest-ratechange (e.g., a change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> productivity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment, <strong>in</strong> thrift, or <strong>in</strong>monetary policy). e error is similar to that <strong>of</strong> ask<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> consequences<strong>of</strong> a change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> wheat whose cause goes unspecified.Nowadays, similarly, we have been hear<strong>in</strong>g much ignorant chatter about<strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> a deficit <strong>in</strong> foreign trade or on current account.


10 Part I: EconomicsOf course, <strong>in</strong>dividual-experiments can be legitimate if performed <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> proper context. What is a dependent variable for <strong>the</strong> economy asa whole may be an <strong>in</strong>dependent variable or datum for <strong>in</strong>dividual units<strong>and</strong> aggregates <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. Someth<strong>in</strong>g that is not a datum for <strong>the</strong> economyas a whole may legitimately be taken as a datum <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>dividualexperiment(Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong> 1965 develops <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>in</strong>dividual<strong>and</strong>market-experiments). But it is important to keep <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction clear.(Some examples <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction would <strong>in</strong>volve dem<strong>and</strong> schedule<strong>and</strong> quantity dem<strong>and</strong>ed; Friedman’s “Marshallian” dem<strong>and</strong> curve, supposedlypurified <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>come effect; <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for money; <strong>and</strong> relationsbetween <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>come.)It can be legitimate to ask about <strong>the</strong> consequences for <strong>the</strong> economy asa whole <strong>of</strong> a variable’s accidentally depart<strong>in</strong>g from or arbitrarily be<strong>in</strong>g setaway from its GE value (even though some <strong>the</strong>orists, e.g., Archibald <strong>and</strong>Lipsey 1958 <strong>and</strong>, more recently, <strong>the</strong> New Classical macroeconomists, havebeen mistakenly unwill<strong>in</strong>g to consider disequilibrium). We might supposesuch a departure to test for stability <strong>of</strong> equilibrium, to show <strong>in</strong>consistency<strong>of</strong> plans <strong>in</strong> a disequilibrium situation, or to show forces at work <strong>and</strong> reasonswhy such a disequilibrium could not last. But <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orist must knowwhat he is do<strong>in</strong>g. Although it can be legitimate to postulate a specifiedk<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> departure from equilibrium for a particular analytical purpose, <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>orist must not imag<strong>in</strong>e a freedom to postulate just any old change <strong>in</strong>a variable so as to trace out <strong>the</strong> consequences for a supposed differentequilibrium. As for postulat<strong>in</strong>g a price floor or ceil<strong>in</strong>g or a change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>money-supply behavior <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> authorities, that can be regarded as a change<strong>in</strong> one <strong>of</strong> what are regarded as ultimate data <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> system. (Implicitly Iam referr<strong>in</strong>g to Buchanan 1958 <strong>and</strong> Eucken 1950, pp. 218–219.). GE shows <strong>the</strong> error <strong>of</strong> imag<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g one-way causation <strong>of</strong> economicvariables when mutual determ<strong>in</strong>ation is at work. It is a mistake to askwhe<strong>the</strong>r price depends on cost or on marg<strong>in</strong>al utility, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terestrate depends on <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al productivity <strong>of</strong> capital goods or <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestmentor on a subjective discount <strong>of</strong> future relative to present goods, <strong>and</strong>whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> wage rate depends on <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al value product <strong>of</strong> laboror on labor’s marg<strong>in</strong>al disutility or on <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al utility <strong>of</strong> alternativeactivities forgone to engage <strong>in</strong> labor.Avoid<strong>in</strong>g false presuppositions about causality helps give <strong>in</strong>sight<strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> identification problem <strong>of</strong> econometrics. For example, does a pattern<strong>of</strong> relations between various prices <strong>and</strong> quantities <strong>of</strong> some productreflect a dem<strong>and</strong> function, a supply function, a confused mixture <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir


Chapter : Should Austrians Scorn General Equilibrium eory? 11properties, or what? We must ask what differences <strong>in</strong> wants, resources,<strong>and</strong> technology underlie <strong>the</strong> different price-<strong>and</strong>-quantity po<strong>in</strong>ts. Fur<strong>the</strong>rsuch examples concern relations between a country’s balance <strong>of</strong> payments<strong>and</strong> exchange rate, monetary policy <strong>and</strong> free reserves, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate<strong>and</strong> monetary policy or <strong>in</strong>vestment or thrift. Did a change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terestrate come from <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>-for-credit side or <strong>the</strong> supply-<strong>of</strong>-credit side,perhaps as <strong>in</strong>fluenced by monetary policy?Recogniz<strong>in</strong>g mutual determ<strong>in</strong>ation does not preclude a causal-genetictrac<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> response to a particular change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> situation. Comparetrac<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> add<strong>in</strong>g a new ball to Marshall’s bowl or anew piece to a Calder mobile.. GE helps avoid many specific fallacies sometimes abetted by <strong>the</strong>partial-equilibrium approach. Some examples follow.(a) e above-mentioned fallacy about <strong>in</strong>terest-sensitivity <strong>and</strong> monetarypolicy.(b) e purchas<strong>in</strong>g-power argument for artificially boost<strong>in</strong>g particularwage rates (or product prices). is ancient argument illegitimatelygeneralizes from a particular firm or <strong>in</strong>dustry. If—if—<strong>the</strong> conditions foran <strong>in</strong>elastic derived dem<strong>and</strong> for its labor are satisfied, <strong>the</strong>n a wage-rate<strong>in</strong>crease will <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>the</strong> purchas<strong>in</strong>g power <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> firm’s or <strong>in</strong>dustry’semployees. But what happens to o<strong>the</strong>r factor shares? Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,widespread wage <strong>in</strong>creases lead <strong>in</strong>to questions <strong>of</strong> monetary <strong>the</strong>ory, whichcannot be h<strong>and</strong>led by partial analysis alone.(c) e pro-efficiency “shock” effect supposedly achieved by boost<strong>in</strong>gwage rates through union or government action. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as <strong>the</strong> greaterefficiency is achieved by greater capital <strong>in</strong>vestment, ei<strong>the</strong>r less capital formationis possible elsewhere or else <strong>the</strong> “shock” somehow promotes sav<strong>in</strong>g,<strong>in</strong> which case <strong>the</strong> argument ought to expla<strong>in</strong> how.(d) e economies-<strong>of</strong>-scale case for advertis<strong>in</strong>g or consumer trad<strong>in</strong>gstamps. Exp<strong>and</strong>ed scale <strong>in</strong> some operations means shrunken scale <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs,unless underemployment <strong>of</strong> resources prevailed <strong>and</strong> is somehow remediedby <strong>the</strong> advertis<strong>in</strong>g. What reason is <strong>the</strong>re to suppose that advertis<strong>in</strong>gpromotes <strong>the</strong> goods that particularly have economies <strong>of</strong> scale? Anyway,<strong>the</strong> argument ought to face up to this general-equilibrium question. If<strong>the</strong> argument depends on st<strong>and</strong>ardization, that ought to be made explicit.(e) e decreas<strong>in</strong>g-cost/marg<strong>in</strong>al-cost-pric<strong>in</strong>g/consumer-surplus argumentfor subsidiz<strong>in</strong>g a particular <strong>in</strong>dustry or runn<strong>in</strong>g it at a loss. Also


12 Part I: Economicsto be considered are <strong>the</strong> conditions <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dustries from which resources arediverted, as well as <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> rais<strong>in</strong>g revenue for <strong>the</strong> subsidies.(f) Similarly, external-economy (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fant-<strong>in</strong>dustry) argumentsfor protection or subsidies for particular <strong>in</strong>dustries, or arguments for governmentf<strong>in</strong>ance <strong>of</strong> particular <strong>in</strong>dustries on <strong>the</strong> grounds that <strong>the</strong> governmentcan borrow more cheaply than private enterprise, or argumentsfor credit allocation toward such <strong>in</strong>dustries. As GE teaches us, it is notenough to consider one <strong>in</strong>dustry or one aspect at a time.(g) e idea that government loan guarantees can promote (or rescue)desirable projects or activities at little or no cost to <strong>the</strong> taxpayers. eargument forgets that “capital”—or whatever we may call <strong>the</strong> resourcewhose price is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>and</strong> that is fur<strong>the</strong>r rationed by <strong>the</strong> decisions<strong>of</strong> loan <strong>of</strong>ficers <strong>and</strong> bond buyers—is a scarce resource whose diversion tosome uses necessarily withholds it from o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> possibly more highlydesired uses.(h) Capital-import-<strong>and</strong>-export arguments for trade <strong>in</strong>terventions. Ina develop<strong>in</strong>g country, protect<strong>in</strong>g a particular <strong>in</strong>dustry will perhaps havea “tariff-factory” effect; but will protection <strong>in</strong> general promote capitalimport <strong>in</strong> general? Agreed, admitt<strong>in</strong>g a particular product duty-free mayencourage home firms to export capital to produce that good abroad, but itdoes not follow that removal <strong>of</strong> protection <strong>in</strong> general will promote overallcapital export.(i) e fallacious argument for tariffs to <strong>the</strong> effect that our governmentcollects taxes on <strong>in</strong>comes generated by domestic production <strong>of</strong> importcompet<strong>in</strong>ggoods but not on <strong>in</strong>comes generated by produc<strong>in</strong>g importedgoods abroad.(j) e real-bills doctr<strong>in</strong>e about <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>flationary effect <strong>of</strong>money <strong>and</strong> credit created to f<strong>in</strong>ance productive activities, a fallacy thatkeeps gett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dependently re<strong>in</strong>vented <strong>in</strong> slightly different versions by<strong>in</strong>competent amateur monetary <strong>the</strong>orists.(k) Merely superficial attention to secondary or “collateral” effects <strong>of</strong>a particular activity, such as supposed benefits to local bus<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> a newhighway or sports stadium, ignor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> diversion <strong>of</strong> resources from o<strong>the</strong>rplaces or activities.(l) A catchall category: o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>stances <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fallacy <strong>of</strong> composition<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> policy arguments that unduly restrict attention to close <strong>and</strong> shortruneffects to <strong>the</strong> relative neglect <strong>of</strong> more remote <strong>and</strong> long-run effects.GE promotes awareness that <strong>the</strong> wisdom <strong>of</strong> a particular measure cannot


14 Part I: Economics<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> equilibrium equations also, so that <strong>the</strong> systemrema<strong>in</strong>s determ<strong>in</strong>ate.Cassel justifiably claims that hisequations reveal <strong>the</strong> true nature <strong>of</strong> pric<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> pric<strong>in</strong>g process cannotbe accurately presented <strong>in</strong> any simpler form. e dem<strong>and</strong> for a productrepresents an attempt to attract certa<strong>in</strong> factors <strong>of</strong> production to aparticular use. Conflict<strong>in</strong>g with this attempt are similar attempts <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>form <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s for o<strong>the</strong>r products. ere arises <strong>in</strong> this way a strugglefor <strong>the</strong> relatively scarce factors <strong>of</strong> production, which is decided <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> exchange economy by plac<strong>in</strong>g uniform prices on <strong>the</strong> factors, whichprices <strong>in</strong> turn determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> products <strong>and</strong> thus form ameans <strong>of</strong> effect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> necessary restriction <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>. e dem<strong>and</strong> fora particular factor <strong>of</strong> production aris<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>uous dem<strong>and</strong> foreach particular product is totalled for each unit period, to form a totaldem<strong>and</strong> for that factor <strong>of</strong> production, ... which must, <strong>in</strong> a state <strong>of</strong> equilibrium,equal <strong>the</strong> given quantity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> factor <strong>of</strong> production. (1932/1967,p. 145)In this passage <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> equation system it describes, Cassel thusprovides a deep <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> cost, opportunity cost. He goeson to po<strong>in</strong>t out how his system portrays <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terplay <strong>of</strong> both subjective<strong>and</strong> objective factors <strong>in</strong> price determ<strong>in</strong>ation. As he says,All <strong>the</strong>se factors are essential <strong>in</strong> determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g prices. An “objective” or“subjective” <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> value, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> a <strong>the</strong>ory that would attribute<strong>the</strong> settlement <strong>of</strong> prices to objective or subjective factors alone, is <strong>the</strong>reforeabsurd; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> controversy between <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong>value, which has occupied such a disproportionately large place <strong>in</strong> economicliterature, is a pure waste <strong>of</strong> energy. (p. 146)E.H. Phelps Brown presents a general-equilibrium equation systemsimple enough to be solved numerically, as it was even when Brownfirst published it <strong>in</strong> 1936, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> days before computers <strong>and</strong> even beforeelectronic pocket calculators (though not before mechanical desk calculators).Nowadays, when computers <strong>and</strong> calculators remove so much gruntwork, <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> exercises like Brown’s has <strong>in</strong>creased. Much may besaid for work<strong>in</strong>g one’s way not only through simplified systems but alsothrough Walras’s Elements itself, that l<strong>and</strong>mark <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> economicthought.It is easy to say that <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ts illum<strong>in</strong>ated by GE are “obvious” <strong>and</strong>that its pretentious equations are unnecessary. Conceivably so. But are


Chapter : Should Austrians Scorn General Equilibrium eory? 15its critics quite sure that <strong>the</strong>ir acqua<strong>in</strong>tance with GE does not help makethose po<strong>in</strong>ts seem obvious? Would <strong>the</strong>y have grasped <strong>the</strong>ir full significanceeven without contemplat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> equation systems?Only ra<strong>the</strong>r simple ma<strong>the</strong>matics is required for reap<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> benefitsclaimed for GE. (Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g work like Gerard Debreu’s is ano<strong>the</strong>rmatter.) is br<strong>in</strong>gs up a related po<strong>in</strong>t. Quite a few Austrians ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>that ma<strong>the</strong>matics is out <strong>of</strong> place <strong>in</strong> economics. But how can <strong>the</strong>y be confident?eir not see<strong>in</strong>g how to do anyth<strong>in</strong>g useful with it is no reasonto suppose that no one else can use it any better. People with differentpersonal abilities, backgrounds, <strong>and</strong> tastes legitimately pursue differentresearch topics <strong>and</strong> employ different methods <strong>and</strong> styles <strong>of</strong> exposition. Anapproach lack<strong>in</strong>g appeal to oneself may convey valuable <strong>in</strong>sights to o<strong>the</strong>rpersons. It is paradoxical for Austrians, especially those who like to expatiateon subjectivity <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>effability <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> unpredictability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> future,to predict <strong>the</strong> usefulness <strong>of</strong> particular methods <strong>and</strong> to try practically tolegislate on such matters.Ala<strong>in</strong> Enthoven, <strong>the</strong>n apply<strong>in</strong>g economics <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Defense Department,testified to how overlearn<strong>in</strong>g or overstudy, as one might call it, canhelp cl<strong>in</strong>ch one’s grasp <strong>of</strong> economic reality. e analytical tools that he<strong>and</strong> his colleagues usedare <strong>the</strong> simplest, most fundamental concepts <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory, comb<strong>in</strong>edwith <strong>the</strong> simplest quantitative methods. e requirements for success<strong>in</strong> this l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> work are a thorough underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong>, if youlike, belief <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> relevance <strong>of</strong> such concepts as marg<strong>in</strong>al products <strong>and</strong>marg<strong>in</strong>al costs, <strong>and</strong> an ability to discover <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al products <strong>and</strong>costs <strong>in</strong> complex situations, comb<strong>in</strong>ed with a good quantitative sense.e advanced ma<strong>the</strong>matical techniques <strong>of</strong> econometrics <strong>and</strong> operationsresearch have not proved to be particularly useful <strong>in</strong> deal<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>problems I have described. Although a good grasp <strong>of</strong> this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>maticsis very valuable as <strong>in</strong>tellectual formation, we are not apply<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>earprogramm<strong>in</strong>g, formal game <strong>the</strong>ory, queu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ory, multiple regression<strong>the</strong>ory, nonl<strong>in</strong>ear programm<strong>in</strong>g under uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, or anyth<strong>in</strong>g likeit. e economic <strong>the</strong>ory we are us<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory most <strong>of</strong> us learned assophomores. e reason Ph.D.’s are required is that many economists donot believe what <strong>the</strong>y have learned until <strong>the</strong>y have gone through graduateschool <strong>and</strong> acquired a vested <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al analysis. (Enthoven1963, p. 422)Partial-equilibrium, process-oriented, <strong>and</strong> GE approaches are not necessarilyrivals. Admittedly, only partial-equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory is “operational”


16 Part I: Economics<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Chicago sense <strong>of</strong> yield<strong>in</strong>g fairly specific predictions, as <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequences<strong>of</strong> a change <strong>in</strong> an excise tax. And even this admission goes too far;GE is not totally without operational application. Still, its ma<strong>in</strong> serviceis as a conceptual framework accommodat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> more readily applicablestr<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> partial analysis.True, <strong>the</strong> Walrasian system is formal. It is absurd to envisage solv<strong>in</strong>g aWalrasian system for numerical parameters <strong>of</strong> reality (pace Wassily Leontief’s aspirations for his <strong>in</strong>put-output system). “Walras’ system was oncecorrectly described as resembl<strong>in</strong>g a palace <strong>of</strong> no relevance to <strong>the</strong> hous<strong>in</strong>gproblem” (Eucken 1950, p. 27). GE is a major str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>, approach to, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tegrat<strong>in</strong>g factor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wholebody <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory. A s<strong>in</strong>gle correct body <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory is what all creativeeconomists presumably strive for, even though probably no one everwill achieve it complete <strong>and</strong> error-free. Reality is consistent with itself,<strong>and</strong> so must <strong>the</strong> correct <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> it be. To say so is not to deny <strong>the</strong> value<strong>of</strong> different schools with <strong>the</strong>ir own favorite topics, approaches, researchmethods, <strong>and</strong> styles <strong>of</strong> exposition. A researcher can ga<strong>in</strong> encouragement<strong>and</strong> stimulus from know<strong>in</strong>g that he has colleagues out <strong>the</strong>re who are readyto read him sympa<strong>the</strong>tically. ey accord him a presumption—defeasible<strong>of</strong> course—that he is right. us, <strong>the</strong>re is legitimate scope for <strong>the</strong> AustrianSchool, as for o<strong>the</strong>rs.But <strong>the</strong> Austrians should th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves as mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir owndist<strong>in</strong>ctive contributions, critical as well as positive, to an emerg<strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>glecorrect body <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. eir objective should not be to differentiate <strong>the</strong>mselvesfrom <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream <strong>in</strong> a hostile manner but ra<strong>the</strong>r to contribute to<strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream <strong>and</strong> help steer it <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> right direction. Correct economic<strong>the</strong>ory does not come <strong>in</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>compatible br<strong>and</strong>s, one for Austrians,one for Marxians, one for conservatives <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> style <strong>of</strong> William F.Buckley <strong>and</strong> Russell Kirk, one for libertarians, one for left-liberals, <strong>and</strong>so forth. To suppose that it does is what Ludwig von Mises (1949/1966,chap. III) eloquently condemned as “polylogism.”Allais, Maurice. Remarks at McGill University, Montreal. Reported <strong>in</strong> IMF Survey( June 1989): 185.


Chapter : Should Austrians Scorn General Equilibrium eory? 17Archibald, G.C., <strong>and</strong> R.G. Lipsey. “Monetary <strong>and</strong> Value eory: A Critique <strong>of</strong>Lange <strong>and</strong> Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>.” Review <strong>of</strong> Economic Studies 26 (1958): 9–17.Arrow, Kenneth J., <strong>and</strong> Frank H. Hahn. General Competitive Analysis. San Francisco:Holden-Day, 1971.Boettke, Peter J., <strong>and</strong> David L. Prychitko. “Introduction: Varieties <strong>of</strong> <strong>Market</strong>Process eory.” In <strong>Market</strong> Process eories, edited by Boettke <strong>and</strong> Prychitko,vol. 1: ix–xxvii. Cheltenham, U.K., <strong>and</strong> Northampton, Mass.: Elgar, 1998.Brown, E.H. Phelps. e Framework <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Pric<strong>in</strong>g System. 1936. Lawrence: University<strong>of</strong> Kansas, Student Union Book Store, 1949.Buchanan, James M. “Ceteris Paribus: Some Notes on Methodology.” Sou<strong>the</strong>rnEconomic Journal 24 (1958): 259–270.. “<strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>: 1957–1982.” Lecture <strong>of</strong> 20 April 1983. In Ideas, eirOrig<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> eir Consequences, edited by omas Jefferson Center Foundation,119–130. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.: American Enterprise Institute, 1988.Cassel, Gustav. e eory <strong>of</strong> Social <strong>Economy</strong>. 1932. Translated by S.L. Barron.New York: Kelley, 1967.Clower, Robert. “Reflections on <strong>the</strong> Keynesian Perplex.” 1975. In Money <strong>and</strong> <strong>Market</strong>s,edited by Donald A.Walker, chap. 14. New York: Cambridge UniversityPress, 1986.. “Axiomatics <strong>in</strong> Economics.” Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Economic Journal 62 (1995):307–319.Debreu, Gerard. eory <strong>of</strong> Value. New York: Wiley, 1959.Enthoven, Ala<strong>in</strong> C. “Economic Analysis <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Department <strong>of</strong> Defense.” AmericanEconomic Review 53 (May 1963): 413–423.Eucken, Walter. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Economics. Translated by T.W. Hutchison.London: Hodge, 1950.. Grundsätze der Wirtschaftspolitik. Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen: Mohr, 1952.. Kapital<strong>the</strong>oretische Untersuchungen. 2ⁿ ed. Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen: Mohr, 1954.Fisher, Irv<strong>in</strong>g. e eory <strong>of</strong> Interest. 1930. New York: Kelley, 1970.High, Jack. “e Austrian eory <strong>of</strong> Price.” In e Elgar Companion to AustrianEconomics, edited by Peter J. Boettke, 151–155. Aldershot, U.K., <strong>and</strong>Brookfield, Vt.: Elgar, 1994.


18 Part I: EconomicsHuerta de Soto, Jesús. Socialismo, Cálculo Económico y Función Empresarial.Madrid: Unión Editorial, 1992.Klamer, Arjo. Conversations with Economists. Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Allanheld,1983.Kuenne, Robert E. e eory <strong>of</strong> General Economic Equilibrium. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.:Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press, 1963.. Microeconomic eory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> Mechanism: A General EquilibriumApproach. New York: Macmillan, 1968.Lucas, Robert E., Jr., <strong>and</strong> omas J. Sargent. “After Keynesian Macroeconomics.”In After <strong>the</strong> Phillips Curve: Persistence <strong>of</strong> High Inflation <strong>and</strong> HighUnemployment, 49–72. Boston: Federal Reserve Bank <strong>of</strong> Boston, 1978.Mayer, omas. <strong>Truth</strong> versus Precision <strong>in</strong> Economics. Aldershot, U.K., <strong>and</strong> Brookfield,Vt.: Elgar, 1993.Meade, James E. Trade <strong>and</strong> Welfare. London: Oxford University Press, 1955.Mises, Ludwig von. Human Action. 1949. 3 rev. ed. San Francisco: Fox & Wilkes,1966.Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Don. Money, Interest, <strong>and</strong> Prices. 2ⁿ ed. New York: Harper & Row,1965.Saffran, Bernard. “Recommendations for Fur<strong>the</strong>r Read<strong>in</strong>g.” Journal <strong>of</strong> EconomicPerspectives 9 (Fall 1995): 227–234.Salerno, Joseph T. “Reply to Lel<strong>and</strong> B. Yeager.” Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 7,no. 2 (1994): 111–125.V<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, Rutledge. On Apprais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Performance <strong>of</strong> an Economic System. NewYork: Cambridge University Press, 1984.Walras, Léon. Elements <strong>of</strong> Pure Economics. Translated by William Jaffé. Homewood,Ill.: Irw<strong>in</strong>, 1954.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d.” Journal <strong>of</strong> EconomicMethodology 2 (1995): 1–33. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted here as chapter .


Why Subjectivism? * Economists <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian School emphasize subjectivism. is articlereviews why subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights are important, but it also warns aga<strong>in</strong>stexaggerations. e latter part, while briefer, particularly warrants attention<strong>in</strong> Austrian circles.Various writers def<strong>in</strong>e subjectivism <strong>in</strong> ways that, though not necessarily<strong>in</strong>consistent, do seem quite different. Empirical concepts (as opposedto ma<strong>the</strong>matical concepts, like “triangle”) necessarily have an “open texture”(Waismann 1965). An open-textured concept just cannot be def<strong>in</strong>edso precisely <strong>and</strong> comprehensively as to rule out <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> an unforeseensituation or case or example that would require modify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> earlierdef<strong>in</strong>ition. I feel no duty, <strong>the</strong>n, to start with a def<strong>in</strong>ition. Instead, <strong>the</strong>mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> subjectivism will emerge from <strong>the</strong> topics covered <strong>and</strong> fromcontrasts with nonsubjectivist attitudes. Subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights contribute to positive economics—to underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>ghow <strong>the</strong> world works (or would work with circumstances changed <strong>in</strong> specifiedways). ey do not bear primarily on policy. As an expository device,however, it is convenient to beg<strong>in</strong> by consider<strong>in</strong>g subjectivism applied—orignored—<strong>in</strong> policymak<strong>in</strong>g.Perhaps <strong>the</strong> broadest subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sight is that economics deals withhuman choices <strong>and</strong> actions, not with mechanistically dependable relations.e economy is no mach<strong>in</strong>e whose “structure” can be ascerta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong>manipulated with warranted confidence. Economics knows noth<strong>in</strong>g comparableto Avogadro’s number, atomic weights <strong>and</strong> numbers, <strong>the</strong> speed<strong>of</strong> light <strong>in</strong> a vacuum, <strong>and</strong> similar constants <strong>of</strong> nature (Mises 1949/1963,*From Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics , no. 1 (1987): 5–31.19


20 Part I: Economicsp. 55). Or if such constants do exist, an economist could earn a great reputationby demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g a few <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. No amount <strong>of</strong> cleverness wi<strong>the</strong>conometrics can make <strong>the</strong> nonexistent exist after all.One reason why no endur<strong>in</strong>g “structural parameters” characterize <strong>the</strong>economic system is that how people behave <strong>in</strong> markets, as <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r aspects<strong>of</strong> life, depends on <strong>the</strong>ir experiences <strong>and</strong> expectations <strong>and</strong> on what doctr<strong>in</strong>es<strong>the</strong>y have come to believe. (Here is one area <strong>of</strong> overlap betweenAustrian economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> rational-expectations school.) ese circumstancesare <strong>in</strong>herently changeable. One implication warns aga<strong>in</strong>st policieswhose success presupposes unrealistic k<strong>in</strong>ds or degrees <strong>of</strong> knowledge. Itwarns aga<strong>in</strong>st overambition <strong>in</strong> attempt<strong>in</strong>g detailed central control.Subjectivist economics po<strong>in</strong>ts out, for example, what is lost when policymakes simplistic dist<strong>in</strong>ctions between necessities <strong>and</strong> luxuries or when,unlike voluntary transactions, policy fails to take account <strong>of</strong> subtle differencesbetween <strong>the</strong> circumstances <strong>and</strong> tastes <strong>of</strong> different people. (I leavepersonal rights aside not because <strong>the</strong>y are unimportant but because <strong>the</strong>present topic is ra<strong>the</strong>r different.)Examples abound, <strong>in</strong> ird World countries <strong>and</strong> elsewhere, <strong>of</strong> attemptsto conserve scarce foreign-exchange earn<strong>in</strong>gs for “essentials” byexchange controls, multiple exchange rates, import quotas, <strong>and</strong> selectiveimport duties designed to limit or penalize <strong>the</strong> waste <strong>of</strong> foreign exchangeon “luxury” or “nonessential” imports.e arguments <strong>of</strong>fered for such controls, like arguments for consumerration<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> wartime, are not always sheer nonsense. But subjectivist considerationsseverely qualify <strong>the</strong>m. It is impossible to make <strong>and</strong> implementa clear dist<strong>in</strong>ction between luxuries <strong>and</strong> essentials. Suppose that a governmenttightly rations foreign exchange for pleasure cruises <strong>and</strong> travelabroad but classifies oil as an essential import. Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> oil may g<strong>of</strong>or heat<strong>in</strong>g at domestic resorts operat<strong>in</strong>g on a larger scale than if <strong>the</strong>cruises had not been restricted. e restrictions may <strong>in</strong> effect divert factors<strong>of</strong> production from o<strong>the</strong>r activities <strong>in</strong>to provid<strong>in</strong>g recreation o<strong>the</strong>rwiseobta<strong>in</strong>able at lower cost through foreign travel. Because <strong>of</strong> poor climateat home, it may well be that <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al units <strong>of</strong> foreign exchange spenton imported oil go to satisfy wants <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same general sort—while satisfy<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>m less effectively—as wants o<strong>the</strong>rwise satisfied by foreign travel.Restrict<strong>in</strong>g travel <strong>and</strong> supposedly nonessential imports is likely to promoteimports <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir substitutes <strong>and</strong> also divert domestic <strong>and</strong> importedresources or materials <strong>in</strong>to home production <strong>of</strong> substitutes. e diversionsmay also impede exports that earn foreign exchange.


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 21It is particularly dubious to try to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between essential <strong>and</strong>frivolous imports accord<strong>in</strong>g to whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y serve production (or “economicgrowth”) or mere consumption. All production supposedly aimsat satisfy<strong>in</strong>g human wants, immediately or ultimately. Produc<strong>in</strong>g mach<strong>in</strong>eryor build<strong>in</strong>g factories is no more <strong>in</strong>herently worthy than produc<strong>in</strong>grestaurant meals or nightclub enterta<strong>in</strong>ment, for <strong>the</strong> mach<strong>in</strong>ery or factoriesare po<strong>in</strong>tless unless <strong>the</strong>y can sooner or later yield goods or servicesthat do satisfy human wants. To favor production-oriented (or exportoriented)imports over consumption-oriented imports is to prefer a roundaboutachievement <strong>of</strong> ultimate consumer satisfactions to <strong>the</strong>ir more directachievement merely because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> greater roundaboutness. It is to confuseends <strong>and</strong> means.People obta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir satisfactions <strong>in</strong> highly diverse ways (even altruisticways). Some policymakers evidently do not underst<strong>and</strong> how <strong>the</strong> pricesystem br<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>to play <strong>the</strong> dispersed knowledge that people have about<strong>the</strong>ir own tastes <strong>and</strong> circumstances. A journalist illustrated such misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>gwhen badger<strong>in</strong>g Alan Greenspan, <strong>the</strong>n Chairman <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Council<strong>of</strong> Economic Advisers, with questions about whe<strong>the</strong>r bus<strong>in</strong>ess firmswould cont<strong>in</strong>ue produc<strong>in</strong>g essential goods when frivolous goods happenedto be more pr<strong>of</strong>itable. As Greenspan properly replied (<strong>in</strong> Mitchell 1974,pp. 74–76), people differ widely <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir tastes. Some choose to buy extraord<strong>in</strong>aryth<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> deliberately deprive <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs generallycounted as necessities.One might conceivably—though not conclusively—urge controls ascorrectives for specific market distortions. Barr<strong>in</strong>g such identified distortions,subjectivist economists would let ultimate consumers appraise“essentiality.” Sweep<strong>in</strong>g philosophical comparisons are unnecessary. Peoplecan act on <strong>the</strong>ir own comparisons <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> satisfactions <strong>the</strong>y expect froman additional dollar’s worth <strong>of</strong> this <strong>and</strong> that. Consumers <strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>essmencan judge <strong>and</strong> act on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wants that various goods can satisfy,ei<strong>the</strong>r directly or by contribut<strong>in</strong>g to fur<strong>the</strong>r processes <strong>of</strong> production.St<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>the</strong>oretical reservations about this suggestion—argumentsfor government discrim<strong>in</strong>ations <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> some <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong>st o<strong>the</strong>r particulargoods <strong>and</strong> services—<strong>in</strong>voke <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>of</strong> externalities, <strong>of</strong> meritwants <strong>and</strong> merit goods, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come redistribution. Yet how can policymakersbe confident that supposed externalities are genu<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> important,that supposed merit wants really deserve cultivation, or that discrim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>gamong goods will accomplish <strong>the</strong> desired redistribution <strong>of</strong>real <strong>in</strong>come? Any one <strong>of</strong> many goods, considered by itself, might seem


22 Part I: Economicsdeserv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> special favor; yet how relatively deserv<strong>in</strong>g different goodsare may rema<strong>in</strong> highly uncerta<strong>in</strong>, particularly when no one knows justhow severely <strong>the</strong> diversion <strong>of</strong> resources <strong>in</strong>to particular l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> productionwill impair production <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r l<strong>in</strong>es that might even be more meritoriousby <strong>the</strong> policymaker’s criteria. (Tunnel vision is a fail<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> policymakersnot thoroughly familiar with <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> general economic <strong>in</strong>terdependence.)More fundamentally, particular goods do not possess qualities deserv<strong>in</strong>gspecial consideration globally, or by <strong>the</strong>ir very nature. On <strong>the</strong> contrary,usefulness or desirability is a relation between th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> humanwants. e usefulness <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g—specifically, its marg<strong>in</strong>al utility—is<strong>the</strong> smaller <strong>the</strong> more abundant <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g is. Ideally, decisions about adjust<strong>in</strong>gquantities <strong>of</strong> various th<strong>in</strong>gs should consider <strong>the</strong>ir usefulness at <strong>the</strong>marg<strong>in</strong>. It is easy to imag<strong>in</strong>e circumstances <strong>in</strong> which an additional dollar’sworth or an additional ounce <strong>of</strong> penicill<strong>in</strong> or polio vacc<strong>in</strong>e wouldcontribute less to human satisfaction than an additional unit <strong>of</strong> orchids.e concept <strong>of</strong> priorities does not properly apply <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> contexts consideredhere. For <strong>the</strong> reasons mentioned, <strong>and</strong> also <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> how <strong>the</strong> politicalprocess works <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> ample experience with controls, it is unrealistic toexpect <strong>the</strong> government to choose “social priorities” reasonably. Consider,for example, <strong>the</strong> botch <strong>of</strong> energy policy, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> long record <strong>of</strong> subsidiz<strong>in</strong>genergy consumption <strong>in</strong> travel <strong>and</strong> transport (through <strong>the</strong> underpric<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> road <strong>and</strong> airport facilities) <strong>and</strong> also <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g tax exemptions <strong>and</strong>subsidized loans granted to rural electric cooperatives, even while government<strong>of</strong>ficials plead for energy conservation.Policies adopted or advocated dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> energy crises <strong>of</strong> 1974 <strong>and</strong> 1979betray ignorance <strong>of</strong> subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights. Examples are ration<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> gasol<strong>in</strong>enot so much by price as by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>convenience <strong>and</strong> apprehension <strong>of</strong>hav<strong>in</strong>g to hunt around for it <strong>and</strong> wait <strong>in</strong> long l<strong>in</strong>es to buy it, or be<strong>in</strong>gallowed to buy gasol<strong>in</strong>e only on odd- or even-numbered days accord<strong>in</strong>gto one’s license-plate number. A former chairman <strong>of</strong> Inl<strong>and</strong> Steel Company( Joseph L. Block <strong>in</strong> Committee for Economic Development 1974,pp. 79–80) suggested requir<strong>in</strong>g each car owner to choose one day <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>week when he would be forbidden to drive. at prohibition, enforcedwith appropriate stickers, would supposedly have elim<strong>in</strong>ated some needlessdriv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> encouraged use <strong>of</strong> public transportation. Ano<strong>the</strong>r examplewas a decision by <strong>the</strong> California Public Utilities Commission bann<strong>in</strong>g natural-gasheat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> new swimm<strong>in</strong>g pools (Charlottesville Daily Progress,29 February 1976, p. E11).


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 23Such measures <strong>and</strong> proposals underrate <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>and</strong> flexibility.Arbitrary measures burden some people lightly <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs heavilybecause different people’s lives afford different scopes <strong>of</strong> substitut<strong>in</strong>gaway from <strong>the</strong> restricted consumption <strong>and</strong> make advance schedul<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>activities difficult <strong>and</strong> unrestricted flexibility important <strong>in</strong> widely differ<strong>in</strong>gdegrees. In unrestricted voluntary transactions, by contrast, peoplecan allow for such differences.A narrowly technological outlook is <strong>of</strong>ten l<strong>in</strong>ked with puritanical moraliz<strong>in</strong>g.(I remember my maternal gr<strong>and</strong>mo<strong>the</strong>r, who used to bewail <strong>the</strong>waste <strong>of</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g a teabag only once if it could be made to serve twice <strong>and</strong><strong>of</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> wash<strong>in</strong>g a large plate if <strong>the</strong> food could be crammed onto asmall plate.) Recovery techniques left too much oil <strong>and</strong> gas <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ground,natural gas on <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>ental shelf was flared, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> prevail<strong>in</strong>g practice<strong>in</strong> coal m<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g left half <strong>of</strong> a seam <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ground merely because it wasneeded <strong>the</strong>re as a support<strong>in</strong>g column or because gett<strong>in</strong>g it all out was tooexpensive—so went one compla<strong>in</strong>t (Freeman 1974, pp. 230–232). Energyhas been wasted by “too little” <strong>in</strong>sulation <strong>of</strong> build<strong>in</strong>gs.Yet so-called waste was probably sensible at <strong>the</strong> lower energy prices <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> past. ere can be such a th<strong>in</strong>g as too much conservation; for example,produc<strong>in</strong>g alum<strong>in</strong>um for storm w<strong>in</strong>dows <strong>in</strong>stalled under tax <strong>in</strong>centiveseven consumes energy <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r directions. Ample heat <strong>and</strong> air condition<strong>in</strong>gbrought comfort, <strong>and</strong> fast driv<strong>in</strong>g saved valuable time. Not hav<strong>in</strong>g toconcentrate on ferret<strong>in</strong>g out ways to conserve energy saved mental capacityfor o<strong>the</strong>r purposes. Now, at today’s higher prices, a dollar spent onenergy no longer buys as much comfort or saves as much time or thoughtas before; <strong>and</strong> people respond accord<strong>in</strong>gly. Conceivably, <strong>of</strong> course, <strong>the</strong>energy prices <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past, distorted downward by <strong>in</strong>terventions, may haveled people to consume more energy than <strong>the</strong>y would have done at freemarketprices; but if so, <strong>the</strong> specific distortions should have been identified<strong>and</strong> addressed. Moraliz<strong>in</strong>g about ways <strong>of</strong> consum<strong>in</strong>g less was <strong>of</strong>f <strong>the</strong> track.Such moraliz<strong>in</strong>g almost regards waste as someth<strong>in</strong>g perpetrated onlywith material resources, not with people’s time or comfort or peace <strong>of</strong>m<strong>in</strong>d. Ironically, this str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> materialism sometimes occurs among peoplewho announce Galbraithian scorn for <strong>the</strong> alleged materialism <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>affluent society. Ano<strong>the</strong>r apparent str<strong>and</strong> sometimes found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> attitude<strong>of</strong> such people is self-congratulation on heroic hard-headedness <strong>in</strong> recogniz<strong>in</strong>gnecessary austerities. (Speak<strong>in</strong>g at a conference <strong>in</strong> Beverly Hills on26 April 1975, Senator Gaylord Nelson welcomed <strong>the</strong> challenge <strong>of</strong> help<strong>in</strong>gto create <strong>the</strong> new <strong>and</strong> simpler lifestyles <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> future.)


24 Part I: EconomicsMaterialistic energy-conservation proposals illustrate a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>grelated to what F.A. Hayek (1952) has called scientism. It is someth<strong>in</strong>gquite different from science or <strong>the</strong> scientific outlook. One aspect <strong>of</strong> scientismis <strong>the</strong> feel<strong>in</strong>g that results somehow do not count unless <strong>the</strong>y havebeen deliberately arranged for. A person with <strong>the</strong> scientistic attitude doesnot underst<strong>and</strong> how millions <strong>of</strong> persons <strong>and</strong> companies, trad<strong>in</strong>g freelyamong <strong>the</strong>mselves, can express <strong>and</strong> arrange for satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> wants <strong>the</strong>y<strong>the</strong>mselves consider most <strong>in</strong>tense. He does not appreciate self-adjust<strong>in</strong>gprocesses, like someone’s decision to forgo a gas-heated swimm<strong>in</strong>g pool,or any pool at all, <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prices to be paid. He assumes that agr<strong>and</strong>mo<strong>the</strong>rly state must take charge, <strong>and</strong> he performs feats <strong>of</strong> rout<strong>in</strong>eorig<strong>in</strong>ality <strong>in</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> new ways for it to do so—as by requir<strong>in</strong>g thatcars get 30 miles to <strong>the</strong> gallon, by impos<strong>in</strong>g st<strong>and</strong>ards for build<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sulation,or by bann<strong>in</strong>g pilot lights <strong>in</strong> gas appliances. Tax gimmicks <strong>and</strong> ideasare a dime a dozen—<strong>in</strong>centives for storm w<strong>in</strong>dows <strong>and</strong> solar heat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> plowback <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>in</strong>to oilfield development <strong>and</strong> what not. e current,or recent, vogue for partial national economic plann<strong>in</strong>g under <strong>the</strong>name <strong>of</strong> “<strong>in</strong>dustrial policy” provides fur<strong>the</strong>r examples.Subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights illum<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> military draft. (Forearly discussions by University <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia Ph.D. graduates <strong>and</strong> graduatestudents, see Miller 1968.) Many persons have advocated <strong>the</strong> drafton <strong>the</strong> grounds that an all-volunteer force is too costly. ey underst<strong>and</strong>cost <strong>in</strong> an excessively materialistic <strong>and</strong> account<strong>in</strong>g-oriented way. In truth,costs are subjective—unpleasantnesses <strong>in</strong>curred <strong>and</strong> satisfactions forgone.In keep<strong>in</strong>g down monetary outlays, <strong>the</strong> draft conceals part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>and</strong>shifts it from <strong>the</strong> taxpayers be<strong>in</strong>g defended to <strong>the</strong> draftees compelled toserve at wages <strong>in</strong>adequate to obta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir voluntary service. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,<strong>the</strong> draft <strong>in</strong>creases total costs through <strong>in</strong>efficiency. It imposes unnecessarilylarge costs on draftees who f<strong>in</strong>d military life particularly unpleasant orwhose foreclosed civilian pursuits are particularly reward<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>mselves<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. At <strong>the</strong> same time it wastes opportunities to obta<strong>in</strong> relativelylow-cost service from men who happen to escape <strong>the</strong> draft but would havebeen will<strong>in</strong>g to serve at wages below those necessary to obta<strong>in</strong> voluntaryservice from men <strong>in</strong> fact drafted. e opposite method—recruit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>desired number <strong>of</strong> service men <strong>and</strong> women by <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g wages adequateto attract <strong>the</strong>m as volunteers—br<strong>in</strong>gs to bear <strong>the</strong> knowledge that people<strong>the</strong>mselves have <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own abilities, <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ations, <strong>and</strong> alternativeopportunities. So do<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> market-oriented method holds down <strong>the</strong>true, subjectively assessed, costs <strong>of</strong> staff<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> armed forces. (Of course,


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 25considerations <strong>in</strong> addition to <strong>the</strong>se also figure <strong>in</strong> arguments over <strong>the</strong> militarydraft.)Subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights help one underst<strong>and</strong> why compensation at actualmarket value for property seized under em<strong>in</strong>ent doma<strong>in</strong> probably will notleave <strong>the</strong> former owner as well <strong>of</strong>f as he had been. His hav<strong>in</strong>g cont<strong>in</strong>ued tohold <strong>the</strong> property <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g already sold it suggests that he valuedit more highly than <strong>the</strong> sales proceeds or o<strong>the</strong>r property purchasable withthose proceeds.Neglect <strong>of</strong> subjectivism is central to <strong>the</strong> fallacy <strong>of</strong> “comparable worth.”Accord<strong>in</strong>g to that doctr<strong>in</strong>e, fashionable among fem<strong>in</strong>ists <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terventionists,<strong>the</strong> worth <strong>of</strong> work performed <strong>in</strong> different jobs can be objectively ascerta<strong>in</strong>ed<strong>and</strong> compared. People perform<strong>in</strong>g different jobs that are never<strong>the</strong>lessjudged alike, on balance, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir arduousness or pleasantness, <strong>the</strong>irrequirements <strong>in</strong> ability <strong>and</strong> tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> degrees <strong>of</strong> responsibility <strong>in</strong>volved,<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r supposedly ascerta<strong>in</strong>able characteristics should receive <strong>the</strong> samepay; <strong>and</strong> government, presumably, should enforce equal pay. Formulasshould replace wage-sett<strong>in</strong>g by voluntary agreements reached under <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>fluences <strong>of</strong> supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>.is idea ducks <strong>the</strong> questions <strong>of</strong> how to ration jobs sought especiallyeagerly at <strong>the</strong>ir formula-determ<strong>in</strong>ed wages <strong>and</strong> how to prod people <strong>in</strong>tojobs that would o<strong>the</strong>rwise go unfilled at such wages. It ducks <strong>the</strong> questions<strong>of</strong> what k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> economic system <strong>and</strong> what k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> society wouldtake <strong>the</strong> place <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free-market system, with its processes <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>gdecentralized voluntary activities. (ough writ<strong>in</strong>g before comparableworth became a prom<strong>in</strong>ent issue, Hayek 1960, chap. 6, aptly warnedaga<strong>in</strong>st displac<strong>in</strong>g market processes by nonmarket assessments <strong>of</strong> entitlementsto <strong>in</strong>comes.) e comparable-worth doctr<strong>in</strong>e neglects <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>effable<strong>in</strong>dividual circumstances <strong>and</strong> subjective feel<strong>in</strong>gs that enter <strong>in</strong>to workers’decisions to seek or avoid particular jobs, employers’ efforts to fill <strong>the</strong>m,<strong>and</strong> consumers’ dem<strong>and</strong>s for <strong>the</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> services produced <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. Yetwages <strong>and</strong> prices set through market processes do take account <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualcircumstances <strong>and</strong> personal feel<strong>in</strong>gs (a po<strong>in</strong>t I’ll say more aboutlater on).Subjectivist economists recognize <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tangible assets,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g knowledge, a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> “human capital.” ey recognize <strong>the</strong> scopefor <strong>in</strong>genuity <strong>in</strong> gett<strong>in</strong>g around government controls <strong>of</strong> various k<strong>in</strong>ds,whereas <strong>the</strong> layman’s tacit case for controls <strong>in</strong>volves a mechanistic conception<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reality to be manipulated, without due appreciation <strong>of</strong>human flexibility. Controls, <strong>and</strong> responses to <strong>the</strong>m, destroy human capital


26 Part I: Economicsby artificially hasten<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> obsolescence <strong>of</strong> knowledge; <strong>the</strong>y impose <strong>the</strong>costs <strong>of</strong> keep<strong>in</strong>g abreast <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> artificially chang<strong>in</strong>g scene <strong>and</strong> divert material<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual resources, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ventiveness, from productiveemployments. Credit-allocation measures <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r controls on f<strong>in</strong>ancial<strong>in</strong>stitutions, for example—even reserve requirements <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest-rateceil<strong>in</strong>gs—have bred <strong>in</strong>novations to circumvent <strong>the</strong>m. Managers have to betra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r start-up costs borne for new <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> practices,<strong>and</strong> customers must spend time <strong>and</strong> trouble learn<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong>m. Price<strong>and</strong> wage controls <strong>and</strong> energy-conservation rules provide fur<strong>the</strong>r illustrations<strong>of</strong> such wastes.Arbitrar<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> unfairness figure among <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> controls <strong>in</strong>tendedto buck market forces. As controls become more comprehensive<strong>and</strong> complex, <strong>the</strong>ir adm<strong>in</strong>istrators are less able to base <strong>the</strong>ir decisions onrelatively objective criteria. Bureaucratic rules become more necessary <strong>and</strong>decisions based on <strong>in</strong>complete <strong>in</strong>formation less avoidable. Multiplication<strong>of</strong> categories entitled to special treatment <strong>in</strong>vites <strong>the</strong> plead<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> special<strong>in</strong>terests. Even morality, ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>tangible asset, is eroded.e complexity <strong>of</strong> detailed monitor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> enforcement suggests appeal<strong>in</strong>gfor voluntary compliance, compliance with <strong>the</strong> spirit <strong>and</strong> not just<strong>the</strong> letter <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> regulations. (Controls over foreign trade <strong>and</strong> payments forbalance-<strong>of</strong>-payments purposes, such as President Johnson attempted <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> mid-1960s, provide still fur<strong>the</strong>r examples; see Yeager 1965.) Whe<strong>the</strong>rcompliance is avowedly voluntary, or whe<strong>the</strong>r ease <strong>of</strong> evasion makes compliancevoluntary <strong>in</strong> effect, such an approach tends to penalize publicspiritedcitizens who do comply <strong>and</strong> gives <strong>the</strong> advantage to o<strong>the</strong>rs. Exhort<strong>in</strong>gpeople to act aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong>ir own economic <strong>in</strong>terest tends to undercut<strong>the</strong> signal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> motivat<strong>in</strong>g functions <strong>of</strong> prices. How are people to know,<strong>the</strong>n, when it is proper <strong>and</strong> when improper to pursue economic ga<strong>in</strong>?To exhort people to th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> compliance as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>in</strong>terest whenit pla<strong>in</strong>ly is not, or to call for self-sacrifice as if it were <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong>morality, is to undercut <strong>the</strong> rational basis <strong>of</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> even undercutrationality itself.A k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> perverse selection results. Public-spirited car owners whoheed appeals for restra<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> driv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>reby leave more gasol<strong>in</strong>e available,<strong>and</strong> at a lower price than o<strong>the</strong>rwise, to less public-spirited drivers. Sellerswho do comply with price ceil<strong>in</strong>gs or guidel<strong>in</strong>es must consequentlyturn away some customers unsatisfied, to <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong> black-marketeers<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r less scrupulous sellers. Eventually such effects become evident,streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> idea that morality is for suckers <strong>and</strong> dupes.


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 27Subjectivists know better than to erect efficiency, somehow conceived,<strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> overrid<strong>in</strong>g criterion ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> particular processes or <strong>in</strong>stitutionsor <strong>of</strong> entire economic systems. e pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> comparative advantagediscredits <strong>the</strong> idea that each product should necessarily be produced whereverit can be produced most efficiently <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> technological sense. No presumptionholds, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, that any particular l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> production necessarilyshould be carried on <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> technologically most advanced way; for<strong>the</strong> resources required <strong>in</strong> such production are dem<strong>and</strong>ed by o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>dustriesalso, where <strong>the</strong>y may well contribute more at <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong> to consumersatisfactions, as judged by what consumers are will<strong>in</strong>g to pay.Efficiency <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> Pareto optimality is <strong>of</strong>ten taken as a criterion<strong>of</strong> policy. Pareto efficiency is <strong>in</strong>deed a useful concept <strong>in</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g microeconomic <strong>the</strong>ory. It is useful <strong>in</strong> contemplat<strong>in</strong>g outcomes<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market process <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> particular—but abstractlyconceived—allocations <strong>of</strong> resources <strong>and</strong> goods. Economists seldom ifever face an occasion or opportunity to appraise concrete, specific allocations,<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> real world. As Rutledge V<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g properly emphasizes, legislators<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir expert advisors necessarily are choos<strong>in</strong>g among alternativesets <strong>of</strong> legal <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutional constra<strong>in</strong>ts ra<strong>the</strong>r than among alternativespecific results or allocations. (See V<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g 1985 <strong>and</strong> Yeager 1978.) Suchconstra<strong>in</strong>ts are rules <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> game with<strong>in</strong> which people strive to make <strong>the</strong>most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir opportunities amidst ceaseless change <strong>in</strong> wants, resources,<strong>and</strong> technology. e very po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g rules <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions presupposes<strong>the</strong>ir hav<strong>in</strong>g a certa<strong>in</strong> stability <strong>and</strong> dependability, which would beunderm<strong>in</strong>ed by cont<strong>in</strong>ual efforts to make supposedly optimal changes<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m.What is useful <strong>in</strong> policy discussions, <strong>the</strong>n, is not <strong>the</strong> supposed benchmark<strong>of</strong> Pareto efficiency but, ra<strong>the</strong>r, comparison <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic <strong>and</strong>social systems that alternative sets <strong>of</strong> rules lead to. If we must have a st<strong>and</strong>ardaga<strong>in</strong>st which to appraise reality, we might well adopt <strong>the</strong> view <strong>of</strong> acompetitive market economy as a collection <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> practicesfor ga<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> transmitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives concern<strong>in</strong>g notyet-exhaustedopportunities for ga<strong>in</strong>s from trade (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g “trade withnature” through production or rearrangements <strong>of</strong> production). Subjectivists recognize <strong>the</strong> many k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation that market prices<strong>and</strong> processes br<strong>in</strong>g to bear on decisions about production <strong>and</strong> consumption.


28 Part I: Economicsese k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>in</strong>clude what F.A. Hayek (1945) called “knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particularcircumstances <strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong> place,” knowledge that could hardly becodified <strong>in</strong> textbooks or assembled for <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> central planners, knowledgethat can be used, if at all, only by numerous <strong>in</strong>dividual “men on <strong>the</strong>spot.” It <strong>in</strong>cludes knowledge about all sorts <strong>of</strong> details <strong>of</strong> runn<strong>in</strong>g bus<strong>in</strong>essfirms, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g knowledge <strong>of</strong> fleet<strong>in</strong>g local conditions. It <strong>in</strong>cludes whatpeople know about <strong>the</strong>ir own tastes <strong>and</strong> particular circumstances as consumers,workers, savers, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors. Subjectivist economists recognizehow such factors not only underlie <strong>the</strong> prices that consumers are preparedto pay for goods but also underlie costs <strong>of</strong> production.Each consumer decides how much <strong>of</strong> each particular good to buy<strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good itself, <strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r goods, his<strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong> wealth, <strong>and</strong> his own needs <strong>and</strong> preferences. Subject to qualificationsabout how possible <strong>and</strong> how worthwhile precise calculation seems,he leaves no opportunity unexploited to <strong>in</strong>crease his total satisfaction bydivert<strong>in</strong>g a dollar from one purchase to ano<strong>the</strong>r. Under competition, <strong>the</strong>price <strong>of</strong> each good tends to express <strong>the</strong> total <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> additional<strong>in</strong>puts necessary to supply an additional unit <strong>of</strong> that good. eseresource prices tend, <strong>in</strong> turn, to measure <strong>the</strong> values <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r marg<strong>in</strong>al outputssacrificed by diversion <strong>of</strong> resources away from <strong>the</strong>ir production. Prices<strong>the</strong>refore tell <strong>the</strong> consumer how much worth <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r production must beforgone to supply him with each particular good. e money values <strong>of</strong> forgonealternative production tend, <strong>in</strong> turn, to reflect consumer satisfactionsexpectedly obta<strong>in</strong>able from that forgone production. (I say “reflect”—takeaccount <strong>of</strong>—<strong>in</strong> order not to claim anyth<strong>in</strong>g about actual measurement <strong>of</strong>what is <strong>in</strong>herently unmeasurable. I speak only <strong>of</strong> tendencies, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,for markets never fully reach competitive general equilibrium.)With prices br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>ir attention <strong>the</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> choice posed by<strong>the</strong> objective realities <strong>of</strong> production possibilities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> subjective realities<strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r persons’ preferences, consumers choose <strong>the</strong> patterns <strong>of</strong> production<strong>and</strong> resource use that <strong>the</strong>y prefer. eir bidd<strong>in</strong>g tends to keep anyunit <strong>of</strong> a resource from go<strong>in</strong>g to meet a less <strong>in</strong>tense will<strong>in</strong>gness to pay forits productive contribution (<strong>and</strong> thus <strong>the</strong> denial <strong>of</strong> a more <strong>in</strong>tense will<strong>in</strong>gness).Ideally—<strong>in</strong> competitive equilibrium, <strong>and</strong> subject to qualificationsstill to be mentioned—no opportunity rema<strong>in</strong>s unexploited to <strong>in</strong>crease<strong>the</strong> total value <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs produced by transferr<strong>in</strong>g a unit <strong>of</strong> any resourcefrom one use to ano<strong>the</strong>r. Changes <strong>in</strong> technology <strong>and</strong> consumer preferencesalways keep creat<strong>in</strong>g such opportunities afresh, but <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it motivekeeps prodd<strong>in</strong>g bus<strong>in</strong>essmen to ferret <strong>the</strong>m out <strong>and</strong> exploit <strong>the</strong>m.


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 29To determ<strong>in</strong>e how resources go <strong>in</strong>to produc<strong>in</strong>g what th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> whatquantities, consumers need freedom to spend <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>comes as <strong>the</strong>y wish,unregimented by actual ration<strong>in</strong>g. But <strong>the</strong>y need more: opportunities tomake choices at unrigged prices tend<strong>in</strong>g to reflect true production alternatives.We could speak <strong>the</strong>n <strong>of</strong> “consumers’ sovereignty,” but <strong>the</strong> term is a bitnarrow. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as <strong>the</strong>ir abilities permit, people can br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir preferencesamong occupations as well as among consumer goods to bear on <strong>the</strong> pattern<strong>of</strong> production. In fact, <strong>in</strong>vestors’ preferences, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g notions about<strong>the</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> glamor <strong>of</strong> different <strong>in</strong>dustries <strong>and</strong> companies, alsohave some <strong>in</strong>fluence; <strong>and</strong> we might speak <strong>of</strong> “<strong>in</strong>vestors’ sovereignty” aswell. (See Rothbard 1962, p. 452 n. 12, <strong>and</strong> pp. 560–562 on what Rothbardcalls “<strong>in</strong>dividual sovereignty.”)Suppose that many people craved be<strong>in</strong>g actors strongly enough toaccept wages below those paid <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r jobs requir<strong>in</strong>g similar levels <strong>of</strong>ability <strong>and</strong> tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g. is will<strong>in</strong>gness would help keep down <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong>produc<strong>in</strong>g plays, <strong>and</strong> cheap tickets would draw audiences, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gjobs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ater. Suppose, <strong>in</strong> contrast, that almost everyone hated m<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gcoal. e high wages needed to attract m<strong>in</strong>ers would enter <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>production cost <strong>and</strong> price <strong>of</strong> coal, signal<strong>in</strong>g power companies to buildhydroelectric or nuclear or oil-burn<strong>in</strong>g ra<strong>the</strong>r than coal-burn<strong>in</strong>g plants<strong>and</strong> signal<strong>in</strong>g consumers to live <strong>in</strong> warmer climates or smaller or better<strong>in</strong>sulatedhouses than <strong>the</strong>y would do if fuel were cheaper. Such responseswould hold down <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> distasteful m<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g jobs to be filled. efew workers still do<strong>in</strong>g that work would be ones whose distaste for it wasrelatively mild <strong>and</strong> capable <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g assuaged by high wages.No pr<strong>of</strong>ound dist<strong>in</strong>ction holds between workers’ sovereignty <strong>and</strong> consumers’sovereignty or between gett<strong>in</strong>g satisfactions or avoid<strong>in</strong>g dissatisfactions<strong>in</strong> choos<strong>in</strong>g what work to do <strong>and</strong> what goods to consume. Consumergoods are not ultimate ends <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves but just particular means<strong>of</strong> obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g satisfactions or avoid<strong>in</strong>g dissatisfactions. People make <strong>the</strong>irpersonal tastes <strong>and</strong> circumstances count by how <strong>the</strong>y act on <strong>the</strong> marketsfor labor <strong>and</strong> goods alike.Our broadened concept <strong>of</strong> consumers’ <strong>and</strong> workers’ sovereignty by nomeans upsets <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> opportunity cost. We need only recognize thatpeople choose not simply among commodities but ra<strong>the</strong>r among packages<strong>of</strong> satisfactions <strong>and</strong> dissatisfactions. e choice between additionalamounts <strong>of</strong> A <strong>and</strong> B is really a choice between satisfactions ga<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong>dissatisfactions avoided by people as consumers <strong>and</strong> producers <strong>of</strong> A <strong>and</strong>


30 Part I: Economicssatisfactions ga<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> dissatisfactions avoided by people as consumers<strong>and</strong> producers <strong>of</strong> B. Choos<strong>in</strong>g package A costs forgo<strong>in</strong>g package B. Ideally,<strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> products A <strong>and</strong> B <strong>in</strong>dicate <strong>the</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> exchange, so tospeak, between <strong>the</strong> entire comb<strong>in</strong>ations <strong>of</strong> satisfactions ga<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> dissatisfactionsavoided at <strong>the</strong> relevant marg<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> connection with <strong>the</strong> two products.Prices reflect <strong>in</strong>timately personal circumstances <strong>and</strong> feel<strong>in</strong>gs as wellas physical or technological conditions <strong>of</strong> production <strong>and</strong> consumption.None <strong>of</strong> this amounts to claim<strong>in</strong>g that different persons’ feel<strong>in</strong>gs aboutgoods <strong>and</strong> jobs (<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment opportunities) can be accurately measured<strong>and</strong> compared by price or <strong>in</strong> any o<strong>the</strong>r def<strong>in</strong>ite way. However, people’sfeel<strong>in</strong>gs do count <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ways that <strong>the</strong>ir choices are expressed <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>iractivities coord<strong>in</strong>ated through <strong>the</strong> price system, <strong>and</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir feel<strong>in</strong>gsdo affect <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>of</strong> production <strong>in</strong> directions that make <strong>in</strong>tuitivelygood sense.Clearly, <strong>the</strong>n, economic <strong>the</strong>ory need not assume that people act exclusivelyor even primarily from materialistic motives. Pecuniary considerationscome <strong>in</strong>to play, but along with o<strong>the</strong>rs. As <strong>the</strong> laws <strong>of</strong> supply <strong>and</strong>dem<strong>and</strong> describe, an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pecuniary rewards or charges—oro<strong>the</strong>r rewards or costs—attached to some activity will <strong>in</strong>crease or decreaseits chosen level, o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>centives <strong>and</strong> dis<strong>in</strong>centives rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g unchanged.Money prices <strong>and</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m can thus <strong>in</strong>fluence behavior <strong>and</strong>promote coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> chosen behaviors <strong>of</strong> different people, eventhough pecuniary considerations do not carry decisive weight <strong>and</strong> perhapsnot even preponderant weight. e role <strong>of</strong> subjectivism <strong>in</strong> solv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> diamond-<strong>and</strong>-water paradox, replac<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> labor <strong>the</strong>ory or o<strong>the</strong>r real-cost <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> value, <strong>and</strong> accomplish<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>alist revolution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1870s, is too well known torequire more than a bare rem<strong>in</strong>der here. Subjectivism must be dist<strong>in</strong>guishedfrom import<strong>in</strong>g psychology <strong>in</strong>to economics (Mises 1949/1963,pp. 122–127, 486–488). Dim<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g marg<strong>in</strong>al utility is a pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> sensiblemanagement ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>of</strong> psychology: a person will apply a limitedamount <strong>of</strong> some good (gra<strong>in</strong>, say, as <strong>in</strong> Menger 1871/1950, pp. 129–130) towhat he considers its most important uses, <strong>and</strong> a larger <strong>and</strong> larger amountwill permit its application to successively less important uses also.Subjectivists do not commit <strong>the</strong> error <strong>of</strong> John Rusk<strong>in</strong>, who thoughtthat “Whenever material ga<strong>in</strong> follows exchange, for every plus <strong>the</strong>re is a


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 31precisely equal m<strong>in</strong>us” (quoted <strong>in</strong> Sh<strong>and</strong> 1984, p. 120). ey recognize thatwealth is produced not only by physically shap<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs or grow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mbut also by exchang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m. In <strong>the</strong> words <strong>of</strong> Henry George (1898/1941,pp. 331–332), who <strong>in</strong>dependently achieved several Austrian <strong>in</strong>sights, “Each<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two parties to an exchange ... [gets] someth<strong>in</strong>g that is more valuableto him than what he gives.... us <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> transaction an actual<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> wealth, an actual production <strong>of</strong> wealth.”Subjectivists recognize nonmaterial elements <strong>in</strong> costs as well as dem<strong>and</strong>s.Every price is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by many circumstances classifiableunder <strong>the</strong> head<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> “subjective factors” <strong>and</strong> “objective factors” (or“wants” <strong>and</strong> “resources <strong>and</strong> technology”). An alternative classification dist<strong>in</strong>guishesbetween dem<strong>and</strong> factors <strong>and</strong> supply factors. is alternative isnot equivalent to <strong>the</strong> first classification because <strong>the</strong>re is no reason to supposethat subjective factors operate only on <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> a marketwhile objective factors dom<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong> supply side.On <strong>the</strong> contrary, subjective factors operate on both sides. e supplyschedule <strong>of</strong> a good does not reflect merely <strong>the</strong> quantities <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>puts technologicallyrequired for various amounts <strong>of</strong> output, toge<strong>the</strong>r with givenprices <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>puts. e <strong>in</strong>put prices are <strong>the</strong>mselves variables determ<strong>in</strong>edby bidd<strong>in</strong>g among various firms <strong>and</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> production <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> light <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>puts’ capabilities to contribute to produc<strong>in</strong>g goods valued by consumers.Consumers’ subjective feel<strong>in</strong>gs about o<strong>the</strong>r goods thus enter <strong>in</strong>to determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> money costs <strong>of</strong> supply<strong>in</strong>g quantities <strong>of</strong> any particular product.Subjective factors operate <strong>in</strong> both blades <strong>of</strong> Marshall’s scissors. (Mislead<strong>in</strong>gly,Marshall 1920/1947, pp. 348, 813ff., had referred to a utility blade<strong>and</strong> a cost blade, as if utility <strong>and</strong> cost were quite dist<strong>in</strong>ct.)By <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> a price system, <strong>the</strong>n, money cost br<strong>in</strong>gs to <strong>the</strong> attention<strong>of</strong> persons decid<strong>in</strong>g on production processes <strong>and</strong> output volumes <strong>in</strong> anyparticular l<strong>in</strong>e—<strong>and</strong> ultimately to <strong>the</strong> attention <strong>of</strong> its consumers—whatconditions prevail <strong>in</strong> all o<strong>the</strong>r sectors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g persons’attitudes toward goods <strong>and</strong> employments. Money prices <strong>and</strong> costs convey<strong>in</strong>formation about subjective conditions outside <strong>the</strong> direct ken <strong>of</strong> particulardecisionmakers.At this po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>the</strong> subjectivism <strong>of</strong> Austrian economists re<strong>in</strong>forces <strong>the</strong>irawareness <strong>of</strong> general economic <strong>in</strong>terdependence <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir concern withcoord<strong>in</strong>ation among <strong>the</strong> plans <strong>and</strong> actions <strong>of</strong> different people. ey arewary (as many textbook writers seem not to be) <strong>of</strong> focus<strong>in</strong>g so narrowlyon <strong>the</strong> choices <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual household <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual firm as to detractattention from <strong>the</strong> big picture.


32 Part I: EconomicsRecogniz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> subjective aspects <strong>of</strong> cost, we ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>dubiousness <strong>of</strong> expect<strong>in</strong>g prices to correspond to costs <strong>in</strong> any precise way.Costs represent values <strong>of</strong> forgone alternatives: costs are <strong>in</strong>timately l<strong>in</strong>kedwith acts <strong>of</strong> choice.Cost curves are no more objectively given to bus<strong>in</strong>ess firms than aredem<strong>and</strong> curves for <strong>the</strong>ir products. A large part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> entrepreneurs<strong>and</strong> managers is to learn what <strong>the</strong> cost (<strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>) curves are <strong>and</strong> topress <strong>the</strong> cost curves down, so to speak, through <strong>in</strong>spired <strong>in</strong>novations <strong>in</strong>technology, organization, purchas<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> market<strong>in</strong>g. Outsiders are <strong>in</strong> apoor position to second-guess <strong>the</strong>ir decisions.Subjectivists appreciate <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> expectations. Well before <strong>the</strong>vogue <strong>of</strong> “rational expectations” <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics, Ludwig von Mises(1953/1981, pp. 459–460) recognized that an <strong>in</strong>flationary policy could notgo on <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>itely giv<strong>in</strong>g real “stimulus” to an economy; people wouldcatch on to what was happen<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed stimulus would dissipateitself <strong>in</strong> price <strong>in</strong>creases. Mises also argued (1949/1963, p. 586) thatdisorders such as <strong>the</strong> corn-hog cycle would be self-corrective. Unless <strong>the</strong>government protected farmers from <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> unperceptive orun<strong>in</strong>telligent behavior, farmers would learn about <strong>the</strong> cycle, if it did <strong>in</strong> factoccur; <strong>and</strong> by anticipat<strong>in</strong>g it would forestall it. (ose who did not learnwould <strong>in</strong>cur losses <strong>and</strong> be elim<strong>in</strong>ated from <strong>the</strong> market.)Much expressed nowadays are notions such as “<strong>the</strong> market’s” expectation<strong>of</strong> some future magnitude—<strong>the</strong> dollar-mark exchange rate <strong>in</strong> threemonths, or whatever. Subjectivists are skeptical. ey underst<strong>and</strong> that“<strong>the</strong> market” does not form expectations or change light bulbs (“Howmany right-w<strong>in</strong>g economists does it take to change a light bulb?”) or doanyth<strong>in</strong>g else. People do, people act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g on markets. S<strong>in</strong>ceexpectations are formed by people, <strong>the</strong>y are underst<strong>and</strong>ably loose, diverse,<strong>and</strong> changeable.All this <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>es with <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>herent unpredictability <strong>of</strong> future humanaffairs. It is not even possible to make an exhaustive list <strong>of</strong> all possible outcomes<strong>of</strong> some decision, let alone attach probability scores to outcomes(Shackle 1972, esp. p. 22). Policymakers should take this po<strong>in</strong>t to heart<strong>and</strong> restra<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir optimism about be<strong>in</strong>g able to control events.is is not to deny that some predictions can be made with warrantedconfidence, notably <strong>the</strong> if-this-<strong>the</strong>n-that predictions <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> science <strong>in</strong> general. Foretell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> future is quite ano<strong>the</strong>r matter.Economists, like o<strong>the</strong>r people, have only limited time <strong>and</strong> energy. It isreasonable for each one to stick to work exploit<strong>in</strong>g his own comparative


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 33advantages <strong>and</strong> hunches about fruitfulness <strong>and</strong> not let himself be badgered<strong>in</strong>to foretell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> unforetellable.James Buchanan achieved one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> greatest triumphs <strong>of</strong> subjectivism<strong>in</strong> demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g (1958/1999) that <strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> government spend<strong>in</strong>gcan <strong>in</strong>deed be largely shifted onto future generations by deficit f<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>gthrough issue <strong>of</strong> bonds. e conventional wisdom among economists(shared even by Ludwig von Mises, though not by <strong>the</strong> general public)had been unduly materialistic: <strong>the</strong> burden cannot be shifted through time,s<strong>in</strong>ce resources are used when <strong>the</strong>y are used. Buchanan recognized that aburden is someth<strong>in</strong>g subjectively perceived. Persons who voluntarily giveup current comm<strong>and</strong> over resources <strong>in</strong> exchange for government bondsthat <strong>the</strong>y f<strong>in</strong>d attractive suffer no burden <strong>in</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g so. It is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> futurethat people—<strong>in</strong> general, people o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al bond-buyers—willbear <strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> pay<strong>in</strong>g taxes to service <strong>the</strong> debt or <strong>of</strong> los<strong>in</strong>g throughits <strong>in</strong>flationary or outright repudiation. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, bond-f<strong>in</strong>anced governmentdeficits do affect allocation <strong>of</strong> resources <strong>in</strong> time by trench<strong>in</strong>gon private capital formation, <strong>the</strong>reby worsen<strong>in</strong>g future economic opportunities. e ultrasubjectivist view <strong>of</strong> cost put forward by James Buchanan (1969)<strong>and</strong> writers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> London School tradition (some <strong>of</strong> whose articles arerepr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Buchanan <strong>and</strong> irlby 1973/1981) has been largely adopted byAustrian economists (Vaughn 1980 <strong>and</strong> 1981; Seldon 1981).In exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g this view, we must avoid false presuppositions about howwords relate to th<strong>in</strong>gs. It is not true that each word has a s<strong>in</strong>gle def<strong>in</strong>ite<strong>and</strong> unequivocal mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> that it labels a specific th<strong>in</strong>g or action orrelation objectively exist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, many wordshave wide ranges <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g. One way to learn what writers mean bya word is to see what implications <strong>the</strong>y draw from propositions conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>git.is is true <strong>of</strong> “cost” as <strong>in</strong>terpreted by Buchanan <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> London economists.ose writers associate particular policy positions with <strong>the</strong> fuzz<strong>in</strong>essthat <strong>the</strong>y attribute to cost. ey heap scorn on cost-oriented rules formanag<strong>in</strong>g enterprises. Unaccountably, I somehow forgot to mention this achievement <strong>of</strong> Buchanan’s untilit was too late to change this article while it was be<strong>in</strong>g orig<strong>in</strong>ally published.


34 Part I: EconomicsAdvocates <strong>of</strong> such rules typically attribute important welfare propertiesto <strong>the</strong>m. Probably <strong>the</strong> most prom<strong>in</strong>ent such rule is <strong>the</strong> one requir<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> output <strong>of</strong> an enterprise to be set at such a level that price equalsmarg<strong>in</strong>al costs. (In <strong>the</strong> same general cost-oriented family, however, wouldbe rules like <strong>the</strong> one that total revenue should just cover total cost.) Onestr<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> argument for socialism, <strong>in</strong> fact, is that socialized enterprisescould be made to follow such rules, unlike unregulated private enterprises.Even under capitalism, such rules supposedly might be useful <strong>in</strong> fram<strong>in</strong>gantimonopoly policy <strong>and</strong> regulat<strong>in</strong>g public utilities. ey might also figure<strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r government economic <strong>in</strong>terventions <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> simulat<strong>in</strong>g marketresults <strong>in</strong> nonmarket sett<strong>in</strong>gs, as <strong>in</strong> tort settlements.e case for socialism <strong>and</strong> milder government economic <strong>in</strong>terventionscan be weakened, <strong>the</strong>n, by discredit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> measurability <strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong> conceptualdef<strong>in</strong>iteness <strong>of</strong> “cost.” is, I conjecture, is a clue to <strong>the</strong> ultrasubjectivistview <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept. “Cost,” says Buchanan (1969, pp. 42–43), “is thatwhich <strong>the</strong> decisionmaker sacrifices or gives up when he makes a choice. Itconsists <strong>in</strong> his own evaluation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> enjoyment or utility that he anticipateshav<strong>in</strong>g to forego as a result <strong>of</strong> selection among alternative courses <strong>of</strong>action.” If cost can thus be portrayed as a thoroughly subjective concept ormagnitude, if no one but <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual decisionmaker (entrepreneur ormanager) can know what cost is or was, <strong>and</strong> if such knowledge is <strong>in</strong>effable<strong>and</strong> practically <strong>in</strong>communicable, <strong>the</strong>n no outside authority can reasonablyimpose cost-oriented rules on him. e case for displac<strong>in</strong>g or overrid<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> market dissolves.is l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> argument has some merit. As already observed, cost curvesdo not objectively exist. Instead, bus<strong>in</strong>ess decisionmakers have <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong>discover<strong>in</strong>g or <strong>in</strong>vent<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m <strong>and</strong> modify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m by happy <strong>in</strong>novations.Unfortunately, as a later section <strong>of</strong> this article shows, Buchanan <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>London economists carry <strong>the</strong>ir subjectivist l<strong>in</strong>e too far <strong>and</strong> so tend to discreditit.Subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights about expectations have o<strong>the</strong>r notable policy implications.e history <strong>of</strong> energy policy, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> politicians’ demagogy, providesreason for expect<strong>in</strong>g future repetition <strong>of</strong> past <strong>in</strong>fr<strong>in</strong>gements on propertyrights. Firms <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors must recognize that if <strong>the</strong>y make decisionsthat turn out <strong>in</strong> some future energy crisis to have been wise—for example,stockpil<strong>in</strong>g oil, cultivat<strong>in</strong>g nonconventional energy sources, adopt<strong>in</strong>gconservation measures, or build<strong>in</strong>g flexibility <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>ir facilities <strong>and</strong> operationsto be able to cope relatively well with energy squeezes—<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>ywill not be allowed to reap exceptional pr<strong>of</strong>its from <strong>the</strong>ir risk-bear<strong>in</strong>g,


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 35<strong>the</strong>ir correct hunches, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir good luck. ey will be victimizedby seizure <strong>of</strong> oil stocks, by adverse treatment under ration<strong>in</strong>g schemes,by price controls, or <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r ways. Government reassurances, even ifmade, would nowadays not be credible. e benefits <strong>of</strong> diverse privateresponses to diverse expectations about energy supplies are thus partlyforestalled.is example rem<strong>in</strong>ds subjectivists <strong>of</strong> a broader po<strong>in</strong>t about remoterepercussions <strong>of</strong> particular policies, repercussions remote <strong>in</strong> time or <strong>in</strong>economic sector. A violation <strong>of</strong> property rights may seem <strong>the</strong> economical<strong>and</strong> expedient policy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual case. Yet <strong>in</strong> contribut<strong>in</strong>g toan atmosphere <strong>of</strong> uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, it can have grave repercussions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>long run.Because expectations <strong>in</strong>fluence behavior, a policy’s credibility conditionsits effectiveness, as <strong>the</strong> rational-expectations <strong>the</strong>orists, <strong>and</strong> WilliamFellner (1976) before <strong>the</strong>m, have emphasized. e question <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> withdrawalpangs <strong>of</strong> end<strong>in</strong>g an entrenched price <strong>in</strong>flation provides an example.When money-supply growth is slowed or stopped, <strong>the</strong> reduced growth <strong>of</strong>nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>come is split between price deceleration <strong>and</strong> slowed real production<strong>and</strong> employment. Expectations affect how favorable or unfavorablethis split is. If <strong>the</strong> anti-<strong>in</strong>flation program is not credible—if wagenegotiators <strong>and</strong> price-setters th<strong>in</strong>k that <strong>the</strong> policymakers will lose <strong>the</strong>irnerve <strong>and</strong> switch gears at <strong>the</strong> first sign <strong>of</strong> recessionary side effects—<strong>the</strong>nthose private parties will expect <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>flation to cont<strong>in</strong>ue <strong>and</strong> will make<strong>the</strong>ir wage <strong>and</strong> price decisions accord<strong>in</strong>gly; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> monetary slowdownwill bite ma<strong>in</strong>ly on real activity. If, on <strong>the</strong> contrary, people are conv<strong>in</strong>cedthat <strong>the</strong> authorities will persist <strong>in</strong> monetary restriction <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>itely no matterhow bad <strong>the</strong> side-effects, so that <strong>in</strong>flation is bound to abate, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>perceptive price-setter or wage-negotiator will realize that if he never<strong>the</strong>lesspersists <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>creases at <strong>the</strong> same old pace, he will f<strong>in</strong>d himselfout ahead <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>stalled <strong>in</strong>flationary procession <strong>and</strong> will lose customersor jobs. People will moderate <strong>the</strong>ir price <strong>and</strong> wage dem<strong>and</strong>s, mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>split relatively favorable to cont<strong>in</strong>ued real activity.It is only superficially paradoxical, <strong>the</strong>n, that <strong>in</strong> two alternative situationswith <strong>the</strong> same degree <strong>of</strong> monetary restra<strong>in</strong>t, <strong>the</strong> situation <strong>in</strong> which<strong>the</strong> authorities are believed ready to tolerate severe recessionary sideeffectswill actually exhibit milder ones than <strong>the</strong> situation <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>authorities are suspected <strong>of</strong> irresolution. Subjectivists underst<strong>and</strong> how<strong>in</strong>tangible factors like <strong>the</strong>se can affect outcomes under objectively similarconditions.


36 Part I: Economics Capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory is a particular case or application <strong>of</strong> generalvalue <strong>the</strong>ory, but its subjectivist aspects can conveniently occupy a section<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own.Subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights help dispel some paradoxes cultivated by neo-Ricardians <strong>and</strong> neo-Marxists at Cambridge University. ese paradoxesseem to impugn st<strong>and</strong>ard economic <strong>the</strong>ory (particularly <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>alproductivity<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> factor remuneration), <strong>and</strong> by implication <strong>the</strong>y call<strong>the</strong> entire logic <strong>of</strong> a market economy <strong>in</strong>to question.Review<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> paradoxes <strong>in</strong> detail is unnecessary here (see Yeager 1976<strong>and</strong> Garrison 1979). One much-employed arithmetical example describestwo alternative techniques for produc<strong>in</strong>g a def<strong>in</strong>ite amount <strong>of</strong> some product.ey <strong>in</strong>volve different time-patterns <strong>of</strong> labor <strong>in</strong>puts. In each technique,compound <strong>in</strong>terest accrues, so to speak, on <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestedlabor. Technique A is cheaper at <strong>in</strong>terest rates above 100 percent, B ischeaper at rates between 50 <strong>and</strong> 100 percent, <strong>and</strong> A is cheaper aga<strong>in</strong> atrates below 50 percent.If a decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate through one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se two critical levelsbr<strong>in</strong>gs a switch from <strong>the</strong> less to <strong>the</strong> more capital-<strong>in</strong>tensive <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two techniques,which seems normal enough, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> switch to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r techniqueas <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate decl<strong>in</strong>es through <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r switch po<strong>in</strong>t is paradoxical.If we view <strong>the</strong> latter switch <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> opposite direction, an <strong>in</strong>creased<strong>in</strong>terest rate prompts a more <strong>in</strong>tensive use <strong>of</strong> capital. Capital <strong>in</strong>tensity canrespond perversely to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate.Examples <strong>of</strong> such perversity seem not to depend on trickery <strong>in</strong> measur<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> stock <strong>of</strong> capital. e physical specifications <strong>of</strong> a technique, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> tim<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its <strong>in</strong>puts <strong>and</strong> its output, stay <strong>the</strong> same regardless <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>and</strong> regardless <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> technique is actually <strong>in</strong> use. Ifone technique employs physically more capital than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> relationto labor or to output at one switch po<strong>in</strong>t, <strong>the</strong>n it still employs more at anyo<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>terest rate. is comparison rema<strong>in</strong>s valid with any conventionfor physically measur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> capital, provided only that onedoes not change measurement conventions <strong>in</strong> mid-example. If <strong>the</strong> capital<strong>in</strong>tensities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two techniques are such that <strong>the</strong> switch between <strong>the</strong>mat one critical <strong>in</strong>terest rate is nonparadoxical, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> switch at <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rmust be paradoxical—a change <strong>in</strong> capital <strong>in</strong>tensity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same direction as<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate. We cannot deny perversity at both switch po<strong>in</strong>ts—unlesswe ab<strong>and</strong>on a purely physical conception <strong>of</strong> capital.


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 37e paradox-mongers commit several faults. ey slide from compar<strong>in</strong>galternative static states <strong>in</strong>to speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> responses to those changes. ey avoid specify<strong>in</strong>g what supposedlydeterm<strong>in</strong>es <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>and</strong> what makes it change.e key to dispell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> paradoxes, however, is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sight that capital—orwhatever it is that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate is <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong>—cannot be measured<strong>in</strong> purely physical terms. One must appreciate <strong>the</strong> value aspect—<strong>the</strong>subjective aspect—<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g whose price is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate. It is convenientto conceive <strong>of</strong> that th<strong>in</strong>g as a factor <strong>of</strong> production. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Cassel(1903/1971, pp. 41ff. <strong>and</strong> passim), we might name it “wait<strong>in</strong>g.” It is <strong>the</strong> ty<strong>in</strong>gup <strong>of</strong> value over time, which is necessary <strong>in</strong> all production processes. (isconceptualization is “convenient” not only because it conforms to reality<strong>and</strong> because it dispels <strong>the</strong> paradoxes but also because it displays parallelsbetween how <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r factor prices are determ<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong>what <strong>the</strong>ir functions are: it br<strong>in</strong>gs capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory comfortably<strong>in</strong>to l<strong>in</strong>e with general microeconomic <strong>the</strong>ory.)In a physically specified production process, a reduced <strong>in</strong>terest rate notonly is a cheapen<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>the</strong> ty<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>of</strong> value over time) thatmust be done but also reduces its required value-amount. It reduces <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>terest element <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> notional prices <strong>of</strong> semif<strong>in</strong>ished <strong>and</strong> capital goodsfor whose ripen<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to f<strong>in</strong>al consumer goods <strong>and</strong> services still fur<strong>the</strong>rwait<strong>in</strong>g must be done. Increased thrift is productive not only because itsupplies more <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g required for production but also because, bylower<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate, it reduces <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g required byany physically specified technique.e amounts <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g required by alternative physically specifiedtechniques will <strong>in</strong> general decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> different degrees, which presents<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> reswitch<strong>in</strong>g between techniques, as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> example mentioned.When a decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate br<strong>in</strong>gs an apparently perverseswitch to a technique that is less capital-<strong>in</strong>tensive by some physical criterion,<strong>the</strong> explanation is that <strong>the</strong> decl<strong>in</strong>e, although reduc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>tensities<strong>of</strong> both techniques, reduces <strong>the</strong>m differentially <strong>in</strong> such a wayas to br<strong>in</strong>g a larger reduction <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> overall expense <strong>of</strong> produc<strong>in</strong>g by <strong>the</strong>adopted technique.Preconceived <strong>in</strong>sistence on measur<strong>in</strong>g all factor quantities <strong>and</strong> factor<strong>in</strong>tensities<strong>in</strong> purely physical terms clashes with <strong>the</strong> fact <strong>of</strong> reality—orarithmetic—that <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> ty<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>of</strong> value over time required <strong>in</strong>achiev<strong>in</strong>g a physically specified result does <strong>in</strong>deed depend on that factor’sown price. Not only <strong>the</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g-<strong>in</strong>tensity <strong>of</strong> a physically specified process


38 Part I: Economicsbut also <strong>the</strong> relative wait<strong>in</strong>g-<strong>in</strong>tensities <strong>of</strong> alternative processes really areaffected by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate. When a switch <strong>of</strong> technique occurs, <strong>the</strong> techniqueadopted really is <strong>the</strong> more economical on <strong>the</strong> whole, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>puts,wait<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>cluded, be<strong>in</strong>g valued at <strong>the</strong>ir prices. When a rise <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terestrate triggers a switch <strong>of</strong> techniques, <strong>the</strong> displaced one has become relativelytoo wait<strong>in</strong>g-<strong>in</strong>tensive to rema<strong>in</strong> economically viable. It is irrelevantas a criticism <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory that by some o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>in</strong>applicable, criterion<strong>the</strong> displaced technique counts as less capital-<strong>in</strong>tensive.Fur<strong>the</strong>r discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed paradoxes would display parallelsbetween reswitch<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> conceivable phenomenon <strong>of</strong> multiple <strong>in</strong>ternalrates <strong>of</strong> return <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>vestment option, which is hardly mysteriousat all (Hirshleifer 1970, pp. 77–81). Already, though, I’ve said enough toshow how a subjectivist conceptualization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> factor whose price is <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>terest rate can avoid fallacies flow<strong>in</strong>g from a materialist or objective conceptualization.“ ”On a few po<strong>in</strong>ts, some Austrian economists may not have been subjectivistenough. Murray Rothbard (1962, pp. 153–154) seems to th<strong>in</strong>k that acontract under which no property has yet changed h<strong>and</strong>s—for example,an exchange <strong>of</strong> promises between a movie actor <strong>and</strong> a studio—is somehowless properly enforceable than a contract under which some payment hasalready been made. Blackmail is a less actionable <strong>of</strong>fense than extortionthrough application or threat <strong>of</strong> physical force (1962, p. 443 n. 49). If avilla<strong>in</strong> compels me to sell him my property at a mere token price underthreat <strong>of</strong> ru<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g my reputation <strong>and</strong> my bus<strong>in</strong>ess by spread<strong>in</strong>g vicious butplausible lies, his action is somehow less <strong>of</strong> a crime or tort than if he had<strong>in</strong>stead threatened to kick me <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sh<strong>in</strong>s or trample one <strong>of</strong> my tomatoplants (Rothbard 1982, esp. pp. 121–127, 133–148, <strong>and</strong> personal correspondence).e material element <strong>in</strong> a transaction or a threat supposedly makesa great difference.I may be at fault <strong>in</strong> not grasp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctions made <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>seexamples, but it would be helpful to have fur<strong>the</strong>r explanation <strong>of</strong> whatsuperficially seems like an untypical lapse from subjectivism <strong>in</strong>to materialism.Far more common is <strong>the</strong> lapse <strong>in</strong>to overstat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> subjectivist positionso badly as to risk discredit<strong>in</strong>g it. F.A. Hayek is not himself to blame,but a remark <strong>of</strong> his (1952, p. 31) has been quoted ad nauseam (for example


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 39by Ludwig Lachmann <strong>in</strong> Spadaro 1978, p. 1; Walter Gr<strong>in</strong>der <strong>in</strong> his <strong>in</strong>troductionto Lachmann 1977, p. 23; <strong>and</strong> Littlechild 1979, p. 13). It has had asignificance attributed to it that it simply cannot bear. “It is probably noexaggeration to say that every important advance <strong>in</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory dur<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> last hundred years was a fur<strong>the</strong>r step <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> consistent application<strong>of</strong> subjectivism.”is proposition <strong>of</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>al history could be strictly correct withoutimply<strong>in</strong>g that every subjectivist step was an important advance. Moreover,past success with extend<strong>in</strong>g subjectivism <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> degrees <strong>and</strong> directionsdoes not imply that any <strong>and</strong> all fur<strong>the</strong>r extensions constitute valid contributionsto economics.A <strong>the</strong>orist is not necessarily entitled to take pride <strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g able to boast,“I am more subjectivist than thou.” More important than subjectivism forits own sake is gett<strong>in</strong>g one’s analysis straight.e most sweep<strong>in</strong>g extensions <strong>of</strong> subjectivism occur <strong>in</strong> remarks abouta purely subjective <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> value, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a pure time-preference <strong>the</strong>ory<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate. Closely related remarks scorn <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> mutualdeterm<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> economic magnitudes, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory expounded by systems<strong>of</strong> simultaneous equations <strong>of</strong> general equilibrium. e ultrasubjectivists<strong>in</strong>sist on monocausality <strong>in</strong>stead. Causation supposedly runs <strong>in</strong> one directiononly, from consumers’ assessments <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al utility <strong>and</strong> value <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> relative utilities or values <strong>of</strong> future <strong>and</strong> present consumption to prices<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>and</strong> sectoral <strong>and</strong> temporal patterns <strong>of</strong> resource allocation<strong>and</strong> production (Rothbard 1962, pp. 302–303).Taken with uncharitable literalness, <strong>the</strong> ultrasubjectivist slogans implythat people’s feel<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> assessments have everyth<strong>in</strong>g to do <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> realities<strong>of</strong> nature, science, <strong>and</strong> technology have noth<strong>in</strong>g to do with determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gprices <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rates <strong>and</strong> all <strong>in</strong>terrelated economic magnitudes.Actually, <strong>the</strong>se objective realities do <strong>in</strong>teract with people’s tastes. ey conditionhow abundant various resources <strong>and</strong> goods are, or could be madeto be, <strong>and</strong> so help determ<strong>in</strong>e marg<strong>in</strong>al utilities.For two reasons I know that <strong>the</strong> ultrasubjectivists do not really believeall <strong>the</strong>y say. First, <strong>the</strong> propositions <strong>in</strong> question, taken literally, are too preposterousfor anyone to believe. Second, subjectivist writ<strong>in</strong>gs sometimesdiscuss production functions, <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> dim<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g marg<strong>in</strong>al physicalproduct, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r physical relations, conced<strong>in</strong>g some importance tosuch matters.What I object to, <strong>the</strong>n, is not so much substantive beliefs as mislead<strong>in</strong>glanguage, language that sometimes misleads even its users, language


40 Part I: Economicsadopted on <strong>the</strong> presupposition that subjectivism is good <strong>and</strong> more <strong>of</strong> it isbetter.Subjectivists may contend that physical reality counts only throughpeople’s subjective perceptions <strong>of</strong> it <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> valuations <strong>the</strong>y make <strong>in</strong>accord with it. But that contention does not banish <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> objectivereality. Bus<strong>in</strong>essmen (<strong>and</strong> consumers) who perceive reality correctlywill thrive better on <strong>the</strong> market than those who misperceive it. A k<strong>in</strong>d<strong>of</strong> natural selection sees to it that objective reality does get taken <strong>in</strong>toaccount.Full-dress argument for purely subjective value <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong>for unidirectional causality appears rarely <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>t. It keeps be<strong>in</strong>g asserted<strong>in</strong> sem<strong>in</strong>ars, conversation, <strong>and</strong> correspondence, however, as I for one cantestify <strong>and</strong> as c<strong>and</strong>id Austrians will presumably acknowledge. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,such assertions do appear <strong>in</strong> authoritative Austrian publications.(For example, see Rothbard 1962, pp. 117, 122, 293, 307, 332, 363–364, 452 n.16, 455 n. 12, 457 n. 27, 508, 528, 557, 893 n. 14; Rothbard, <strong>in</strong>troduction toFetter 1977; Taylor 1980, pp. 26, 32, 36, 47, 50; <strong>and</strong> Sh<strong>and</strong> 1984, pp. 23, 44,45, 54, 56.) Garrison (1979, pp. 220–221) avoids <strong>the</strong> word “pure” <strong>in</strong> recommend<strong>in</strong>ga time-preference <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>and</strong> a subjectivist <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong>value <strong>in</strong> general, but he does contrast <strong>the</strong>m favorably with what he calls“eclectic” <strong>the</strong>ories, such as <strong>the</strong> “st<strong>and</strong>ard Fisherian” <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest. Foroutright avowal <strong>of</strong> a pure time-preference <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory, see Kirzner’smanuscript.)e po<strong>in</strong>t repeatedly turns up <strong>in</strong> Austrian discussions that goods thatpeople consider different from each o<strong>the</strong>r are <strong>in</strong>deed different goods, nomatter how closely <strong>the</strong>y resemble each o<strong>the</strong>r physically. is po<strong>in</strong>t isnot downright fallacious, but <strong>the</strong> significance attributed to it is excessive,<strong>and</strong> its use <strong>in</strong> question-begg<strong>in</strong>g ways is likely to repel ma<strong>in</strong>stream economists.An example is <strong>the</strong> contention that when a manufacturer sells essentially<strong>the</strong> same good under different labels at different prices, he is never<strong>the</strong>lessnot practic<strong>in</strong>g price discrim<strong>in</strong>ation; for <strong>the</strong> goods bear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>different labels are considered by <strong>the</strong> consumers to be different goods,which makes <strong>the</strong>m different goods <strong>in</strong> all economically relevant senses.e manufacturer is supposedly just charg<strong>in</strong>g different prices for differentth<strong>in</strong>gs.Quite probably his practice is not one that perceptive economists <strong>and</strong>social philosophers would want to suppress by force <strong>of</strong> law; but we shouldnot let our policy judgments, any more than our subjectivist methodologicalpreconceptions, dictate our economic analysis or remove certa<strong>in</strong>


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 41questions from its scope. It may be more fruitful to recognize that pricediscrim<strong>in</strong>ation is <strong>in</strong>deed go<strong>in</strong>g on, with <strong>the</strong> different labels be<strong>in</strong>g used toseparate customers accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>ir dem<strong>and</strong> elasticities.Crypticism sometimes accompanies <strong>in</strong>sistence on pure subjectivism.An example is a l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> attack taken aga<strong>in</strong>st ma<strong>in</strong>stream <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory,which enlists considerations <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tertemporal transformability (that is, <strong>the</strong>productivity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment) as well as <strong>the</strong> subjective time-preference element.is <strong>the</strong>ory is epitomized by Irv<strong>in</strong>g Fisher’s diagram (1930/1970,pp. 234ff.; Hirshleifer 1970, passim) show<strong>in</strong>g a transformation curvebetween present <strong>and</strong> future goods (or consumption), as well as a map<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>difference curves between present <strong>and</strong> future goods. A familiar Austrianobjection is to <strong>in</strong>sist that <strong>the</strong> diagram, specifically <strong>the</strong> transformationcurve, fails to make <strong>the</strong> required dist<strong>in</strong>ction between physical productivity<strong>and</strong> value productivity.If not deliberate obscurantism, this objection does <strong>in</strong>dicate misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> Fisher’s <strong>the</strong>ory (or impatience with or prejudice aga<strong>in</strong>stit). Of course, some technological change that <strong>in</strong>creases <strong>the</strong> physicalproductivity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> some specific l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> production, say widgets,may not <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>the</strong> value productivity <strong>of</strong> such <strong>in</strong>vestment. e<strong>in</strong>creased physical amount <strong>of</strong> future widgets obta<strong>in</strong>able for a given presentsacrifice may <strong>in</strong>deed have a reduced total value relative to o<strong>the</strong>r goods<strong>and</strong> services <strong>in</strong> general (<strong>the</strong> future dem<strong>and</strong> for widgets may be price<strong>in</strong>elastic).Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> new opportunities created by technological changewill <strong>in</strong>deed be unattractive to <strong>in</strong>vestors. In <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> greater productivity<strong>of</strong> more roundabout methods <strong>of</strong> production, Böhm-Bawerk(1884/1889/1909–1912/1959, vol. II: pp. 82–84; vol. III: pp. 45–56) was referr<strong>in</strong>gto “well-chosen” or “skillfully chosen” or “wisely selected” methods;<strong>and</strong> a similar stipulation applies to <strong>the</strong> present case. Technological changesthat <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>the</strong> physical productivity <strong>of</strong> particular roundabout methodsbroaden <strong>the</strong> range <strong>of</strong> opportunities among which <strong>in</strong>vestors can exercisewise choice, <strong>and</strong> implement<strong>in</strong>g some <strong>of</strong> those choices does add to <strong>the</strong>dem<strong>and</strong> for wait<strong>in</strong>g, tend<strong>in</strong>g to bid up <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate.e ultrasubjectivist objection is open to ano<strong>the</strong>r str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> reply. It isillegitimate to <strong>in</strong>voke a contrast between physical productivity <strong>and</strong> valueproductivity by restrict<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> discussion to examples <strong>of</strong> sacrific<strong>in</strong>g specificpresent goods to get more future goods <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same k<strong>in</strong>d. What is conveyedby borrow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> lend<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r transactions <strong>in</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g) is notcomm<strong>and</strong> over <strong>in</strong>vestible resources that would o<strong>the</strong>rwise have gone <strong>in</strong>toproduc<strong>in</strong>g specific present goods but comm<strong>and</strong> over resources <strong>in</strong> general.


42 Part I: EconomicsIt is legitimate to do what Fisher’s diagram helps us to do: to conceive<strong>of</strong> present goods <strong>in</strong> general be<strong>in</strong>g sacrificed for larger amounts <strong>of</strong> futuregoods <strong>in</strong> general.With <strong>the</strong>ir admirable general emphasis on process <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> decisions<strong>and</strong> actions <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual persons, Austrian economists should notrest content with attacks on ma<strong>in</strong>stream capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory thatrely on cryptic allusions to a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between physical productivity <strong>and</strong>value productivity (or, similarly, to assertions that factor prices will adjust).ey should defend <strong>the</strong>ir pure subjectivism on this topic, if <strong>the</strong>y can, witha detailed process analysis <strong>of</strong> how persons act.Next I turn to exaggerations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> subjectivist cost doctr<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> Buchanan<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> London School. ese <strong>the</strong>orists <strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> aparticular course <strong>of</strong> action as <strong>the</strong> next-best course perceived <strong>and</strong> forgoneby <strong>the</strong> decisionmaker. Ronald Coase (quoted with approval <strong>in</strong> Buchanan1969, p. 28) says that “e cost <strong>of</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g anyth<strong>in</strong>g consists <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> receiptswhich would have been obta<strong>in</strong>ed if that particular decision had not beentaken.... To cover costs <strong>and</strong> to maximize pr<strong>of</strong>its are essentially two ways<strong>of</strong> express<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> same phenomenon.”Well, suppose <strong>the</strong> best course <strong>of</strong> action open to me is, <strong>in</strong> my judgment,to open a restaurant <strong>of</strong> a quite specific type <strong>in</strong> a specific location. e nextbestcourse, <strong>the</strong>n, is presumably to open a restaurant identical <strong>in</strong> all butsome trivial detail, such as <strong>the</strong> particular hue <strong>of</strong> green <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> lampshades.If so, <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> precise restaurant chosen is presumably an all butidentical restaurant worth to me, <strong>in</strong> my judgment, almost fully as much.Generaliz<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> a chosen th<strong>in</strong>g or course <strong>of</strong> action is very nearly<strong>the</strong> full value that <strong>the</strong> decisionmaker attributes to it.My counterexample to <strong>the</strong> Coase-Buchanan cost concept may seemfrivolous, but it raises a serious question. How far from identical to <strong>the</strong>chosen course <strong>of</strong> action must <strong>the</strong> next best alternative be to count as adist<strong>in</strong>ct alternative? e po<strong>in</strong>t conveyed by questions like this is that ei<strong>the</strong>rradical error or sterile word-jugg<strong>in</strong>g is afoot. (Nozick 1977, esp. pp. 372–373,expresses some compatible though not identical doubts about subjectivistconcepts <strong>of</strong> cost <strong>and</strong> preference.)More ord<strong>in</strong>ary concepts <strong>of</strong> cost, however, are mean<strong>in</strong>gful, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> money cost <strong>in</strong> a particular l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> production as away <strong>of</strong> convey<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation to decisionmakers <strong>in</strong> it about conditions(<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g personal tastes) <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sectors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy.Buchanan (1969, p. 43) draws six implications from his choice-boundconception <strong>of</strong> cost, <strong>and</strong> Littlechild (<strong>in</strong> Spadaro 1978, pp. 82–83) quotes


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 43<strong>the</strong>m all with apparent approval. I’ll quote <strong>and</strong> comment only on <strong>the</strong> first,second, <strong>and</strong> fifth.1. Most importantly, cost must be borne exclusively by <strong>the</strong> decisionmaker;it is not possible for cost to be shifted to or imposed on o<strong>the</strong>rs.2. Cost is subjective; it exists <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> decisionmaker <strong>and</strong>nowhere else....5. Cost cannot be measured by someone o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> decisionmakerbecause <strong>the</strong>re is no way that subjective experience can be directly observed.As for <strong>the</strong> first word <strong>and</strong> second implications, <strong>of</strong> course cost can beimposed on o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>in</strong> quite ord<strong>in</strong>ary senses <strong>of</strong> those words; it is not alwayskept <strong>in</strong>side <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> decisionmaker. What about adverse externalities—smokedamage <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like? What about losses imposed on stockholdersby an <strong>in</strong>competent bus<strong>in</strong>ess management? What about <strong>the</strong> coststhat a government imposes on a population by taxation or <strong>in</strong>flation (or itscomm<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> resources, however f<strong>in</strong>anced)? <strong>Is</strong>n’t it notoriously true that agovernment <strong>of</strong>ficial need not personally bear all <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> his decisions?What about <strong>in</strong>voluntarily drafted soldiers? Even an ord<strong>in</strong>ary bus<strong>in</strong>ess decisionhas objective aspects <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong> resources devoted to <strong>the</strong>chosen activity are withdrawn or withheld from o<strong>the</strong>r activities.Of course <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>in</strong>curred <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se examples have subjective aspectsalso—<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ds or <strong>the</strong> perceptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> draftees <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> persons whowould have been consumers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> goods from whose production <strong>the</strong>resources <strong>in</strong> question are competed away. What is odd is <strong>the</strong> contentionthat no cost occurs except subjectively <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> decisionmakeralone.As for <strong>the</strong> fifth implication, it is true that cost cannot be measured—notmeasured precisely, that is, whe<strong>the</strong>r by <strong>the</strong> decisionmaker or someone else.But measurability itself is evidently what is at issue, not <strong>the</strong> admittedimprecision <strong>of</strong> measurement <strong>of</strong> cost, as <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r economic magnitudes.e money costs <strong>of</strong> produc<strong>in</strong>g a def<strong>in</strong>ite amount <strong>of</strong> some product, or <strong>the</strong>marg<strong>in</strong>al money cost <strong>of</strong> its production, can <strong>in</strong>deed be estimated. Estimates<strong>of</strong> money cost take <strong>in</strong>to account, <strong>in</strong> particular, <strong>the</strong> prices multipliedby <strong>the</strong>ir quantities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>puts required to produce specified marg<strong>in</strong>alamounts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good <strong>in</strong> question. True, cost account<strong>in</strong>g has no objective<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>fallible rules <strong>and</strong> must employ conventions. For this <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r reasons,estimates <strong>of</strong> money cost are just that—estimates. But <strong>the</strong>y are nottotally arbitrary; <strong>the</strong>y are not mean<strong>in</strong>gless.


44 Part I: EconomicsMoney costs <strong>of</strong> production, as well as <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>put prices that enter <strong>in</strong>toestimat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m, play a vital role <strong>in</strong> convey<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation to particularbus<strong>in</strong>ess decisionmakers about conditions <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sectors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy.Money costs <strong>and</strong> prices reflect—do not measure precisely, but reflect—<strong>the</strong>values <strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong> utilities attributed by consumers to <strong>the</strong> goods <strong>and</strong>services whose production is forgone to make <strong>the</strong> required <strong>in</strong>puts availableto <strong>the</strong> particular l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> production whose costs are <strong>in</strong> question. (Moneycosts <strong>and</strong> factor prices also reflect, as noted above, <strong>the</strong> preferences <strong>and</strong>attitudes <strong>of</strong> workers <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors.)It is <strong>the</strong>refore subversive to <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> a pricesystem to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that cost is entirely subjective, falls entirely on <strong>the</strong>decisionmaker, <strong>and</strong> cannot be felt by anyone else.Perhaps this risk <strong>of</strong> subversion is be<strong>in</strong>g run <strong>in</strong> a good cause. A healthyskepticism is <strong>in</strong> order about socialism, nationalization, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> imposition<strong>of</strong> cost rules on nationalized <strong>and</strong> private enterprises. However, we shouldbeware <strong>of</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to obta<strong>in</strong> substantive conclusions from preconceptionsabout method or about policy. Sound conclusions <strong>and</strong> policy judgments<strong>in</strong>cur discredit from association with questionable verbal maneuvers.Valid subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights jo<strong>in</strong> with <strong>the</strong> fact that general equilibriumnever actually prevails <strong>in</strong> recommend<strong>in</strong>g skepticism about policies thatwould unnecessarily impose imitation markets or <strong>the</strong> mere feign<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>market processes. e fact <strong>of</strong> disequilibrium prices does not, <strong>of</strong> course,recommend junk<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> market system <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g else. <strong>Market</strong>prices, although not precise <strong>in</strong>dicators <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> trade-<strong>of</strong>fs posed by reality,are at least under <strong>the</strong> pressures <strong>of</strong> supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> entrepreneurialalertness to become more nearly accurate measures.e recommended skepticism does have some application, however,with regard to compensation for seizures under em<strong>in</strong>ent doma<strong>in</strong>, damageawards <strong>in</strong> tort cases, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> case law. It also hassome application <strong>in</strong> cost-benefit studies. Personal rights, not such exercises,should <strong>of</strong> course dom<strong>in</strong>ate many policy decisions.Aga<strong>in</strong>, though, I want to warn aga<strong>in</strong>st overstatement. Admittedly,costs <strong>and</strong> benefits are largely subjective, market prices are at disequilibriumlevels, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r bases <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g estimates are <strong>in</strong>accurate also. Butwhat is to be done when some decision or o<strong>the</strong>r has to be made—abouta new airport, a subway system, a dam, or a proposed environmentalregulation? Does one simply ramble on about how imponderable everyth<strong>in</strong>gis, or does one try <strong>in</strong> good faith to quantify benefits <strong>and</strong> costs?Of course <strong>the</strong> estimates will be crude, even very crude, but perhaps <strong>the</strong>


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 45preponderance <strong>of</strong> benefits or costs will turn out great enough to be unmistakableanyway. In any case, expect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> advocates <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibledecisions to quantify <strong>the</strong>ir assertions <strong>and</strong> lay <strong>the</strong>m out for scrut<strong>in</strong>ywill impose a healthy discipl<strong>in</strong>e on <strong>the</strong> arguments made. It will weaken<strong>the</strong> relative <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> sheer poetry, oratory, demagogy, <strong>and</strong> politicalmaneuver<strong>in</strong>g.My last example <strong>of</strong> subjectivism exaggerated <strong>and</strong> abused is what evensome members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian School have identified as a “nihilism”about economic <strong>the</strong>ory. Nihilistic writ<strong>in</strong>gs stress <strong>the</strong> unknowability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>future, <strong>the</strong> dependence <strong>of</strong> market behavior on divergent <strong>and</strong> vague <strong>and</strong>ever-chang<strong>in</strong>g subjective expectations, <strong>the</strong> “kaleidic” nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economicworld, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> poor basis for any belief that market forces are tend<strong>in</strong>gto work toward ra<strong>the</strong>r than away from equilibrium (if, <strong>in</strong>deed, equilibriumhas any mean<strong>in</strong>g). Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se assertions are relevant enough<strong>in</strong> particular contexts, but ultrasubjectivists b<strong>and</strong>y <strong>the</strong>m sweep<strong>in</strong>gly aboutas if will<strong>in</strong>g to cast discredit not merely on attempts to foretell <strong>the</strong> futurebut even on scientific predictions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> if-this-<strong>the</strong>n-that type. It is hardto imag<strong>in</strong>e why an economist who thus wallows <strong>in</strong> unknowability cont<strong>in</strong>uesto represent himself as an economist at all. (One hunch: he may th<strong>in</strong>khe has an all-purpose methodological weapon for strik<strong>in</strong>g down whateverstr<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> analysis or policy argument he happens not to like. But<strong>the</strong>n his own analysis <strong>and</strong> arguments—if he has any—would be equallyvulnerable.)ere is no po<strong>in</strong>t try<strong>in</strong>g to conceal from knowledgable Austrian readerswhat economist I particularly have <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, so I’ll refer to <strong>the</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>of</strong> Ludwig Lachmann listed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> references (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g his articles<strong>in</strong> Dolan 1976 <strong>and</strong> Spadaro 1978), as well as Lachmann’s admiration<strong>of</strong> Shackle’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs on <strong>the</strong> imponderability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> future. Also seeO’Driscoll’s refresh<strong>in</strong>g criticism (<strong>in</strong> Spadaro 1978, esp. pp. 128–134) <strong>of</strong>Lachmann for practically repudiat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market’s coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>gprocesses <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> spontaneous order.Most recently, Lachmann has shown evident delight <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> phrase“dynamic subjectivism.” “[A]t least <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> Austrian doctr<strong>in</strong>e, subjectivismhas become progressively more dynamic” (1985, p. 2). “To Austrians,<strong>of</strong> all people, committed to radical subjectivism, <strong>the</strong> news <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>move from static to dynamic subjectivism should be welcome news” (1985,pp. 1–2). e word “committed” is reveal<strong>in</strong>g. Instead <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> scientific attitude,Lachmann evidently values commitment—commitment to a doctr<strong>in</strong>eor to a methodology. Recall<strong>in</strong>g Fritz Machlup’s essay on “Statics


46 Part I: Economics<strong>and</strong> Dynamics: Kaleidoscopic Words” (1959/1975), I wish Machlup werealive today to heap onto “dynamic subjectivism” <strong>the</strong> ridicule it deserves. As Gustav Cassel wrote <strong>in</strong> a book first published <strong>in</strong> English long ago, itwas an absurd waste <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual energy for economists still to be disput<strong>in</strong>gwhe<strong>the</strong>r prices were determ<strong>in</strong>ed by objective factors or subjectivefactors (1932/1967, p. 146). Referr<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong> particular, Irv<strong>in</strong>gFisher (1930/1970, p. 312) called it “a sc<strong>and</strong>al <strong>in</strong> economic science” that twoschools were still cross<strong>in</strong>g swords on <strong>the</strong> supposed issue. Prices, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>terest rates, are determ<strong>in</strong>ed by factors <strong>of</strong> both k<strong>in</strong>ds. As noted earlier,say<strong>in</strong>g so does not mean identify<strong>in</strong>g objective factors with <strong>the</strong> supply side<strong>and</strong> subjective factors with <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> markets, nor vice versa.Both sorts <strong>of</strong> factors operate on both sides.For a grasp <strong>of</strong> how subjective <strong>and</strong> objective factors thoroughly <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>e<strong>in</strong> a system <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>terdependence, a study <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> simplifiedgeneral-equilibrium equation system presented <strong>in</strong> Cassel’s (1932/1967)chapter 4 is well worth while. e reader should pay attention, amongo<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs, to <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> technical coefficients, ones <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>amounts <strong>of</strong> each <strong>in</strong>put used <strong>in</strong> produc<strong>in</strong>g a unit <strong>of</strong> each product. Casseldoes not need to suppose, <strong>of</strong> course, that <strong>the</strong>se coefficients are rigidlydeterm<strong>in</strong>ed solely by nature <strong>and</strong> technology. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, an elaboration<strong>of</strong> his system can take account <strong>of</strong> how many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se coefficients are<strong>the</strong>mselves variable <strong>and</strong> subject to choice <strong>in</strong> response to prices, which are<strong>the</strong>mselves determ<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> system <strong>of</strong> mutual <strong>in</strong>terdependence.Study <strong>of</strong> Cassel’s chapter (or similar expositions) should also disabuse<strong>the</strong> open-m<strong>in</strong>ded reader <strong>of</strong> any l<strong>in</strong>ger<strong>in</strong>g belief <strong>in</strong> unidirectional causality.Mutual determ<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> economic variables is a fact <strong>of</strong> reality; <strong>and</strong> noblanket prejudice aga<strong>in</strong>st general-equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, which does affordimportant <strong>in</strong>sights, should bl<strong>in</strong>d one to that fact.Of course, when one <strong>in</strong>vestigates <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> a specifiedchange—say <strong>in</strong> tastes, technology, taxes, or a fixed exchange rate—it isnot enough (nor, realistically, is it possible) to solve a general-equilibriumequation system with one or more parameters changed <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n compare<strong>the</strong> new <strong>and</strong> old solutions. An adequate analysis traces out, perhapseven sequentially, <strong>the</strong> reactions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> persons <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>and</strong> shows<strong>the</strong> reasonableness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>orized reactions from <strong>the</strong>ir own po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong>view. But <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g on such a causal analysis does not presuppose belief <strong>in</strong>


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 47monocausality. e specified disturbance does <strong>in</strong>deed imp<strong>in</strong>ge on a system<strong>of</strong> mutual determ<strong>in</strong>ation. Both <strong>the</strong> new <strong>and</strong> old constellations <strong>of</strong> economicactivities result from multidirectional <strong>in</strong>teractions <strong>of</strong> a great manysubjective <strong>and</strong> objective factors.Austrian economists have important messages to convey about subjectiveelements that, on all sides, pervade market behavior, signals, <strong>and</strong> outcomes.eir <strong>in</strong>sights have important implications for policy. It is a shameto impede communication by remarks about purely subjective value <strong>the</strong>ory,pure time-preference <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> alleged fallacy <strong>of</strong> multidirectionalcausality.Austrians cannot really mean what such remarks, taken literally, convey.ey mislead <strong>and</strong> repel people outside <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner circle. e ma<strong>in</strong>goal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrians is presumably not to recite slogans that re<strong>in</strong>forcecozy feel<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> camaraderie among members <strong>of</strong> an elite. Instead, <strong>the</strong>irgoal, shared with o<strong>the</strong>r economists who wish well for mank<strong>in</strong>d, is presumablyto ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> communicate underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> economic (<strong>and</strong> political)processes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world as it is, has been, <strong>and</strong> potentially could be. eywant to extend <strong>and</strong> communicate such knowledge so as to <strong>in</strong>crease whateverchance <strong>the</strong>re may be that man’s deepest values will ultimately prevail.Respect for <strong>the</strong> straightforward mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> words will aid <strong>in</strong> thatendeavor.Besides shunn<strong>in</strong>g deceptive slogans, Austrian economists should beware<strong>of</strong> surround<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir doctr<strong>in</strong>es with a fog <strong>of</strong> methodological preachments,preachments suggestive, moreover, <strong>of</strong> pervasive snip<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> sourgrapes (as, for example, about <strong>the</strong> elegant formal <strong>the</strong>ory that some ma<strong>in</strong>streameconomists rightly or wrongly delight <strong>in</strong>). Above all, Austriansshould avoid discredit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> sound core <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir doctr<strong>in</strong>e by contam<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>git with bits <strong>of</strong> downright <strong>and</strong> readily exposable error (or what comesacross as error on any straightforward read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> words used). Austrianshave positive contributions to make <strong>and</strong> should make <strong>the</strong>m.Böhm-Bawerk, Eugen von. Capital <strong>and</strong> Interest. 1884, 1889, 1909–1912. Translatedby G.D. Huncke <strong>and</strong> H.F. Sennholz. 3 vols. South Holl<strong>and</strong>, Ill.: LibertarianPress, 1959.Buchanan, James M. Cost <strong>and</strong> Choice. Chicago: Markham, 1969.. Public Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> Public Debt. 1958. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1999.


48 Part I: EconomicsBuchanan, James M., <strong>and</strong> G.F. irlby, eds. L.S.E. <strong>Essays</strong> on Cost. 1973. NewYork: New York University Press, 1981.Cassel, Gustav. e Nature <strong>and</strong> Necessity <strong>of</strong> Interest. 1903. New York: Kelley, 1971.. e eory <strong>of</strong> Social <strong>Economy</strong>. 1932. Translated by S.L. Barron. New York:Kelley, 1967.Committee for Economic Development. Achiev<strong>in</strong>g Energy Independence. NewYork: CED, 1974.Dolan, Edw<strong>in</strong> G., ed. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Modern Austrian Economics. Kansas City,Kans.: Sheed <strong>and</strong> Ward, 1976.Fellner, William. Towards a Reconstruction <strong>of</strong> Macroeconomics. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.:American Enterprise Institute, 1976.Fetter, Frank A. Capital, Interest, <strong>and</strong> Rent. Edited with an <strong>in</strong>troduction by MurrayN. Rothbard. Kansas City, Kans.: Sheed Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, 1977.Fisher, Irv<strong>in</strong>g. e eory <strong>of</strong> Interest. 1930. New York: Kelley, 1970.Freeman, S. David. Energy: e New Era. New York: Walker, 1974.Garrison, Roger. “Wait<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Vienna.” In Time, Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, <strong>and</strong> Disequilibrium,edited by Mario J. Rizzo, 215–226. Lex<strong>in</strong>gton, Mass.: Lex<strong>in</strong>gton Books, 1979.George, Henry. e Science <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>. 1898. New York: SchalkenbachFoundation, 1941.Hayek, Friedrich A. “e Use <strong>of</strong> Knowledge <strong>in</strong> Society.” American EconomicReview 35 (September 1945): 519–530.. e Counter-Revolution <strong>of</strong> Science. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1952.. e Constitution <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1960.Hirshleifer, Jack. Investment, Interest, <strong>and</strong> Capital. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: PrenticeHall, 1970.Kirzner, <strong>Is</strong>rael M. “Pure Time-Preference eory: A Post Script to <strong>the</strong> ‘Gr<strong>and</strong>Debate’.” New York: New York University, manuscript, undated but early1980s.Lachmann, Ludwig M. Capital, Expectations, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> Process. Edited withan <strong>in</strong>troduction by Walter E. Gr<strong>in</strong>der. Kansas City, Kans.: Sheed Andrews<strong>and</strong> McMeel, 1977.


Chapter : Why Subjectivism? 49. Review <strong>of</strong> e Economics <strong>of</strong> Time <strong>and</strong> Ignorance, by Gerald P. O’Driscoll<strong>and</strong> Mario J. Rizzo. <strong>Market</strong> Process 3 (Fall 1985): 1–4, 17–18.Littlechild, Stephen C. e Fallacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Mixed <strong>Economy</strong>. San Francisco: CatoInstitute, 1979.Machlup, Fritz. “Statistics <strong>and</strong> Dynamics: Kaleidoscopic Words.” 1959. In <strong>Essays</strong><strong>in</strong> Economic Semantics, 9–42. New York: New York University Press, 1975.Marshall, Alfred. Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> Economics. 1920. 8 ed. London: Macmillan, 1947.Menger, Carl. Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> Economics. 1871. Translated by J. D<strong>in</strong>gwall <strong>and</strong> B.F.Hoselitz. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1950.Miller, James C., III, ed. Why <strong>the</strong> Draft? e Case for a Volunteer Army. Baltimore:Pengu<strong>in</strong>, 1968.Mises, Ludwig von. Human Action. 1949. 2ⁿ ed. New Haven, Conn.: Yale UniversityPress, 1963.. e eory <strong>of</strong> Money <strong>and</strong> Credit. 1953. Translated by H.E. Batson. Indianapolis:Liberty Classics, 1981.Mitchell, Edward J., ed. Dialogue on World Oil. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.: AmericanEnterprise Institute, 1974.Nozick, Robert. “On Austrian Methodology.” Syn<strong>the</strong>se 36 (November 1977):353–392.Rothbard, Murray N. Man, <strong>Economy</strong>, <strong>and</strong> State. 2 vols. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. VanNostr<strong>and</strong>, 1962.. e Ethics <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Atlantic Highl<strong>and</strong>s, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1982.Seldon, James R. “e Relevance <strong>of</strong> Subjective Costs: Comment.” Sou<strong>the</strong>rn EconomicJournal 48 ( July 1981): 216–221.Shackle, G.L.S. Epistemics <strong>and</strong> Economics. New York: Cambridge UniversityPress, 1972.Sh<strong>and</strong>, Alex<strong>and</strong>er H. e Capitalist Alternative: An Introduction to Neo-AustrianEconomics. New York: New York University Press, 1984.Spadaro, Louis M., ed. New Directions <strong>in</strong> Austrian Economics. Kansas City, Kans.:Sheed Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, 1978.Taylor, omas C. e Fundamentals <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics. San Francisco: CatoInstitute, 1980.


50 Part I: EconomicsVaughn, Karen I. “Does It Matter at Costs Are Subjective?” Sou<strong>the</strong>rn EconomicJournal 46 ( January 1980): 702–715.. “e Relevance <strong>of</strong> Subjective Costs: Reply.” Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Economic Journal48 ( July 1981): 222–226.V<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, Rutledge. On Apprais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Performance <strong>of</strong> an Economic System. NewYork: Cambridge University Press, 1985.Waismann, Friedrich. “Verifiability.” In Logic <strong>and</strong> Language, Anchor ed., editedby Antony Flew, 122–151. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1965.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “Balance-<strong>of</strong>-Payments Cure Worse than <strong>the</strong> Disease.” Commercial<strong>and</strong> F<strong>in</strong>ancial Chronicle 202, no. 2 (September 1965): 3, 29.. “Toward Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g Some Paradoxes <strong>in</strong> Capital eory.” EconomicInquiry 14 (September 1976): 313–346.. “Pareto Optimality <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Libertarian Studies 2,no. 3 (1978): 199–216.


Henry George <strong>and</strong> AustrianEconomics *Henry George has been widely pigeonholed <strong>and</strong> dismissed as a s<strong>in</strong>gletaxer. Actually, he was a pr<strong>of</strong>ound <strong>and</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al economist. He <strong>in</strong>dependentlyarrived at several <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most characteristic <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> AustrianSchool, which is enjoy<strong>in</strong>g a revival nowadays. Yet George scorned <strong>the</strong>Austrians <strong>of</strong> his time, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir present-day successors show scant appreciation<strong>of</strong> his work. An apparent lapse <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual communication callsfor repair. e Austrian School traces to <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> Carl Menger, one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> leaders<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al-utility revolution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1870s, <strong>and</strong> his fellow countrymen,Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk <strong>and</strong> Friedrich von Wieser. Notable contributors<strong>of</strong> a later generation <strong>in</strong>clude Ludwig von Mises, F.A. Hayek, <strong>and</strong>Ludwig Lachmann, each <strong>of</strong> whom worked first <strong>in</strong> Austria or Germany<strong>and</strong> later <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States, <strong>and</strong> also <strong>the</strong> American Frank A. Fetter. Ina still later generation, em<strong>in</strong>ent Austrians—<strong>the</strong> word no longer carriesany implications about nationality or mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue—<strong>in</strong>clude MurrayRothbard <strong>and</strong> <strong>Is</strong>rael Kirzner. Some em<strong>in</strong>ent young members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> schoolare Dom<strong>in</strong>ick Armentano, Gerald O’Driscoll, Mario Rizzo, Steven Littlechild,<strong>and</strong> Karen Vaughn; <strong>and</strong> apologies are <strong>in</strong> order for not extend<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> list fur<strong>the</strong>r. *From History <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> 16 (Summer 1984): 157–174. is article derives froma talk given at St. John’s University, Jamaica, New York, on 29 March 1982. I am <strong>in</strong>debtedto my hosts <strong>the</strong>re, <strong>and</strong> particularly to Pr<strong>of</strong>essor M. Northrup Buechner, for suggestions<strong>and</strong> encouragement. S<strong>in</strong>ce this article chiefly concerns Henry George, I am assum<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> reader hasenough acqua<strong>in</strong>tance with contemporary Austrian economics to make detailed citationsunnecessary. In addition to <strong>the</strong> specifically cited works <strong>of</strong> Menger, Böhm-Bawerk, Mises,51


52 Part I: EconomicsWhat follows is an impression <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> lead<strong>in</strong>g characteristics <strong>of</strong> Austrianeconomics.(i) Austrians are concerned with <strong>the</strong> big picture—with how a wholeeconomic system functions. ey avoid tunnel vision; <strong>the</strong>y do not focustoo narrowly on <strong>the</strong> adm<strong>in</strong>istration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual bus<strong>in</strong>ess firm <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual household. ey <strong>in</strong>vestigate how <strong>the</strong> specialized activities<strong>of</strong> millions <strong>of</strong> persons, who are mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir decisions <strong>in</strong> a decentralizedmanner, can be coord<strong>in</strong>ated. ese diverse activities are <strong>in</strong>terdependent;yet no particular agency takes charge <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>and</strong> nonewould be competent to do so. e relevant knowledge—about resources,technology, human wants, <strong>and</strong> market conditions—is <strong>in</strong>evitably fragmentedamong millions, even billions, <strong>of</strong> separate human m<strong>in</strong>ds.(ii) Austrians take <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> how alternative sets <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions canfunction. Mises <strong>in</strong> particular, <strong>and</strong> later Hayek, demonstrated <strong>the</strong> impossibility<strong>of</strong> economic calculation—schedul<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> economic activities <strong>in</strong>accordance with accurate assessment <strong>of</strong> values <strong>and</strong> costs—under socialism.Centralized mobilization <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> activities is admittedlyconceivable. In a Swiss Family Rob<strong>in</strong>son sett<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> head <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>family could survey <strong>the</strong> available resources <strong>and</strong> technology <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> capabilities<strong>and</strong> needs <strong>and</strong> wants <strong>of</strong> family members <strong>and</strong> could sensibly decide on<strong>and</strong> monitor production <strong>and</strong> consumption <strong>in</strong> some detail. In a large, moderneconomy, however, sensible central direction is not possible. Austriansare alert to possibilities <strong>of</strong> unplanned order <strong>and</strong> to what Hayek (1967)has called “<strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> human action but not <strong>of</strong> human design.” ey<strong>in</strong>vestigate how <strong>the</strong> market <strong>and</strong> prices function as a vast communicationssystem <strong>and</strong> computer, transmitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives <strong>and</strong> soputt<strong>in</strong>g to use scattered knowledge that would o<strong>the</strong>rwise necessarily go towaste.(iii) Not only do Austrians appreciate <strong>the</strong> implications <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>complete,imperfect, <strong>and</strong> scattered knowledge; <strong>the</strong>y also appreciate <strong>the</strong> implications<strong>of</strong> change, uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, <strong>and</strong> unpredictability <strong>in</strong> human affairs. ey take<strong>the</strong>se facts <strong>of</strong> reality seriously not only <strong>in</strong> confront<strong>in</strong>g supposed <strong>the</strong>oretical<strong>and</strong> econometric models <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy but also <strong>in</strong> assess<strong>in</strong>g alternativesets <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> policy.(iv) In connection with <strong>the</strong> implications <strong>of</strong> fragmented knowledge,change, <strong>and</strong> unpredictability, Austrians pay attention to disequilibrium,Hayek, <strong>and</strong> Rothbard, he might well consult, for orientation, books written or edited byDolan, Moss, O’Driscoll, <strong>and</strong> Spadaro; see <strong>the</strong> bibliography.


Chapter : Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics 53process, <strong>and</strong> entrepreneurship. While not totally scornful <strong>of</strong> elaborateanalysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> properties <strong>of</strong> imag<strong>in</strong>ary equilibrium states <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> comparative-staticanalysis, <strong>the</strong>y recognize how <strong>in</strong>complete a contribution suchanalyses can make to <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> how economic systems function.ey do not suppose, for example, that cost curves <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>curves are somehow “given” to bus<strong>in</strong>ess decisionmakers. On <strong>the</strong> contrary,one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> services <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> competitive process is to press for discovery <strong>of</strong>ways to get <strong>the</strong> costs curves down—if one adopts such term<strong>in</strong>ology at all.Austrians tend to accept <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> X-efficiency <strong>and</strong> to appreciate <strong>the</strong>role <strong>of</strong> competition <strong>in</strong> promot<strong>in</strong>g it. Far from be<strong>in</strong>g an ideal state <strong>of</strong> affairswith which <strong>the</strong> real world is to be compared—unfavorably—competitionis seen as a process. Entrepreneurs play key roles <strong>in</strong> that process; <strong>the</strong>y aremen <strong>and</strong> women alert to opportunities for advantageously undertak<strong>in</strong>gnew activities or adopt<strong>in</strong>g new methods.(v) As already implied, Austrians have certa<strong>in</strong> methodological predilections.ey are unhappy with <strong>the</strong> tacit view <strong>of</strong> economic activityas <strong>the</strong> resultant <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terplay among objective conditions <strong>and</strong> impersonalforces. ey are unhappy with <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> aggregates <strong>and</strong>averages (real GNP, <strong>the</strong> price level, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like). ey take pa<strong>in</strong>s totrace <strong>the</strong>ir analyses back to <strong>the</strong> perceptions, decisions, <strong>and</strong> actions <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual persons: methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism is a key aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>irapproach. Austrians recognize <strong>in</strong>trospection as one legitimate source <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> facts underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g economic <strong>the</strong>ory. ey emphasize subjectivism:not only do personal tastes help determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> economic activity,but even <strong>the</strong> objective facts <strong>of</strong> resources <strong>and</strong> technology operateonly as <strong>the</strong>y are filtered through <strong>the</strong> perceptions <strong>and</strong> evaluations <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals.Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as Austrians recognize macroeconomics as a legitimatetopic at all, <strong>the</strong>y are concerned to provide it with microeconomic underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs.(vi) Although Austrians like to th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir economics as value-free<strong>and</strong> although some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, at least, emphasize that it is not logicallyl<strong>in</strong>ked with any particular policy position, Austrian <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to positiveeconomics, coupled with plausible value judgments <strong>of</strong> a humanitarian<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualistic nature, undeniably do tend toward a particular policyposition—non-<strong>in</strong>terventionistic, laissez-faire, libertarian. More aboutthis later. See, <strong>in</strong> particular, Leibenste<strong>in</strong> 1976. (Leibenste<strong>in</strong> himself, however, is not usuallyconsidered an Austrian.)


54 Part I: Economics’ I shall try to show Henry George’s aff<strong>in</strong>ities with <strong>the</strong> Austrians by cit<strong>in</strong>gpassages from his writ<strong>in</strong>gs. e demonstration proceeds from partialagreement on <strong>the</strong>oretical po<strong>in</strong>ts to agreement on major questions. First,however, we should note George’s misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> even scornfor <strong>the</strong> Austrians <strong>of</strong> his time, suggest<strong>in</strong>g that his Austrian-like <strong>in</strong>sightswere orig<strong>in</strong>al with him. George did not underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al revolution<strong>in</strong> value <strong>the</strong>ory that was gett<strong>in</strong>g under way <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> last decades <strong>of</strong> hislife. He regretted that “<strong>the</strong> classical school <strong>of</strong> political economy” seemedto have been ab<strong>and</strong>oned:What has succeeded is usually denom<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>the</strong> Austrian School, for noo<strong>the</strong>r reason that I can discover than that “far k<strong>in</strong>d have long horns.” If ithas any pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, I have been utterly unable to f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>m. e <strong>in</strong>quireris usually referred to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>comprehensible works <strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor AlfredMarshall <strong>of</strong> Cambridge, Engl<strong>and</strong> ... ; to <strong>the</strong> ponderous works <strong>of</strong> EugenV. Böhm-Bawerk, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>, first <strong>in</strong> Innsbruck <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>n at Vienna ... ; or to a lot <strong>of</strong> German works written by men he neverheard <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> whose names he cannot even pronounce.is pseudoscience gets its name from a foreign language, <strong>and</strong> uses forits terms words adapted from <strong>the</strong> German—words that have no place<strong>and</strong> no mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> an English work. It is, <strong>in</strong>deed, admirably calculatedto serve <strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> those powerful <strong>in</strong>terests dom<strong>in</strong>ant <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> colleges... that must fear a simple <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>able political economy, <strong>and</strong>who vaguely wish to have <strong>the</strong> poor boys who are subjected to it by <strong>the</strong>irpr<strong>of</strong>essors rendered <strong>in</strong>capable <strong>of</strong> thought on economic subjects. (SPE,p. 208) Later, as quoted below, George compla<strong>in</strong>s about <strong>the</strong> “grotesque confusions”<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian School. One referee hypo<strong>the</strong>sizes that George <strong>and</strong> some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrians, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Mises,were deriv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>spiration <strong>in</strong> common from French liberals such as Bastiat <strong>and</strong> Dunoyer.Investigat<strong>in</strong>g that hypo<strong>the</strong>sis must be left for ano<strong>the</strong>r occasion—or for ano<strong>the</strong>r researcher. Citations are made to George’s works by abbreviated titles. e abbreviations, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>same order as <strong>the</strong> titles <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bibliography, are P&P, SP, PFT, PPH, <strong>and</strong> SPE.Referr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> particular to confusion over <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> wealth, George compla<strong>in</strong>sthat “<strong>the</strong> ‘economic revolution’ which has <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> meanwhile displaced from <strong>the</strong>ir chairs<strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>n orthodox political economy <strong>in</strong> order to give place to so-called‘Austrians,’ or similar pr<strong>of</strong>essors <strong>of</strong> ‘economics,’ ha[s] only made confusion worse confounded”(SPE, p. 121).


Chapter : Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics 55e Austrians, for <strong>the</strong>ir part, have not adequately appreciated George.Böhm-Bawerk criticized <strong>the</strong> natural-fructification <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest presented<strong>in</strong> Progress <strong>and</strong> Poverty, apparently unaware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> advance (discussedbelow) that George achieved <strong>in</strong> e Science <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>(Böhm-Bawerk 1884/1959, vol. 1: pp. 336–339, 366, 474). Among presentdayAustrians, Murray Rothbard shows <strong>the</strong> greatest acqua<strong>in</strong>tance withGeorge’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs, or some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. (For example, he recognizes Georgeas a free trader <strong>and</strong> applauds his “excellent discussion” <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctionbetween patents <strong>and</strong> copyrights.) Yet Rothbard is mostly concerned withwhat he considers <strong>the</strong> unsatisfactory moral <strong>and</strong> economic arguments used<strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle tax. With <strong>the</strong> Austrians, as with o<strong>the</strong>r presentdayeconomists, George’s reputation does seem to suffer from his be<strong>in</strong>gpigeonholed as a propag<strong>and</strong>ist for dubious reforms. : , , George held a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> labor-<strong>in</strong>-exchange or exertion-saved <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong>value, follow<strong>in</strong>g Adam Smith, but not a Marxian labor-cost <strong>the</strong>ory (SPE,pp. 212–256, 503). Still, he had some Austrian-like subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights:<strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> any time <strong>and</strong> place is <strong>the</strong> largest amount <strong>of</strong> exertionthat any one will render <strong>in</strong> exchange for it; or to make <strong>the</strong> estimate from<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side, ... it is <strong>the</strong> smallest amount <strong>of</strong> exertion for which any onewill part with it <strong>in</strong> exchange.Value is thus an expression which, when used <strong>in</strong> its proper economicsense <strong>of</strong> value <strong>in</strong> exchange, has no direct relation to any <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic quality<strong>of</strong> external th<strong>in</strong>gs, but only to man’s desires. Its essential element issubjective, not objective; that is to say, ly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d or will <strong>of</strong> man,<strong>and</strong> not ly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs external to <strong>the</strong> human will or m<strong>in</strong>d.ere is no material test for value. Whe<strong>the</strong>r a th<strong>in</strong>g is valuable or notvaluable, or what may be <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>of</strong> its value, we cannot really tell byits size or shape or color or smell, or any o<strong>the</strong>r material quality, exceptso far as such <strong>in</strong>vestigations may enable us to <strong>in</strong>fer how o<strong>the</strong>r men mayregard <strong>the</strong>m....Now this fact that <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> value spr<strong>in</strong>gs from a feel<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> man,<strong>and</strong> has not at bottom any relation to <strong>the</strong> external world—a fact that Rothbard 1962, vol. 1: pp. 148–149, 152, 410, 442; vol. 2: pp. 512–513, 813–814, 888, 915,930, 933, 944–945; Rothbard 1970, pp. 37, 57, 91–100, 200, 201, 204, 209, 210; Rothbard1973, pp. 333–335.


56 Part I: Economicshas been much ignored <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> expositions <strong>of</strong> acceptedeconomists—is what lies at <strong>the</strong> bottom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> grotesque confusionswhich, under <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian school <strong>of</strong> political economy,have with<strong>in</strong> recent years so easily captured <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> pretty muchall <strong>the</strong> universities <strong>and</strong> colleges <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> English-speak<strong>in</strong>g world. (SPE,pp. 251–252)George goes on to say that <strong>the</strong> Austrians have drawn wrong <strong>in</strong>ferencesfrom<strong>the</strong> truth that value is not a quality <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs but an affectation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>human m<strong>in</strong>d toward th<strong>in</strong>gs....What is subjective is <strong>in</strong> itself <strong>in</strong>communicable. A feel<strong>in</strong>g so long as itrema<strong>in</strong>s merely a feel<strong>in</strong>g can be known only to <strong>and</strong> can be measuredonly by him who feels it. It must come out <strong>in</strong> some way <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> objectivethrough action before any one else can appreciate or <strong>in</strong> any way measureit....... what value determ<strong>in</strong>es is not how much a th<strong>in</strong>g is desired, but howmuch any one is will<strong>in</strong>g to give for it; not desire <strong>in</strong> itself, but ... <strong>the</strong> desireto possess, accompanied by <strong>the</strong> ability <strong>and</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness to give <strong>in</strong> return.us it is that <strong>the</strong>re is no measure <strong>of</strong> value among men save competitionor <strong>the</strong> jiggl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market, a matter that might be worth <strong>the</strong> consideration<strong>of</strong> those amiable reformers who so lightly propose to abolishcompetition.It is never <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> labor that has been exerted <strong>in</strong> br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g a th<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>to be<strong>in</strong>g that determ<strong>in</strong>es its value, but always <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> labor thatwill be rendered <strong>in</strong> exchange for it. (SPE, pp. 252–253)Actually, George <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrians were not as far apart as he thoughtwhen alleg<strong>in</strong>g “grotesque confusions.” Admittedly, though, some presentdayAustrians do <strong>in</strong>vite misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g by <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g that value <strong>in</strong> general,as well as <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>in</strong> particular, is entirely a subjective phenomenon,<strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g determ<strong>in</strong>ed—as <strong>of</strong> course it is—by <strong>in</strong>teractionbetween objective reality <strong>and</strong> subjective perceptions <strong>and</strong> appraisals.e valid subjective element <strong>in</strong> George’s doctr<strong>in</strong>e also appears <strong>in</strong> hisrecognition that wealth can be produced not only () by physically shap<strong>in</strong>gth<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> () by grow<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs but also () by exchang<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs:this third mode <strong>of</strong> production consists <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> utilization <strong>of</strong> a power orpr<strong>in</strong>ciple or tendency manifested only <strong>in</strong> man, <strong>and</strong> belong<strong>in</strong>g to him byvirtue <strong>of</strong> his peculiar gift <strong>of</strong> reason....


Chapter : Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics 57... [I]t is by <strong>and</strong> through his disposition <strong>and</strong> power to exchange, <strong>in</strong> whichman essentially differs from all o<strong>the</strong>r animals, that human advance goeson.... [I]n itself exchange br<strong>in</strong>gs about a perceptible <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sum<strong>of</strong> wealth.... Each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two parties to an exchange aims to get, <strong>and</strong>as a rule does get, someth<strong>in</strong>g that is more valuable to him than wha<strong>the</strong> gives—that is to say, that represents to him a greater power <strong>of</strong> laborto satisfy desire. us <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> transaction an actual <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> wealth, an actual production <strong>of</strong> wealth.... Each party to <strong>the</strong>exchange gets <strong>in</strong> return for what costs it comparatively little labor whatwould cost it a great deal <strong>of</strong> labor to get by ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r modes <strong>of</strong>production. Each ga<strong>in</strong>s by <strong>the</strong> act.... [T]he jo<strong>in</strong>t wealth <strong>of</strong> both parties,<strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wealth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world, is by <strong>the</strong> exchange itself <strong>in</strong>creased.(SPE, pp. 331–332)George had some glimmer<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>alist <strong>and</strong> Austrian idea<strong>of</strong> imputation: <strong>the</strong> values <strong>and</strong> remunerations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> factors <strong>of</strong> productionare imputed to <strong>the</strong>m accord<strong>in</strong>g to what <strong>the</strong>y contribute to produc<strong>in</strong>g outputsvalued by consumers. Labor, George expla<strong>in</strong>ed, does not transmitvalue <strong>in</strong>to whatever it is applied to. Instead, labor derives its wages fromits productive contribution <strong>and</strong> from <strong>the</strong> value that consumers attribute to<strong>the</strong> output produced. is <strong>in</strong>sight refuted <strong>the</strong> wages-fund doctr<strong>in</strong>e (P&P,pp. 23, 50–70). Even labor employed on a project <strong>of</strong> long duration is effectivelyderiv<strong>in</strong>g its wages from <strong>the</strong> project’s growth <strong>in</strong> value as it comesgradually closer to completion.Some authorities credit George with contribut<strong>in</strong>g to development <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al-productivity <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> functional <strong>in</strong>come distribution. EvenJohn Bates Clark recognized his contribution:It was <strong>the</strong> claim advanced by Mr. Henry George, that wages are fixedby <strong>the</strong> product which a man can create by till<strong>in</strong>g rentless l<strong>and</strong>, that firstled me to seek a method by which <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> labor everywhere maybe disentangled from <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> cooperat<strong>in</strong>g agents <strong>and</strong> separatelyidentified; <strong>and</strong> it was this quest which led to <strong>the</strong> atta<strong>in</strong>ment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> lawthat is here presented, accord<strong>in</strong>g to which <strong>the</strong> wages <strong>of</strong> all labor tend,under perfectly free competition, to equal <strong>the</strong> product that is separatelyattributable to <strong>the</strong> labor. e product <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “f<strong>in</strong>al unit” <strong>of</strong> labor is <strong>the</strong>same as that <strong>of</strong> every unit, separately considered; <strong>and</strong> if normal tendenciescould work <strong>in</strong> perfection, it would be true not only <strong>of</strong> each unit, but1979. See Charles Collier, pp. 223–226, <strong>and</strong> Aaron Fuller, pp. 298–300, both <strong>in</strong> Andelson


58 Part I: Economics<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g force as a whole, that its product <strong>and</strong> its pay are identical.(1899/1908, p. viii)George did not see how his marg<strong>in</strong>al-productivity <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wages<strong>of</strong> labor applied <strong>in</strong> a similar way to all factor remunerations (Collier <strong>in</strong>Andelson 1979, p. 228). Nei<strong>the</strong>r did <strong>the</strong> early Austrians; it was left to Wicksteedto make that contribution <strong>in</strong> 1894.Regard<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>and</strong> rent, George was avowedly a follower <strong>of</strong> Ricardo (P&P,pp. 165–172). His conceptions <strong>of</strong> capital <strong>and</strong> its productivity were <strong>in</strong>complete.He had a fructification <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest, center<strong>in</strong>g around a supposed“reproductive or vital force <strong>of</strong> nature,” illustrated by <strong>the</strong> growth <strong>of</strong>crops, <strong>the</strong> reproduction <strong>of</strong> animals, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> matur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> w<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> storage(P&P, esp. pp. 179–182).He did share <strong>in</strong>sights with <strong>the</strong> Austrians, however, on <strong>the</strong> vital role <strong>of</strong>time <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> productive process. He devotes a whole chapter <strong>of</strong> SPE to thistopic:if I go to a builder <strong>and</strong> say to him, “In what time <strong>and</strong> at what price will youbuild me such <strong>and</strong> such a house?” he would, after th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g, name a time,<strong>and</strong> a price based on it. is specification <strong>of</strong> time would be essential....is I would soon f<strong>in</strong>d if, not quarrel<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> price, I ask him largelyto lessen <strong>the</strong> time ... I might get <strong>the</strong> builder somewhat to lessen <strong>the</strong>time ... ; but only by greatly <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> price, until f<strong>in</strong>ally a po<strong>in</strong>twould be reached where he would not consent to build <strong>the</strong> house <strong>in</strong> lesstime no matter at what price. He would say [that <strong>the</strong> house just couldnot be built any faster]....e importance ... <strong>of</strong> this pr<strong>in</strong>ciple that all production <strong>of</strong> wealth requirestime as well as labor we shall see later on; but <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple that time is anecessary element <strong>in</strong> all production we must take <strong>in</strong>to account from <strong>the</strong>very first. (SPE, pp. 369–370)e implication, which practically cries out to be made explicit, is thatoutput is not even ultimately attributable to labor (<strong>and</strong> l<strong>and</strong>) alone; <strong>the</strong>ty<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>of</strong> wealth over time is also necessary. S<strong>in</strong>ce this service is bothproductive <strong>and</strong> scarce—s<strong>in</strong>ce it is dem<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> is limited <strong>in</strong> supply—onecan hardly expect it to be free. In short, George was on <strong>the</strong> right track <strong>in</strong>capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory; but his achievement was <strong>in</strong>complete.George <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrians shared <strong>in</strong>sights even on such relatively specifictopics as money <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> analogy that money <strong>and</strong> language bear to each


Chapter : Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics 59o<strong>the</strong>r. ey were not simply agree<strong>in</strong>g with everyone else that both areuseful social <strong>in</strong>stitutions. ey recognized both, <strong>in</strong> Hayek’s words, as“results <strong>of</strong> human action but not <strong>of</strong> human design.” (at <strong>in</strong>sight maybe familiar nowadays, but it was not so when George <strong>and</strong> Menger <strong>and</strong>even when Hayek were develop<strong>in</strong>g it.) Instead <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g deliberately<strong>in</strong>vented <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stituted, money evolved spontaneously. George expla<strong>in</strong>sthat it evolved from <strong>the</strong> most readily exchangeable commodities, which<strong>in</strong>dividuals employed <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>direct barter because do<strong>in</strong>g so afforded <strong>the</strong>meconomies <strong>in</strong> conduct<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir transactions. e medium <strong>of</strong> exchangenaturally drifted <strong>in</strong>to be<strong>in</strong>g also used as <strong>the</strong> measure <strong>of</strong> value or unit <strong>of</strong>account.George anticipated <strong>the</strong> analogy more recently developed by Hayek<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs:While <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> money is almost as universal as <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> languages,<strong>and</strong> it everywhere follows general laws as does <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> languages, yetas we f<strong>in</strong>d language differ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> time <strong>and</strong> place, so do we f<strong>in</strong>d moneydiffer<strong>in</strong>g. In fact, as we shall see, money is <strong>in</strong> one <strong>of</strong> its functions a k<strong>in</strong>d<strong>of</strong> language—<strong>the</strong> language <strong>of</strong> value. (SPE, p. 494)George anticipated, <strong>in</strong> at least a rudimentary way, <strong>the</strong> cash-balanceapproach to monetary <strong>the</strong>ory later developed <strong>in</strong>dependently by Mises(1912/1981) <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. e dem<strong>and</strong> for cash balances is accounted for by<strong>the</strong> services that <strong>the</strong>y render to <strong>the</strong>ir holders (George presents examples <strong>in</strong>SPE, pp. 484–487). e development <strong>of</strong> credit promotes economics <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>hold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> transfer <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> actual medium <strong>of</strong> exchange. “Money’s mostimportant use today is as a measure <strong>of</strong> value.” , , So far this study has reviewed po<strong>in</strong>ts on which George shared or anticipatedAustrian <strong>in</strong>sights only <strong>in</strong>completely. Now it turns to some majorpo<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> agreement. e quotation is taken from a subhead<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> SPE, p. 504. e <strong>in</strong>sight expressed<strong>the</strong>re br<strong>in</strong>gs to m<strong>in</strong>d present-day proposals for achiev<strong>in</strong>g monetary reform <strong>and</strong> macroeconomicstability by def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a stable measure <strong>of</strong> value dist<strong>in</strong>ct from <strong>the</strong> medium <strong>of</strong>exchange, with <strong>the</strong> choice <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> supply <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter be<strong>in</strong>g left to unregulated privateenterprise. Describ<strong>in</strong>g such proposals, however, would carry us too far from our presenttopic.


60 Part I: EconomicsHe <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrians agree that a central task <strong>of</strong> economics is toexpla<strong>in</strong> how specialized human activities may be coord<strong>in</strong>ated withoutdeliberate direction. First he dist<strong>in</strong>guishes two k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> cooperation, each<strong>of</strong> which <strong>in</strong>creases productive power. One k<strong>in</strong>d is <strong>the</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong>effort, illustrated by men jo<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g forces to remove a rock or lift a log tooheavy for any one to move alone. e o<strong>the</strong>r is <strong>the</strong> separation <strong>of</strong> effort—<strong>the</strong>division <strong>of</strong> labor, specialization. Next George dist<strong>in</strong>guishes two ways <strong>of</strong>arrang<strong>in</strong>g cooperation itself. e first is conscious direction by a controll<strong>in</strong>gwill, illustrated (ideally) by <strong>the</strong> deployment <strong>of</strong> an army.e second way, achiev<strong>in</strong>g “spontaneous or unconscious cooperation,”draws George’s chief attention. One example, rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> Bastiat’sessay, “Natural <strong>and</strong> artificial social order” (1850/1964, pp. 1–19), ise provid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a great city with all <strong>the</strong> manifold th<strong>in</strong>gs which are constantlyneeded by its <strong>in</strong>habitants.... is k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> cooperation is far wider,far f<strong>in</strong>er, far more strongly <strong>and</strong> delicately organized, than <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong>cooperation <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> movements <strong>of</strong> an army, yet it is broughtabout not by subord<strong>in</strong>ation to <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> one conscious will, whichknows <strong>the</strong> general result at which it aims; but by <strong>the</strong> correlation <strong>of</strong> actionsorig<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> many <strong>in</strong>dependent wills, each aim<strong>in</strong>g at its own small purposewithout care for or thought <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> general result. (SPE, p. 383)As fur<strong>the</strong>r examples <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation, George <strong>of</strong>fered,respectively, <strong>the</strong> sail<strong>in</strong>g (arrangement <strong>of</strong> sails <strong>and</strong> so forth) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> construction<strong>and</strong> equipp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a large ship. He elaborated on <strong>the</strong> latter example<strong>in</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r poetic passages:Consider <strong>the</strong> timbers, <strong>the</strong> planks, <strong>the</strong> spars; <strong>the</strong> iron <strong>and</strong> steel <strong>of</strong> variousk<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>and</strong> forms; <strong>the</strong> copper, <strong>the</strong> brass, <strong>the</strong> bolts, screws, spikes, cha<strong>in</strong>s;<strong>the</strong> ropes, <strong>of</strong> steel <strong>and</strong> hemp <strong>and</strong> cotton; <strong>the</strong> canvas <strong>of</strong> various textures;<strong>the</strong> blocks <strong>and</strong> w<strong>in</strong>ches <strong>and</strong> w<strong>in</strong>dlasses; <strong>the</strong> pumps, <strong>the</strong> boats, <strong>the</strong> sextants,<strong>the</strong> chronometers, <strong>the</strong> spy-glasses <strong>and</strong> patent logs, <strong>the</strong> barometers<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>rmometers, charts, nautical almanacs, rockets <strong>and</strong> colored lights;food, cloth<strong>in</strong>g, tools, medic<strong>in</strong>es <strong>and</strong> furniture, <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong> various th<strong>in</strong>gs,which it would be tiresome fully to specify, that go to <strong>the</strong> construction<strong>and</strong> furnish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a first-class sail<strong>in</strong>g ship <strong>of</strong> modern type, to say noth<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> still greater complexity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first-class steamer. Directed cooperationnever did, <strong>and</strong> I do not th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs it ever could,make <strong>and</strong> assemble such a variety <strong>of</strong> products, <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g as many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>mdo <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> costly mach<strong>in</strong>ery <strong>and</strong> consummate skill, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence<strong>of</strong> subsidiary products <strong>and</strong> processes. (SPE, p. 389)


Chapter : Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics 61When he receives an order for such a ship, <strong>the</strong> builder does not sendmen out with detailed <strong>in</strong>structions for do<strong>in</strong>g all <strong>the</strong> necessary work—cutt<strong>in</strong>gvarious woods, m<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> ref<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g various metals, plant<strong>in</strong>g hemp <strong>and</strong>cotton <strong>and</strong> breed<strong>in</strong>g silkworms:Nor does he attempt to direct <strong>the</strong> manifold operations by which <strong>the</strong>seraw materials are to be brought <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> required forms <strong>and</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ations,<strong>and</strong> assembled <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> place where <strong>the</strong> ship is to be built. Such atask would transcend <strong>the</strong> wisdom <strong>and</strong> power <strong>of</strong> a Solomon. What hedoes is to avail himself <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> resources <strong>of</strong> a high civilization, for withoutthat he would be helpless, <strong>and</strong> to make use for his purpose <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unconsciouscooperation by which without his direction, or any general direction,<strong>the</strong> efforts <strong>of</strong> many men, work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> many different places <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>occupations which cover almost <strong>the</strong> whole field <strong>of</strong> a m<strong>in</strong>utely diversified<strong>in</strong>dustry, each animated solely by <strong>the</strong> effort to obta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> satisfaction<strong>of</strong> his personal desires <strong>in</strong> what to him is <strong>the</strong> easiest way, have broughttoge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> materials <strong>and</strong> productions needed for <strong>the</strong> putt<strong>in</strong>g toge<strong>the</strong>r<strong>of</strong> such a ship. (SPE, pp. 389–390)Deploy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sights later also achieved by F.A. Hayek (1945), Georgegoes on to speak <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mobilization <strong>of</strong> knowledge that is <strong>in</strong>evitably dispersed<strong>and</strong> that simply could not be centralized <strong>and</strong> put to use by a s<strong>in</strong>glem<strong>in</strong>d or a s<strong>in</strong>gle organization:So far from any lifetime suffic<strong>in</strong>g to acquire, or any s<strong>in</strong>gle bra<strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g ableto hold, <strong>the</strong> varied knowledge that goes to <strong>the</strong> build<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> equipp<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> a modern sail<strong>in</strong>g-ship, already becom<strong>in</strong>g antiquated by <strong>the</strong> still morecomplex steamer, I doubt if <strong>the</strong> best-<strong>in</strong>formed man on such subjects,even though he took a twelvemonth to study up, could give even <strong>the</strong>names <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> various separate divisions <strong>of</strong> labor <strong>in</strong>volved.A modern ship, like a modern railway, is a product <strong>of</strong> modern civilization... ; <strong>of</strong> that unconscious cooperation which does not come by personaldirection ... but grows ... by <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> efforts <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals,each seek<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> satisfaction <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual desires. A mere master <strong>of</strong>men, though he might comm<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> services <strong>of</strong> millions, could not makesuch a ship unless <strong>in</strong> a civilization prepared for it. (SPE, pp. 390–391)e cooperation required for sail<strong>in</strong>g a ship is relatively simple. ek<strong>in</strong>d required for build<strong>in</strong>g one is beyond <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> conscious directionto order or improve. “e only th<strong>in</strong>g that conscious direction can do to aidit is to let it alone; to give it freedom to grow, leav<strong>in</strong>g men free to seek <strong>the</strong>


62 Part I: Economicsgratification <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own desires <strong>in</strong> ways that to <strong>the</strong>m seem best” (SPE,p. 391).George has more to say on <strong>the</strong> spontaneous mobilization <strong>of</strong> dispersedknowledge. Physical force can be aggregated, but not <strong>in</strong>telligence:Two men cannot see twice as far as one man, nor a hundred thous<strong>and</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>e one hundred thous<strong>and</strong> times as well.... No one ever said, “Ina multitude <strong>of</strong> generals <strong>the</strong>re is victory.” On <strong>the</strong> contrary, <strong>the</strong> adage is,“One poor general is better than two good ones.” (SPE, p. 392)In spontaneous cooperation, however,what is utilized <strong>in</strong> production is not merely <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> physical power<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> units, but <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>telligence.... while <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> coöperation <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence utilizedis that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> coöperat<strong>in</strong>g units, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong>coöperation it is only that <strong>of</strong> a very small part.In o<strong>the</strong>r words it is only <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent action that <strong>the</strong> full powers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>man may be utilized. e subord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> one human will to ano<strong>the</strong>rhuman will, while it may <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> ways secure unity <strong>of</strong> action, mustalways, where <strong>in</strong>telligence is needed, <strong>in</strong>volve loss <strong>of</strong> productive power.(SPE, pp. 392–393)George underst<strong>and</strong>s <strong>the</strong> roles <strong>of</strong> exchange, markets, prices, <strong>and</strong> money<strong>in</strong> accomplish<strong>in</strong>g spontaneous coord<strong>in</strong>ation; <strong>and</strong> he is skeptical (SPE,pp. 445–446) that government regulation <strong>of</strong> prices <strong>and</strong> wages <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terestrates can achieve its <strong>in</strong>tended purposes:Exchange is <strong>the</strong> great agency by which ... <strong>the</strong> spontaneous or unconsciouscoöperation <strong>of</strong> men <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> wealth is brought about<strong>and</strong> economic units are welded <strong>in</strong>to that social organism which is <strong>the</strong>Greater Leviathan. To this economic body, this Greater Leviathan, <strong>in</strong>towhich it builds <strong>the</strong> economic units, it is what <strong>the</strong> nerves or perhaps <strong>the</strong>ganglions are to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual body. Or, to make use <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r illustration,it is to our material desires <strong>and</strong> powers <strong>of</strong> satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m what<strong>the</strong> switchboard <strong>of</strong> a telegraph or telephone or o<strong>the</strong>r electric system is tothat system, a means by which exertion <strong>of</strong> one k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> one place may betransmitted <strong>in</strong>to satisfaction <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r place, <strong>and</strong> thus<strong>the</strong> efforts <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual units be conjo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> correlated so as to yieldsatisfactions <strong>in</strong> most useful place <strong>and</strong> form, <strong>and</strong> to an amount exceed<strong>in</strong>gwhat o<strong>the</strong>rwise would be possible. (SPE, pp. 399–400)


Chapter : Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics 63George rejects socialism, understood as collective or state management <strong>of</strong>all means <strong>of</strong> production (SPE, p. 198), on <strong>the</strong> grounds that it would restrict<strong>the</strong> scope <strong>of</strong> spontaneous coord<strong>in</strong>ation. Attempt<strong>in</strong>g conscious coord<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>of</strong> work requir<strong>in</strong>g spontaneous coord<strong>in</strong>ationis like ask<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> carpenter who can build a chicken-house to build achicken also.is is <strong>the</strong> fatal defect <strong>of</strong> all forms <strong>of</strong> socialism—<strong>the</strong> reason <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact,which all observation shows, that any attempt to carry conscious regulation<strong>and</strong> direction beyond <strong>the</strong> narrow sphere <strong>of</strong> social life <strong>in</strong> which it isnecessary, <strong>in</strong>evitably works <strong>in</strong>jury, h<strong>in</strong>der<strong>in</strong>g even what it is <strong>in</strong>tended tohelp.And <strong>the</strong> rationale <strong>of</strong> this great fact may ... be perceived when we considerthat <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g element <strong>in</strong> all production is thought or <strong>in</strong>telligence,<strong>the</strong> spiritual not <strong>the</strong> material. is spiritual element, this <strong>in</strong>telligence orthought power as it appears <strong>in</strong> man, cannot be comb<strong>in</strong>ed or fused as canmaterial force. (SPE, pp. 391–392)e last sentences quoted rem<strong>in</strong>d us <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> emphasis <strong>of</strong> present-dayAustrians on <strong>the</strong> creative role <strong>of</strong> entrepreneurship. ey also rem<strong>in</strong>d us <strong>of</strong>Julian Simon’s emphasis, <strong>in</strong> a recent book, on e Ultimate Resource—human<strong>in</strong>telligence <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>genuity.To develop his po<strong>in</strong>ts fur<strong>the</strong>r, George asks us to imag<strong>in</strong>e that “<strong>the</strong>very wisest <strong>and</strong> best <strong>of</strong> men were selected” to direct a socialist economy.Consider<strong>the</strong> task that would be put upon <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> order<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> when,where, how <strong>and</strong> by whom that would be <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligentdirection <strong>and</strong> supervision <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> almost <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely complex <strong>and</strong> constantlychang<strong>in</strong>g relations <strong>and</strong> adjustments <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> such division<strong>of</strong> labor as goes on <strong>in</strong> a civilized community. e task transcends <strong>the</strong>power <strong>of</strong> human <strong>in</strong>telligence at its very highest. It is evidently as muchbeyond <strong>the</strong> ability <strong>of</strong> conscious direction as <strong>the</strong> correlation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> processesthat ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> human body <strong>in</strong> health <strong>and</strong> vigor is beyond it.[e human body functions without be<strong>in</strong>g consciously directed by <strong>the</strong>m<strong>in</strong>d.] ...And so it is <strong>the</strong> spontaneous, unconscious cooperation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualswhich, go<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dustrial body, ... conjo<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>dividual efforts <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> wealth, to <strong>the</strong> enormous <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> productive power,


64 Part I: Economics<strong>and</strong> distributes <strong>the</strong> product among <strong>the</strong> units <strong>of</strong> which it is composed. Itis <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> laws <strong>of</strong> such cooperation that it is <strong>the</strong> primary prov<strong>in</strong>ce<strong>of</strong> political economy to ascerta<strong>in</strong>. (SPE, pp. 394–396)ese passages rem<strong>in</strong>d us aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> chief task<strong>of</strong> economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> his <strong>and</strong> Mises’s analyses <strong>of</strong> why accurate economiccalculation would be impossible under full-fledged socialism. George’s views on methodology are remarkably similar to those <strong>of</strong> CarlMenger <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> modern Austrians. George <strong>and</strong> Menger agree that<strong>the</strong> economist’s job is not merely to catalogue economic phenomena butto search for cause-<strong>and</strong>-effect relations among <strong>the</strong>m, to formulate lawsexpress<strong>in</strong>g dependable coexistences <strong>and</strong> sequences, <strong>and</strong> to discover uniformitiesunderly<strong>in</strong>g superficial diversities.Perhaps <strong>the</strong> lead<strong>in</strong>g methodological tenet <strong>of</strong> both men is that <strong>the</strong>seelementary uniformities cannot be found solely <strong>in</strong> panoramic study <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>economic system as a whole. ey must be sought by penetrat<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>level where decisions are actually made, <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual person,family, firm, <strong>and</strong> agency. is approach, recommended by today’s Austriansas methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism, recognizes <strong>the</strong> legitimacy <strong>and</strong> necessity<strong>of</strong> appeal<strong>in</strong>g to purpose <strong>and</strong> motive. e relevant facts <strong>in</strong>clude notonly <strong>the</strong> objective characteristics <strong>of</strong> resources <strong>and</strong> activities <strong>and</strong> productsbut also <strong>the</strong> characteristics attributed to <strong>the</strong>m by fallible human be<strong>in</strong>gs,as well as human preferences <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentions. Aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> subjectivism <strong>of</strong>George <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrians comes to <strong>the</strong> fore. Both recognize that economicsdoes, after all, concern human action (<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>se two words form<strong>the</strong> title <strong>of</strong> Mises’s magnum opus).George asserts a basic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple that people seek to satisfy <strong>the</strong>ir desireswith <strong>the</strong> least possible exertion, <strong>and</strong> Menger expresses similar ideas. is For o<strong>the</strong>r comments by George on socialism, though earlier <strong>and</strong> less <strong>in</strong>sightful ones,see his PFT, pp. 320–334. Although an emphatic opponent <strong>of</strong> socialism, George did advocatenot only public schools but also government ownership <strong>of</strong> what he conceived to benatural monopolies. In <strong>the</strong>se he <strong>in</strong>cluded railroads, <strong>the</strong> telegraph <strong>and</strong> telephone, <strong>and</strong> urbansystems <strong>of</strong> water, gas, heat, <strong>and</strong> electricity (SP, p. 198ff.). George’s remarks on <strong>the</strong> topic occur mostly <strong>in</strong> SPE, with a chapter <strong>in</strong> PFT <strong>and</strong>scattered observations <strong>in</strong> P&P. Menger develops his views <strong>in</strong> 1871/1950 <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> 1883. Anearlier discussion, with more detailed citations, appears <strong>in</strong> Yeager 1954.


Chapter : Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics 65is not an assumption that people behave like <strong>the</strong> economic man <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>familiar caricature or that <strong>the</strong>y act only on selfish motives. George <strong>and</strong> Menger, as well as Mises <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r later Austrians, helpclarify <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> so-called armchair <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g. Economists can discoverbasic facts by observation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people’s decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g.ey even have <strong>the</strong> advantage <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g able to observe <strong>the</strong>basic elements <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>oretical generalizations (human <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>ir striv<strong>in</strong>gs) directly, while <strong>the</strong> natural scientists must postulate or <strong>in</strong>fer<strong>the</strong>ir basic but not directly observable elements from whatever phenomena<strong>the</strong>y can observe directly. Much as geometers deduce many <strong>the</strong>oremsfrom a few axioms, so economists deduce a powerful body <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oryfrom a relatively few empirical generalizations, ones so crush<strong>in</strong>gly obviousthat <strong>the</strong>ir failure to hold true is almost <strong>in</strong>conceivable <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> worldas we know it. e axioms underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g economic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong>clude oneslike George’s least-exertion pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that labor cont<strong>in</strong>uedbeyond some po<strong>in</strong>t becomes irksome (as well as o<strong>the</strong>rs that could beadded to George’s list, such as <strong>the</strong> fact <strong>of</strong> scarcity itself <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<strong>of</strong> eventually dim<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g marg<strong>in</strong>al returns). (e banality <strong>of</strong> empiricalobservations is not related <strong>in</strong>versely to <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>and</strong> importance <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>ir implications <strong>in</strong> economics; <strong>in</strong>deed, one might argue that a directrelation is <strong>the</strong> more plausible.) Armchair <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g need not be <strong>the</strong> meresterile juggl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> arbitrary assumptions; it can have a sound empiricalbasis.George considers how economists can disentangle <strong>the</strong> complex <strong>in</strong>term<strong>in</strong>gl<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> many causes <strong>and</strong> many effects that occurs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> real world. Heexpla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> method <strong>of</strong> “mental or imag<strong>in</strong>ative experiment,” <strong>the</strong> method<strong>of</strong> test<strong>in</strong>g “<strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> known pr<strong>in</strong>ciples by mentally separat<strong>in</strong>g, comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gor elim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g conditions” (SPE, p. 100; PFT, pp. 27–29).George <strong>and</strong> Menger share a skeptical attitude toward <strong>the</strong> “organic”conception <strong>of</strong> society. Both recognize how an economic system seems tohave a life <strong>and</strong> purpose <strong>and</strong> orderl<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> its own, as if it had been shaped<strong>and</strong> were operat<strong>in</strong>g by deliberate design. Yet <strong>the</strong>y do not jo<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> holists<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutionalists <strong>in</strong> suppos<strong>in</strong>g that this apparent organic unity requiresconcentrat<strong>in</strong>g research on <strong>the</strong> system’s overall <strong>in</strong>stitutional arrangements<strong>and</strong> supposed evolutionary trends. Instead <strong>of</strong> tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> coherence <strong>and</strong>order <strong>of</strong> a market economy for granted, <strong>the</strong>y regard <strong>the</strong>se as among <strong>the</strong> See SPE, esp. pp. 91, 99. In this respect George anticipated Wicksteed 1910/1933, esp.chap. 5.


66 Part I: Economicschief phenomena cry<strong>in</strong>g out for explanation. Both employ methodological<strong>in</strong>dividualism <strong>in</strong> develop<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir explanations.George <strong>and</strong> Menger <strong>of</strong>fer <strong>the</strong> same two examples <strong>of</strong> how features<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> system as a whole can arise, without be<strong>in</strong>g deliberately contrived,from <strong>the</strong> efforts <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals to gratify <strong>the</strong>ir separate desires: () moneyevolves from <strong>the</strong> most marketable <strong>of</strong> commodities under barter; () newcommunities grow <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir economic activities evolve <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> appearance<strong>of</strong> a rational pattern, even though settlers move <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> take up particularoccupations only with a view to satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir separate desires.George <strong>and</strong> Menger—to summarize—conceive <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>oryas a body <strong>of</strong> deductions from a few compell<strong>in</strong>gly strong empirical generalizations.ey employ methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism because <strong>the</strong>y realizethat economists’ “<strong>in</strong>side” underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> human purposes <strong>and</strong> decisionsis a lead<strong>in</strong>g source <strong>of</strong> empirical axioms. (Not shar<strong>in</strong>g George’s <strong>and</strong>Menger’s underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> how empirical content can enter <strong>in</strong>to armchair<strong>the</strong>ory, many economists <strong>of</strong> our own day apparently regard <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong>empirical work as two dist<strong>in</strong>ct fields, with adverse consequences for both.) A f<strong>in</strong>al aff<strong>in</strong>ity between George <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> modern Austrians concernssocial or political philosophy. Austrian economists tend to be libertarians(although several <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>sist that <strong>the</strong>re is no necessary connection).Many libertarians—to look at <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around—tendto regard Austrianism as <strong>the</strong>ir own “house br<strong>and</strong>” <strong>of</strong> economics. is isunfortunate. Anyway, <strong>the</strong> ideological aff<strong>in</strong>ity between George <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austriansrema<strong>in</strong>s a fact. As C. Lowell Harriss says:George could probably have considered himself a libertarian had <strong>the</strong>term been current <strong>in</strong> his day.... And such twentieth-century libertarian Economics is a tool for underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> possibly reshap<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> world—for try<strong>in</strong>gto make one’s deepest values prevail, whatever <strong>the</strong>y may be. Everyone, <strong>the</strong>refore, has an<strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> gett<strong>in</strong>g his economics straight. e truths <strong>of</strong> economics, as <strong>of</strong> any o<strong>the</strong>r field<strong>of</strong> objective research, once discovered, will be <strong>the</strong> same for everyone. ere is no onetruth for libertarians, ano<strong>the</strong>r for collectivists, <strong>and</strong> so on. Of course, both George <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>Austrians have much to contribute toward gett<strong>in</strong>g economics straight; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> capacityto contribute is not conf<strong>in</strong>ed to any particular school. What is unfortunate is a belief <strong>in</strong>different house br<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> truth. Ludwig von Mises (1949) was duly emphatic <strong>in</strong> attack<strong>in</strong>gthis notion, which he called “polylogism.”


Chapter : Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics 67champions as Albert Jay Nock <strong>and</strong> Frank Chodorov pr<strong>of</strong>essed <strong>the</strong>mselvesoutright Georgists. It was Nock, <strong>in</strong> fact, who acclaimed George“<strong>the</strong> philosopher <strong>of</strong> freedom,” “<strong>the</strong> exponent <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualism as aga<strong>in</strong>stStatism,” “<strong>the</strong> very best friend <strong>the</strong> capitalist ever had,” <strong>and</strong> “<strong>the</strong> architect<strong>of</strong> a society based on voluntary cooperation ra<strong>the</strong>r than on enforcedcooperation.” (Harriss <strong>in</strong> Andelson 1979, p. 367; citations omitted here.) George rejected socialism not only out <strong>of</strong> concern for economic efficiencybut also (anticipat<strong>in</strong>g Hayek 1944) out <strong>of</strong> concern for human freedom:e proposal which socialism makes is that <strong>the</strong> collectivity or state shallassume <strong>the</strong> management <strong>of</strong> all means <strong>of</strong> production, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>and</strong>, capital<strong>and</strong> man himself; do away with all competition, <strong>and</strong> convert mank<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>to two classes, <strong>the</strong> directors, tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir orders from government <strong>and</strong>act<strong>in</strong>g by governmental authority, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> workers, for whom everyth<strong>in</strong>gshall be provided, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> directors <strong>the</strong>mselves.... It is more destitute<strong>of</strong> any central <strong>and</strong> guid<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple than any philosophy I know<strong>of</strong>.... It has no system <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual rights whereby it can def<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong>extent to which <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual is entitled to liberty or to which <strong>the</strong> statemay go <strong>in</strong> restra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g it. (SPE, p. 198)George, like many libertarian Austrians, champions <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong>natural rights or <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong> man. He emphatically <strong>in</strong>cludes propertyrights. He was no redistributionist.In a chapter entitled “e Rights <strong>of</strong> Man,” he asserts:some facts [are] so obvious as to be beyond <strong>the</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> argument.And one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se facts, attested by universal consciousness, is that <strong>the</strong>reare rights as between man <strong>and</strong> man which existed before <strong>the</strong> formation<strong>of</strong> government, <strong>and</strong> which cont<strong>in</strong>ue to exist <strong>in</strong> spite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> abuse <strong>of</strong> government;that <strong>the</strong>re is a higher law than any human law—to wit, <strong>the</strong> law<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Creator, impressed upon <strong>and</strong> revealed through nature, which isbefore <strong>and</strong> above human laws, <strong>and</strong> upon conformity to which all humanlaws must depend for <strong>the</strong>ir validity. To deny this is to assert that <strong>the</strong>re isno st<strong>and</strong>ard whatever by which <strong>the</strong> rightfulness or wrongfulness <strong>of</strong> laws<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions can be measured; to assert that <strong>the</strong>re can be no actions<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves right <strong>and</strong> none <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves wrong; to assert that an edict Harriss goes on to cite passages from P&P, pp. 434–436, that make George look likea supply-sider also, passages on <strong>the</strong> great release <strong>of</strong> productive energies to be expected iflaborer <strong>and</strong> capitalist alike were allowed, through <strong>the</strong> abolition <strong>of</strong> taxes (o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong>s<strong>in</strong>gle tax), to reap <strong>the</strong> full reward <strong>of</strong> what <strong>the</strong>y produce. Besides <strong>the</strong> passages cited below, see Andelson <strong>in</strong> Andelson 1979, pp. 386–387.


68 Part I: Economicswhich comm<strong>and</strong>ed mo<strong>the</strong>rs to kill <strong>the</strong>ir children should receive <strong>the</strong> samerespect as a law prohibit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fanticide.ese natural rights, this higher law, form <strong>the</strong> only true <strong>and</strong> sure basisfor social organization. (SP, p. 92)He denies any “real antagonism between <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong> men <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>rights <strong>of</strong> property—s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> right <strong>of</strong> property is but <strong>the</strong> expression <strong>of</strong> afundamental right <strong>of</strong> man.” He challenges those who imag<strong>in</strong>e any conflictbetween human <strong>and</strong> property rights “to name any denial <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong>men which is not or does not <strong>in</strong>volve a denial <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong> property;or any denial <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong> property which is not or does not <strong>in</strong>volve adenial <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong> men” (PPH, pp. 209–210):is is not an accidental, but a necessary connection. e right <strong>of</strong> life<strong>and</strong> liberty—that is to say, <strong>the</strong> right <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> man to himself—is not reallyone right <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> right <strong>of</strong> property ano<strong>the</strong>r right. ey are two aspects<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same perception—<strong>the</strong> right <strong>of</strong> property be<strong>in</strong>g but ano<strong>the</strong>r side, adifferently stated expression, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> right <strong>of</strong> man to himself. e right<strong>of</strong> life <strong>and</strong> liberty, <strong>the</strong> right <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual to himself, presupposes<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> right <strong>of</strong> property, which is <strong>the</strong> exclusive right <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual to <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs his exertion has produced.is is <strong>the</strong> reason why we who really believe <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> law <strong>of</strong> liberty, wewho see <strong>in</strong> freedom <strong>the</strong> great solvent for all social evils, are <strong>the</strong> stanchest<strong>and</strong> most unfl<strong>in</strong>ch<strong>in</strong>g supporters <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong> property, <strong>and</strong> wouldguard it as scrupulously <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> millionaire as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>day-laborer. (PPH, pp. 210–211)I have been an active, consistent <strong>and</strong> absolute free trader, <strong>and</strong> an opponent<strong>of</strong> all schemes that would limit <strong>the</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual. I havebeen a stancher denier <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> assumption <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> right <strong>of</strong> society to <strong>the</strong>possessions <strong>of</strong> each member, <strong>and</strong> a clearer <strong>and</strong> more resolute upholder <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong> property than has Mr. Spencer. I have opposed every propositionto help <strong>the</strong> poor at <strong>the</strong> expense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rich. I have always <strong>in</strong>sistedthat no man should be taxed because <strong>of</strong> his wealth, <strong>and</strong> that no matterhow many millions a man might rightfully get, society should leave tohim every penny <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. (PPH, pp. 70–71)is, <strong>and</strong> this alone, I contend for—that he who makes should have; tha<strong>the</strong> who saves should enjoy. I ask <strong>in</strong> behalf <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> poor noth<strong>in</strong>g whateverthat properly belongs to <strong>the</strong> rich. Instead <strong>of</strong> weaken<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> confus<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> property, I would surround it with stronger sanctions. Instead Herbert Spencer is <strong>the</strong> person referred to <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> book’s title <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> passage quoted.


Chapter : Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics 69<strong>of</strong> lessen<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>centive to <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> wealth, I would make itmore powerful by mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> reward more certa<strong>in</strong>. Whatever any manhas added to <strong>the</strong> general stock <strong>of</strong> wealth, or has received <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free will<strong>of</strong> him who did produce it, let that be his as aga<strong>in</strong>st all <strong>the</strong> world—his touse or to give, to do with it whatever he may please, so long as such usedoes not <strong>in</strong>terfere with <strong>the</strong> equal freedom <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. For my part, I wouldput no limit on acquisition. No matter how many millions any man canget by methods which do not <strong>in</strong>volve <strong>the</strong> robbery <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs—<strong>the</strong>y arehis: let him have <strong>the</strong>m. I would not even ask him for charity, or haveit d<strong>in</strong>ned <strong>in</strong>to his ears that it is his duty to help <strong>the</strong> poor. at is hisown affair. Let him do as he pleases with his own, without restriction<strong>and</strong> without suggestion. If he gets without tak<strong>in</strong>g from o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>and</strong> useswithout hurt<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>rs, what he does with his wealth is his own bus<strong>in</strong>ess<strong>and</strong> his own responsibility. (SP, pp. 86–87)’ In conclusion I rem<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> reader, but without quot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> whole passageverbatim, <strong>of</strong> Joseph Schumpeter’s assessment <strong>of</strong> Henry George. “He wasa self-taught economist, but he was an economist.” He acquired most <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> economics taught <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> universities <strong>of</strong> his time. He was at home <strong>in</strong>scientific economics up to <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Mill’s Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, although hedid fail to underst<strong>and</strong> Marshall <strong>and</strong> Böhm-Bawerk. Barr<strong>in</strong>g his s<strong>in</strong>gle tax<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> phraseology connected with it, he was an orthodox economist,conservative <strong>in</strong> method. Whatever else might be said about his panacea,it was not nonsense; <strong>and</strong> as a competent economist, “he was careful t<strong>of</strong>rame his ‘remedy’ <strong>in</strong> such a manner as to cause <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>imum <strong>in</strong>jury to<strong>the</strong> efficiency <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> private-enterprise economy.” What George said about<strong>the</strong> economic benefits to be expected if it were possible (as Schumpeterdoubted) to remove o<strong>the</strong>r taxes was even “obvious wisdom” (Schumpeter1954, p. 865).e present article lends support, I hope, to this assessment.Andelson, Robert W., ed. Critics <strong>of</strong> Henry George. Ru<strong>the</strong>rford, N.J.: FairleighDick<strong>in</strong>son University Press, 1979. Articles cited: Andelson, “Neo-Georgism,”pp. 381–393; Charles Collier, “Ru<strong>the</strong>rford: e Devil Quotes Scripture,”pp. 222–233; Aaron B. Fuller, “Davenport: ‘S<strong>in</strong>gle Taxer <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> LooserObservance,’” pp. 293–302; <strong>and</strong> C. Lowell Harriss, “Rothbard’s Anarcho-Capitalist Critique,” pp. 354–370.


70 Part I: EconomicsBastiat, Frédéric. 1850. Economic Harmonies. Translated by W. Hayden Boyers.Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>, 1964.Böhm-Bawerk, Eugen von. Capital <strong>and</strong> Interest. 1884. Translated by George D.Huncke <strong>and</strong> Hans F. Sennholz. 3 vols. South Holl<strong>and</strong>, Ill.: Libertarian Press,1959.Clark, John Bates. e Distribution <strong>of</strong> Wealth. 1899. New York: Macmillan, 1908.Dolan, Edw<strong>in</strong> G., ed. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Modern Austrian Economics. Kansas City,Kans.: Sheed <strong>and</strong> Ward, 1976.George, Henry. 1879. Progress <strong>and</strong> Poverty. New York: Robert SchalkenbachFoundation, 1940. P&P.. 1883. Social Problems. New York: Doubleday Page, 1904. SP.. 1886. Protection or Free Trade. New York: Doubleday Page, 1905. PFT.. A Perplexed Philosopher. 1892. New York: Doubleday Page, 1904. PPH.. 1898. e Science <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>. New York: Robert SchalkenbachFoundation, 1941. SPE.Hayek, Friedrich A. e Road to Serfdom. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press,1944.. “e Use <strong>of</strong> Knowledge <strong>in</strong> Society.” American Economic Review 35(September 1945): 519–530.. “e Results <strong>of</strong> Human Action but Not <strong>of</strong> Human Design.” In Studies<strong>in</strong> Philosophy, Politics, <strong>and</strong> Economics, 96–105. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1967.Leibenste<strong>in</strong>, Harvey. Beyond Economic Man. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard UniversityPress, 1976.Menger, Carl. Untersuchungen über die Methode der Socialwissenschaften und derpolitischen ökonomie <strong>in</strong>sbesondere. Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot, 1883.. 1871. Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> Economics. Translated <strong>and</strong> edited by James D<strong>in</strong>gwall<strong>and</strong> Bert F. Hoselitz. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1950.Mises, Ludwig von. Human Action. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press,1949.. e eory <strong>of</strong> Money <strong>and</strong> Credit. 1912. Translated by H.E. Batson. Indianapolis:Liberty Classics, 1981.


Chapter : Henry George <strong>and</strong> Austrian Economics 71Moss, Laurence S., ed. e Economics <strong>of</strong> Ludwig von Mises. Kansas City, Kans.:Sheed <strong>and</strong> Ward, 1976.O’Driscoll, Gerald P. Economics as a Coord<strong>in</strong>ation Problem. Kansas City, Kans.:Sheed Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, 1977.Rothbard, Murray N. Man, <strong>Economy</strong>, <strong>and</strong> State. 2 vols. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. VanNostr<strong>and</strong>, 1962.. Power <strong>and</strong> <strong>Market</strong>. Menlo Park, Calif.: Institute for Humane Studies,1970.. For a New Liberty. New York: Macmillan, 1973.Schumpeter, Joseph. History <strong>of</strong> Economic Analysis. New York: Oxford UniversityPress, 1954.Simon, Julian L. e Ultimate Resource. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton UniversityPress, 1981.Spadaro, Louis M., ed. New Directions <strong>in</strong> Austrian Economics. Kansas City, Kans.:Sheed Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, 1978.Wicksteed, Philip H. 1910. e Common Sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>. Rev. <strong>and</strong>enlarged ed. London: Routledge, 1933.. An Essay on <strong>the</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Laws <strong>of</strong> Distribution. 1894. London:London School <strong>of</strong> Economics, 1932.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “e Methodology <strong>of</strong> Henry George <strong>and</strong> Carl Menger.” AmericanJournal <strong>of</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> Sociology 13 (1954): 233–238.


e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong>a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> *Non-academic socialists have <strong>in</strong> general bo<strong>the</strong>red little about how a socialisteconomy would work. Even Karl Marx preferred to attack capitalismra<strong>the</strong>r than describe socialism. In popular thought, socialist productionwas to be organized very simply, with sole regard to <strong>the</strong> needs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> comrades.e popular slogan “production for use, not for pr<strong>of</strong>it” overlooks <strong>the</strong>fundamental economic problem <strong>of</strong> scarcity. It is simply impossible to satisfyall <strong>of</strong> everybody’s wants fully. Without some <strong>in</strong>dexes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensity<strong>and</strong> satiability <strong>of</strong> wants <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> scarcity <strong>of</strong> resources relative to usefulness,rational economic calculation is out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> question. Suppose tenmore small radios could be produced at <strong>the</strong> sacrifice <strong>of</strong> one large televisionset. Would national output <strong>the</strong>reby be <strong>in</strong>creased or decreased? Withoutsome concept <strong>of</strong> “value,” <strong>the</strong> question is mean<strong>in</strong>gless. Suppose a certa<strong>in</strong>product could be produced ei<strong>the</strong>r with ten units <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> plus five <strong>of</strong> laboror with four units <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> plus n<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> labor. Which method <strong>of</strong> productionis more economical? Without some concept <strong>of</strong> “value,” <strong>the</strong> questionis mean<strong>in</strong>gless.When socialism became an immediate political issue at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong>World War I, <strong>the</strong> Austrian economist Ludwig von Mises spoke forth todeny that socialism is economically practicable. Mises’s ma<strong>in</strong> argumentcan be summarized—as <strong>the</strong> socialist H.D. Dick<strong>in</strong>son (1939, p. 111) hasdone—<strong>in</strong> three statements:. Rational economic activity requires <strong>the</strong> pric<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> all goods, productiongoods as well as consumption goods.*Presented <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Department <strong>of</strong> Economics staff sem<strong>in</strong>ar, Texas A&M University(<strong>the</strong>n College), November 1949. Pr<strong>in</strong>ted here unchanged except for st<strong>and</strong>ardization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>format <strong>of</strong> references.72


Chapter : e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> 73. Pric<strong>in</strong>g requires <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> a market.. A market requires <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent owners <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> goodsexchanged.Listen to Mises’s own words:In any social order, even under Socialism, it can very easily be decidedwhich k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong> what number <strong>of</strong> consumption goods should be produced.No one has ever denied that. But once this decision has been made, <strong>the</strong>restill rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> ascerta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g how <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g means <strong>of</strong> productioncan be used most effectively to produce <strong>the</strong>se goods <strong>in</strong> question.In order to solve this problem it is necessary that <strong>the</strong>re should beeconomic calculation. And economic calculation can only take place bymeans <strong>of</strong> money prices established <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> market for production goods<strong>in</strong> a society rest<strong>in</strong>g on private property <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> means <strong>of</strong> production. atis to say, <strong>the</strong>re must exist money prices <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>, raw materials, semimanufactures;that is to say, <strong>the</strong>re must be money wages <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terestrates. (1922/1981, pp. 141–142)At about <strong>the</strong> same time that Mises’s famous article appeared <strong>in</strong> 1920,similar ideas came from <strong>the</strong> pens <strong>of</strong> Max Weber <strong>in</strong> Germany <strong>and</strong> BorisBrutzkus <strong>in</strong>—<strong>of</strong> all places—Russia. Brutzkus, for <strong>in</strong>stance, wrote:just as capitalism possessed a general measure <strong>of</strong> value <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> rouble, sosocialism would have to possess an analogous unit for <strong>the</strong> evaluation <strong>of</strong> itselements.... Without evaluation any rational economic conduct, under whateverk<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> economic system, is impossible. (1935, p. 15; italics <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al)Mises, Weber, <strong>and</strong> Brutzkus were not <strong>the</strong> first writers to question <strong>the</strong>economic efficiency <strong>of</strong> arbitrary plann<strong>in</strong>g. For <strong>in</strong>stance, as early as 1902,<strong>the</strong> Dutch economist Nicolaas G. Pierson (1935, pp. 41–85) had emphasizedthat a socialist community would have to face <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> value.But it was left for Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Mises to revolutionize academic discussion.is Mises accomplished by his dogmatic <strong>in</strong>sistence that rational economiccalculation under socialism would be impossible. In Mises’s ownwords, “Every step that takes us away from private ownership <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> means<strong>of</strong> production <strong>and</strong> from <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> money also takes us away from rationaleconomics” (1920/1935, p. 104).Ensu<strong>in</strong>g discussion <strong>of</strong> how to avoid <strong>the</strong> pitfalls stressed by Mises becamerem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> an article published by Enrico Barone <strong>in</strong> 1908. In his“e M<strong>in</strong>istry <strong>of</strong> Production <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Collectivist State,” Barone had applied


74 Part I: EconomicsPareto’s system <strong>of</strong> equations to demonstrate that “all <strong>the</strong> economic categories<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> old regime must reappear, though maybe with o<strong>the</strong>r names:prices, salaries, <strong>in</strong>terest, rent, pr<strong>of</strong>it, sav<strong>in</strong>g, etc.” (1908/1935, p. 289). eM<strong>in</strong>istry <strong>of</strong> Production, through deliberate arrangement, would have tosatisfy <strong>the</strong> two conditions that would result automatically from perfectcompetition, that is, equalization <strong>of</strong> prices with cost, <strong>and</strong> m<strong>in</strong>imization<strong>of</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> production. e system <strong>of</strong> equations giv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> correct allocation<strong>of</strong> resources <strong>and</strong> labor would be identical with <strong>the</strong> system reflect<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> operation <strong>of</strong> free competition. However, Barone assumed that <strong>the</strong>M<strong>in</strong>istry would actually have to formulate <strong>and</strong> solve such equations, sohe referred skeptically to “<strong>the</strong> laborious <strong>and</strong> colossal centralization work<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> M<strong>in</strong>istry (assum<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> practical possibility <strong>of</strong> such a system)”(p. 290).e concept <strong>of</strong> “optimum conditions” is ei<strong>the</strong>r explicit or implicit <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> Barone <strong>and</strong> many post-Mises writers. If one makes a number<strong>of</strong> assumptions—such as that people’s preferences as workers <strong>and</strong> consumersare to “count” <strong>and</strong> that an ethically desirable <strong>in</strong>come distributioncan be achieved—<strong>the</strong>n it is possible to deduce certa<strong>in</strong> conditionswhich must prevail <strong>in</strong> a situation <strong>of</strong> maximum welfare as a situation <strong>in</strong>which no household could be made still better without some o<strong>the</strong>r householdbe<strong>in</strong>g made worse <strong>of</strong>f <strong>in</strong> consequence. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Vilfredo Pareto,J.R. Hicks, Paul Samuelson, Abram Bergson, M.W. Reder, Abba Lerner,Oskar Lange, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r recent writers have explicitly formulated sets <strong>of</strong>optimum conditions. e optimum conditions are <strong>the</strong> heart <strong>of</strong> modernwelfare economics.To save time, I shall not read a typical set <strong>of</strong> optimum conditions. econditions are more easily followed when seen <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>t than when merelyheard, anyway. Suffice to say that Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Hayek has summed up several<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conditions very neatly: “<strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al rates <strong>of</strong> substitution betweenany two commodities or factors must be <strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong> all <strong>the</strong>ir differentuses” (1948, p. 77).e optimum conditions may be restated briefly <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> “costs.”e total cost <strong>in</strong>curred <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> optimum amount <strong>of</strong>any commodity must be a m<strong>in</strong>imum, that is, <strong>the</strong> average cost at optimumoutput must be a m<strong>in</strong>imum. e optimum output <strong>of</strong> each commodityis specified by <strong>the</strong> condition that marg<strong>in</strong>al cost equal price. e“prices” used <strong>in</strong> valu<strong>in</strong>g outputs <strong>and</strong> measur<strong>in</strong>g costs need not be thought<strong>of</strong> as market prices; <strong>the</strong>y can—<strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple—be mere <strong>in</strong>dexes <strong>in</strong>verselyproportional to <strong>the</strong> common subjective marg<strong>in</strong>al rates <strong>of</strong> substitution for


Chapter : e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> 75households <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> common marg<strong>in</strong>al technical rates <strong>of</strong> substitution forfirms.e po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussion so far is that a socialist plann<strong>in</strong>g boardcould formulate a set <strong>of</strong> optimum conditions <strong>and</strong> translate <strong>the</strong>se conditions<strong>in</strong>to ma<strong>the</strong>matical equations. If <strong>the</strong> plann<strong>in</strong>g board knew <strong>in</strong> completedetail <strong>the</strong> preferences <strong>of</strong> all people as workers <strong>and</strong> as consumers,if it knew <strong>the</strong> production functions <strong>of</strong> all productive processes, if it haddetailed <strong>in</strong>formation on <strong>the</strong> stocks <strong>of</strong> all resources, <strong>and</strong> if it could decide onsome scheme <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come distribution, <strong>the</strong>n—conceivably—it could determ<strong>in</strong>e<strong>the</strong> amounts <strong>of</strong> each <strong>and</strong> every sort <strong>of</strong> good <strong>and</strong> service which“should” be allocated to each <strong>and</strong> every use. If <strong>the</strong> plann<strong>in</strong>g board wereomniscient, <strong>the</strong>n—as Hayek remarks—<strong>the</strong> solution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> community’seconomic problem would be a matter <strong>of</strong> pure logic (Hayek 1948, p. 77).For <strong>the</strong> board would embody its omniscience <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical equations.As Barone showed, <strong>the</strong>re would be as many equations as unknowns. eequations are to be solved simultaneously, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> solution would be determ<strong>in</strong>ate.Writers before <strong>the</strong> time <strong>of</strong> Mises’s famous article—notably Wieser,Pareto, <strong>and</strong> Cassel, as well as Barone—had used <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> equilibriumdeterm<strong>in</strong>ation through simultaneous equations as an expositorydevice. But some socialist writers have envisaged <strong>the</strong> solution <strong>of</strong> simultaneousequations as <strong>the</strong> actual method <strong>of</strong> socialist resource allocation (for<strong>in</strong>stance, Carl L<strong>and</strong>auer, <strong>and</strong>—at one time—H.D. Dick<strong>in</strong>son).On this approach, <strong>the</strong> comments <strong>of</strong> Lionel Robb<strong>in</strong>s are most pert<strong>in</strong>ent.I quote from Robb<strong>in</strong>s, e Great Depression (1934, pp. 150–151).On paper we can conceive this problem to be solved by a series <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>maticalcalculations. We can imag<strong>in</strong>e tables to be drawn up express<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> consumers’ dem<strong>and</strong>s for all <strong>the</strong> different commodities at all conceivableprices. And we can conceive technical <strong>in</strong>formation giv<strong>in</strong>g us <strong>the</strong>productivity, <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> different commodities, which couldbe produced by each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> various possible comb<strong>in</strong>ations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> factors<strong>of</strong> production. On such a basis a system <strong>of</strong> simultaneous equations couldbe constructed whose solution would show <strong>the</strong> equilibrium distribution<strong>of</strong> factors <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> equilibrium production <strong>of</strong> commodities.But <strong>in</strong> practice this solution is quite unworkable. It would necessitate <strong>the</strong>draw<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>of</strong> millions <strong>of</strong> equations on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> millions <strong>of</strong> statisticaltables based on many more millions <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual computations. By<strong>the</strong> time <strong>the</strong> equations were solved, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation on which <strong>the</strong>y werebased would have became obsolete <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y would need to be calculated


76 Part I: Economicsanew. e suggestion that a practical solution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> plann<strong>in</strong>gis possible on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Paretian equations simply <strong>in</strong>dicates thatthose who put it forward have not begun to grasp what <strong>the</strong>se equationsreally mean. ere is no hope <strong>in</strong> this direction <strong>of</strong> discover<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> relativesacrifices <strong>of</strong> alternative k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment. ere is no hope here <strong>of</strong> ameans <strong>of</strong> adjust<strong>in</strong>g production to meet <strong>the</strong> preferences <strong>of</strong> consumers.In his article “On <strong>the</strong> Economic eory <strong>of</strong> Socialism,” Oskar Langemakes fun <strong>of</strong> Robb<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Hayek for worry<strong>in</strong>g about whe<strong>the</strong>r socialistspropose to solve simultaneous equations (Lange <strong>and</strong> Taylor 1938, p. 88).But before decid<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r Robb<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Hayek deserve this ridicule,lets see what Carl L<strong>and</strong>auer wrote <strong>in</strong> a book published as recently as 1944.e follow<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>es are, to me, among <strong>the</strong> funniest <strong>in</strong> all economics:Price formation on <strong>the</strong> market is a search for an equilibrium throughtrial <strong>and</strong> error. e sellers <strong>and</strong> buyers change <strong>the</strong>ir charges <strong>and</strong> bidd<strong>in</strong>gsuntil a price is established which just equilibrates supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>.e plann<strong>in</strong>g board can carry this process out on paper with <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itelyless cost <strong>and</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> time than it can be carried out by sellers <strong>and</strong> buyers<strong>in</strong> reality.... it is possible to establish a system <strong>of</strong> simultaneous equations, <strong>in</strong> which<strong>the</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ed effects, <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> utility produced, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> physical quantities<strong>of</strong> each element <strong>in</strong> each comb<strong>in</strong>ation appear as <strong>the</strong> knowns <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>unit values <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> elements as <strong>the</strong> unknowns.ere is no difficulty at all <strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g as many equations as we wish, s<strong>in</strong>ce<strong>the</strong>re are almost <strong>in</strong>numerable comb<strong>in</strong>ations <strong>of</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> we have alwaysenough to calculate <strong>the</strong> unknowns.Instead <strong>of</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> rules <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical text-book, we maysystematically change all <strong>the</strong> elements <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> equations until we arrive atmagnitudes which will satisfy <strong>the</strong> conditions.e plann<strong>in</strong>g board ... applies <strong>the</strong> trial-<strong>and</strong>-error process on paper....is form <strong>of</strong> experimental variation is an immense economy <strong>in</strong> time,effort, <strong>and</strong> material as compared with <strong>the</strong> experiments <strong>in</strong> steel <strong>and</strong> timber,copper <strong>and</strong> labor, selection <strong>of</strong> occupation <strong>and</strong> expenditure <strong>of</strong> consumerdollars, which is <strong>the</strong> prevalent form <strong>of</strong> approach<strong>in</strong>g an equilibriumunder <strong>the</strong> status quo.... <strong>the</strong> equations will not reach a fabulous number, but it is quite possiblethat a few hundred thous<strong>and</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ations have to be taken <strong>in</strong>to account.Why this should exceed <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> algebraic analysis is difficultto see. It probably does not exceed <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> calculation work


Chapter : e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> 77which a hundred middle-sized eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g firms have to perform <strong>in</strong> aweek.It is a crude method to search for an equilibrium by experimentallyvary<strong>in</strong>g all <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ants until <strong>the</strong>y fit toge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong>, although it is<strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely more economical to carry out <strong>the</strong>se variations on paper than <strong>in</strong>reality, a fur<strong>the</strong>r great economy <strong>of</strong> effort might be achieved through <strong>the</strong>development <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical shortcuts. A future generation may lookupon <strong>the</strong> trial-<strong>and</strong>-error process very much as a second-year schoolboy,know<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> multiply<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> divid<strong>in</strong>g techniques, looks at <strong>the</strong>abacus. But <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> meantime, <strong>the</strong> abacus method serves <strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong>demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> problem is <strong>in</strong> any case soluble, practically as wellas <strong>the</strong>oretically. (L<strong>and</strong>auer 1944, pp. 34–41)Before proceed<strong>in</strong>g to socialist schemes that assign a large role to prices,let’s exam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> optimum condition that for every product, marg<strong>in</strong>al costshould equal price. is is Abba Lerner’s famous <strong>in</strong>struction to managers<strong>of</strong> socialized enterprises. Its implications have been one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> hottesttopics <strong>of</strong> debate <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> field <strong>of</strong> welfare economics.First, just why should marg<strong>in</strong>al cost <strong>and</strong> price be equal? e marg<strong>in</strong>alcost <strong>of</strong> commodity A is <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> additional factor-unitsneeded to make an extra unit <strong>of</strong> commodity A. e price to a producer <strong>of</strong>commodity A <strong>of</strong> each factor-unit equals <strong>the</strong> factor’s marg<strong>in</strong>al value productivityelsewhere. If consumers will pay more for commodity A thanits marg<strong>in</strong>al cost, this means that <strong>the</strong> necessary additional factors will producemore satisfaction (as measured by what consumers are will<strong>in</strong>g to pay)<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> commodity A than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> anyth<strong>in</strong>g else.If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, consumers will not pay as much for commodity A asits marg<strong>in</strong>al cost, this means that marg<strong>in</strong>al factors will produce more consumersatisfaction elsewhere. Now, an additional unit <strong>of</strong> any factor shouldhave <strong>the</strong> same marg<strong>in</strong>al value productivity—that is, <strong>the</strong> same marg<strong>in</strong>alproductivity <strong>of</strong> consumer satisfactions—<strong>in</strong> all its uses. erefore, production<strong>of</strong> commodity A should be exp<strong>and</strong>ed or contracted to <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t atwhich marg<strong>in</strong>al cost <strong>and</strong> price are equal.If average cost <strong>of</strong> a commodity decreases throughout <strong>the</strong> relevant rangeas output exp<strong>and</strong>s, marg<strong>in</strong>al cost is less than average cost. e total amount In a footnote L<strong>and</strong>auer cites <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> Henry Schultz to show that actual dem<strong>and</strong>curves can be found.In <strong>the</strong> book quoted, L<strong>and</strong>auer, an old-time socialist, is ostensibly argu<strong>in</strong>g for “plann<strong>in</strong>g”ra<strong>the</strong>r than for “socialism.” However, it would be mere quibbl<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> wordsto deny that L<strong>and</strong>auer’s proposals are socialism.


78 Part I: Economicspaid for <strong>the</strong> commodity on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al-cost pric<strong>in</strong>g will thusfall short <strong>of</strong> total costs. But s<strong>in</strong>ce price should equal marg<strong>in</strong>al cost, <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>dustry should run at a loss, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> government should make up <strong>the</strong>loss out <strong>of</strong> general taxation.Alfred Marshall had already <strong>in</strong> his Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples (1890/1920, pp. 469–473)championed subsidies to decreas<strong>in</strong>g-cost <strong>in</strong>dustries <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> old-fashionedlanguage <strong>of</strong> “consumers’ surplus.” In recent years Harold Hotell<strong>in</strong>g (1938,pp. 242–269) <strong>and</strong> Abba Lerner (1947, esp. pp. 194–199) have <strong>in</strong>sisted vigorouslyon <strong>the</strong> proposition; <strong>and</strong> though <strong>the</strong> conclusion is startl<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>Hotell<strong>in</strong>g-Lerner logic, summarized above, seems impeccable.e disconcert<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>g is that ano<strong>the</strong>r cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g leads to aseem<strong>in</strong>gly opposite conclusion. R.H. Coase (1946, pp. 169–182, esp. p. 172)states two pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> optimum pric<strong>in</strong>g:. For each <strong>in</strong>dividual consumer <strong>the</strong> same factor should have <strong>the</strong> sameprice <strong>in</strong> whatever use it is employed. O<strong>the</strong>rwise consumers would notbe able to choose rationally, on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> price, <strong>the</strong> use <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>ypreferred to have <strong>the</strong> factor employed.. e price <strong>of</strong> a factor should equate its supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> shouldbe <strong>the</strong> same for all consumers <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> all uses.From <strong>the</strong>se pr<strong>in</strong>ciples Coase draws <strong>the</strong> implication that <strong>the</strong> amountpaid for a product should be equal to <strong>the</strong> total value that <strong>the</strong> factors used<strong>in</strong> its production have <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r use or to ano<strong>the</strong>r user. In o<strong>the</strong>r words,<strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> a product should be equal to its full cost.Coase argues that if certa<strong>in</strong> factors <strong>of</strong> production can be obta<strong>in</strong>ed free<strong>in</strong> one use (because <strong>the</strong>y do not enter <strong>in</strong>to marg<strong>in</strong>al cost), but have tobe paid for <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r use (because <strong>the</strong>y do enter <strong>in</strong>to marg<strong>in</strong>al cost),<strong>the</strong>n consumers may choose to employ <strong>the</strong>se factors <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> use <strong>in</strong> which<strong>the</strong>y are free, even though <strong>the</strong>y would <strong>in</strong> fact prefer to employ <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>some o<strong>the</strong>r way. If <strong>the</strong> Hotell<strong>in</strong>g-Lerner solution were adopted, <strong>the</strong>rewould be only one way out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> difficulty. at would be for <strong>the</strong> stateto decide whe<strong>the</strong>r or not each consumer should be supplied with <strong>the</strong>particular good <strong>in</strong> question. is would be done by estimat<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>ror not each consumer would be will<strong>in</strong>g to pay <strong>the</strong> full cost <strong>of</strong> supply<strong>in</strong>ghim if he were called upon to do so. Coase fur<strong>the</strong>r argues that nogovernment could estimate <strong>in</strong>dividual dem<strong>and</strong>s accurately; that if all pric<strong>in</strong>gwere on a marg<strong>in</strong>al-cost basis, <strong>the</strong>re would be less <strong>in</strong>formation availableby which such an estimate could be made; <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>centive


Chapter : e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> 79to correct forecast<strong>in</strong>g would suffer if <strong>the</strong>re were no subsequent markettest <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r such estimates <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual dem<strong>and</strong> were corrector not.Coase’s second objection to Hotell<strong>in</strong>g-Lerner pric<strong>in</strong>g is that it wouldredistribute <strong>in</strong>come <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> patrons <strong>of</strong> decreas<strong>in</strong>g-cost <strong>in</strong>dustries. It isnot easy to imag<strong>in</strong>e how such a redistribution might be considered ethicallydesirable. For <strong>in</strong>stance, Harry Norris (1947, pp. 54–62) imag<strong>in</strong>es twocountries which are identical except that one is lighted by a constant-costgas <strong>in</strong>dustry <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r is lighted by a decreas<strong>in</strong>g-cost electric <strong>in</strong>dustry.In each country ten percent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> taxpayers are backwoodsmen liv<strong>in</strong>gbeyond <strong>the</strong> range <strong>of</strong> utility service. In <strong>the</strong> gas-lit country, each householdpays for its light<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> full. But accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> Hotell<strong>in</strong>g-Lernersolution, <strong>the</strong> backwoods taxpayers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> electric country should subsidize<strong>the</strong> light<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> city dwellers. Yet this arrangement could hardlybe defended on ethical grounds.A third objection to Hotell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Lerner is that <strong>the</strong> taxation necessaryto raise subsidy money would have <strong>the</strong> familiar dis<strong>in</strong>centive effectswhere imposed.A fourth set <strong>of</strong> objections to marg<strong>in</strong>al-cost pric<strong>in</strong>g is mentioned,strangely enough, by a champion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Hotell<strong>in</strong>g-Lerner solution <strong>and</strong>opponent <strong>of</strong> Coase’s proposals. William Vickrey (1948, pp. 218–238) po<strong>in</strong>tsout that <strong>in</strong> some <strong>in</strong>stances <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> Hotell<strong>in</strong>g-Lerner pric<strong>in</strong>gmight <strong>in</strong>volve serious political <strong>and</strong> sociological consequences. Vickreymay have <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> dangers <strong>of</strong> any new excuse for raids on <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates Treasury.R.H. Coase (1946, pp. 169–182, esp. pp. 173ff.) seeks to reconcile <strong>the</strong>implications <strong>of</strong> his own <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Hotell<strong>in</strong>g-Lerner reason<strong>in</strong>g by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>geniousdevice <strong>of</strong> multi-part pric<strong>in</strong>g. Patrons <strong>of</strong> decreas<strong>in</strong>g-cost <strong>in</strong>dustriesare charged a lump sum or series <strong>of</strong> lump sums which are supposed tocover <strong>in</strong>tra-marg<strong>in</strong>al costs. Each consumer is <strong>the</strong>n allowed to obta<strong>in</strong> additionalunits <strong>of</strong> product at <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al cost. e advantage <strong>of</strong> multi-partpric<strong>in</strong>g is that consumers can be asked to pay a total amount which is equalto <strong>the</strong> total cost. erefore, it is possible to discover whe<strong>the</strong>r consumersvalue <strong>the</strong> total supply at least <strong>the</strong> total cost <strong>of</strong> supply<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m. (Under apric<strong>in</strong>g system, whe<strong>the</strong>r consumers are will<strong>in</strong>g to pay an amount equalto total cost can be discovered only by actually ask<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m to pay thisamount.) At <strong>the</strong> same time, additional units are supplied at additionalcost, <strong>and</strong> so <strong>the</strong> right output can be obta<strong>in</strong>ed; that is, <strong>the</strong> Lerner allocation<strong>of</strong> factors can be achieved.


80 Part I: EconomicsWilliam Vickrey (1948, pp. 218–238) raises a number <strong>of</strong> practical objectionsto multi-part pric<strong>in</strong>g. But—to put it mildly—a number <strong>of</strong> practicalobjections could be leveled aga<strong>in</strong>st Hotell<strong>in</strong>g-Lerner pric<strong>in</strong>g also. Insummary, I believe that Coase’s multi-part pric<strong>in</strong>g scheme rema<strong>in</strong>s at leastas <strong>in</strong>tellectually respectable as marg<strong>in</strong>al-cost pric<strong>in</strong>g.Writers who were unhappy about <strong>the</strong> prospect <strong>of</strong> actually hav<strong>in</strong>g tosolve millions <strong>of</strong> simultaneous equations formulated <strong>the</strong> so-called “competitive”or “trial-<strong>and</strong>-error” solution to <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> socialist resourceallocation. ere is a large measure <strong>of</strong> agreement <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideas <strong>of</strong> OskarLange <strong>and</strong> Fred W. Taylor (1938), A.C. Pigou (1937), R.L. Hall (1937),H.D. Dick<strong>in</strong>son (1939), <strong>and</strong> Burnham P. Beckwith (1949).Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> “competitive solution,” households have freedom <strong>of</strong>choice <strong>in</strong> regard to jobs <strong>and</strong> consumer goods. Households receive <strong>and</strong>spend actual cash. e central authority <strong>in</strong>structs <strong>the</strong> manager <strong>of</strong> eachproduction unit to operate <strong>in</strong> accord with two basic rules. For any givenscale <strong>of</strong> output, he must comb<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> factors <strong>of</strong> production <strong>in</strong> such a wayas, at <strong>the</strong> established prices, to m<strong>in</strong>imize average cost per unit <strong>of</strong> output.Secondly, he must fix output so that marg<strong>in</strong>al cost <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> product equalsits established price.e question arises: How do <strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> consumer goods, <strong>in</strong>termediategoods, <strong>and</strong> productive resources get “established”? Answer: <strong>the</strong> centralauthority does it. (Incidentally, <strong>the</strong> prices for all th<strong>in</strong>gs except labor <strong>and</strong>consumer goods need not be market prices; <strong>the</strong>y can be mere account<strong>in</strong>gprices.) e central authority decrees a price for each good. If <strong>the</strong> managers<strong>of</strong> productive units follow <strong>the</strong> rules, <strong>the</strong>y will—like entrepreneursunder perfect competition—regard <strong>the</strong> prices as parameters. Of course,<strong>the</strong> prices decreed by <strong>the</strong> central authority will not be correct at first. erewill be shortages <strong>of</strong> some th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> surpluses <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. Consequently,<strong>the</strong> authority will raise <strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> excess dem<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> lower<strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> excess supply. By constant experiment<strong>in</strong>g—by trial<strong>and</strong>-error—<strong>the</strong>central authority is supposed to make everyth<strong>in</strong>g work outall right.Similarly, <strong>the</strong> central authority could make capital freely available to<strong>the</strong> socialist enterprises at an established rate <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest. Interest wouldbe reckoned among <strong>the</strong> elements <strong>in</strong> cost. In many socialist bluepr<strong>in</strong>ts,<strong>the</strong> central authority would arbitrarily fix <strong>the</strong> total amount <strong>of</strong> liquid capitalavailable. In any case, <strong>the</strong> authority could conceivably equate <strong>the</strong>dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> supply <strong>of</strong> capital by manipulat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate, just as itwould manipulate o<strong>the</strong>r prices. Incidentally, Enrico Barone had already


Chapter : e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> 81mentioned <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate by trial <strong>and</strong> error <strong>in</strong> hisessay <strong>of</strong> 1908 (pp. 268–269).e ma<strong>in</strong> feature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Competitive Solution, <strong>the</strong>n, is that someBoard, ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> market, adjusts prices to br<strong>in</strong>g supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>to l<strong>in</strong>e.Several questions about this Lange-Taylor “solution” are obvious:. How would <strong>the</strong> Board force managers to obey <strong>the</strong> “rules”? For<strong>in</strong>stance, enterprises that were large <strong>in</strong> relation to <strong>the</strong>ir market mightpr<strong>of</strong>it by tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to account <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir actions on <strong>the</strong> Board’sprice-sett<strong>in</strong>g decisions. e managers might restrict output <strong>in</strong> much <strong>the</strong>same way as monopolists do under capitalism. Even assum<strong>in</strong>g away allquestions <strong>of</strong> monopolistic motives, <strong>the</strong>re still rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong>whe<strong>the</strong>r managers should be allowed to act upon <strong>the</strong>ir anticipations <strong>of</strong>price changes by <strong>the</strong> Board.. How would <strong>the</strong> Board judge <strong>the</strong> efficiency <strong>of</strong> managers?Of course, <strong>in</strong> cop<strong>in</strong>g with those two difficulties, <strong>the</strong> Board might look<strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> books <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual production units. But if carried to anylength, this practice would conflict with <strong>the</strong> essential aim <strong>of</strong> decentraliz<strong>in</strong>gdecisionmak<strong>in</strong>g.. How would <strong>the</strong> Lange-Taylor solution apply to <strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> commoditiesthat cannot be st<strong>and</strong>ardized, such as large units <strong>of</strong> capital equipmentwhich must be made to order? In all such cases <strong>the</strong>re would be nobasis for centralized fix<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> prices so as “to equalize dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> supply.”Socialist writers simply ignore <strong>the</strong> various complications that wouldarise.. If <strong>the</strong> price-sett<strong>in</strong>g authority perceives, for example, that <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>for rubber exceeds <strong>the</strong> supply, how is it to know whe<strong>the</strong>r this <strong>in</strong>dicatestoo low a price for rubber or too high a price for tires? If <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>for sheet alum<strong>in</strong>um is less than <strong>the</strong> supply, is <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> alum<strong>in</strong>um toohigh, or is <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> plywood too low? If <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for gasol<strong>in</strong>e fallsshort <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> supply, is this due to too high a price for gasol<strong>in</strong>e or too higha price for automobiles? e po<strong>in</strong>t is that <strong>the</strong> central authority would haveto work with Walrasian, <strong>and</strong> not merely Marshallian supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>functions. e authority could not change a s<strong>in</strong>gle price without chang<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> equilibrium prices <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r goods. Trial-<strong>and</strong>-error would not besimply a matter <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g particular prices higher or lower; it would bea problem <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g at least many millions <strong>of</strong> possible patterns <strong>of</strong> price<strong>in</strong>creases or decreases. And for each <strong>in</strong>crease or decrease <strong>the</strong>re would be<strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> how much.


82 Part I: EconomicsFur<strong>the</strong>rmore, cont<strong>in</strong>ual shifts <strong>and</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> functions<strong>the</strong>mselves would blur <strong>the</strong> central authority’s view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong>its trials-<strong>and</strong>-errors.Still fur<strong>the</strong>r comments on Lange-Taylor socialism are <strong>in</strong> order. Likesome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> forego<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>ts, <strong>the</strong>y are stated most cogently <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Hayek (1948, chaps. IX <strong>and</strong> IV). For <strong>in</strong>stance, by <strong>the</strong> verynature <strong>of</strong> adm<strong>in</strong>istrative decisions, such price changes as were made wouldoccur later than if <strong>the</strong> prices were determ<strong>in</strong>ed on a free market. Secondly,<strong>the</strong> central price authority would differentiate much less than a free marketwould between <strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> commodities accord<strong>in</strong>g to differences <strong>of</strong>quality <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> circumstances <strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong> place. is means that managers<strong>of</strong> production would have no <strong>in</strong>ducement, <strong>and</strong> even no real possibility, tomake use <strong>of</strong> special opportunities, special barga<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong> little advantages<strong>of</strong>fered by special temporary or local conditions. Society could notmake full use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> dispersed knowledge that cannot be collected<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> statistics, for example, knowledge <strong>of</strong> vacant space <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>hold <strong>of</strong> a tramp steamer about to sail, knowledge <strong>of</strong> a mach<strong>in</strong>e that is notbe<strong>in</strong>g fully used, knowledge <strong>of</strong> a particular person’s skill that might bebetter utilized.Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong>orists <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Lange-Taylor school err <strong>in</strong> regard<strong>in</strong>gcost curves as “given.” One function <strong>of</strong> capitalist price competition isto reduce costs to a m<strong>in</strong>imum. Under socialism, <strong>the</strong> new man with <strong>the</strong>new idea is not able to enter an <strong>in</strong>dustry <strong>and</strong> undercut old producersunless <strong>the</strong> central authority approves his projects und provides him withcapital.Fur<strong>the</strong>r comments on Lange-Taylor socialism apply to an even moredecentralized type <strong>of</strong> socialism as well. I will save <strong>the</strong>se comments until<strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> that o<strong>the</strong>r type.Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Pigou, for one, recognizes <strong>the</strong> difficulties that would besetany attempt to apply his Competitive Solution to <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> socialism.He says: “Evidently ... <strong>the</strong> practical difficulty <strong>of</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g such a processwill be enormous.... Far-reach<strong>in</strong>g errors are almost <strong>in</strong>evitable.” Never<strong>the</strong>less,Pigou congratulates himself on <strong>the</strong> fact that his “analysis shows that<strong>the</strong> allocation problem is soluble <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple” (1937, p. 115). is br<strong>in</strong>gsme to remark that I cannot underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> common charge that critics<strong>of</strong> socialism base <strong>the</strong>ir case on “merely practical” objections. As LionelRobb<strong>in</strong>s observes, “it is one th<strong>in</strong>g to sketch <strong>the</strong> requirements <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> plan.It is ano<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>g to conceive <strong>of</strong> its execution” (1934, p. 150). Of course<strong>the</strong> allocation problem is soluble <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. But it is just as possible, <strong>in</strong>


Chapter : e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> 83pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, to breed w<strong>in</strong>ged elephants. Anyone who doubts this can f<strong>in</strong>d outhow from me later.Some socialist writers, notably Maurice Dobb, f<strong>in</strong>d it hard to take seriously<strong>the</strong> suggestion that plant managers should “play an elaborate game<strong>of</strong> bidd<strong>in</strong>g for capital on a market, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> transmitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation(about productivities) direct to some plann<strong>in</strong>g authority” (1946, p. 302).Dobb <strong>and</strong> his school take refuge <strong>in</strong> a large measure <strong>of</strong> central plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> Soviet type. Paul Sweezy, also, favors comprehensive plann<strong>in</strong>g; <strong>in</strong>deed,he agrees with H.D. Dick<strong>in</strong>son that centralization is all but <strong>in</strong>evitableunder socialism. Yet Sweezy (1949, pp. 232–239) cites Lange’s On <strong>the</strong> Economiceory <strong>of</strong> Socialism “as hav<strong>in</strong>g f<strong>in</strong>ally removed any doubts about <strong>the</strong>capacity <strong>of</strong> socialism to utilize resources rationally,” <strong>and</strong> he seems not torealize <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>consistency <strong>of</strong> his own position.S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> centralized-plann<strong>in</strong>g approach is unquestionably vulnerableto <strong>the</strong> criticisms advanced long ago by Mises, I f<strong>in</strong>d it a peculiarly un<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gform <strong>of</strong> socialism. erefore, let’s go on to an extremely decentralizedform <strong>of</strong> socialism.Abba Lerner, <strong>in</strong> e Economics <strong>of</strong> Control (1947), <strong>and</strong> Lerner <strong>and</strong> OskarLange, <strong>in</strong> a pamphlet published <strong>in</strong> 1944, advocate “free enterprise.” By this,Lerner <strong>and</strong> Lange mean that both government <strong>and</strong> private entrepreneursshould be free to enter any l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess not reserved to <strong>the</strong> government.Perhaps this arrangement would be <strong>the</strong> famous “mixed economy”ra<strong>the</strong>r than full-blown socialism. Franco Modigliani (1947, pp. 441–514)advocates a decentralized socialism <strong>in</strong> a lengthy article published <strong>in</strong> 1947,though he does not go nearly as far towards so-called “free enterprise” asdo Lerner <strong>and</strong> Lange.Lerner <strong>and</strong> Lange recognize thatwhat <strong>the</strong> manager <strong>of</strong> every factory needs is some simple <strong>in</strong>dication<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> usefulness for alternative production <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> goods tha<strong>the</strong> might use. Such an <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> alternative productivity <strong>of</strong>each factor is provided by its price. For this we must have marketsfor <strong>the</strong> factors <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> price equates <strong>the</strong> supply to <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>,with appropriate rules govern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> factors <strong>of</strong> productionby <strong>the</strong> various managers <strong>in</strong> charge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> public enterprises. (1944,p. 18)Incidentally, I cannot help but <strong>in</strong>terpret that quotation from two <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> most competent socialist writers as anyth<strong>in</strong>g less than an outrightconcession <strong>of</strong> at least two-thirds <strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Mises’s orig<strong>in</strong>al argument.


84 Part I: EconomicsIt is also noteworthy that Lange has ab<strong>and</strong>oned <strong>the</strong> position he held <strong>in</strong>On <strong>the</strong> Economic eory <strong>of</strong> Socialism.Of <strong>the</strong> various <strong>in</strong>structions which Lerner, Lange, <strong>and</strong> Modiglianiaddress to <strong>the</strong> managers <strong>of</strong> production, <strong>the</strong> most important is our oldfriend: equate marg<strong>in</strong>al cost <strong>and</strong> price. But <strong>the</strong> central plann<strong>in</strong>g boardnow seems to have lost its job <strong>of</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>g prices by trial <strong>and</strong> error.In e Economics <strong>of</strong> Control, Lerner writes:In each market, whe<strong>the</strong>r for factors or for products, prices are raisedwhenever <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for any product or factor is greater than <strong>the</strong> supply<strong>and</strong> lowered when <strong>the</strong> supply is greater than <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> until a set <strong>of</strong>prices is reached <strong>in</strong> which each dem<strong>and</strong> is equal to <strong>the</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>gsupply. (p. 63)It is not clear who is to do <strong>the</strong> rais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> lower<strong>in</strong>g. Lerner seems toleave <strong>the</strong> task to a market ra<strong>the</strong>r than to a Board. But if prices are notparameters ei<strong>the</strong>r established by atomistic competition or by some Board,<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> rule “equate marg<strong>in</strong>al cost <strong>and</strong> price” is not unambiguous.Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Morgner has suggested to me that perhaps <strong>the</strong> idea is tohave each manager operate at <strong>the</strong> output <strong>and</strong> sell at <strong>the</strong> price <strong>in</strong>dicatedby <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tersection <strong>of</strong> his average revenue <strong>and</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al cost curves. Someremarks by Paul A. Samuelson suggest that this <strong>in</strong>terpretation may becorrect:<strong>the</strong> decentralized operators <strong>in</strong> a planned society should refra<strong>in</strong> from aliteral ap<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> atomistic, passive, parametric price behavior. Instead <strong>of</strong>pretend<strong>in</strong>g that dem<strong>and</strong> curves are <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely elastic when <strong>the</strong>y are not,<strong>the</strong> correct shape <strong>of</strong> that curve is to be taken <strong>in</strong>to account. is doesnot mean that <strong>the</strong> decentralized operators should take account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<strong>in</strong>fluence on price as a monopolist would. (1948, p. 232)Assum<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> equat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al cost <strong>and</strong> average revenue iswhat Lerner, Lange, <strong>and</strong> Modigliani have <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, let’s see how this systemwould work:. Barr<strong>in</strong>g extreme co<strong>in</strong>cidences, different enterprises would be try<strong>in</strong>gto charge different prices for <strong>the</strong> same product. ere is no reason forassum<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al-cost-average-revenue <strong>in</strong>tersections <strong>of</strong> differententerprises would be at <strong>the</strong> same price.. If managers receive prestige, power, or bonuses accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>prosperity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir enterprises, <strong>the</strong>y would have an <strong>in</strong>centive to take


Chapter : e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> 85advantage <strong>of</strong> imperfect competition by overcharg<strong>in</strong>g buyers <strong>and</strong> underpay<strong>in</strong>gsuppliers. If <strong>the</strong> central authority tried to enforce rigorous adherenceto <strong>the</strong> “rules,” <strong>the</strong>re would have to be duplication <strong>of</strong> management <strong>and</strong> soperhaps centralized plann<strong>in</strong>g after all.. Managers might not know <strong>the</strong>ir own marg<strong>in</strong>al cost curves, even ifdeterm<strong>in</strong>ate. Most important, managers almost certa<strong>in</strong>ly could not know<strong>the</strong>ir average revenue curves for <strong>the</strong> simple reason that such curves wouldnot exist as <strong>in</strong>dependent entities. To be specific, <strong>the</strong> socialized enterpriseswould almost certa<strong>in</strong>ly be oligopolies, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> outst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g characteristic<strong>of</strong> oligopoly is absence <strong>of</strong> any determ<strong>in</strong>ate average revenue curve. Noticethat I am not talk<strong>in</strong>g about “mere practical difficulties” <strong>of</strong> measurement.My po<strong>in</strong>t is that nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> most powerful statistical techniques nor <strong>the</strong>fact <strong>of</strong> government ownership could provide an oligopolistic firm withsometh<strong>in</strong>g nonexistent, that is, with a determ<strong>in</strong>ate average revenue curve.us it appears that <strong>the</strong> Lerner-Lange-Modigliani rules do not yieldany determ<strong>in</strong>ate price-output situation at all. e socialist economy wouldsimply have to wallow <strong>in</strong> chaos.Several observations apply both to Lange-Taylor socialism <strong>and</strong> toLerner-Lange-Modigliani socialism:. e adoption <strong>of</strong> competition or quasi-competition means giv<strong>in</strong>g upwhatever advantages centralized plann<strong>in</strong>g might afford (if those advantageswere considered worth <strong>the</strong> price <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> grave disadvantages).For example, competitive socialism has no sure cure for <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle.Dick<strong>in</strong>son, Modigliani, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs who discuss <strong>the</strong> problem p<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir faithon what are essentially <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> Keynesian fiscal policies that capitalismcould adopt. But Beckwith has <strong>the</strong> most elegantly simple device for gett<strong>in</strong>grid <strong>of</strong> unemployment: just cut wage rates to whatever extent may benecessary. With regard to wages, Dick<strong>in</strong>son <strong>and</strong> Beckwith declare <strong>the</strong>mselvesfor piece-rates <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r trapp<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> Taylorism. Incidentally,few socialist price-<strong>the</strong>orists try to pretend that <strong>the</strong>ir systems hold anyplace for unionism as we know it today. To my knowledge, only Lerner<strong>and</strong> Lange cannot bear to stop mouth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> shibboleths <strong>of</strong> contemporaryunionism.. It is questionable whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> diligence <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> decisions <strong>of</strong> socialistmanagers <strong>of</strong> production would be governed by suitable <strong>in</strong>centives. AsMises po<strong>in</strong>ts out, <strong>the</strong> capitalist entrepreneurdoes not just <strong>in</strong>vest his capital <strong>in</strong> those undertak<strong>in</strong>gs which <strong>of</strong>fer high<strong>in</strong>terest or high pr<strong>of</strong>it; he attempts ra<strong>the</strong>r to strike a balance between hisdesire for pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>and</strong> his estimate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> risk <strong>of</strong> loss. He must exercise


86 Part I: Economicsforesight. If he does not do so <strong>the</strong>n he suffers losses—losses that br<strong>in</strong>git about that his disposition over <strong>the</strong> factors <strong>of</strong> production is transferredto <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs who know better how to weigh <strong>the</strong> risks <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>prospects <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess speculation.Capitalists <strong>and</strong> speculators cannot be expected to act as mere agents<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> community, for<strong>the</strong> function which capitalists <strong>and</strong> speculators perform under Capitalism,namely direct<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> capital goods <strong>in</strong>to that direction <strong>in</strong>which <strong>the</strong>y best serve <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> consumer, is only performedbecause <strong>the</strong>y are under <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>centive to preserve <strong>the</strong>ir property <strong>and</strong> tomake pr<strong>of</strong>its. (1922/1981, pp. 140–141)Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong>re is no reason to th<strong>in</strong>k that <strong>the</strong> recklessness <strong>of</strong> somesocialist managers would compensate for <strong>the</strong> over-cautiousness <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs.Two wrongs don’t make a right.. As I have already implied, <strong>the</strong> schemes <strong>of</strong> price-<strong>the</strong>ory socialistshave an extreme static bias. We may well jo<strong>in</strong> with Pr<strong>of</strong>essors Hayek,Mises, <strong>and</strong> Robb<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> ask<strong>in</strong>g: What is to be <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent bus<strong>in</strong>essunit? Who is to be <strong>the</strong> manager? What resources are to be entrusted tohim? How is his success or failure to be tested? On what pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is<strong>the</strong> control <strong>of</strong> productive facilities to be transferred from one managerto ano<strong>the</strong>r (Hayek 1948, esp. pp. 172, 196–197)? e idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>struct<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> controllers <strong>of</strong> various <strong>in</strong>dustrial units to act as if <strong>the</strong>y were capitalistentrepreneurs ignores <strong>the</strong> fundamental problem <strong>of</strong> a dynamic economy,<strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> decid<strong>in</strong>g what resources should be risked <strong>in</strong> what venturesunder <strong>the</strong> control <strong>of</strong> what men. As Robb<strong>in</strong>s says,For competition to be free <strong>the</strong> entrepreneur must be at liberty to withdrawhis capital altoge<strong>the</strong>r from one l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> production, sell his plant <strong>and</strong> hisstocks <strong>and</strong> go <strong>in</strong>to o<strong>the</strong>r l<strong>in</strong>es. He must be at liberty to break up <strong>the</strong>adm<strong>in</strong>istrative unit. It is difficult to see how liberty <strong>of</strong> this sort, whichis necessary if <strong>the</strong> market is to be <strong>the</strong> register <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> vary<strong>in</strong>g pulls <strong>of</strong>all <strong>the</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> data, is compatible with <strong>the</strong> requirements <strong>of</strong> asociety whose raison d’etre is ownership <strong>and</strong> control at <strong>the</strong> centre. (1934,pp. 153–154)Mises remarks that when socialist <strong>the</strong>orists assume stationary conditions,<strong>the</strong> essential function <strong>of</strong> economic calculation has by hypo<strong>the</strong>sisalready been performed (1949, pp. 137ff.).R.L. Hall worries about how anyone could tell whe<strong>the</strong>r a socialistmonopoly were as efficient as it might be. In Hall’s words,


Chapter : e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> 87If a world champion has no one aga<strong>in</strong>st which to measure himself, howcan he tell <strong>of</strong> what he is capable? A runner can run aga<strong>in</strong>st himself bymeans <strong>of</strong> a stop-watch: will a state concern be prepared to make cont<strong>in</strong>uousefforts to reduce its own costs? If it does not do so, no one else can.In a capitalist state Nemesis is always wait<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> lethargic monopoly,as <strong>the</strong> calamity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal combustion eng<strong>in</strong>e fell upon <strong>the</strong> railways.But it is doubtful whe<strong>the</strong>r anyone <strong>in</strong> a collectivist state would have anyhope <strong>of</strong> start<strong>in</strong>g a rival department. (1937, pp. 138–139). Few bluepr<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> socialism make much specific provisions foreconomic development. Even Franco Modigliani’s meager remarks areunusual <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature (1947, pp. 463–465). Modigliani faces squarely <strong>the</strong>disadvantage that decisions about new products would have to be madeby an adm<strong>in</strong>istrative body. He perceives <strong>the</strong> tw<strong>in</strong> dangers <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>ertia due tolack <strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>in</strong>centive <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> recklessness due to lack <strong>of</strong> a loss-penalty.(Modigliani feels that <strong>the</strong> tendency toward <strong>in</strong>ertia is probably more characteristic<strong>of</strong> bureaucracy.) To avoid <strong>the</strong>se dangers, Modigliani proposesa Research Commission to decide on new big <strong>in</strong>vestments <strong>and</strong> on newproducts requir<strong>in</strong>g new plants. e Research Commission <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> various<strong>in</strong>dustrial managers are to share <strong>the</strong> responsibility for mere productmodifications, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> managers are to receive bonuses for successful <strong>in</strong>novations.Doubts about <strong>the</strong> progressiveness <strong>of</strong> socialism do not rest on any supposedlack <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives for scientists. As Brutzkus writes,Scientific discoveries, it is true, are not made out <strong>of</strong> a desire for pr<strong>of</strong>itbut <strong>in</strong> answer to humanity’s unquenchable search for truth. In <strong>the</strong> case<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>ventions <strong>the</strong> scientific <strong>in</strong>terest recedes <strong>in</strong> favour <strong>of</strong> practical motives.But nei<strong>the</strong>r scientists nor even <strong>in</strong>ventors are directly responsible for economicprogress; it is <strong>the</strong> organizers <strong>and</strong> practical men who stimulatedevelopment.Even suppos<strong>in</strong>g ... that <strong>the</strong> highest posts were filled <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> best possiblemanner, <strong>the</strong>re would still rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> danger that each <strong>in</strong>novation couldonly be tested <strong>in</strong> a def<strong>in</strong>ite place....If ... <strong>the</strong> socialist organization succeeded <strong>in</strong> assum<strong>in</strong>g stable forms itwould be dist<strong>in</strong>guished by immense <strong>in</strong>dolence <strong>and</strong> conservatism. It would<strong>of</strong>fer noth<strong>in</strong>g which could be compared to <strong>the</strong> unceas<strong>in</strong>g movement <strong>of</strong>economic life under capitalism. (1935, pp. 67–69)In his essay On Liberty, John Stuart Mill uses his arguments for freedom<strong>of</strong> expression as a case for freedom <strong>of</strong> enterprise:


88 Part I: Economicse management <strong>of</strong> purely local bus<strong>in</strong>ess by <strong>the</strong> localities, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>great enterprises <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dustry by <strong>the</strong> union <strong>of</strong> those who voluntarily supply<strong>the</strong> pecuniary means, is fur<strong>the</strong>r recommended by all <strong>the</strong> advantageswhich have been set forth <strong>in</strong> this Essay as belong<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>dividuality <strong>of</strong>development, <strong>and</strong> diversity <strong>of</strong> modes <strong>of</strong> action. Government operationstend to be everywhere alike. With <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>and</strong> voluntary associations,on <strong>the</strong> contrary, <strong>the</strong>re are varied experiments, <strong>and</strong> endless diversity <strong>of</strong>experience. (1859/1929, p. 131)Modigliani’s Research Commission would hardly be an adequate substitutefor Mill’s “diversity <strong>of</strong> modes <strong>of</strong> action,” even if it were staffedentirely by scientific <strong>and</strong> technical experts. e very essence <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>novationis that it embodies ideas divergent from prevail<strong>in</strong>g thought. Progresscannot be completely plotted <strong>and</strong> bluepr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> advance; that is why it isprogress. Often discovery can be identified only <strong>in</strong> retrospect (cf. Harper1949, pp. 72–76). If <strong>the</strong> government Research Commission decided not to“waste” resources on some new idea, it would be ruled out; that’s all. But<strong>in</strong> a competitive enterprise system, an idea discarded by n<strong>in</strong>ety-n<strong>in</strong>e companiesstill has a chance with a hundredth company. And no company canafford to be too rash <strong>in</strong> reject<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>novations, for fear that its competitorswill “get <strong>the</strong> jump” on it. In a competitive system, a research worker wh<strong>of</strong>eels frustrated <strong>in</strong> one job can take his ideas to ano<strong>the</strong>r employer. Undersocialism th<strong>in</strong>gs would be different.With regard to <strong>in</strong>vention, R.L. Hall writes:<strong>the</strong>re does not seem to be any criterion by which <strong>the</strong> Socialist state c<strong>and</strong>ecide <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> resources which it is proper to spend: so that <strong>the</strong>ycannot rationally create a pr<strong>of</strong>ession <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>ventors. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, if<strong>the</strong>se matters are left to <strong>the</strong> chance on which <strong>the</strong>y depend <strong>the</strong> path <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>novator will be even harder than it is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> capitalist state. In <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>terests <strong>of</strong> economy it is necessary to discourage cranks; but it is probablethat <strong>the</strong> leaders <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dustry will consider that all <strong>in</strong>novators are cranks.In <strong>the</strong> capitalist state <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ventor is free to devote any resources whichhe <strong>in</strong>herits, or can earn or can wheedle from patrons, to his researches.In a socialist state he will get noth<strong>in</strong>g which he does not earn <strong>and</strong> hemay f<strong>in</strong>d himself <strong>in</strong> a labour camp if he neglects his work. e progress<strong>of</strong> spontaneous <strong>in</strong>vention may well be slowed unless care is devoted topreserv<strong>in</strong>g a receptive frame <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> higher <strong>of</strong>ficials. But if <strong>the</strong>yare too receptive <strong>the</strong>re may be dissipation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> national resources <strong>in</strong>gr<strong>and</strong>iose projections doomed to failure. It is difficult to follow a middlecourse when no one knows where <strong>the</strong> middle is: <strong>the</strong> socialist state will


Chapter : e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> 89have no certa<strong>in</strong>ty, nor can any o<strong>the</strong>r form <strong>of</strong> organization give it. (1937,pp. 192–193)In summary, <strong>in</strong>novations start out <strong>in</strong> a progressive economy as <strong>the</strong>whim <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> few <strong>and</strong> are adopted only later by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ert masses. Innovationwould be slowed <strong>in</strong> an economy which did not allow <strong>the</strong> widest possiblescope for variety, whims, even eccentricities.It may be objected that <strong>the</strong> forego<strong>in</strong>g considerations are political objectionsto socialism, but do not constitute an economic argument. I do notth<strong>in</strong>k this is so. Whe<strong>the</strong>r an economic system is efficient or not is verylargely a matter <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r it is progressive or not. e mere fact thatwe cannot h<strong>and</strong>le questions <strong>of</strong> economic development by <strong>the</strong> precise <strong>and</strong>elegant techniques <strong>of</strong> price <strong>the</strong>ory does not mean that such questions falloutside <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>of</strong> economics.e political case aga<strong>in</strong>st socialism is quite different. It would emphasize,among o<strong>the</strong>r matters, <strong>the</strong> danger that pressure groups could sabotageprogress. Suppose, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that <strong>the</strong> automobile had not yet been<strong>in</strong>vented, but that some men had ideas for develop<strong>in</strong>g “horseless carriages.”Now which pressure group would have <strong>the</strong> ear <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> government ResearchCommission—<strong>the</strong> buggy makers, with <strong>the</strong>ir thous<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> votes, or <strong>the</strong>would-be automobile makers, with <strong>the</strong>ir mere h<strong>and</strong>ful <strong>of</strong> votes?is paper does not h<strong>and</strong>le <strong>the</strong> political case aga<strong>in</strong>st socialism or <strong>the</strong>question <strong>of</strong> freedom or serfdom under socialism. I’ll leave <strong>the</strong>se matters fordiscussion afterward. But I do want to record my conviction that political<strong>and</strong> cultural considerations about socialism rival <strong>in</strong> importance <strong>the</strong> purelyeconomic considerations. It does seem futile to worry about whe<strong>the</strong>r asocialist government could manage <strong>the</strong> economy efficiently <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> accordwith people’s wishes, when <strong>the</strong> more immediate question is whe<strong>the</strong>r powerfulrulers could at all times be forced to want to rule <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>of</strong>all <strong>the</strong> people.It seems to me that <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> socialist literature is a history <strong>of</strong>cont<strong>in</strong>ual attempts to get rid <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> difficulties <strong>in</strong> socialist bluepr<strong>in</strong>ts. Andas <strong>the</strong>se difficulties are elim<strong>in</strong>ated, socialism comes to look more <strong>and</strong> morelike competitive enterprise. erefore, it is not without some justificationthat Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Mises, with his characteristic dogmatism, now claims f<strong>in</strong>alvictory <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> debate over <strong>the</strong> efficiency <strong>of</strong> socialism. In his latest bookMises writes:It is ... noth<strong>in</strong>g short <strong>of</strong> a full acknowledgment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> correctness <strong>and</strong>irrefutability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economists’ analysis <strong>and</strong> devastat<strong>in</strong>g critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>


90 Part I: Economicssocialists’ plans that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual leaders <strong>of</strong> socialism are now busydesign<strong>in</strong>g schemes for a socialist system <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> market, marketprices for <strong>the</strong> factors <strong>of</strong> production, <strong>and</strong> catallactic competition are to bepreserved. e overwhelm<strong>in</strong>gly rapid triumph <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> demonstration thatno economic calculation is possible under a socialist system is withoutprecedent <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> human thought. e socialists canno<strong>the</strong>lp admitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir crush<strong>in</strong>g f<strong>in</strong>al defeat. ey no longer claim thatsocialism is matchlessly superior to capitalism because it brushes awaymarkets, market prices, <strong>and</strong> competition. On <strong>the</strong> contrary. ey are noweager to justify socialism by po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out that it is possible to preserve<strong>the</strong>se <strong>in</strong>stitutions even under socialism. ey are draft<strong>in</strong>g outl<strong>in</strong>es for asocialism <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>re are prices <strong>and</strong> competition.What <strong>the</strong>se neosocialists suggest is really paradoxical. ey want to abolishprivate control <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> means <strong>of</strong> production, market exchange, marketprices, <strong>and</strong> competition. But at <strong>the</strong> same time <strong>the</strong>y want to organize<strong>the</strong> socialist Utopia <strong>in</strong> such a way that people could act as if <strong>the</strong>seth<strong>in</strong>gs were still present. ey want people to play market as childrenplay war, railroad, or school. ey do not comprehend how such childishplay differs from <strong>the</strong> real th<strong>in</strong>g it tries to imitate. (1949, pp. 702–703;footnote omitted)Perhaps <strong>the</strong> culm<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free-enterprise trend <strong>in</strong> socialist th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>gis James E. Meade’s Plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Price Mechanism (1948). Meadecalls himself a socialist, but his proposals amount to scarcely more thana program for <strong>the</strong> reconstruction <strong>of</strong> competitive capitalism, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g amoderate amount <strong>of</strong> government enterprise.e implication <strong>of</strong> my remarks should be clear by now. If economistsare bent on see<strong>in</strong>g socialism substituted for capitalism, <strong>the</strong>y should leave<strong>the</strong> task to <strong>the</strong>ir colleagues who are better qualified for <strong>the</strong> job, namely, to<strong>the</strong> lexicographers.Barone, Enrico. “e M<strong>in</strong>istry <strong>of</strong> Production <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Collectivist State.” 1908. InHayek 1935.Beckwith, Burnham P. e Economic eory <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong>. Stanford,Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1949.Brutzkus, Boris. Economic Plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Soviet Russia. London: Routledge & Sons,1935.


Chapter : e Debate about <strong>the</strong> Efficiency <strong>of</strong> a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> 91Coase, R.H. “e Marg<strong>in</strong>al Cost Controversy.” Economica (August 1946):169–182.Dick<strong>in</strong>son, H.D. e Economics <strong>of</strong> Socialism. London: Oxford University Press,1939.Dobb, Maurice. <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> <strong>and</strong> Capitalism. London: Routledge, 1946.Hall, R.L. e Economic System <strong>in</strong> a Socialist State. London: Macmillan, 1937.Harper, F.A. Liberty. Irv<strong>in</strong>gton-on-Hudson, N.Y.: Foundation for EconomicEducation, 1949.. Individualism <strong>and</strong> Economic Order. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1948.Hayek, F.A., ed. Collectivist Economic Plann<strong>in</strong>g. London: Routledge & KeganPaul, 1935.Hotell<strong>in</strong>g, Harold. “e General Welfare <strong>in</strong> Relation to Problems <strong>of</strong> Taxation<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Railway <strong>and</strong> Utility Rates.” Econometrica ( July 1938): 242–269.L<strong>and</strong>auer, Carl. eory <strong>of</strong> National Economic Plann<strong>in</strong>g. Berkeley <strong>and</strong> Los Angeles:University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1944.Lange, Oskar, <strong>and</strong> Fred M. Taylor. On <strong>the</strong> Economic eory <strong>of</strong> Socialism. Edited byBenjam<strong>in</strong> E. Lipp<strong>in</strong>cott. M<strong>in</strong>neapolis: University <strong>of</strong> M<strong>in</strong>nesota Press, 1938.Lerner, Abba. e Economics <strong>of</strong> Control. New York: Macmillan, 1947.Lerner, Abba, <strong>and</strong> Oskar Lange. e American Way <strong>of</strong> Bus<strong>in</strong>ess. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton:National Education Association, 1944.Marshall, Alfred. Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> Economics. 1890. 8 ed. London: Macmillan, 1920.Meade, James E. Plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Price Mechanism. London: Allen & Unw<strong>in</strong>,1948.Mill, John Stuart. On Liberty <strong>and</strong> O<strong>the</strong>r <strong>Essays</strong>. 1859. New York: Book League <strong>of</strong>America, 1929.Mises, Ludwig von. “Economic Calculation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Socialist Commonwealth.”1920. In Hayek 1935.. Human Action. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1949.. Socialism: An Economic <strong>and</strong> Sociological Analysis. 1922. Translated byJ. Kahane. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1981.


92 Part I: EconomicsModigliani, Franco. “L’organizzazione e la direzione della produzione <strong>in</strong>un’economia socialista.” Giornale degli Economisti (September/October 1947):441–514.Norris, Harry. “State Enterprise Price <strong>and</strong> Output Policy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong>Cost Imputation.” Economica (February 1947): 54–62.Pierson, Nicolaas G. “e Problem <strong>of</strong> Value <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Socialist Community.” 1902.In Collectivist Economic Plann<strong>in</strong>g, edited by F.A. Hayek. London: Routledge& Kegan Paul, 1935.Pigou, A.C. Socialism versus Capitalism. London: Macmillan, 1937.Robb<strong>in</strong>s, Lionel. e Great Depression. London: Macmillan, 1934.Samuelson, Paul A. Foundations <strong>of</strong> Economic Analysis. Cambridge, Mass.: HarvardUniversity Press, 1948.Sweezy, Paul. Socialism. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1949.Vickrey, William. “Some Objections to Marg<strong>in</strong>al-Cost Pric<strong>in</strong>g.” Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong><strong>Economy</strong> ( June 1948): 218–238.


e Debate overCalculation <strong>and</strong> Knowledge *Peter Boettke <strong>and</strong> Roger Koppl jo<strong>in</strong> a discussion launched by MurrayRothbard, Joseph Salerno, Jeffrey Herbener, Hans-Hermann Hoppe, <strong>and</strong>Jörg Guido Hülsmann. ose five contributors to <strong>the</strong> Review <strong>of</strong> AustrianEconomics seek, as <strong>the</strong>y say, to “dehomogenize” Ludwig von Mises <strong>and</strong>F.A. Hayek, differentiat<strong>in</strong>g between <strong>the</strong>ir doctr<strong>in</strong>es. Subtly or not so subtly,<strong>the</strong>se “chasmologists,” as Koppl calls <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>of</strong>ten disparage Hayek.In many writ<strong>in</strong>gs Hayek portrayed social <strong>in</strong>stitutions—notably, language,<strong>the</strong> common law, money, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> market economy itself—as “spontaneous”products <strong>of</strong> evolutionary processes. ough <strong>the</strong>se <strong>in</strong>stitutionswere unplanned as wholes, <strong>the</strong>y have benefited from a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> naturalselection tend<strong>in</strong>g to weed out <strong>the</strong>ir most <strong>in</strong>expedient forms, leav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irrelatively successful ones still <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> runn<strong>in</strong>g.Salerno (1990a) attacks <strong>the</strong>se aspects <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s work. Some <strong>of</strong>Hayek’s formulations, taken out <strong>of</strong> context, may admittedly seem exaggerated.Some disciples have <strong>in</strong>deed sometimes perverted Hayek’s ideas,erect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> fact <strong>of</strong> or capacity for “spontaneous” emergence <strong>in</strong>to a test <strong>of</strong>*Orig<strong>in</strong>ally entitled “Introduction to Papers by Boettke <strong>and</strong> Koppl,” from a “Symposium:Did Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek Have Conflict<strong>in</strong>g Views <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> World?” is paper comesfrom Peter Boettke <strong>and</strong> Sanford Ikeda, eds., Advances <strong>in</strong> Austrian Economics (1998): 123–129.Peter Boettke <strong>and</strong> Roger Koppl orig<strong>in</strong>ally wrote <strong>the</strong>ir contributions for a session at <strong>the</strong>meet<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Economic Association <strong>in</strong> Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, November 1996. Boettkeaddresses <strong>the</strong> calculation issue specifically. Koppl probes beneath it, exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g philosophical,psychological, <strong>and</strong> methodological aspects <strong>of</strong> Mises’s <strong>and</strong> Hayek’s work. ey bothf<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> positions <strong>of</strong> Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek largely reconcilable.My <strong>in</strong>troduction, slightly modified here, summarizes po<strong>in</strong>ts made by Boettke <strong>and</strong>Koppl <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Symposium, by me <strong>in</strong> “Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek on Calculation <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,”Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 7, no. 2 (1994): 93–109, <strong>and</strong> by Joseph Salerno, Jörg GuidoHülsmann, Jeffrey M. Herbener, Hans-Hermann Hoppe, <strong>and</strong> me <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Review <strong>of</strong> AustrianEconomics (1996 <strong>and</strong> 1997): vols. 9 <strong>and</strong> 10. For <strong>the</strong> calculation-not-knowledge (Misesnot-Hayek)side <strong>of</strong> this debate <strong>in</strong> its members’ own words, see <strong>the</strong>ir papers available athttp://mises.org/periodical.aspx?Id=5.93


94 Part I: Economicswhe<strong>the</strong>r particular <strong>in</strong>stitutions are desirable. Hayek’s own <strong>in</strong>sight is consistent,though, with po<strong>in</strong>ts made by Mises <strong>and</strong> reiterated by Salerno: howeverunplanned as a whole <strong>the</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>stitution may be, moststeps <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> process were taken by <strong>in</strong>dividuals act<strong>in</strong>g rationally <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> light<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own purposes <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation. Human rationality must not bedisparaged <strong>and</strong> bl<strong>in</strong>d impersonal processes exalted. Surely, however, <strong>the</strong>reis no need to imag<strong>in</strong>e a rationalist Mises <strong>and</strong> irrationalist Hayek at loggerheadswith one ano<strong>the</strong>r. Nor is <strong>the</strong>re any warrant for imput<strong>in</strong>g to Hayek<strong>the</strong> view that “Whatever is, is right”; his writ<strong>in</strong>gs on economic <strong>and</strong> politicalreform demonstrate <strong>the</strong> contrary. e two men’s <strong>in</strong>sights are mutuallyre<strong>in</strong>forc<strong>in</strong>g.e dehomogenizers particularly disparage Hayek’s elaborations onMises’s analysis <strong>of</strong> why accurate economic calculation is impossible undersocialism. An early example appears <strong>in</strong> Salerno’s 1993 article, which criticizesseveral Austrian economists’ diverse contributions to a Festschriftfor Hans Sennholz. Salerno dist<strong>in</strong>guishes between two paradigms. e“Hayekian” one “stresses <strong>the</strong> fragmentation <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> its dispersionamong <strong>the</strong> multitude <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual consumers <strong>and</strong> producers as <strong>the</strong>primary problem <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>and</strong> social cooperation <strong>and</strong> views <strong>the</strong> market’sprice system as <strong>the</strong> means by which such dispersed knowledge isferreted out <strong>and</strong> communicated to <strong>the</strong> relevant decision-makers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>production process” (1993, p. 115). e “Misesian” paradigm “focuses onmonetary calculation us<strong>in</strong>g actual market prices as <strong>the</strong> necessary preconditionfor <strong>the</strong> rational allocation <strong>of</strong> resources with<strong>in</strong> an economic systemfeatur<strong>in</strong>g specialization <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> division <strong>of</strong> labor” (p. 125). Surely, though,no sharp contrast is warranted. Both str<strong>and</strong>s enter <strong>in</strong>to a full description<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>and</strong> process <strong>of</strong> economic calculation.Salerno emphasizes that numerical data, especially market prices, arenecessary for economic calculation; qualitative <strong>in</strong>formation is not enough(1993, p. 121). Without genu<strong>in</strong>e exchanges <strong>of</strong> factors <strong>and</strong> genu<strong>in</strong>e marketdeterm<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir prices, central planners could not “cost” resources<strong>and</strong> allocate <strong>the</strong>m efficiently or purposefully (p. 130). Agreed: quantitativeresults—suitable product <strong>and</strong> factor quantities—presuppose quantitative<strong>in</strong>puts. ese must <strong>in</strong>clude, somewhere <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> calculation process, <strong>the</strong>numerical specifics <strong>of</strong> utility <strong>and</strong> production functions. But <strong>the</strong>se, alongwith <strong>the</strong> qualitative <strong>in</strong>formation also necessary, could never all be availablefor centralized, nonmarket decisions.<strong>Market</strong> prices, though necessary for calculation, are not ultimate data.Prices represent <strong>in</strong>termediate steps <strong>in</strong> tak<strong>in</strong>g account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> more nearly


Chapter : e Debate over Calculation <strong>and</strong> Knowledge 95ultimate data (<strong>of</strong>ten labeled “wants, resources, <strong>and</strong> technology”). By “cost<strong>in</strong>g,”Salerno presumably (<strong>and</strong> if so, correctly) means tak<strong>in</strong>g account both<strong>of</strong> how much <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r outputs would have to be forgone to make <strong>in</strong>crementalquantities <strong>of</strong> a resource available for <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> production contemplated<strong>and</strong> also <strong>of</strong> how highly consumers would have valued <strong>the</strong> forgonealternative outputs. Cost<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>cludes, <strong>the</strong>n, tak<strong>in</strong>g account <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>numerablebits <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation about production opportunities <strong>and</strong> processes <strong>and</strong>about consumer tastes. Calculat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> worth a prospective action requiresknow<strong>in</strong>g “<strong>the</strong> importance to o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> services one commitsto that action, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> importance to o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> goods one will obta<strong>in</strong>from that action” (Kirzner 1996, p. 150; quoted <strong>in</strong> Boettke’s Symposiumcontribution, note 22).Already it is clear that <strong>the</strong> calculation problem cannot be dist<strong>in</strong>ct from<strong>the</strong> knowledge problem.Unlike Friedrich von Wieser <strong>and</strong> Hayek, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Salerno, “Misesheld that <strong>the</strong> social appraisement <strong>of</strong> productive factors via entrepreneurialcompetition <strong>in</strong> resource markets, which is <strong>the</strong> very basis <strong>of</strong> economic calculation<strong>and</strong> purposive action, can only proceed <strong>in</strong> monetary terms” (1993,p. 135). As if Hayek would deny that, as if his stress on <strong>the</strong> knowledgeproblem disparaged money prices <strong>and</strong> appraisals <strong>in</strong> money!Strangely, <strong>the</strong> “chasmologists” fail to give a clear, precise, <strong>and</strong> compactstatement <strong>of</strong> just how <strong>the</strong>y conceive <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> economic calculation.eir writ<strong>in</strong>gs have a curiously allusive tone, at best allud<strong>in</strong>g to po<strong>in</strong>tsthat <strong>the</strong>y <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir readers alike are presumed to have <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d. To demonstrate—notjust assert—that <strong>the</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> calculation problems <strong>of</strong>socialism are dist<strong>in</strong>ct, one would first have to state <strong>the</strong> calculation problemadequately. Surely it <strong>in</strong>volves more than bits <strong>of</strong> arithmetic performedon money prices. I am tempted to speculate—but perhaps <strong>the</strong> speculationis wild if not forbidden—that absence <strong>of</strong> a full statement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problemreflects an <strong>in</strong>adequate grasp <strong>of</strong> it.Sure, <strong>the</strong> dehomogenizers do emphasize that calculation <strong>in</strong>cludescompar<strong>in</strong>g benefits <strong>and</strong> costs <strong>and</strong> estimat<strong>in</strong>g prospective pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>and</strong> losses<strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>se comparisons <strong>and</strong> estimates require arithmetic done withcard<strong>in</strong>al units <strong>of</strong> value. Echo<strong>in</strong>g Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek both, <strong>the</strong>y place wellwarrantedemphasis on <strong>the</strong> crucial importance <strong>of</strong> genu<strong>in</strong>e prices expressed<strong>in</strong> money, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g prices <strong>of</strong> privately owned factors <strong>of</strong> production <strong>and</strong>capital goods exchanged on genu<strong>in</strong>e markets. Yet <strong>the</strong>ir writ<strong>in</strong>gs are curiously<strong>in</strong>adequate <strong>in</strong> expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g what real circumstances are reflected, <strong>and</strong>how, <strong>in</strong> money prices, costs, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>comes. Beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> transactions <strong>and</strong>


96 Part I: Economicsabstentions <strong>and</strong> bids <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>fers <strong>of</strong> current <strong>and</strong> would-be owners <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>th<strong>in</strong>gs exchanged lie <strong>the</strong>se traders’ purposes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir knowledge <strong>and</strong>estimates <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> entrepreneurial conjectures about resource availabilities,technical possibilities, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g complementarities <strong>and</strong> substitutabilities<strong>in</strong> production, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r persons’ tastes. Moneyprices embody or reflect knowledge, knowledge brought through <strong>the</strong>mto bear on production <strong>and</strong> consumption decisions without be<strong>in</strong>g centralized<strong>and</strong>, for much <strong>of</strong> it, without even be<strong>in</strong>g articulated <strong>in</strong> words <strong>and</strong>numbers.I won’t repeat my 1994 description <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic-calculation problem,but I’ll add a bit to what I have already said here. Accurate calculationwould assign productive resources to <strong>the</strong>ir most highly valued uses, tak<strong>in</strong>gaccount <strong>of</strong> people’s diverse tastes (as consumers, workers, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors),as well as <strong>of</strong> production technologies, resource availabilities, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples<strong>of</strong> dim<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g marg<strong>in</strong>al utility <strong>and</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al productivity. Ideally,each consumer is <strong>in</strong>formed how much worth <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs must be forgoneto supply him with an <strong>in</strong>crement <strong>of</strong> each particular product. us<strong>in</strong>formed about alternatives, each consumer ideally leaves no opportunityunexploited to <strong>in</strong>crease his expected total satisfaction by divert<strong>in</strong>g any dollarfrom one purchase to ano<strong>the</strong>r. In this sense consumers choose <strong>the</strong> pattern<strong>of</strong> production <strong>and</strong> resource use that <strong>the</strong>y prefer. Ideally, <strong>the</strong>ir bidd<strong>in</strong>gkeeps any unit <strong>of</strong> a resource from go<strong>in</strong>g to satisfy a less <strong>in</strong>tense effectivedem<strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> denial <strong>of</strong> a more <strong>in</strong>tense one.e result <strong>of</strong> fully successful economic calculation is a state <strong>of</strong> affairs <strong>in</strong>which—apart from changes <strong>in</strong> wants, technology, <strong>and</strong> resource availabilities—n<strong>of</strong>ur<strong>the</strong>r rearrangement <strong>of</strong> patterns <strong>of</strong> production <strong>and</strong> resourceallocation could achieve an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>of</strong> value to consumers from any particulargood at <strong>the</strong> mere cost <strong>of</strong> a lesser sacrifice <strong>of</strong> value from some o<strong>the</strong>rgood. (Even if a dictatorial central planner totally disregarded consumers’tastes <strong>and</strong> was concerned only with gratify<strong>in</strong>g his own, he would still needvast amounts <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>formation.)In a competitive market economy, patterns <strong>of</strong> resource allocation, production,<strong>and</strong> consumption get established on a decentralized basis. Ofcourse, <strong>the</strong> market does not work with all imag<strong>in</strong>able perfection; nor doesany o<strong>the</strong>r human <strong>in</strong>stitution. But entrepreneurs have <strong>in</strong>centives to ferretout price discrepancies <strong>and</strong> unexploited opportunities.<strong>in</strong>gs are different under socialism. When Mises first wrote about<strong>the</strong> calculation problem <strong>in</strong> 1920 <strong>and</strong> 1922, socialism was generally understoodas a centrally directed (or “planned”) economy, with government


Chapter : e Debate over Calculation <strong>and</strong> Knowledge 97ownership (or <strong>the</strong> equivalent) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> means <strong>of</strong> production. Mises ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>edthat socialist planners could not adequately duplicate <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong>a market economy.In a series <strong>of</strong> articles beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1930s <strong>and</strong> culm<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> his1945 article on “e Use <strong>of</strong> Knowledge <strong>in</strong> Society,” Hayek spelled out <strong>and</strong>elaborated on Mises’s argument. is, anyway, is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>discussion that I share with Pr<strong>of</strong>essors Boettke <strong>and</strong> Koppl. How couldcentral planners know, for each resource, its potential contribution to <strong>the</strong>value <strong>of</strong> output at all possible marg<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>in</strong> all possible comb<strong>in</strong>ations witho<strong>the</strong>r factors <strong>of</strong> production, <strong>in</strong> all possible l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> production?e planners would need to know more than <strong>the</strong> technical aspects <strong>of</strong>production <strong>and</strong> more than <strong>the</strong> actual <strong>and</strong> potential tastes <strong>of</strong> consumers <strong>and</strong>workers. Efficient use <strong>of</strong> resources would fur<strong>the</strong>r require <strong>the</strong>ir br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g tobear <strong>of</strong> what Hayek called “knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular circumstances <strong>of</strong>time <strong>and</strong> place.” Examples are knowledge <strong>of</strong> a mach<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong>ten st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>gidle, <strong>of</strong> whom to call on for emergency repair <strong>of</strong> a leak<strong>in</strong>g boiler, <strong>of</strong> anemployee’s skills that could be put to more valuable use, <strong>of</strong> stocks <strong>of</strong> materialsthat might be drawn on dur<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>terruption <strong>of</strong> supplies, <strong>of</strong> emptyspace <strong>in</strong> a freighter about to set sail, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> fleet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ter-local differences<strong>in</strong> commodity prices. Such localized <strong>and</strong> temporary knowledge can beused only by decisionmakers on <strong>the</strong> spot <strong>and</strong> would go to waste undercentralization.But decentralized decision makers cannot work with this particularknowledge alone, or with it comb<strong>in</strong>ed with technological knowledge. Efficientdecisions must also take account <strong>of</strong> conditions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole rest<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic system—<strong>the</strong> availabilities <strong>and</strong> value-productivities <strong>of</strong>resources <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>numerable l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> production that compete for <strong>the</strong>m.Here Hayek’s story br<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> price system as a vast computer<strong>and</strong> as a communicator <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives, <strong>in</strong> abbreviated form,to all consumer <strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess decisionmakers to whom particular bits arerelevant. Here, also—if <strong>the</strong> example were not already so familiar—wouldbe <strong>the</strong> place to recite Hayek’s example <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> changed prices <strong>in</strong>motivat<strong>in</strong>g appropriate responses to an <strong>in</strong>creased scarcity <strong>of</strong> t<strong>in</strong>, whe<strong>the</strong>rcaused by a blockage <strong>of</strong> normal supplies or by development <strong>of</strong> new usesfor t<strong>in</strong>.A vaguely expressed misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g sometimes attributes to Hayek<strong>the</strong> claim that prices convey all <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation necessary for well-calculatedeconomic decisions. Yet prices are no substitute for knowledge<strong>of</strong> production techniques <strong>in</strong> various <strong>in</strong>dustries <strong>and</strong> firms. Nor are prices


98 Part I: Economicsa substitute for “knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular circumstances <strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong>place,” which is not so much conveyed by prices as, ra<strong>the</strong>r, reflected <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>actions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> decentralized decision makers who possess it.But prices do convey much knowledge, though not all. ey play anessential role <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> economywide coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>numerable decentralizeddecisions. ey are essential to economic calculation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> narrowestsense—<strong>the</strong> evaluation <strong>of</strong> benefits <strong>and</strong> costs <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> calculation <strong>of</strong> past <strong>and</strong>prospective pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>and</strong> losses.In emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>in</strong> economic calculation, Hayekwas mak<strong>in</strong>g explicit <strong>and</strong> elaborat<strong>in</strong>g on po<strong>in</strong>ts already implicit <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> arguments<strong>of</strong> Mises. In no way was he creat<strong>in</strong>g a “chasm” between two rivalpositions. is, <strong>in</strong> agreement with Kirzner (1987, 1996), is what I haveargued <strong>in</strong> my 1994 article <strong>and</strong> my 1996 <strong>and</strong> 1997 replies to <strong>the</strong> contrary<strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong> Salerno, Herbener, Hülsmann, <strong>and</strong> Hoppe. To try todrive a wedge between Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek on this issue, especially to <strong>the</strong>disparagement <strong>of</strong> Hayek, is unfair to <strong>the</strong>se two great men, unfaithful to<strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> economic thought, subversive <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g an importantstr<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> economic analysis <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> ultimate collapse <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> communist economies <strong>of</strong> Eastern Europe, <strong>and</strong> subversive <strong>of</strong> analytical<strong>and</strong> historical underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g that is vital for future policymak<strong>in</strong>g.Boettke, Peter, <strong>and</strong> Sanford Ikeda, eds. Advances <strong>in</strong> Austrian Economics 5, Greenwich,Conn.: JAI Press, 1998. Includes <strong>the</strong> Symposium contributions <strong>of</strong> PeterBoettke <strong>and</strong> Roger Koppl, pp. 131–158 <strong>and</strong> 159–179.Hayek, F.A. “e Use <strong>of</strong> Knowledge <strong>in</strong> Society.” American Economic Review 35(September 1945): 519–530.Herbener, Jeffrey M. “Ludwig von Mises <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian School <strong>of</strong> Economics.”Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 5, no. 2 (1991): 33–50.. “Calculation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Question <strong>of</strong> Arithmetic.” Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics9, no. 1 (1996): 151–162.Hoppe, Hans-Hermann. “Socialism: A Property or Knowledge Problem.” Review<strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 9, no. 1 (1996): 143–149.Hülsmann, Jörg Guido. “Knowledge, Judgment, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Use <strong>of</strong> Property.” Review<strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 9, no. 1 (1997): 23–28.


Chapter : e Debate over Calculation <strong>and</strong> Knowledge 99Kirzner, <strong>Is</strong>rael. “e Economic Calculation Debate: Lessons for Austrians.”Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 2 (1987): 1–18.. “Reflections on <strong>the</strong> Misesian Legacy <strong>in</strong> Economics.” Review <strong>of</strong> AustrianEconomics 9, no. 2 (1996): 143–154.Mises, Ludwig von. “Economic Calculation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Socialist Commonwealth.”1920. Translated by S. Adler. Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute,1990.. Socialism: An Economic <strong>and</strong> Sociological Analysis. 1922. Indianapolis: LibertyFund, 1981.. Human Action. 3 ed. Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1949.Rothbard, Murray N. “e End <strong>of</strong> Socialism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Calculation DebateRevisited.” Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 5, no. 2 (1991): 51–76.Salerno, Joseph T. “Ludwig von Mises as Social Rationalist.” Review <strong>of</strong> AustrianEconomics 4 (1990): 26–54.. “Postscript: Why a Socialist <strong>Economy</strong> is ‘Impossible’.” Postscript toEconomic Calculation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Socialist Commonwealth, by Ludwig von Mises.Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1990.. “Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek Dehomogenized.” Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 6,no. 2 (1993): 113–146.. “Reply to Lel<strong>and</strong> B. Yeager on ‘Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek on Calculation <strong>and</strong>Knowledge’.” Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 7, no. 2 (1994): 111–125.. “A F<strong>in</strong>al Word: Calculation, Knowledge, <strong>and</strong> Appraisement.” Review<strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 9, no. 1 (1996): 141–142.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek on Calculation <strong>and</strong> Knowledge.” Review <strong>of</strong>Austrian Economics 1, no. 2 (1994): 93–109.. “Salerno on Calculation, Knowledge, <strong>and</strong> Appraisement.” Review <strong>of</strong>Austrian Economics 9, no. 1 (1996): 137–139.. “Calculation <strong>and</strong> Knowledge: Let’s Write F<strong>in</strong>is.” Review <strong>of</strong> AustrianEconomics 10, no. 1 (1997): 133–136.


Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong> *Dur<strong>in</strong>g a conference <strong>in</strong> 1987, a member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> audience asked me whatschool <strong>of</strong> economics I belonged to. Instead <strong>of</strong> repudiat<strong>in</strong>g this label-monger<strong>in</strong>g,as perhaps I should have, I answered that I was a card-carry<strong>in</strong>gmember <strong>of</strong> no school but a fellow-traveler <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Chicago <strong>and</strong> Austrianschools both—if that is possible. Yes, it is possible, said Fred Glahe,ano<strong>the</strong>r member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> panel; for he too was a fellow-traveler <strong>of</strong> bothschools. I have been study<strong>in</strong>g works <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian tradition ever s<strong>in</strong>cehappen<strong>in</strong>g onto writ<strong>in</strong>gs by Ludwig von Mises <strong>and</strong> F.A. Hayek <strong>in</strong> 1946 or1947. Only a small part <strong>of</strong> my own work, however, has had a deliberatelyAustrian character. I say this because two th<strong>in</strong>gs might o<strong>the</strong>rwise suggest,wrongly, that I am a spokesman for <strong>the</strong> Austrian School: my academic title<strong>and</strong> my be<strong>in</strong>g asked to comment on an earlier version <strong>of</strong> Sherw<strong>in</strong> Rosen’spaper at <strong>the</strong> Mont Péler<strong>in</strong> Society meet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Vienna <strong>in</strong> September 1996<strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong> on its revision <strong>in</strong> this journal.Rosen recognizes, <strong>in</strong> broad strokes, some contributions <strong>of</strong> Austrianeconomics, especially its <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to decentralization <strong>and</strong> competition.However, his recognition <strong>of</strong> Austrian strengths should be amplified <strong>and</strong>his criticisms s<strong>of</strong>tened. I will also argue that his appeal to a market testfor judg<strong>in</strong>g academic work risks encourag<strong>in</strong>g anti-<strong>in</strong>tellectual attitudes<strong>and</strong> practices. I’ll list some Austrian strengths that merit more attention, caution<strong>in</strong>g,however, that not all Austrians cultivate every one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>mes mentioned.Austrians are concerned with <strong>the</strong> big picture, with how a whole economicsystem functions, <strong>and</strong> with alternative sets <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions. is is*From Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic Perspectives 11 (Fall 1997): 153–165.100


Chapter : Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong> 101what Rosen presumably means by curiously label<strong>in</strong>g Austrian economics a“macro” ra<strong>the</strong>r than “micro” <strong>the</strong>ory. Austrians <strong>in</strong>vestigate how <strong>the</strong> specializedactivities <strong>and</strong> decentralized decisions <strong>of</strong> millions or billions <strong>of</strong> persons<strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess firms are coord<strong>in</strong>ated. Decentralization allows use <strong>of</strong>what Hayek called “knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular circumstances <strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong>place”—<strong>in</strong>formation that would o<strong>the</strong>rwise go to waste or not even emerge<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place. In br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>formation even about remote parts<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy to <strong>the</strong> attention <strong>of</strong> decentralized decisionmakers <strong>and</strong> byapply<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>centives for its use, <strong>the</strong> market system <strong>and</strong> prices functionas a vast computer <strong>and</strong> communications system. No particular agencytakes charge <strong>of</strong> this coord<strong>in</strong>ation, <strong>and</strong> none would be competent to do so.In what Rosen calls “<strong>the</strong>ir f<strong>in</strong>est hour,” Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek demonstratedthat efficient economic calculation was impossible under centrally plannedsocialism. To most neoclassical economists with whom Rosen identifies,however, <strong>and</strong> as he acknowledges, <strong>the</strong> recent collapse <strong>of</strong> communist economiescame as a surprise.Austrians underst<strong>and</strong> how useful <strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> marketsystem itself, money, <strong>the</strong> common law, ethics, <strong>and</strong> language, can evolve“spontaneously,” by a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> natural selection, ra<strong>the</strong>r than by consciousimplementation <strong>of</strong> any overall design. Of course, <strong>in</strong>dividual participants<strong>in</strong> unplanned processes act rationally by <strong>the</strong>ir own lights. Austrians treat<strong>in</strong>stitutions not as givens that can be captured by a parameter or two <strong>in</strong> aneconomic model but ra<strong>the</strong>r as complex social arrangements whose evolutionrequires serious thought. While not assert<strong>in</strong>g that “whatever is,is right” <strong>and</strong> without reject<strong>in</strong>g possible reforms, Austrians do counsel acerta<strong>in</strong> humility aga<strong>in</strong>st temptations to overthrow spontaneously evolved<strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> practices merely because <strong>the</strong>ir rationales have not beenfully understood <strong>and</strong> articulated.Austrians recognize <strong>the</strong> time dimension <strong>in</strong> economic life. ey takechange, uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, <strong>and</strong> unpredictability seriously not only <strong>in</strong> confront<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> econometric models but also <strong>in</strong> assess<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong>policies. ey recognize that complex structures <strong>of</strong> heterogeneous capitalgoods reflect not only diverse <strong>and</strong> changeable consumption patterns <strong>and</strong>production processes but also diverse time horizons adopted <strong>in</strong> specific<strong>in</strong>vestment decisions.Austrians are not obsessed with contemplat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> compar<strong>in</strong>g equilibriumstates. ey pay attention to disequilibrium <strong>and</strong> process. ey donot suppose that dem<strong>and</strong> curves <strong>and</strong> cost curves, nor even tastes <strong>and</strong> technologies,are somehow “given” to decisionmakers. ey recognize that


102 Part I: Economicssuch entities emerge with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> processes <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> implement<strong>in</strong>gdecisions. ey see how competition presses toward reduc<strong>in</strong>g costs. eyvalue <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>of</strong> entrepreneurs alert to pr<strong>of</strong>it opportunities <strong>in</strong> arbitrag<strong>in</strong>gaway imperfections <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g new products <strong>and</strong>methods. ey reject policies aimed at mak<strong>in</strong>g reality conform to textbookmodels <strong>of</strong> pure <strong>and</strong> perfect competition.Austrians are relatively resistant to <strong>the</strong> methodological fads <strong>and</strong> halftacitsermons <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> academic ma<strong>in</strong>stream. Austrians stress <strong>the</strong> subjectiveelement <strong>in</strong> value: economics is primarily about people <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir purposes,not about th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> quantities. ey push <strong>the</strong>ir analysis to <strong>the</strong> level wheredecisions are actually made, <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual person, family, firm,<strong>and</strong> agency. However, <strong>the</strong>y do not get trapped <strong>in</strong> a narrow perspective;<strong>the</strong>y remember that <strong>the</strong> real challenge is to underst<strong>and</strong> economywide coord<strong>in</strong>ation.Austrians, or many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, correctly dist<strong>in</strong>guish between value judgments<strong>and</strong> value-free propositions <strong>of</strong> positive economics. ey underst<strong>and</strong>how <strong>the</strong> corpus <strong>of</strong> economic propositions can itself rema<strong>in</strong> positive, eventhough it comb<strong>in</strong>es with plausible humanitarian value judgments <strong>in</strong> support<strong>in</strong>ga libertarian political philosophy.<strong>Is</strong> Rosen’s focus on <strong>the</strong> processes <strong>of</strong> competition a fair sketch <strong>of</strong> whatis central to Austrian economics <strong>and</strong> differentiates it from neoclassicism?e two schools’ treatments <strong>of</strong> competition do characterize <strong>the</strong>ir differencesbut hardly exhaust <strong>the</strong>m. In neoclassical competition, buyers aretypically price-takers, while sellers face flat dem<strong>and</strong> curves (<strong>in</strong> pure competition)or downslop<strong>in</strong>g dem<strong>and</strong> curves (<strong>in</strong> imperfect competition) <strong>and</strong>maximize pr<strong>of</strong>its accord<strong>in</strong>gly. e Austrian conception is closer to <strong>the</strong>everyday underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> competition: rivalry to ga<strong>in</strong> customers by betterservice, <strong>and</strong> not necessarily <strong>in</strong> price alone but <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r dimensions aswell. Machovec (1995) reviews how classical <strong>and</strong> Austrian <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>competitive process became lost from <strong>the</strong> neoclassical ma<strong>in</strong>stream.Where does lack <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian perspective take neoclassical economicsfur<strong>the</strong>st <strong>of</strong>f track? Neoclassicism downplays <strong>the</strong> reality <strong>of</strong> fragmentary,scattered, unarticulated, <strong>and</strong> undiscovered knowledge. Neoclassicalstend to treat <strong>in</strong>formation as someth<strong>in</strong>g objective, bought <strong>and</strong> sold on<strong>the</strong> market, <strong>in</strong> carry<strong>in</strong>g out maximization decisions. ey tend to ignore<strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> knowledge that simply does not exist before entrepreneurs discoveror create it (Huerta de Soto, 1996, p. 5). e big economic problemcomprises more than just scarcity <strong>and</strong> choice. Equilibrium is not automatic<strong>and</strong> is <strong>in</strong> fact never reached. Entrepreneurs have wide scope <strong>and</strong>


Chapter : Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong> 103play a central role. All this gets shunted aside by fasc<strong>in</strong>ation with <strong>the</strong> maximization<strong>of</strong> an objective function subject to known constra<strong>in</strong>ts. As a mere fellow-traveler <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian School, <strong>and</strong> not even <strong>of</strong> it alone,I am bound by no party l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> am free to reject some favorite positionsheld by many (but certa<strong>in</strong>ly not all) Austrians. ese <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>the</strong>specifics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>the</strong>ir ultra-subjectivism <strong>in</strong> value<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> particularly <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest-rate <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>sistence on unidirectionalcausality ra<strong>the</strong>r than general <strong>in</strong>terdependence, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir fondnessfor methodological brood<strong>in</strong>g, po<strong>in</strong>tless pr<strong>of</strong>undities, <strong>and</strong> verbal gymnastics.Provoked by ma<strong>in</strong>stream abuses <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> frequentmerely decorative <strong>and</strong> pretentious use <strong>of</strong> symbols, some Austrianshave wanted to ban ma<strong>the</strong>matics from economics. But is it not arrogantfor someone who does not see how to use certa<strong>in</strong> techniques constructivelyto suppose that no one else will ever see how ei<strong>the</strong>r? ese Austriansshould remember how, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r contexts, <strong>the</strong>y emphasize <strong>the</strong> openness <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> future <strong>and</strong> scope for novelty.My next compla<strong>in</strong>t presupposes know<strong>in</strong>g that fairly dist<strong>in</strong>ct groups<strong>of</strong> Austrians are active or have studied at New York University, GeorgeMason University, <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Georgia, <strong>and</strong> California State Universityat Hayward. O<strong>the</strong>rs are associated with, though not necessarilylocated at, Auburn University’s Ludwig von Mises Institute. Still o<strong>the</strong>rAustrians are scattered elsewhere <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States <strong>and</strong> abroad, witha few even <strong>in</strong> Austria. Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se groups severely criticize not onlyma<strong>in</strong>stream economics but each o<strong>the</strong>r. Interpreted optimistically, <strong>the</strong>irmutual criticisms betoken a dynamic research program. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rh<strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong>fight<strong>in</strong>g among <strong>the</strong> various Austrian sects sometimes threatens tomake <strong>the</strong> whole school look ridiculous, especially as some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> combatants,fortunately few, employ questionable tactics <strong>of</strong> scholarly controversy.While not all is well <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian camp, <strong>the</strong> same is true, for differentreasons, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> neoclassical camp—more on this later.Rosen stresses a criticism related to <strong>the</strong> Austrians’ distaste for ma<strong>the</strong>matics.He prefers <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream practice <strong>of</strong> manipulat<strong>in</strong>g preciselyspecified models to obta<strong>in</strong> precise results. e Austrians, <strong>in</strong> contrast, dislikepursu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> “given conditions,” which “greatly limits<strong>the</strong> empirical scope <strong>and</strong> consequences” <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>ory. ey shun “what<strong>the</strong>y consider to be ‘rout<strong>in</strong>e’ ma<strong>the</strong>matical optimization problems that


104 Part I: Economicsunderlie much <strong>of</strong> empirical economics.” Some Austrians go so far as tosuspect an aff<strong>in</strong>ity between statism <strong>and</strong> a passion for statistics. Austrianempirical work consists ma<strong>in</strong>ly <strong>of</strong> historical case studies, but Rosen f<strong>in</strong>ds<strong>the</strong> uniqueness <strong>of</strong> each case limit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> usefulness <strong>of</strong> that approach. Heexpects a more quantitative approach to rema<strong>in</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ant, thus alreadyallud<strong>in</strong>g to a market test <strong>and</strong> a notion that “dom<strong>in</strong>ant” means “better.”If Rosen’s critique <strong>of</strong> Austrian nonempiricism is on target, it hits anouter r<strong>in</strong>g, not <strong>the</strong> bull’s-eye. First, an <strong>in</strong>tellectual division <strong>of</strong> labor can belegitimate <strong>and</strong> fruitful; a diversity <strong>of</strong> research styles is not a weakness buta strength <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e. Second, <strong>the</strong> frequently narrow <strong>and</strong> honorificuse <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term “empirical” is mislead<strong>in</strong>g. Austrians do take seriously <strong>the</strong>most pervasive <strong>and</strong> dependable facts about empirical reality. ese <strong>in</strong>cludehuman purpose <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>trospectively known realities, scarcity <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>necessity <strong>of</strong> choice, <strong>the</strong> phenomenon <strong>of</strong> dim<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g marg<strong>in</strong>al returns, <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> fragmentation <strong>of</strong> knowledge. ey <strong>in</strong>clude o<strong>the</strong>r features <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> realworld that unavoidably restrict atomistic competition to be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> exceptionra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> rule <strong>and</strong> that accord entrepreneurs a large role <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> markets. Fur<strong>the</strong>r observed facts are that sellers are typicallynot sell<strong>in</strong>g as much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir output or labor as <strong>the</strong>y would like to sell atprevail<strong>in</strong>g prices, that most prices <strong>and</strong> wages are not determ<strong>in</strong>ed impersonallybut are consciously set (although set with an eye on supply <strong>and</strong>dem<strong>and</strong>), <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r circumstances cause or reveal pricestick<strong>in</strong>ess (a fact crucial to macroeconomics). Facts are facts, regardless <strong>of</strong>whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y are known <strong>in</strong> a methodologically fashionable way. Austriansare guilty less <strong>of</strong>ten than <strong>the</strong> neoclassicals <strong>of</strong> what P.T. Bauer (1987)aptly diagnosed as “<strong>the</strong> disregard <strong>of</strong> reality.” Austrians do not conf<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong>honorific term “empirical” to propositions dug out by arduous econometriclabor <strong>and</strong>, after all, <strong>of</strong> doubtful general validity (as dist<strong>in</strong>guished frompossible validity <strong>in</strong> specific historical circumstances).Readers should not misunderst<strong>and</strong> Ludwig von Mises’s call<strong>in</strong>g economic<strong>the</strong>ory (unlike economic history) an “a priori” science. Mises used<strong>the</strong> term <strong>in</strong> an unusual way. He referred to empirical axioms like <strong>the</strong> ones Yet hear Herbert Simon (1992, p. 1504), review<strong>in</strong>g studies <strong>of</strong> firms <strong>and</strong> governmentagencies: “Although case studies are only samples <strong>of</strong> one, such samples are <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely more<strong>in</strong>formative than samples <strong>of</strong> none ... valid hypo<strong>the</strong>ses are more likely to emerge fromdirect, <strong>in</strong>timate encounter with organizations than from speculation.” Ma<strong>the</strong>matics <strong>and</strong> econometrics contribute, says Bauer (1987, p. 36), to <strong>in</strong>vert<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>“story <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Emperor’s New Clo<strong>the</strong>s. Here <strong>the</strong>re are new clo<strong>the</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> at times <strong>the</strong>y arehaute couture. But all too <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>the</strong>re is no Emperor with<strong>in</strong>.”


Chapter : Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong> 105alluded to above, ones <strong>in</strong>escapably obvious even to mere armchair observation.Rosen himself recognizes that large-scale, gross, nonnumerical evidence<strong>of</strong>ten is more secure than quantitative evidence, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ten quiteuseful (compare Summers 1991).Austrians are also more fact-oriented <strong>in</strong> recogniz<strong>in</strong>g what methodshave <strong>and</strong> what methods have not been relatively fruitful <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> progress<strong>of</strong> economic thought. As for predictions, Austrians take ano<strong>the</strong>r fact seriously:<strong>the</strong> economic world is an open ra<strong>the</strong>r than closed system <strong>and</strong> assuch has an unknowable future. Except, perhaps, for short-run extrapolationsor <strong>in</strong> identify<strong>in</strong>g wide ranges <strong>of</strong> possible outcomes, numerical forecastscannot be reliable. A pretense <strong>of</strong> satisfy<strong>in</strong>g unsatisfiable dem<strong>and</strong>sfor forecasts is <strong>in</strong>tellectually disreputable. e best that can be suppliedare qualitative predictions, recognitions <strong>of</strong> patterns, <strong>and</strong> explanations <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> likely consequences <strong>of</strong> contemplated actions. Such predictions are wellworth heed<strong>in</strong>g, as <strong>the</strong>ir frequent disregard <strong>in</strong> policymak<strong>in</strong>g illustrates bycontrast.Austrians make too much <strong>of</strong> def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g entrepreneurialactivities, says Rosen; s<strong>in</strong>ce we cannot measure <strong>the</strong>m, we cannot assess<strong>the</strong>ir importance. My reply is <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard remark about keys <strong>and</strong> lamppost.Aga<strong>in</strong> we see <strong>the</strong> difference between a narrow empiricism that looksonly at numbers <strong>and</strong> a broader empiricism that draws on direct observation.Rosen does recognize, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, that ignor<strong>in</strong>g entrepreneurshipconstra<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> neoclassical view <strong>of</strong> competition, <strong>and</strong> on this topic heexpects <strong>the</strong> largest ga<strong>in</strong>s from <strong>in</strong>tellectual trade.Rosen faults <strong>the</strong> Austrians for not spell<strong>in</strong>g out empirical criteria forassess<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> performance <strong>of</strong> an economic system. While neoclassical welfareeconomics must respect given preferences <strong>and</strong> technologies, Austriansare will<strong>in</strong>g, as he notes, to ask “what k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> social <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> rules<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> game make for a good society.” Well, good for <strong>the</strong> Austrians. econcepts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical welfare economics, though applicable <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong>exercises, are no substitute for no-holds-barred analysis <strong>of</strong> how alternativesets <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions are likely to facilitate or impede people’s pursuit <strong>of</strong>happ<strong>in</strong>ess. Neoclassicism is ma<strong>in</strong>ly concerned with establishment <strong>of</strong> equilibriumunder known conditions. With <strong>the</strong> choice set, technology, preferences,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> number <strong>and</strong> varieties <strong>of</strong> goods all given <strong>and</strong> known, it <strong>in</strong>vestigates


106 Part I: Economicsa well-def<strong>in</strong>ed solution to <strong>the</strong> resource-allocation problem. Rosen admiresthis approach. As he expla<strong>in</strong>s, neoclassical economists <strong>of</strong>ten apply <strong>the</strong> welfare<strong>the</strong>orems to describe an optimum or central-plann<strong>in</strong>g solution consistentwith specified technology <strong>and</strong> tastes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n, “without study<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>dividual maximiz<strong>in</strong>g decisions at all,” suppose that markets somehow“must do it” that way. Rosen also notes that disequilibrium analysis isnot possible <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> neoclassical scheme, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> entrepreneur has noth<strong>in</strong>gto do.James Buchanan, who acknowledges Austrian <strong>in</strong>fluence but is no cardcarry<strong>in</strong>gmember <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> school, has noted such neoclassical features byway <strong>of</strong> severe criticism. He deplores <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream tendency to trivialize<strong>the</strong> economic problem by forc<strong>in</strong>g all analyzable behavior <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>straitjacket <strong>of</strong> maximiz<strong>in</strong>g an objective function under known constra<strong>in</strong>ts.Utility functions are presumed to exist <strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> processeswhereby persons make actual choices. Concern with processes <strong>of</strong> voluntaryagreement among trad<strong>in</strong>g parties gives way to <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> an“efficient” allocation <strong>of</strong> resources exist<strong>in</strong>g “out <strong>the</strong>re,” aga<strong>in</strong>st which all<strong>in</strong>stitutional arrangements are to be tested. Economics turns <strong>in</strong>to appliedma<strong>the</strong>matics or eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g. Actually, <strong>the</strong> economy does not have a s<strong>in</strong>gleobjective function to be maximized, nor does it have a s<strong>in</strong>gle maximizer.No wonder Buchanan said that an article chosen at r<strong>and</strong>om out<strong>of</strong> any economics journal is unlikely “to have a social productivity greaterthan zero.” “Academic programs almost everywhere are controlled by rentrecipientswho simply try to ape <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream work <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir peers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>discipl<strong>in</strong>e.” (Quotations, paraphrases, <strong>and</strong> citations appear <strong>in</strong> Yeager 1990,esp. pp. 209–211.)e academic respectability <strong>of</strong> various ideologies has shifted so much<strong>in</strong> recent decades that some self-conscious neoclassicals have now carried<strong>the</strong>ir free-marketry, along with <strong>the</strong>ir methodological prejudices, to <strong>the</strong>extent <strong>of</strong> its contam<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir positive analysis. is phenomenon isparticularly evident <strong>in</strong> one <strong>of</strong> my own favorite fields, macroeconomics.Unfortunately, many Austrians venture beyond such criticisms to makea bugbear <strong>of</strong> what <strong>the</strong>y blanket under <strong>the</strong> label <strong>of</strong> “general-equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory.” Yet <strong>the</strong>re need be no tension between it <strong>and</strong> Austrian economics.Mises’s <strong>and</strong> Hayek’s <strong>in</strong>sights about socialist calculation illum<strong>in</strong>ate general<strong>in</strong>terdependence <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> various tasks to be accomplished somehow oro<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> any economic system. General equilibrium illum<strong>in</strong>ates opportunitycost—a favorite Austrian concept—<strong>in</strong> a way not o<strong>the</strong>rwise possible.All too commonly, opportunity cost is def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> choices


Chapter : Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong> 107made by a particular decisionmaker: <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> a chosen course <strong>of</strong> action is<strong>the</strong> next best course <strong>the</strong>reby forgone. at def<strong>in</strong>ition, br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g to m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>considerations <strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong> agonies <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g a decision, seemsfamiliar to <strong>the</strong> layman. is deceptive familiarity trivializes <strong>the</strong> concept.What requires <strong>the</strong> economist’s expertise is expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g opportunity cost <strong>in</strong>a deeper sense—<strong>the</strong> wider social significance <strong>of</strong> money cost. What needsrepeated explanation is how money costs reflect <strong>the</strong> subjectively appraisedvalues or utilities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r outputs <strong>and</strong> activities necessarily forgoneif resources are withheld from <strong>the</strong>m for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular outputor activity <strong>in</strong> question, as well as how money costs <strong>and</strong> prices transmit<strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives. e ma<strong>in</strong>stream apparatus can deepen <strong>the</strong>underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights so dear to Austrian hearts. Entrepreneurial ventures undergo a market test, <strong>and</strong> Rosen would putideas to <strong>the</strong> same test. He sees “an enormous amount <strong>of</strong> evolutionary Austriancompetition <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> marketplace for ideas,” even though “fashion <strong>and</strong>peer pressure” are sometimes at work. Austrians fare poorly <strong>in</strong> this competition.eir approach “excludes most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs that most economistsdo”; few Austrians belong to today’s pr<strong>of</strong>essional economics community.“What is <strong>the</strong> fact that neoclassical economics has scored higher thanAustrian economics on <strong>the</strong> evolutionary/survival test tell<strong>in</strong>g us?” Rosenrhetorically asks. He evidently holds it aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> Austrians that <strong>the</strong>y donot pass his market test <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual atmosphere created by members<strong>of</strong> his own camp, an atmosphere pervaded by narrow yet tacit methodologicalpreach<strong>in</strong>g. (Tacit preachments are <strong>the</strong> worst k<strong>in</strong>d, or so my thusentitledarticle repr<strong>in</strong>ted below argues.)My colleague Roger Garrison is probably right <strong>in</strong> warn<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st“count<strong>in</strong>g notches on academic armchairs.” Partly for this reason, I haveomitted capsule descriptions <strong>of</strong> work by contemporary Austrian economists.S<strong>in</strong>ce Rosen has raised <strong>the</strong> issue, however, I should mention <strong>the</strong>trouble that authors have generally had <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> last 40 years or so <strong>in</strong> gett<strong>in</strong>garticles on Austrian <strong>the</strong>mes <strong>in</strong>to prestigious journals. Peter Boettke (1994,p. 604) notes some consequences:Most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> articles by <strong>the</strong> younger generation <strong>of</strong> Austrians that haveappeared <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> top pr<strong>of</strong>essional journals are strategic articles. ese articlestake <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r “tenure articles” (that is, articles which do noteven pretend to advance Austrian ideas but ra<strong>the</strong>r pass <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essional


108 Part I: Economicstest needed to earn tenure) or “syn<strong>the</strong>sis articles” (articles which f<strong>in</strong>d asympa<strong>the</strong>tic trend with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n try to build a bridgeto Austrian ideas—which are usually hidden <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> footnotes).... Despite<strong>the</strong>ir strategic importance, however, <strong>the</strong>se articles <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves do notrepresent <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> scientific work required to advance an Austrianunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic <strong>and</strong> social world.Boettke <strong>and</strong> David Prychitko (1994, pp. 290–291) fur<strong>the</strong>r expla<strong>in</strong> pressuresfaced by young economists with Austrian <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ations:to meet <strong>the</strong> formal, positivistic canons <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream, Ph.D. c<strong>and</strong>idates<strong>and</strong> especially untenured economists still committed to free marketliberalism tend to switch <strong>the</strong>ir human capital <strong>in</strong>vestment to neoclassicism,to create <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> a relative degree <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essional respectability<strong>and</strong> acceptance.... Time <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong> young <strong>in</strong>tellectuals born from <strong>the</strong>ideological womb <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics mature years later as scholars<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> halls <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Chicago or UCLA. Reswitch<strong>in</strong>g backto Austrian economics seems all too costly once one’s pr<strong>of</strong>essional reputationhas been established.e central lessons <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics do not readily lend <strong>the</strong>mselvesto <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> embroidery that w<strong>in</strong> high scores <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> academicgame as currently played. Yet this does not mean that those lessons areunimportant for underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> real world. Reality embraces more than<strong>the</strong> academic game. At times, as P.T. Bauer has said (1984, pp. 160–161,179; 1987, pp. 41–42), <strong>the</strong> most important duty <strong>of</strong> an academic is to keep on<strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> obvious.Rosen retells a lightbulb story which, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> version I heard, goes:“How many right-w<strong>in</strong>g economists does it take to change a light bulb?”“None, because <strong>the</strong> free market will take care <strong>of</strong> everyth<strong>in</strong>g.” I wonderwhe<strong>the</strong>r Rosen has fully absorbed <strong>the</strong> story’s po<strong>in</strong>t. It takes a jab at <strong>the</strong>oristswho tacitly regard <strong>the</strong> market as an entity <strong>in</strong> its own right, dist<strong>in</strong>ctfrom <strong>and</strong> superior to <strong>the</strong> mere human be<strong>in</strong>gs who <strong>in</strong>teract on it. It takes ajab at <strong>the</strong> depersonalization <strong>of</strong> economics, as <strong>in</strong> neglect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> entrepreneur<strong>and</strong> as <strong>in</strong> a conception <strong>of</strong> competition that abstracts from rivalry. On my<strong>in</strong>terpretation, <strong>the</strong> story’s targets also <strong>in</strong>clude persons who see <strong>the</strong> supposed<strong>in</strong>tellectual marketplace as a mechanism for differentiat<strong>in</strong>g betweenadmirable <strong>and</strong> disreputable <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>and</strong> methods. Actually, it is <strong>in</strong>dividualswho make appraisals. To rely on <strong>the</strong> supposed market test <strong>in</strong>stead isto ride piggyback on <strong>the</strong> appraisals <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people, who may <strong>in</strong> turn bedo<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> same th<strong>in</strong>g.


Chapter : Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong> 109An example <strong>of</strong> appeal to <strong>the</strong> market test <strong>of</strong> merit occurred when boardmembers <strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>of</strong>essional association were discuss<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r to nom<strong>in</strong>atea particular economist for <strong>of</strong>fice. One member said <strong>in</strong> effect: “Itdoesn’t matter what we here th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> his work; let <strong>the</strong> market decide.” Hewent on to name journals that had pr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>the</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idate’s work. I onceserved on a promotions committee whose members spent much time discuss<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> supposed prestige <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> journals listed on <strong>the</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idates’ vitas.Not only had <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r members evidently not looked through <strong>the</strong> articles<strong>the</strong>mselves; <strong>the</strong>y had not even noticed that one c<strong>and</strong>idate had failedto make copies <strong>of</strong> his articles available. A broadly similar appeal to <strong>the</strong> “market” occurs <strong>in</strong> a rebuff to callsfor better writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> economics. eir numerical evidence persuades <strong>the</strong>authors that effort spent on better writ<strong>in</strong>g does not pay <strong>of</strong>f <strong>in</strong> greater successon <strong>the</strong> market for acceptances <strong>and</strong> citations <strong>of</strong> articles (Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong>Taylor 1992; McCloskey 1992 responds appropriately). At least two th<strong>in</strong>gs are wrong with such appeals to “<strong>the</strong> market.” First,<strong>the</strong> metaphorical academic market is less responsive to <strong>the</strong> wishes <strong>of</strong> whoever<strong>the</strong> ultimate consumer may be than is <strong>the</strong> actual market <strong>in</strong> goods<strong>and</strong> services. e subscriber to journals has an <strong>in</strong>fluence more attenuated<strong>and</strong> more subject to manipulation by o<strong>the</strong>rs than <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> consumer <strong>of</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary goods <strong>and</strong> services. Editors <strong>and</strong> referees havescope for heed<strong>in</strong>g fads <strong>and</strong> cliquish <strong>and</strong> personal considerations. ey arenot risk<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir own money. Subscribers face tie-<strong>in</strong> sales, which <strong>in</strong>cludeassociation memberships <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed prestige <strong>of</strong> subscrib<strong>in</strong>g; <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>y have reason, anyway, to learn even about disagreeable fads. Customershave a harder time <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed academic market than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>real market know<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y got what <strong>the</strong>y paid for. e analogybetween <strong>the</strong> academic <strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess markets is fur<strong>the</strong>r dissected <strong>in</strong> Bartley(1990, chaps. 6 <strong>and</strong> 7), Mirowski (1992, pp. 239, 247), <strong>and</strong> Mayer (1993,pp. 10ff., 84).Appeal<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> metaphorical market test is a variant <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fallacy<strong>of</strong> argumentum ad populum. Some k<strong>in</strong>dergartners were study<strong>in</strong>g a frog,wonder<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r it was a boy frog or a girl frog. One child piped up: e Department <strong>of</strong> Economics at <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia was better <strong>in</strong> this respect:it appo<strong>in</strong>ted committees to actually read <strong>the</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> promotion c<strong>and</strong>idates <strong>and</strong> reportback on <strong>the</strong>ir contents <strong>and</strong> merits.


110 Part I: Economics“I know how we can tell!” “All right,” said <strong>the</strong> teacher, expect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>worst, “how?” e child beamed, “We can vote” (Fumento 1993, p. 283).In ano<strong>the</strong>r variant <strong>of</strong> this approach, an editorial <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Wall Street Journaldrew an admir<strong>in</strong>g analogy between <strong>the</strong> “market” <strong>of</strong> vot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> market<strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>struments (“Toward 2000” 1996, p. A22).I do not deny that <strong>the</strong> market metaphor can have some application.But as Roger Garrison asks, is <strong>the</strong> academic market more like <strong>the</strong> marketfor wheat <strong>in</strong> Chicago or <strong>the</strong> market for tulips <strong>in</strong> 17th-century Holl<strong>and</strong>?A second objection to <strong>the</strong> metaphorical market test is deeper thanthat <strong>the</strong> metaphor is defective. S<strong>in</strong>ce when, anyway, was <strong>the</strong> market, even<strong>the</strong> actual bus<strong>in</strong>ess market, <strong>the</strong> arbiter <strong>of</strong> excellence <strong>in</strong> consumer goods,literature, art, music, science, or scholarship? S<strong>in</strong>ce when does <strong>the</strong> marketdecide truth <strong>and</strong> beauty? A particular good or service passes a ra<strong>the</strong>r literalmarket test if <strong>the</strong> quantity produced f<strong>in</strong>ds buyers will<strong>in</strong>g to pay at leastits full costs. at result suggests that resources are not be<strong>in</strong>g divertedfrom alternative uses <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y could have yielded greater value toconsumers. Success <strong>in</strong> a market niche, even a large one, has no deepersignificance. All <strong>of</strong> us can name bus<strong>in</strong>ess successes achieved by cater<strong>in</strong>gto execrable tastes, <strong>and</strong> analogues occur <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> academic world. (A healthysociety affords scope for noncoercive criticism even <strong>of</strong> tastes; see Wright1951/1962, chap. 2.)e case for <strong>the</strong> free market is someth<strong>in</strong>g quite o<strong>the</strong>r than that it constitutes<strong>the</strong> very criterion <strong>of</strong> what should be admired. An economist ignorant<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> valid case is <strong>in</strong> real trouble.e attitude <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> board <strong>and</strong> committee members mentioned above,<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> child <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> frog story, is <strong>the</strong> very prototype <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “secondh<strong>and</strong>ism”diagnosed by Ayn R<strong>and</strong>. e villa<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> her novels are secondh<strong>and</strong>ers<strong>the</strong>mselves or trade on <strong>the</strong> prevalence <strong>of</strong> that m<strong>in</strong>dset amongo<strong>the</strong>r people. An ambitious secondh<strong>and</strong>er seeks fame, prestige, admiration,envy—greatness <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people’s eyes. e secondh<strong>and</strong>er seeks notso much actual achievement as <strong>the</strong> reputation for achievement. Secondh<strong>and</strong>ismmeans tak<strong>in</strong>g one’s values from o<strong>the</strong>r people, especially peoplethought to be successful, admired, <strong>and</strong> well-connected. It makes a virtueout <strong>of</strong> conformity to <strong>the</strong>ir st<strong>and</strong>ards or examples. A case <strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t is fawn<strong>in</strong>gover celebrities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> market value <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir product endorsements.Secondh<strong>and</strong>ism enters <strong>in</strong>to “groupth<strong>in</strong>k” (’t Hart 1990). Discussions <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> two phenomena differ largely <strong>in</strong> emphasis: those <strong>of</strong> groupth<strong>in</strong>k focuson contexts <strong>in</strong> which it is likely to occur, those <strong>of</strong> secondh<strong>and</strong>ism on <strong>the</strong>characters <strong>and</strong> attitudes <strong>of</strong> persons prone to it.


Chapter : Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong> 111One variety <strong>of</strong> academic secondh<strong>and</strong>ism is <strong>the</strong> quest for perceived<strong>in</strong>fluence on policy. A practitioner <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “realism” dissected by Philbrook(1953) compromises between advis<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> policy that he, as an expert,really th<strong>in</strong>ks best <strong>and</strong> giv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> advice he th<strong>in</strong>ks most likely to be heeded.Philbrook sets forth several reasons why such “realism” is immoral. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,it promotes “[c]onfusion between advancement <strong>of</strong> knowledge<strong>and</strong> promotion <strong>of</strong> policy,” which <strong>in</strong> turn “contributes to <strong>in</strong>difference toreality” (Bauer 1987, p. 37). Confusion between <strong>the</strong> two quite differentk<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> result also impedes assessment <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essional competence (Bauer1959, esp. p. 107).A probably more prevalent <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>sidious variety <strong>of</strong> academic secondh<strong>and</strong>ismmakes a virtue out <strong>of</strong> ap<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> people who congratulate eacho<strong>the</strong>r on work<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> supposed frontiers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e. It affectsjudgments about what questions are worth pursu<strong>in</strong>g, what methods areworth us<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> how much merit <strong>in</strong>dividual pr<strong>of</strong>essors have acquired.Young pr<strong>of</strong>essors do respond to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicators <strong>of</strong> success applied (as notedby Boettke <strong>and</strong> Prychitko 1994, quoted above), even if <strong>the</strong>se <strong>in</strong>dicatorsmay sometimes lead to dysfunctional outcomes, just as manufacturers <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> Soviet Union responded, <strong>of</strong>ten wastefully, to <strong>the</strong> success <strong>in</strong>dicatorsapplied by central planners. Heed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> criteria <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> secondh<strong>and</strong>ersobstructs <strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>dependent m<strong>in</strong>d try<strong>in</strong>g to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> teachhow <strong>the</strong> real world operates. It undercuts <strong>the</strong> value <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> joy <strong>of</strong> academicwork.I know a department head who unabashedly practices secondh<strong>and</strong>ism.He awards po<strong>in</strong>ts to journals for <strong>the</strong>ir supposed prestige. He awards po<strong>in</strong>tsto articles for <strong>the</strong>ir length—<strong>the</strong> wordier <strong>the</strong> better—<strong>and</strong> for his prestigescores <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> journals where <strong>the</strong>y appear. He awards po<strong>in</strong>ts to <strong>the</strong>ir authorsaccord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>se scores <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir articles <strong>and</strong> to citation <strong>in</strong>dexes. issupposed measurement, which spares its practitioners actually hav<strong>in</strong>g toread people’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> come to grips with ideas, jo<strong>in</strong>s with academicpolitics <strong>in</strong> decisions on salaries <strong>and</strong> promotions. e person <strong>in</strong> questioneven does supposed research <strong>of</strong> his own on this sort <strong>of</strong> measurement, asif it were equivalent to <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> real economic world. Academicnarcissism jo<strong>in</strong>s academic secondh<strong>and</strong>ism. ’t Hart 1990, p. 35, notes how “rituals <strong>and</strong> symbolism” re<strong>in</strong>force a sense <strong>of</strong> “we-ness.”In economics, <strong>the</strong> ritual <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> model <strong>and</strong> use <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical symbols come to m<strong>in</strong>d. Sodo psychological experiments <strong>in</strong> which group pressure seems to affect an <strong>in</strong>dividual’s veryperceptions, or reported perceptions, as <strong>of</strong> motions <strong>of</strong> an actually stationary po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> light<strong>in</strong> a dark room or <strong>of</strong> differences between <strong>the</strong> lengths <strong>of</strong> two l<strong>in</strong>es (Tajfel 1968, p. 574).


112 Part I: EconomicsIdeally, scholars build on <strong>and</strong> criticize each o<strong>the</strong>r’s work <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir effortsto advance knowledge. Count<strong>in</strong>g citations to measure excellence is someth<strong>in</strong>gelse aga<strong>in</strong>. It is parasitic on <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> knowledge, <strong>and</strong> even subversive<strong>of</strong> it if <strong>the</strong> workers <strong>in</strong> a field take account <strong>of</strong> extraneous <strong>in</strong>fluencesthat citations may have. Of course, not all ideas <strong>and</strong> approaches deserveequal attention. As P.T. Bauer has remarked somewhere, if everyone hashis say, no one can be heard. Scholars must have some notions <strong>of</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ards<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> fruitful allocations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own time <strong>and</strong> energy. e perniciousth<strong>in</strong>g is subversion <strong>of</strong> genu<strong>in</strong>e st<strong>and</strong>ards by outsiders practic<strong>in</strong>g parasiticalsecondh<strong>and</strong>ism, sometimes garbed <strong>in</strong> spuriously scientific quantification.Rosen, with his notions <strong>of</strong> success <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas, un<strong>in</strong>tentionallyaids <strong>and</strong> abets that sort <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g. He aids <strong>and</strong> abets result<strong>in</strong>gpressures to climb onto b<strong>and</strong>wagons. He now qualifies his notions withreference to <strong>the</strong> long run: eventually <strong>the</strong> market test works <strong>and</strong> correctdoctr<strong>in</strong>es <strong>and</strong> fruitful methods tend to prevail. I too want to believe so.Examples come readily to m<strong>in</strong>d, however, <strong>of</strong> false but long-dom<strong>in</strong>antideas <strong>in</strong> natural science, medic<strong>in</strong>e, geography, <strong>and</strong> even economics. Anyway,no impersonal market achieves <strong>the</strong> eventual triumph <strong>of</strong> truth. atresult depends on honest <strong>and</strong> competent men <strong>and</strong> women exercis<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irown <strong>in</strong>dependent judgment even aga<strong>in</strong>st prestigious op<strong>in</strong>ion. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,<strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> long run <strong>in</strong> defense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market test is an example<strong>of</strong> what Karl Popper would call an immuniz<strong>in</strong>g stratagem: evident failurescan be talked away with <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>the</strong>y will turn <strong>in</strong>to successeseventually.First-h<strong>and</strong> appraisals are not always possible. In everyday life we musttake most <strong>of</strong> our beliefs <strong>and</strong> bases <strong>of</strong> action from o<strong>the</strong>r people. Time isscarce <strong>and</strong> division <strong>of</strong> knowledge necessary. Academic adm<strong>in</strong>istrators <strong>and</strong>committees may underst<strong>and</strong>ably feel a need for outside help <strong>in</strong> assess<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> qualifications <strong>and</strong> character <strong>of</strong> a c<strong>and</strong>idate for a post. In certa<strong>in</strong> circumstances,however, we as <strong>in</strong>dividuals have a duty to express judgments <strong>of</strong>our own. en we are derelict if we subord<strong>in</strong>ate our own direct knowledge(as <strong>of</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idates’ personal <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essional characters) to <strong>the</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ions <strong>of</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r people. If an element <strong>of</strong> secondh<strong>and</strong>ism sometimes seems necessary,we must recognize it as a shortcut <strong>and</strong> seek to reduce its <strong>in</strong>fluence, ra<strong>the</strong>rthan praise our expediency <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> some sort <strong>of</strong> market test. Aboveall, we academics have <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essional duty <strong>of</strong> treat<strong>in</strong>g secondh<strong>and</strong>ism, Machovec’s story (1995) <strong>of</strong> what happened to <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> competition illustrates<strong>the</strong> harm done by b<strong>and</strong>wagonry, by obsession with what is thought most publishablethanks to attunement to contemporary notions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> frontier <strong>of</strong> research.


Chapter : Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong> 113groupth<strong>in</strong>k, anti-<strong>in</strong>tellectualism, phony quantification, diversionary narcissism,<strong>and</strong> perverse success <strong>in</strong>dicators with <strong>the</strong> contempt <strong>the</strong>y deserve. Schools <strong>in</strong> academe—groups <strong>of</strong> scholars work<strong>in</strong>g on favorite topics <strong>and</strong>with favorite methods—have value. Scrut<strong>in</strong>y with<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> across schools canshoot down bad ideas <strong>and</strong> empty fads. Schools can help motivate researchby giv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir members <strong>the</strong> presumption <strong>of</strong> a sympa<strong>the</strong>tic audience.Scholars should approach each school (<strong>and</strong> each sect) for what <strong>the</strong>ycan learn from it, not as a target <strong>of</strong> polemics for polemics’ sake <strong>and</strong> not asa foil for self-congratulation. e neoclassical <strong>and</strong> Austrian schools, eachstripped <strong>of</strong> excrescences, are complementary. Aspir<strong>in</strong>g Austrian economistsshould <strong>in</strong>deed take <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard Ph.D. courses. Austrian economicsis ready aga<strong>in</strong> to contribute, as it once did, to <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream. ContemporaryAustrians have been sett<strong>in</strong>g good examples <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir work on comparativesystems, economic history, <strong>and</strong> entrepreneurial history, <strong>in</strong>dustrialorganization, labor economics, monetary <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions,o<strong>the</strong>r market <strong>in</strong>stitutions for cop<strong>in</strong>g with ignorance <strong>and</strong> uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty,<strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> thought, <strong>and</strong> political philosophy. Austrian macroeconomicshas much <strong>and</strong> could develop more <strong>in</strong> common with new Keynesianism(which <strong>in</strong> its fundamentals, despite its label, is nei<strong>the</strong>r new nor Keynesian).Even <strong>in</strong> fields usually considered remote from dist<strong>in</strong>ctively Austrian<strong>in</strong>terests, criticism from an Austrian perspective, like scientific criticismgenerally, can exert healthy discipl<strong>in</strong>e.If <strong>the</strong> neoclassicals who are obsessed nowadays—apparently withouteven realiz<strong>in</strong>g it—with methodology, prestige, <strong>and</strong> frontiersmanship canshake <strong>of</strong>f <strong>the</strong>se obsessions, <strong>and</strong> if, fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y can resist <strong>the</strong> badger<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>parasitical secondh<strong>and</strong>ers, <strong>the</strong>y can reap ga<strong>in</strong>s from trade with <strong>the</strong> Austrians.Bartley, W.W., III. Unfathomed Knowledge, Unmeasured Wealth: On Universities<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Wealth <strong>of</strong> Nations. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1990.Bauer, P.T. “International Economic Development.” Economic Journal 69 (March1959): 105–123.. “Fur<strong>the</strong>r Reflections on <strong>the</strong> State <strong>of</strong> Economics,” In Reality <strong>and</strong> Rhetoric,chap. 10. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1984.


114 Part I: Economics. “e Disregard <strong>of</strong> Reality.” Cato Journal 7 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g/Summer 1987): 29–42.Boettke, Peter J., ed. e Elgar Companion to Austrian Economics. Aldershot, U.K.,<strong>and</strong> Brookfield, Vt.: Elgar, 1994.Boettke, Peter J., <strong>and</strong> David L. Prychitko, eds. e <strong>Market</strong> Process: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> ContemporaryAustrian Economics. Aldershot, U.K., <strong>and</strong> Brookfield, Vt.: Elgar,1994.Fumento, Michael. Science under Siege. New York: Morrow, 1993.’t Hart, Paul. Groupth<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong> Government: A Study <strong>of</strong> Small Groups <strong>and</strong> Policy Failure.Amsterdam, Rockl<strong>and</strong>, Mass., <strong>and</strong> Berwyn, Pa.: Swets & Zeitl<strong>in</strong>ger,1990.Huerta de Soto, Jesús. “e Ongo<strong>in</strong>g Methodenstreit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian School.”Comment on papers by Sherw<strong>in</strong> Rosen <strong>and</strong> Erich Streissler. Presented at<strong>the</strong> meet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Mont Péler<strong>in</strong> Society, Vienna, September 1996.Lab<strong>and</strong>, David N., <strong>and</strong> Christopher N. Taylor. “e Impact <strong>of</strong> Bad Writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>Economics.” Economic Inquiry (October 1992): 30, 673–688.Machovec, Frank M. Perfect Competition <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Transformation <strong>of</strong> Economics.London <strong>and</strong> New York: Routledge, 1995.Mayer, omas. <strong>Truth</strong> versus Precision <strong>in</strong> Economics. Aldershot, U.K., <strong>and</strong> Brookfield,Vt.: Elgar, 1993.McCloskey, D.N. “Writ<strong>in</strong>g as a Responsibility <strong>of</strong> Science: A Reply to Lab<strong>and</strong><strong>and</strong> Taylor.” Economic Inquiry 30 (October 1992): 689–695.Mirowski, Philip. “ree Vignettes on <strong>the</strong> State <strong>of</strong> Economic Rhetoric.” InPost-Popperian Methodology <strong>of</strong> Economics, edited by Neil de Marchi, 235–259.Boston: Kluwer, 1992.Philbrook, Clarence. “‘Realism’ <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal.” American Economic Review43 (December 1953): 846–859.Rosen, Sherw<strong>in</strong>. “Austrian <strong>and</strong> Neoclassical Economics: Any Ga<strong>in</strong>s from Trade?”Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic Perspectives 11 (Fall 1997): 139–152.Simon, Herbert A. “Review <strong>of</strong> Organization eory”, edited by O.E. Williamson.Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic Literature 30 (September 1992): 1503–1505.Streissler, Erich W. “Methodenstreit: e Austrian vs. Neo-Classical Approachesto Economics.” Paper presented at <strong>the</strong> meet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Mont Péler<strong>in</strong> Society,Vienna, September 1996.


Chapter : Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong> 115Summers, Lawrence H. “e Scientific Illusion <strong>in</strong> Empirical Macroeconomics.”Sc<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>avian Journal <strong>of</strong> Economics 93, no. 2 (1991): 129–148.Tajfel, Henri. “Social Perception.” In International Encyclopedia <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Social Sciences,vol. 11: 567–575. New York: Macmillan <strong>and</strong> Free Press, 1968.“Toward 2000.” Wall Street Journal, 7 November 1996.Wright, David M. Capitalism. 1951. Chicago: Regnery, 1962.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “Buchanan on Scope <strong>and</strong> Method.” Constitutional <strong>Political</strong><strong>Economy</strong> 1, no. 2 (1990): 197–220.. “Tacit Preachments Are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic Methodology2, no. 1 (1995): 1–33. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted here as chapter .


<strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> a <strong>Test</strong> <strong>of</strong><strong>Truth</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Beauty</strong>? * In this Journal <strong>of</strong> Spr<strong>in</strong>g 2000, Robert Tollison jo<strong>in</strong>s David Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>reiterat<strong>in</strong>g a stretched conception <strong>of</strong> market test. Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollisonrecommend grad<strong>in</strong>g academic performance by <strong>the</strong> sorts <strong>of</strong> statistics thatLab<strong>and</strong> compiles, which <strong>in</strong>volve article <strong>and</strong> page counts, impressions <strong>of</strong>journal quality, <strong>and</strong> citations. As I said <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1997 article that Lab<strong>and</strong><strong>and</strong> Tollison attack (<strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g chapter here), not even <strong>the</strong> actual commercialmarket is a test <strong>of</strong> truth <strong>and</strong> beauty or excellence. Granted, if<strong>the</strong> quantity produced <strong>of</strong> some good or service f<strong>in</strong>ds will<strong>in</strong>g buyers at aprice at least cover<strong>in</strong>g all costs, that fact implies that resources have notbeen diverted from alternative outputs that consumers would have valuedmore highly. Losses are a retrospective sign <strong>of</strong> waste (apart from a quasiexceptionfor bus<strong>in</strong>ess owners who derive satisfaction from us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irown wealth even <strong>in</strong> money-los<strong>in</strong>g ways). Such a market test exerts healthydiscipl<strong>in</strong>e.Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, social cooperation through <strong>the</strong> market <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r waysitself has moral value. e market method <strong>of</strong> organiz<strong>in</strong>g economic activityis <strong>in</strong>deed better, by <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> human happ<strong>in</strong>ess, than alternativemethods. But f<strong>in</strong>ancial success <strong>in</strong> some broad or narrow market niche hasno deeper philosophical significance; <strong>in</strong> itself, it is no fur<strong>the</strong>r sign <strong>of</strong> excellenceor virtue. (e lesson <strong>of</strong> Hayek 1960, chap. 6, is well worth tak<strong>in</strong>gto heart.) <strong>Market</strong> success does not prove that <strong>the</strong> tastes catered to, <strong>the</strong>*Orig<strong>in</strong>ally entitled “e Tactics <strong>of</strong> Secondh<strong>and</strong>ism,” this paper comes from <strong>the</strong>Quarterly Journal <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 3 (Fall 2000): 51–61. It replies to a commentthat David N. Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Robert D. Tollison had made on my article repr<strong>in</strong>ted justabove. For Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison’s own words, see <strong>the</strong>ir “On Secondh<strong>and</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> ScientificAppraisal,” Quarterly Journal <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 3, no. 1 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g 2000): 43–48,http://mises.org/journals/qjae/pdf/qjae3_1_4.pdf.116


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> a <strong>Test</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Truth</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Beauty</strong>? 117goods <strong>and</strong> services provided, or <strong>the</strong> providers <strong>the</strong>mselves are admirable.Facts alone do not yield appraisals (you can’t get an “ought” from an “is”).“e market” is a metaphor. It makes no appraisals. “Choices are madeonly by humans ra<strong>the</strong>r than by personified abstractions such as ‘<strong>the</strong> market’”( James M. Buchanan 1995, quoted <strong>in</strong> Lee 1996, p. 787; here <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>his article <strong>of</strong> 2000, Lee makes <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t eloquently). Overreach<strong>in</strong>g claimsfor <strong>the</strong> market, especially as a transpersonal arbiter <strong>of</strong> truth, decency, <strong>and</strong>excellence, tend to discredit <strong>the</strong> valid <strong>and</strong> quite different case for a freesociety. (On backlash from exaggerated claims <strong>of</strong> market perfection, compareHeyne 2000, first full paragraph <strong>of</strong> p. 138.) He is a poor champion <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> market system who cannot defend it as it really is, “warts <strong>and</strong> all.” Itis sad to see public underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> case for <strong>the</strong> market undercut by<strong>the</strong> market’s would-be friends.Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison <strong>in</strong>vite such backlash, un<strong>in</strong>tentionally. ey identify<strong>the</strong>ir own position on “secondh<strong>and</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> scientific appraisal” with“<strong>the</strong> free-market side <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e”; <strong>the</strong>y impute belief <strong>in</strong> “market failure”to <strong>the</strong>ir critics (2000, p. 43). e market system, far from be<strong>in</strong>g asubstitute for good judgment <strong>and</strong> morality, presupposes morality. Yet secondh<strong>and</strong>ismhas morally questionable aspects <strong>in</strong> some <strong>of</strong> its applications(cf. McCloskey 1992, comment<strong>in</strong>g on Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Taylor 1992).If <strong>the</strong> fairly literal test <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> commercial market has limited (thoughgreat) significance, even less significant is its supposed analogue <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>metaphorical market for science <strong>and</strong> scholarship. ere, truth, not marketability,is <strong>the</strong> goal—<strong>and</strong> truth as such, not different, <strong>in</strong>compatiblebr<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> truth for different consumers. (In <strong>the</strong> commercial market, bycontrast, bus<strong>in</strong>esses do cater to widely divergent tastes <strong>and</strong> do, appropriately,satisfy even dem<strong>and</strong>s for <strong>in</strong>expensive goods <strong>of</strong> relatively low quality.)To speak <strong>of</strong> truth is not to traffic <strong>in</strong> metaphysics about <strong>Truth</strong> with a capitalT. I mean merely that scientific endeavor is <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> propositions<strong>of</strong> generality <strong>and</strong> depth correspond<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> way th<strong>in</strong>gs actually are (toborrow words from Peter Bauer <strong>and</strong> George Will separately). Scientific or scholarly or academic life has at least two str<strong>and</strong>s. First istry<strong>in</strong>g to f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong> communicate truth or knowledge. Second is <strong>the</strong> academicgame itself—<strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> prestige, admiration, <strong>and</strong> money. Selfpromotion<strong>and</strong> gamesmanship enter <strong>in</strong>. Of course, <strong>the</strong> two aspects <strong>of</strong>academic life overlap. Even someone overrid<strong>in</strong>gly concerned with truth


118 Part I: Economicsdesires admiration, wants to deserve it, <strong>and</strong> cares about its sources <strong>and</strong>reasons. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, hope for fame <strong>and</strong> fortune can <strong>in</strong>deed be a strong<strong>and</strong> respectable <strong>in</strong>centive to <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> scientific truth (as well as atemptation to politick<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like).Still, how closely <strong>the</strong> two aspects <strong>of</strong> scientific activity correspond isaffected by <strong>the</strong> tone <strong>and</strong> policies prevail<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> academic world. epreach<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison, if heeded, would impair <strong>the</strong> correspondence<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>crease tension between <strong>the</strong> two aspects.“e truth is not relevant if it is not a shared truth,” <strong>the</strong>y write (Lab<strong>and</strong><strong>and</strong> Tollison 2000, p. 43). I am not sure just what <strong>the</strong>y mean by “relevant”or <strong>in</strong> how broad or how narrow a context <strong>the</strong>y apply <strong>the</strong>ir remark. Perhaps<strong>the</strong>y mean relevance to scor<strong>in</strong>g well <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> academic game. eir remarkdoes sound like relativism. Yet reality is what it is, regardless <strong>of</strong> how manyor how few people share a correct perception <strong>of</strong> it. Be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluential orenjoy<strong>in</strong>g prestige may sometimes carry a presumption that one’s ideas areright, but it is not <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong>ir actually be<strong>in</strong>g right.Shar<strong>in</strong>g truth—communicat<strong>in</strong>g ideas—is important, <strong>of</strong> course. Curiously,Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison seem to value communication only <strong>in</strong> a narrow“market” associated with a notion <strong>of</strong> prestigious journals. But hownarrow or how broad a market properly “counts”—how small or large aset <strong>of</strong> persons addressed? No market answers that question by itself. Does<strong>the</strong> appropriate market <strong>in</strong>clude all employers <strong>and</strong> potential employers <strong>of</strong>economists or all actual <strong>and</strong> potential consumers <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>formation?Or is it a much narrower set <strong>of</strong> appraisers, people <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to receive<strong>and</strong> transmit b<strong>and</strong>wagon effects relat<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> supposed frontiers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>discipl<strong>in</strong>e? More comes later about questions like <strong>the</strong>se. I want to forestall mis<strong>in</strong>terpretation. If we had to rank economists <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>past, if all copies <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs’ discussions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir writ<strong>in</strong>gshad been irrecoverably lost, if no <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong>m survivedo<strong>the</strong>r than statistics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds that Lab<strong>and</strong> compiles, <strong>and</strong> if we waive<strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> what purpose a rank<strong>in</strong>g under such circumstances mightserve, <strong>the</strong>n I do suppose that consult<strong>in</strong>g those statistics would be moreplausible than any alternative that comes to m<strong>in</strong>d. Say<strong>in</strong>g so is not much<strong>of</strong> a concession. Act<strong>in</strong>g on a hunch with some slight basis is more plausiblethan act<strong>in</strong>g at r<strong>and</strong>om. Actually, we do not have to rank economistsunder such circumstances <strong>and</strong> by such a method.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> a <strong>Test</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Truth</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Beauty</strong>? 119Two o<strong>the</strong>r po<strong>in</strong>ts, which are not even semiconcessions, already appeared<strong>in</strong> my 1997 article. First, some st<strong>and</strong>ards must apply <strong>in</strong> science<strong>and</strong> scholarship; not all scribbl<strong>in</strong>gs can comm<strong>and</strong> equal respect <strong>and</strong> attention.Partly <strong>in</strong> unavoidable consequence, unfashionable ideas face anuphill battle. Second, life requires much reliance on secondh<strong>and</strong> knowledge.Wholly firsth<strong>and</strong> appraisals (as <strong>of</strong> academic c<strong>and</strong>idates’ qualifications,accomplishments, <strong>and</strong> characters) are scarcely possible; <strong>of</strong>ten one’sown direct knowledge must be supplemented by <strong>the</strong> judgments <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rpeople.Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison’s ersatz st<strong>and</strong>ards partly crowd out sounder ones.Far from be<strong>in</strong>g apologetic, Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison make an actual virtue<strong>of</strong> exaggerated secondh<strong>and</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir stretched conception <strong>of</strong> markettest. Such th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> attitudes, to <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong>y have <strong>in</strong>fluence,worsen <strong>the</strong> defects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> already weak analogy between <strong>the</strong> academicquasi-market <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> real market. Academe is not immune from fads <strong>and</strong>b<strong>and</strong>wagon effects such as occur <strong>in</strong> many areas <strong>of</strong> life, for example, <strong>the</strong>adulation <strong>of</strong> celebrities. Analogues <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Keynesian beauty contest appear<strong>in</strong> economic research <strong>and</strong> styles <strong>of</strong> exposition under pressures to do notso much what <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual economist th<strong>in</strong>ks best as what is thought tow<strong>in</strong> acclaim. Such tendencies tilt <strong>the</strong> play<strong>in</strong>g field more steeply aga<strong>in</strong>stunfashionable ideas.Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison make much <strong>of</strong> citations as <strong>in</strong>dicators <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluenceor fame. Admir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence so registered, even <strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>of</strong> substance,is analogous to admir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> political “realism” justly attackedby Clarence Philbrook (1953)—admir<strong>in</strong>g perceived <strong>in</strong>fluence on policy On <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r matters, I am struck by how little attention Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollisonpay to what I actually wrote <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> article under attack <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>gs I cited. My <strong>and</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r observers’ reasons for concern about secondh<strong>and</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> groupth<strong>in</strong>k may perhapsbe mistaken, but <strong>the</strong>y are relevant to <strong>the</strong> issues under discussion. Brown (1948/1950, pp. 51–53, 63–64), provides an early <strong>and</strong> eloquent diagnosis <strong>of</strong>faddism <strong>in</strong> economics. More recently, macroeconomics provides glar<strong>in</strong>g examples. eimpact <strong>of</strong> “big players” has been analyzed chiefly <strong>in</strong> actual markets, but <strong>the</strong> analysis can beextended to fads <strong>and</strong> b<strong>and</strong>wagon effects <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r activities. “A Big Player is anyone whohabitually exercises discretionary power to <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>the</strong> market while himself rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gwholly or largely immune from <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>and</strong> loss.” Koppl <strong>and</strong> Yeager 1996,p. 368; also see works cited <strong>the</strong>re, as well as Butos <strong>and</strong> Koppl 1995. Or even <strong>of</strong> notoriety, as noted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> text below. Ronald Coase remarked many yearsago (<strong>in</strong> conversation, so I quote only from memory): “In <strong>the</strong> academic game, <strong>the</strong> importantth<strong>in</strong>g is to have been heard <strong>of</strong>. People may forget <strong>in</strong> just what connection <strong>the</strong>y heard <strong>of</strong>you, but <strong>the</strong>y’re likely to remember whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y heard <strong>of</strong> you. It is better to have beenheard <strong>of</strong> for murder<strong>in</strong>g your wife than not to have been heard <strong>of</strong> at all.”


120 Part I: Economicseven when obta<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> advisor’s compromis<strong>in</strong>g with his own honestjudgments. Citations properly serve any <strong>of</strong> several purposes: ey steer<strong>the</strong> reader to facts <strong>and</strong> arguments support<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> author’s po<strong>in</strong>ts or tosupplementary discussions. ey give credit to o<strong>the</strong>r authors for ideas orf<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs or particularly apt formulations. When one researcher is criticiz<strong>in</strong>gano<strong>the</strong>r’s ideas or results, citations give <strong>the</strong> reader a chance to check <strong>the</strong>attacked work <strong>and</strong> see whe<strong>the</strong>r it is be<strong>in</strong>g dealt with fairly. Less admirably,citations may be used as moves <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> academic game—to borrow <strong>the</strong> prestige<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r writers cited, to signal that one’s own work is à la mode,on <strong>the</strong> supposed frontier <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e, or to signal familiarity withrecondite sources or areas <strong>of</strong> knowledge. If an author expects citations tobe put to <strong>the</strong> uses <strong>of</strong> Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison, he might even give or withhold<strong>the</strong>m for that reason. e parasitic use <strong>of</strong> citations can corrupt <strong>the</strong>irprimary use.Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison even claim more for citations as <strong>the</strong>y use <strong>the</strong>mthan for <strong>the</strong> actual market (2000, p. 46):dollar votes are an imprecise measure <strong>of</strong> value. More accurately, <strong>the</strong>yreflect m<strong>in</strong>imum expected value. Citations, by contrast, clearly revealthat <strong>the</strong> academic consumer received value from <strong>the</strong> product cited, irrespective<strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> citation was positive or negative. is is because<strong>the</strong> citations are issued only after purchase <strong>and</strong> consumption <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> product.us, a case can be made that <strong>the</strong> academic market conveys product<strong>in</strong>formation even more accurately through citations than do markets forgoods <strong>and</strong> services us<strong>in</strong>g dollar vot<strong>in</strong>g.e term<strong>in</strong>ology <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole analogy are stra<strong>in</strong>ed; <strong>the</strong> claim is bizarre.I know someone whose idea <strong>of</strong> economic research—as I have toldhim—is to ransack <strong>the</strong> literature for passages that express or can be <strong>in</strong>terpretedas express<strong>in</strong>g fallacies, <strong>the</strong>n triumphantly to pounce on <strong>and</strong> demolishthose fallacies. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison test, even perpetrators<strong>of</strong> crude fallacies, far from deserv<strong>in</strong>g scorn for clutter<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>the</strong>literature, deserve <strong>the</strong> positive po<strong>in</strong>ts that <strong>the</strong>ir citations br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m; for<strong>the</strong> fallacy-hunters have “received value” from <strong>the</strong> works cited.Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison make excuses for assess<strong>in</strong>g people by Lab<strong>and</strong>iannumbers. Some such method is a practical necessity. It possessesobjectivity (or so Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison seem to suggest on p. 47). Yet personaljudgment necessarily enters <strong>in</strong>to construct<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> numerical <strong>in</strong>dexes.Conformably with <strong>the</strong>ir secondh<strong>and</strong> nature, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dexes fail to showwho judged whose work up or down <strong>and</strong> for what reasons. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> a <strong>Test</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Truth</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Beauty</strong>? 121publication <strong>in</strong>dexes cannot realistically be <strong>the</strong> sole measure <strong>of</strong> academicperformance. Pr<strong>of</strong>essors have o<strong>the</strong>r duties, even teach<strong>in</strong>g; <strong>and</strong> subjectivejudgment unavoidably enters <strong>in</strong>to assess<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> weight<strong>in</strong>g various k<strong>in</strong>ds<strong>of</strong> performance.In Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison’s view, “<strong>the</strong> alternative to rely<strong>in</strong>g on markets toassign value to scientific contributions is that we must rely on <strong>the</strong> ostensiblyfirsth<strong>and</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> some central authority, such as Yeager” (p. 46).Never m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>s<strong>in</strong>uation that I aspire to <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> central authority.Notice aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> notion that “markets,” impersonal markets, make judgments<strong>and</strong> that some mechanism or statistical process should “assign valueto scientific contributions.” Yet such value does not exist <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> abstract.A researcher learns from <strong>the</strong> actual substance <strong>of</strong> his colleagues’ work, notfrom mere summary numbers perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to journal quality <strong>and</strong> citations.Writ<strong>in</strong>gs have value for <strong>the</strong> persons who use <strong>the</strong> reported facts <strong>and</strong> ideas,such as o<strong>the</strong>r scientists, eng<strong>in</strong>eers <strong>and</strong> technicians, consumers who ultimatelybenefit from technological progress, <strong>and</strong> citizens <strong>in</strong> general whobenefit from progress <strong>in</strong> economic knowledge (to <strong>the</strong> extent that suchknowledge is actually heeded <strong>in</strong> policymak<strong>in</strong>g).In grad<strong>in</strong>g academics for appo<strong>in</strong>tments, promotions, <strong>and</strong> so forth,<strong>the</strong> alternative to Lab<strong>and</strong>’s approach is not reliance on some supposedcentral authority, such as me. No, <strong>the</strong> alternative is that <strong>the</strong> decisionmakers<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>formed consultants frankly lay out <strong>the</strong>ir own judgments,for which <strong>the</strong>y take responsibility, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> reasons for <strong>the</strong>m. Let<strong>the</strong>m not hide beh<strong>in</strong>d some sort <strong>of</strong> statistical precipitate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> anonymousjudgments <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people. Let <strong>the</strong>se appraisers discuss <strong>the</strong>ir tentativejudgments with one ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> possibly revise <strong>the</strong>m. An academicdepartment might name a committee to actually read c<strong>and</strong>idates’ writ<strong>in</strong>gs,perhaps seek<strong>in</strong>g supplementary <strong>in</strong>formation from outside, <strong>and</strong> to reportits members’ assessments <strong>and</strong> reasons to <strong>the</strong> broader decisionmak<strong>in</strong>ggroup. Economists should underst<strong>and</strong> that people, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g academics, respondto <strong>in</strong>centives <strong>and</strong> that <strong>in</strong>appropriate <strong>in</strong>centives can br<strong>in</strong>g un<strong>in</strong>tended consequences.Responses to “success <strong>in</strong>dicators” <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Soviet planned economyprovided examples. As caricatured <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> humor magaz<strong>in</strong>e Krokodil,if a nail factory’s output was measured <strong>in</strong> number <strong>of</strong> units, <strong>the</strong> factorywould produce very many t<strong>in</strong>y nails; but if total weight counted <strong>in</strong>stead,


122 Part I: Economicsit would produce few but huge nails. (Compare Tullock 1965, chap. 23, onhow bureaucrats react to attempts to measure <strong>the</strong>ir performances numerically.)St<strong>and</strong>ardized tests <strong>of</strong> school children reportedly elicit “teach<strong>in</strong>g totest”; certa<strong>in</strong> measures <strong>of</strong> performance steer <strong>the</strong> attention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> police toviolators easy to catch.e <strong>in</strong>dividually sensible response <strong>of</strong> young pr<strong>of</strong>essors under Lab<strong>and</strong><strong>and</strong>-Tollison-typepressures may well be to toil away <strong>in</strong> some prevalent fadon one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed frontiers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e, which may well <strong>in</strong>volvework addressed to some small <strong>in</strong>-group, resistant to <strong>in</strong>formed evaluationby outsiders <strong>and</strong> enjoy<strong>in</strong>g scant wider relevance—all <strong>in</strong> hopes <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gprestigiously published. (ere is no necessary contradiction <strong>in</strong> identify<strong>in</strong>gboth faddism <strong>and</strong> narrow specialization. Numerous small modish topicsmay exist, as well as methodological, rhetorical, <strong>and</strong> stylistic fads <strong>in</strong>fect<strong>in</strong>gmany specialties at once.)It is perverse to push academics lack<strong>in</strong>g a comparative advantage <strong>in</strong>modish work to waste <strong>the</strong>ir energies on it anyway. Why prod <strong>the</strong>m towrite articles <strong>in</strong> which few people are really <strong>in</strong>terested (except perhaps asa basis for Brownie po<strong>in</strong>ts or as <strong>in</strong>puts to more such work by o<strong>the</strong>r similarlymotivated academics)? ey might make more solid contributions<strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r ways; <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> opportunity cost applies even <strong>in</strong> academe.Even with<strong>in</strong> an academic department, diversity <strong>of</strong> talents <strong>and</strong> specializationshas value.Let’s face it: few economists are capable <strong>of</strong> frequently f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g importantnew knowledge. At <strong>the</strong> same time, widespread ignorance prevailsabout <strong>the</strong> core <strong>of</strong> economics, <strong>the</strong> very logic <strong>of</strong> a market economy. Longexplodederrors persist among policymakers <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> general public. equasi-market works less well for knowledge <strong>in</strong> economics than for knowledge<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural sciences (especially than for <strong>in</strong>dustrially applicable,as dist<strong>in</strong>ct from politically applicable, scientific knowledge). Even economistsfar apart on <strong>the</strong> ideological spectrum do agree on important issuesabout which <strong>the</strong> general public <strong>and</strong> even noneconomist <strong>in</strong>tellectuals areignorant.If economics has much <strong>of</strong> value to teach, <strong>the</strong> persistence <strong>of</strong> ignorance<strong>and</strong> error over <strong>the</strong> decades <strong>and</strong> centuries suggests a lapse <strong>of</strong> communicationworth try<strong>in</strong>g to remedy. Room rema<strong>in</strong>s for devis<strong>in</strong>g improved ways to However <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ts are calculated, only x percent <strong>of</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idates can w<strong>in</strong>d up <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>top x percent; yet much effort <strong>and</strong> talent may be misdirected <strong>in</strong>to try<strong>in</strong>g to w<strong>in</strong>d up <strong>the</strong>reanyway. Economists should underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> differences between a race for positional values<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> creation <strong>of</strong> values <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r k<strong>in</strong>ds.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> a <strong>Test</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Truth</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Beauty</strong>? 123make economic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples clear <strong>and</strong> to communicate <strong>the</strong>m widely. Whyshould such efforts be disda<strong>in</strong>ed? Pr<strong>of</strong>iciency <strong>in</strong> some advanced techniqueor work on <strong>the</strong> frontier <strong>of</strong> some narrow specialty may <strong>in</strong>deed be valuable,but it is no pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong> itself <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> very basics <strong>of</strong> economics.(I have encountered a few economists who constitute examples <strong>of</strong> thispo<strong>in</strong>t.)ese thoughts make me wonder how consistent Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollisonare <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir faith <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> market test. Are <strong>the</strong>y prepared to rank publicationsby <strong>the</strong>ir circulation numbers? Or, as <strong>in</strong> some circles, do skillfully writtencontents <strong>and</strong> wide readership affect appraisals negatively?As for apprais<strong>in</strong>g persons, it is one th<strong>in</strong>g to make appraisals responsiblywhen choices must be made, as among c<strong>and</strong>idates for employment,promotion, <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essional honors. It is ano<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>g to make appraisals<strong>in</strong> a vacuum, out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> necessity—secondh<strong>and</strong> appraisals thatmay even be abused for thirdh<strong>and</strong> appraisals. Turn<strong>in</strong>g academic economics<strong>in</strong>to its own subject matter is narcissism. I wonder whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> apparentpopularity <strong>of</strong> articles rank<strong>in</strong>g departments <strong>and</strong> journals <strong>and</strong> personstraces to <strong>the</strong>ir appeal as material for gossip, like <strong>the</strong> appeal <strong>of</strong> tabloids soldat supermarket checkouts. (Similar thoughts come to m<strong>in</strong>d about somestr<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> economic imperialism, as <strong>in</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>gs that stra<strong>in</strong> to attributerent-seek<strong>in</strong>g motives to ever more <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficials.) --- So far I have been worry<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison market testto <strong>the</strong> extent that it is applied. But do Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison <strong>in</strong> fact have<strong>in</strong>fluence? I do not know. Conceivably, almost everybody ignores <strong>the</strong>m;on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>y are not unique <strong>in</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>the</strong>y do. What Ido know is that <strong>the</strong>y try to have an impact. eir numerical systems <strong>of</strong>rat<strong>in</strong>g persons <strong>and</strong> departments <strong>and</strong> journals are <strong>in</strong>tended to affect whatpeople do. Even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir article, <strong>the</strong>y preach at economists. ey preachabout publish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> prestigious journals, which implies (perhaps un<strong>in</strong>tentionally)preach<strong>in</strong>g about research on topics considered most acceptableto prestigious journals, preach<strong>in</strong>g about what to emphasize <strong>and</strong> what not,preach<strong>in</strong>g about research methods, preach<strong>in</strong>g about styles <strong>of</strong> exposition(sometimes even <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g strategic obscurity), <strong>and</strong> preach<strong>in</strong>g about try<strong>in</strong>gto associate oneself (as by judicious citations) to current fashions <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ession. e message, <strong>in</strong> short, is: compromise your st<strong>and</strong>ards. Put


124 Part I: Economicsless effort <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> work that you consider important, <strong>in</strong> whichyou have a comparative advantage, <strong>and</strong> that you enjoy. ( Joy is a legitimate<strong>in</strong>centive, but one eroded by Lab<strong>and</strong>-<strong>and</strong>-Tollison-type attitudes<strong>and</strong> practices.) Switch toward cater<strong>in</strong>g to editors <strong>and</strong> referees (who <strong>the</strong>mselvesoperate under similar pressures to <strong>the</strong> extent that Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollisonprevail).Such preach<strong>in</strong>g distresses me not merely because it is or might become<strong>in</strong>fluential but because it is <strong>of</strong>ficious <strong>and</strong> repellent <strong>in</strong> itself. Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison beg <strong>the</strong> question <strong>the</strong>y purportedly discuss: as unabashedsecondh<strong>and</strong>ers, <strong>the</strong>y simply assert or assume that <strong>the</strong>ir supposedmarket test is <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>the</strong> correct measure <strong>of</strong> excellence. But what justificationis it <strong>of</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> criteria that <strong>the</strong> players try to satisfy <strong>the</strong>m when<strong>the</strong>y are applied? Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison, cit<strong>in</strong>g earlier papers coauthoredby Lab<strong>and</strong>, argue, for example, that journal editors try to publish “highimpactpapers.” Well, it is no surprise that people respond to <strong>in</strong>centives,but to <strong>of</strong>fer this fact as justify<strong>in</strong>g a particular structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives iscircular reason<strong>in</strong>g.A fur<strong>the</strong>r sign <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> weakness <strong>of</strong> Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison’s case is <strong>the</strong>irresort to emotive words like “sour grapes” <strong>and</strong> “crybabyism.” Such namecall<strong>in</strong>ghardly applies to <strong>the</strong> em<strong>in</strong>ent economists, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Nobel laureates,who have expressed concern about <strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong> much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> academicliterature, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g what might be called its narcissistic or <strong>in</strong>cestuousaspects. What op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature may we <strong>in</strong>fer, by <strong>the</strong> way, preciselyamong economists who excuse neglect<strong>in</strong>g actually to read <strong>the</strong> workeven <strong>of</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idates be<strong>in</strong>g appraised?e personal nature <strong>of</strong> Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison’s attack fur<strong>the</strong>r appears<strong>in</strong> how <strong>the</strong>y characterize an alternative to secondh<strong>and</strong> appraisals, namely,reliance “on <strong>the</strong> ostensibly firsth<strong>and</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> some central authority, Examples <strong>of</strong> concern are cited <strong>in</strong> my articles <strong>of</strong> 1995 <strong>and</strong> 1997. Ano<strong>the</strong>r example isMcCloskey 1995. I cannot resist requot<strong>in</strong>g from McCloskey (p. 414) an exchange betweenGeorge Borts <strong>and</strong> Harry Johnson when both were journal editors. Borts: “[W]e get moregood articles than we know what to do with!” Johnson: “en why don’t you publisha few?”e tragedy <strong>of</strong> misdirected efforts is even worse than one might th<strong>in</strong>k from what actuallygets <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> journals. Economists with experience <strong>in</strong> referee<strong>in</strong>g manuscripts couldtestify to this po<strong>in</strong>t.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> a <strong>Test</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Truth</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Beauty</strong>? 125such as Yeager.” Yet this is not <strong>the</strong> alternative, as I have expla<strong>in</strong>ed above.Fur<strong>the</strong>r, Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison make a snide remark about “<strong>the</strong> literaturethat Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Yeager dotes on”—<strong>the</strong> literature <strong>of</strong> a cult for which “up isdown <strong>and</strong> down is up,” for which “fail<strong>in</strong>g a market test is really pass<strong>in</strong>g it,”<strong>and</strong> whose members are content just to chat among <strong>the</strong>mselves, forgo<strong>in</strong>gWimbledon <strong>in</strong> hopes <strong>of</strong> w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Austrian Open (p. 45). How do <strong>the</strong>yknow that I “dote” on such literature or that I “dote” on any literature? AsI made clear <strong>in</strong> 1997, I am no spokesman for any particular school or sect. Ihave a low op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>of</strong> much Austrian literature, as well as a high op<strong>in</strong>ion<strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> it, op<strong>in</strong>ions that I have formed myself <strong>and</strong> have not takenover secondh<strong>and</strong>. Of course much crummy work, along with excuses forit, is knock<strong>in</strong>g around <strong>in</strong> economics, as <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r fields. What does thatfact have to do with <strong>the</strong> issue under discussion—appraisal by a supposedmarket test?Are Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison will<strong>in</strong>g to let <strong>the</strong>ir remark about what I“dote” on rema<strong>in</strong> as an example <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>of</strong> accuracy <strong>and</strong> relevance?eir analogy with tennis tournaments reflects, by <strong>the</strong> way, <strong>the</strong>irobsession with <strong>the</strong> game aspect <strong>of</strong> academic life.Let me be clear about what I am not say<strong>in</strong>g. I never questioned <strong>the</strong> needfor st<strong>and</strong>ards, nor <strong>the</strong> uphill battle that unpopular ideas necessarily <strong>and</strong>even appropriately face, nor <strong>the</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> secondh<strong>and</strong>ism <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>ds<strong>and</strong> degrees <strong>and</strong> for some purposes. I am not sweep<strong>in</strong>gly condemn<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> literature <strong>of</strong> academic economics. Economists cont<strong>in</strong>ue mak<strong>in</strong>g solidcontributions despite everyth<strong>in</strong>g.I regret <strong>the</strong> perversion <strong>of</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ards through glorification <strong>of</strong> secondh<strong>and</strong>ism.When appraisals are necessary, <strong>the</strong>y should be kept as close aspracticable to persons who have <strong>the</strong> most direct knowledge <strong>and</strong> who bearresponsibility for <strong>the</strong>ir judgments. I regret <strong>the</strong> streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>centivesto jump onto b<strong>and</strong>wagons. I implore readers to learn lessons from <strong>the</strong>characters <strong>in</strong> Ayn R<strong>and</strong>’s novels who ei<strong>the</strong>r are secondh<strong>and</strong>ers <strong>the</strong>mselves I do not know whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g remark (2000, p. 43) is also directed aga<strong>in</strong>stme personally, but it is a sneer at someone, if only a straw man: “It is not enough for <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual qua scientist to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that he has been enlightened <strong>and</strong> knows <strong>the</strong> truth.”While unhappy about <strong>the</strong> likely consequences <strong>of</strong> Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison’s attitudes <strong>and</strong>practices, I am not angry about be<strong>in</strong>g personally attacked. eir attack helps reveal <strong>the</strong>nature <strong>and</strong> weakness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir case.


126 Part I: Economicsor exploit o<strong>the</strong>r people’s secondh<strong>and</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir susceptibility to <strong>in</strong>tellectual<strong>in</strong>timidation. (R<strong>and</strong> provides <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> crav<strong>in</strong>g for prestigethat I could scarcely hope to reproduce here.)We should beware <strong>of</strong> relativism about truth. Beyond <strong>the</strong> game-likeor fame-<strong>and</strong>-fortune side <strong>of</strong> academic careers, <strong>the</strong> truth-<strong>and</strong>-beauty sidedeserves cultivation. Communication is important, even <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g skillfulcommunication <strong>of</strong> knowledge to students <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> broad public.Above all, I warn aga<strong>in</strong>st discredit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> valid case for <strong>the</strong> free societyby misconstru<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> market as an entity <strong>in</strong> its own right that transcends<strong>the</strong> mere men <strong>and</strong> women who trade on it, an entity that makes superiorjudgments even about good <strong>and</strong> bad. Obstacles to underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> logic<strong>of</strong> a market economy are great enough already. A spurious l<strong>in</strong>kage <strong>in</strong> people’sm<strong>in</strong>ds between a twisted version <strong>of</strong> free-marketry <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> serious,valid, <strong>and</strong> quite different case for <strong>the</strong> free market can only harm <strong>the</strong> cause<strong>of</strong> freedom. Overreach<strong>in</strong>g boomerangs.B<strong>in</strong>swanger, Harry, ed. e Ayn R<strong>and</strong> Lexicon. New York: New American Library,1986.Brown, Harry Gunnison. “Two Decades <strong>of</strong> Decadence <strong>in</strong> Economic eoriz<strong>in</strong>g.”1948. In Some Disturb<strong>in</strong>g Inhibitions <strong>and</strong> Fallacies <strong>in</strong> Current Academic Economics,pp. 37–64. New York: Robert Schalkenbach Foundation, 1950.Buchanan, James M. “e Metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> John Gray.” Constitutional <strong>Political</strong><strong>Economy</strong> 6, no. 3 (1995): 293–295.Butos, William N., <strong>and</strong> Roger Koppl. “Big Players <strong>and</strong> Entrepreneurial Traditions:How Keynesian Policies May Create a Kaleidic <strong>Economy</strong>.” Paper for<strong>the</strong> Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Economic Association Meet<strong>in</strong>gs, New Orleans, 1995.Hayek, F.A. e Constitution <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press,1960.Heyne, Paul. Review <strong>of</strong> e Moral <strong>Economy</strong>, by John P. Powelson. IndependentReview 5 (Summer 2000): 137–140. Consider <strong>the</strong> way Lab<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Tollison draw a scarcely veiled contrast between workat <strong>the</strong> supposed frontier <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>ferior work, as well as <strong>the</strong> general tone <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>ir writ<strong>in</strong>g. A whiff appears <strong>of</strong> “<strong>the</strong> argument from <strong>in</strong>timidation,” so identified by AynR<strong>and</strong> (B<strong>in</strong>swanger 1986, pp. 32–34).


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> a <strong>Test</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Truth</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Beauty</strong>? 127Koppl, Roger, <strong>and</strong> Lel<strong>and</strong> B. Yeager. “Big Players <strong>and</strong> Herd<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Asset <strong>Market</strong>s:e Case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Russian Ruble.” Explorations <strong>in</strong> Economic History 33 (1996):367–383.Lab<strong>and</strong>, David N., <strong>and</strong> Christopher N. Taylor. “e Impact <strong>of</strong> Bad Writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>Economics.” Economic Inquiry 30 (October 1992): 673–688.Lab<strong>and</strong>, David N., <strong>and</strong> Robert D. Tollison. “On Secondh<strong>and</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> ScientificAppraisal.” Quarterly Journal <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 3 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g 2000): 43–48.Lee, Dwight R. “e <strong>Market</strong> Didn’t Do It.” e Freeman: Ideas on Liberty 46(December 1996): 787–789.. “Economics with Romance.” Independent Review 5 (Summer 2000):121–129.McCloskey, D.N. “Writ<strong>in</strong>g as a Responsibility <strong>of</strong> Science: A Reply to Lab<strong>and</strong><strong>and</strong> Taylor.” Economic Inquiry 30 (October 1992): 689–695.. “Kelly Green Golf Shoes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Intellectual Range from M to N.”Eastern Economic Journal 21 (Summer 1995): 411–414.Philbrook, Clarence E. “‘Realism’ <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal.” American Economic Review43 (December 1953): 846–859.Tullock, Gordon. e Politics <strong>of</strong> Bureaucracy. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.: Public AffairsPress, 1965.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “Tacit Preachments Are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d.” Journal <strong>of</strong> EconomicMethodology 2, no. 1 (1995): 1–33. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted here as chapter .. “Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> <strong>Test</strong>.” Journal <strong>of</strong>Economic Perspectives 11 (Fall 1997): 153–165. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted here as chapter .


Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong>Coord<strong>in</strong>ation *A more exact, though wordy, title for this chapter would be “Macroeconomics,Coord<strong>in</strong>ation, <strong>and</strong> Discoord<strong>in</strong>ation.” Macroeconomics studiesdisruptions to <strong>the</strong> economywide coord<strong>in</strong>ation processes that microeconomicsexpla<strong>in</strong>s. An emphasis, <strong>in</strong>stead, on aggregate dem<strong>and</strong> fac<strong>in</strong>g aggregatesupply is hopelessly superficial. It is st<strong>and</strong>ard nowadays to bewail disarray <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> monetary<strong>the</strong>ory. Fundamentalist Keynesianism, as we might call it, dom<strong>in</strong>atedtextbooks <strong>and</strong> policy circles for roughly three decades. Experience <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory<strong>the</strong>n discredited it. e fundamentalists brooded about <strong>in</strong>adequacy <strong>of</strong>total spend<strong>in</strong>g (or occasionally <strong>the</strong> reverse), about <strong>the</strong> propensity to consumeout <strong>of</strong> real <strong>in</strong>come, <strong>and</strong> about a sav<strong>in</strong>g gap that grows with <strong>in</strong>come<strong>and</strong> wealth <strong>and</strong> so becomes all <strong>the</strong> harder to fill with <strong>in</strong>vestment spend<strong>in</strong>g,especially as real capital formation leaves fewer attractive opportunities forstill fur<strong>the</strong>r private <strong>in</strong>vestment. Even nowadays, policymakers <strong>and</strong> a feweconomists still cl<strong>in</strong>g to some such doctr<strong>in</strong>e by default <strong>and</strong> still recommendexp<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g “aggregate dem<strong>and</strong>” to “stimulate” national <strong>and</strong> worldeconomies, albeit at <strong>the</strong> risk <strong>of</strong> price <strong>in</strong>flation implied by <strong>the</strong> equally discreditednotion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Phillips curve.An alternative school <strong>of</strong> Keynesian <strong>in</strong>terpretation stems from RobertClower (1984) <strong>and</strong> Axel Leijonhufvud (1968, 1981). As history <strong>of</strong> economicthought it may be questionable, but its substance deserves ample attention.*Orig<strong>in</strong>ally entitled “Austrian emes <strong>in</strong> a Reconstructed Macroeconomics,” thischapter derives from a conference presentation <strong>in</strong> Amsterdam, January 1995, published<strong>in</strong> Austrian Economics <strong>in</strong> Debate, eds. Willem Keizer et al. (London <strong>and</strong> New York: Routledge,1997): 22–41. It is considerably updated here.128


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 129It features such concepts as absence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> (supposed) Walrasian auctioneer,<strong>in</strong>complete <strong>and</strong> costly <strong>and</strong> imperfect <strong>in</strong>formation, false price signals,sluggish price adjustments, quantity changes as well as price adjustments,<strong>the</strong> duality <strong>of</strong> people’s decisions about particular transactions accord<strong>in</strong>gas <strong>the</strong>y are or are not frustrated <strong>in</strong> accomplish<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r desired transactions,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> “<strong>in</strong>come-constra<strong>in</strong>ed process” <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>fectious recession <strong>and</strong>recovery.A quite different group <strong>of</strong> self-styled Keynesians centered at CambridgeUniversity expresses sweep<strong>in</strong>g skepticism about market-orientedeconomic <strong>the</strong>ory. In <strong>the</strong> United States, economists associated with <strong>the</strong>Journal <strong>of</strong> Post Keynesian Economics form still ano<strong>the</strong>r school.Some “monetarists” or “monetary-disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>orists” cont<strong>in</strong>ueactive <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> tradition <strong>of</strong> David Hume, Henry ornton, Clark Warburton,Milton Friedman, Anna Schwartz, Karl Brunner, <strong>and</strong> Allan Meltzer.eir <strong>in</strong>fluence has been eroded, however, by developments that havemade <strong>the</strong>ir formerly suggested policy <strong>of</strong> steady monetary growth no longerapplicable <strong>and</strong> also by mis<strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong> experience. Monetarism hasalso suffered from attention paid to two schools that have distorted <strong>and</strong>exaggerated certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> its tenets. e New Classical economists (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>gRobert Lucas, omas Sargent, <strong>and</strong> Robert Barro) proclaimed rationalexpectations <strong>and</strong> equilibrium always. (In effect, everyth<strong>in</strong>g is alwayscoord<strong>in</strong>ated, or almost so.) eir position ga<strong>in</strong>ed attention more because<strong>of</strong> its coherence with <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> methodological fashion than because<strong>of</strong> its empirical substance, later widely questioned (Howitt 1990, chap. 4).e real-bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle school carried <strong>the</strong> exaggerations <strong>of</strong> New Classicaleconomics still fur<strong>the</strong>r. It <strong>in</strong>terpreted macroeconomic fluctuations asefficient responses to underly<strong>in</strong>g real changes (as <strong>in</strong> technology) ra<strong>the</strong>rthan as consequences <strong>of</strong> monetary disturbances. Robert K<strong>in</strong>g, CharlesPlosser, <strong>and</strong> Edward Prescott have written along this l<strong>in</strong>e; Strong<strong>in</strong> (1988)<strong>and</strong> Stockman (1988) provide convenient surveys. Gary Hansen <strong>and</strong> R<strong>and</strong>allWright (1992) provide an example <strong>of</strong> t<strong>in</strong>ker<strong>in</strong>g with this <strong>the</strong>ory torescue it from recalcitrant facts; <strong>the</strong>y would do well to remember aboutPtolemy <strong>and</strong> epicycles. Gary Hansen <strong>and</strong> Edward Prescott conveyed <strong>the</strong>impression, without explicitly say<strong>in</strong>g so, that <strong>the</strong>y were answer<strong>in</strong>g “yes”to <strong>the</strong> question posed by <strong>the</strong> title <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir 1993 article, “Did TechnologyShocks Cause <strong>the</strong> 1990–1991 Recession?”Both <strong>the</strong> New Classical <strong>and</strong> real-bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle schools tacitly attributednear-perfection to markets (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g “efficient markets” <strong>in</strong> securities),as if <strong>the</strong>ir members were congratulat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mselves on be<strong>in</strong>g “more


130 Part I: Economicsfree-market-oriented than thou.” (I am report<strong>in</strong>g my impression <strong>of</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>es,not conjectur<strong>in</strong>g about anyone’s motives nor say<strong>in</strong>g that exaggerationcrowds out scholarly substance; still, fads do come <strong>and</strong> go <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>academic world.)Self-parody<strong>in</strong>g free-marketry has h<strong>and</strong>ed an opportunity to look sensibleby contrast to self-styled New Keynesians, who share several perceptions<strong>of</strong> reality with <strong>the</strong> monetarists <strong>and</strong> who take imperfect competition<strong>and</strong> price <strong>and</strong> wage stick<strong>in</strong>ess seriously. (Examples <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> this mislead<strong>in</strong>glynamed school appear <strong>in</strong> Mankiw <strong>and</strong> Romer 1991.) As Axel Leijonhufvud(1986) has noted <strong>in</strong> a more general context, macroeconomistshave been play<strong>in</strong>g musical chairs with doctr<strong>in</strong>al positions <strong>and</strong> labels.Nowadays (around 2010), a new-classical/new-Keynesian syn<strong>the</strong>sis,also called dynamic (or dynamic stochastic) general-equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory,enjoys academic prestige. It explores <strong>the</strong> properties <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical models<strong>and</strong> tweaks <strong>the</strong>m to remove blatant contrasts with statistics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>real world. It assumes rational expectations, which is sensible enough iftaken to mean no more than that people will not persist <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g recognizedmistakes. It assumes that markets are always <strong>in</strong> or near equilibrium—<strong>in</strong>some stretched sense <strong>of</strong> that word—so show<strong>in</strong>g scant attentionto <strong>the</strong> issues <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong> discoord<strong>in</strong>ation that concern Austrianeconomists. is disarray <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics gives Austrian-school economists, aswell as monetarists <strong>and</strong> New Keynesians, an opportunity to set <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream <strong>of</strong> macroeconomics on a sounder course. Two major characteristics,besides o<strong>the</strong>rs mentioned below, especially equip Austrians to seizethis opportunity. First, it focuses on <strong>the</strong> central problem bridg<strong>in</strong>g micro<strong>and</strong> macro economics, <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> economywide coord<strong>in</strong>ation. (GeraldO’Driscoll aptly entitled his doctoral dissertation Economics as a Coord<strong>in</strong>ationProblem.) Second, it is readier than o<strong>the</strong>r free-market-orientedschools to face reality as it is, “warts <strong>and</strong> all.”Robert Clower (1984, p. 272) observed that<strong>the</strong> approaches <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Keynesians, monetarists, <strong>and</strong> new classical economiststo monetary <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> macroeconomics will get us exactly nowhere Some might consider this characterization unfair. For an enthusiastic textbook treatment,see Wickens 2008.


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 131because each is founded, one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r, on <strong>the</strong> conventional butempirically fallacious assumption that <strong>the</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> economicactivities is costless.As this remark suggests, <strong>the</strong> key question <strong>of</strong> money/macro <strong>the</strong>ory isnot “What determ<strong>in</strong>es whe<strong>the</strong>r aggregate dem<strong>and</strong> for goods <strong>and</strong> servicesis deficient or excessive or just right?” but “What determ<strong>in</strong>es whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>processes <strong>of</strong> exchange <strong>and</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> an economy <strong>of</strong> decentralizeddecisionmak<strong>in</strong>g are work<strong>in</strong>g smoothly?”Austrian economists recognize <strong>the</strong> disaggregated character <strong>of</strong> economicactivity. ey take seriously <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ound differences between anadvanced economy <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed division <strong>of</strong> labor <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> nearly selfsufficientm<strong>in</strong>iature economy <strong>of</strong> a medieval monastery or manor or <strong>of</strong>Swiss family Rob<strong>in</strong>son on its desert isl<strong>and</strong> (cf. Eucken 1950). Knowledge<strong>of</strong> wants, resources, technology, <strong>and</strong> market opportunities, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>gknowledge <strong>of</strong> temporary <strong>and</strong> local conditions, is radically decentralized<strong>and</strong> simply could not be made available to central planners <strong>in</strong> anyth<strong>in</strong>gapproach<strong>in</strong>g its fullness. If knowledge is not to go to waste, production<strong>and</strong> consumption decisions must be radically decentralized (Hayek1945/1949). Specialization greatly enhances productivity. People produce<strong>the</strong>ir own particular goods <strong>and</strong> services to exchange <strong>the</strong>m away, <strong>the</strong>rebyexercis<strong>in</strong>g dem<strong>and</strong> for what o<strong>the</strong>r specialists are produc<strong>in</strong>g. But what coord<strong>in</strong>atesall <strong>the</strong>se fragmented activities?e debates over economic calculation under socialism <strong>and</strong> capitalism<strong>in</strong>itiated by Ludwig von Mises <strong>and</strong> Friedrich Hayek illum<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong>scope <strong>of</strong> this question (cf. <strong>the</strong> literature reviewed <strong>in</strong> Yeager 1994). Even<strong>the</strong> mere physical mesh<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> activities as portrayed <strong>in</strong> a self-consistent<strong>in</strong>put-output table is hard enough to achieve <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> genu<strong>in</strong>emarkets <strong>and</strong> prices, as Soviet experience testifies. Full coord<strong>in</strong>ation is astill more dem<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g task. It requires tak<strong>in</strong>g account <strong>of</strong> physical <strong>and</strong> subjectivesubstitutabilities <strong>and</strong> complementarities among goods <strong>and</strong> services<strong>and</strong> factors <strong>of</strong> production <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir various uses <strong>in</strong> consumption <strong>and</strong> productionso that no unit <strong>of</strong> a productive resource goes to satisfy a less <strong>in</strong>tenseeffective f<strong>in</strong>al dem<strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> denial <strong>of</strong> a more <strong>in</strong>tense dem<strong>and</strong>. <strong>Market</strong>bids <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>fers for resources <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al goods play a central role <strong>in</strong> thisprocess, but its very complexity permits glitches.Forces <strong>of</strong> unbalanced supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> tend, to be sure, to pressdisequilibrium prices toward <strong>the</strong>ir market-clear<strong>in</strong>g levels. What ensures,however, that <strong>the</strong>se coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g forces operate rapidly enough <strong>and</strong> thatimpediments to transactions do not re<strong>in</strong>force each o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> meanwhile


132 Part I: Economicsto a degree that shows up as recession or depression? Because <strong>the</strong> fundamental<strong>in</strong>sight <strong>of</strong> Say’s Law is correct—supplies <strong>of</strong> particular goods <strong>and</strong>services constitute dem<strong>and</strong>s for o<strong>the</strong>rs, sooner or later—<strong>the</strong> fundamentalmacroeconomic problem cannot be a deficiency <strong>of</strong> aggregate dem<strong>and</strong>.However, anyth<strong>in</strong>g that impairs <strong>the</strong> processes <strong>of</strong> market exchange alsoimpairs production. People work <strong>and</strong> produce <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> expectation <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gable to exchange <strong>the</strong>ir outputs away, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y will not persist <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>itely(especially not <strong>in</strong> buy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>puts for unsalable outputs) if <strong>the</strong>ir attemptedexchanges keep on be<strong>in</strong>g frustrated. Goods <strong>and</strong> services exchange for eacho<strong>the</strong>r not directly but through <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>termediaries <strong>of</strong> money <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> creditdenom<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> ultimately to be settled <strong>in</strong> money. Monetary disordercan snarl up <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> exchange <strong>and</strong> so impede production. Austrians,like monetarists, are prepared to take this snarl seriously.ese considerations help argue, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, for putt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> microsemester <strong>of</strong> a Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> Economics course before <strong>the</strong> macro semester.Students can hardly underst<strong>and</strong> disruptions <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation until <strong>the</strong>yknow that a coord<strong>in</strong>ation problem exists <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>how <strong>the</strong> market process solves it when it is work<strong>in</strong>g well.Coord<strong>in</strong>ation requires more than correct prices. In Walrasian models<strong>of</strong> general equilibrium, <strong>the</strong> “auctioneer” not only achieves <strong>the</strong> whole array<strong>of</strong> market-clear<strong>in</strong>g prices but also puts trad<strong>in</strong>g partners <strong>in</strong> contact withone ano<strong>the</strong>r, obviat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> costly mutual searches o<strong>the</strong>rwise necessary.In effect he makes all assets equally liquid—equally readily marketableor usable as means <strong>of</strong> payment—at <strong>the</strong>ir general-equilibrium prices. Itis questionable whe<strong>the</strong>r models featur<strong>in</strong>g such a mythical personage cancontribute much to illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g macroeconomic issues. In <strong>the</strong> real world, however, a worker may be unemployed not necessarilybecause he <strong>in</strong>sists on too high a wage rate but because he <strong>and</strong>a suitable employer have not yet made contact. Various startup costs <strong>of</strong>a new employer-employee relation also enter <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> story. In <strong>the</strong> realworld, prices are not <strong>the</strong> only bearers <strong>of</strong> signals <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives about potentialtransactions. Quantities also perform <strong>the</strong>se functions—quantities <strong>of</strong>goods, services, <strong>and</strong> factors <strong>in</strong> accomplished transactions, frustrated transactions,<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>ventory buildups <strong>and</strong> rundowns. Inventory management,quality verification, advertis<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formational <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r such activitiesbear on whe<strong>the</strong>r transactions can go forward to <strong>the</strong> mutual benefit <strong>of</strong> Léon Walras did not postulate <strong>the</strong> auctioneer explicitly; that secretary <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market,possess<strong>in</strong>g prodigious <strong>in</strong>formational <strong>and</strong> calculat<strong>in</strong>g abilities, is an <strong>in</strong>vention <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpreters.See chapter , note .


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 133<strong>the</strong> parties. ese activities have “transactions costs” <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>clusive sense<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term. Many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m impede not only actual transactions but evenmessages <strong>of</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness to buy or sell.Recoord<strong>in</strong>ation to recover from recession requires more, <strong>the</strong>n, thanjust adjust<strong>in</strong>g prices <strong>and</strong> wages. Bus<strong>in</strong>ess contacts must be restored orrevised. Information, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation about market conditions,must be brought up to date <strong>and</strong> transmitted. Costs <strong>and</strong> complexities <strong>of</strong> reality help expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> habits, rout<strong>in</strong>es,<strong>and</strong> long-term bus<strong>in</strong>ess relations, as between supplier <strong>and</strong> customer,employer <strong>and</strong> worker, <strong>and</strong> borrower <strong>and</strong> bank. Not every bus<strong>in</strong>ess relationis cont<strong>in</strong>uously open to price revision, as abstract equilibrium <strong>the</strong>orymight seem to recommend. e very concept <strong>of</strong> different degrees <strong>of</strong> liquidity<strong>of</strong> various f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>and</strong> real assets reflects recognition that priceis not <strong>the</strong> only determ<strong>in</strong>ant <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r potential transactions get consummated.If all goods were perfectly liquid, as tacitly assumed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>Walrasian model, <strong>the</strong>n impediments to communication would have beenremoved. Howitt (1990), writ<strong>in</strong>g partly under <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>spiration <strong>of</strong> Clower<strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud, surveys some <strong>of</strong> forego<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mes, as does Okun (1981).Howitt, as well as Hall (1991), comments on difficulties <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g trad<strong>in</strong>gpartners <strong>in</strong> “th<strong>in</strong>” as opposed to “thick” markets. By analogy, my <strong>in</strong>stall<strong>in</strong>ga telephone benefits people who might want to reach me but imposesa congestion cost on people who might want to reach people talk<strong>in</strong>gwith me.Whe<strong>the</strong>r a particular transaction can go forward depends on muchmore than <strong>the</strong> terms subject to negotiation between <strong>the</strong> two potentialtrad<strong>in</strong>g partners. Whe<strong>the</strong>r a manufacturer <strong>and</strong> a potential employee couldboth benefit from <strong>the</strong>ir relation depends on more than <strong>the</strong> wage rate. Itdepends on prices charged by competitors <strong>and</strong> by suppliers <strong>of</strong> materials,on terms on which energy, transportation, <strong>and</strong> credit are available, on marketconditions fac<strong>in</strong>g potential customers, on <strong>in</strong>ventories <strong>of</strong> various k<strong>in</strong>ds,<strong>and</strong> on much else besides.Changes affect<strong>in</strong>g such conditions are cont<strong>in</strong>ually go<strong>in</strong>g on, challeng<strong>in</strong>gentrepreneurs to cope with <strong>the</strong>m, as by develop<strong>in</strong>g new bus<strong>in</strong>ess opportunitiesto replace fad<strong>in</strong>g ones. In ord<strong>in</strong>ary times, entrepreneurs cont<strong>in</strong>uallyaccomplish myriads <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terdependent microeconomic adjustmentswithout palpable macroeconomic disorder.


134 Part I: EconomicsWhen major economywide disruptions occur, however, it is not surpris<strong>in</strong>gthat <strong>the</strong> many necessary <strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g adjustments should stretchout pa<strong>in</strong>fully over time. Much besides prices <strong>and</strong> wages must change, foreven a purely monetary shock (whatever one might be) has “real” consequences.Knowledge must be transmitted <strong>and</strong> received, risk allowedfor, comb<strong>in</strong>ations <strong>of</strong> factors <strong>and</strong> products <strong>in</strong> production <strong>and</strong> consumptionrevised, search conducted, trad<strong>in</strong>g partners contacted, <strong>and</strong> new quantities<strong>of</strong> goods produced <strong>and</strong> exchanged. Stick<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> prices <strong>and</strong> wages delays<strong>the</strong> transmission <strong>of</strong> appropriate signals <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives. (“Price stick<strong>in</strong>ess”may serve as a convenient term allud<strong>in</strong>g to myriad obstacles to prompt<strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>less adjustment. It is a shorth<strong>and</strong> label for a wide range <strong>of</strong> circumstances.)By adopt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> fashionable assumption <strong>of</strong> rational expectations, NewClassicals <strong>and</strong> subsequently even <strong>the</strong> New Keynesians tacitly assumedaway central aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economywide coord<strong>in</strong>ation problem. eyreplaced a vision <strong>of</strong> people try<strong>in</strong>g to set prices <strong>and</strong> quantities <strong>and</strong> strikebarga<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> a world <strong>of</strong> fragmentary <strong>and</strong> dispersed <strong>in</strong>formation with anunrealistic vision <strong>of</strong> remarkably well-<strong>in</strong>formed people—<strong>in</strong>formed, to besure, not <strong>of</strong> specific future quantities <strong>and</strong> prices but well <strong>in</strong>formed onaverage about probability distributions. To assume rational expectationsoversimplifies problems <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g people’s beliefs: “No one makessystematic errors <strong>in</strong> guess<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> values <strong>of</strong> variables that depend <strong>in</strong> turnupon o<strong>the</strong>rs’ guesses” (Howitt 1990, pp. 12–13).“” In us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir word, I am defy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>orists who judge reality “imperfect” <strong>in</strong>comparison with textbook chapters on equilibrium under pure <strong>and</strong> perfectcompetition <strong>and</strong> who <strong>the</strong>reby damn reality for be<strong>in</strong>g real. Of course no“Walrasian” auctioneer is at work achiev<strong>in</strong>g ideal outcomes. Of course notall imag<strong>in</strong>able <strong>in</strong>tertemporal markets <strong>and</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>gent-state markets exist.Of course full coord<strong>in</strong>ation is never achieved; <strong>and</strong> it is approached, to <strong>the</strong>extent that it is, through <strong>the</strong> piecemeal, asynchronous grop<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> myriads<strong>of</strong> entrepreneurs. eory relevant to <strong>the</strong> real world cannot conf<strong>in</strong>e itself toequilibrium analysis <strong>and</strong> comparative statics. Instead <strong>of</strong> a state <strong>of</strong> affairs,competition is a process. Except perhaps for organized exchanges forst<strong>and</strong>ardized commodities <strong>and</strong> securities, no impersonal “market” adjustsprices to changed conditions. People change prices, <strong>and</strong> only after <strong>the</strong>yhave perceived reasons to do so. Reasons <strong>in</strong>clude opportunities <strong>of</strong>fered


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 135by changes <strong>in</strong> technology <strong>and</strong> notably <strong>in</strong>clude perceived market imbalances<strong>and</strong> frustrations <strong>of</strong> transactions at <strong>the</strong> old prices. Perceptions <strong>and</strong>responses are not <strong>in</strong>stantaneous.Already <strong>in</strong> his eory <strong>of</strong> Money <strong>and</strong> Credit (1912/1981, pp. 186–187), Ludwigvon Mises recognized such facts <strong>of</strong> reality. Many prices are deliberatelyset, obviously <strong>in</strong> retail trade, <strong>and</strong> set by trial <strong>and</strong> error.Now this phenomenon is not accidental. It is an <strong>in</strong>evitable phenomenon<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unorganized market. In <strong>the</strong> unorganized market, <strong>the</strong> seller doesnot come <strong>in</strong>to contact with all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> buyers, but only with s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>in</strong>dividualsor groups.... Consequently <strong>the</strong> seller fixes a price that <strong>in</strong> his op<strong>in</strong>ioncorresponds approximately to what <strong>the</strong> price ought to be (<strong>in</strong> which it isunderst<strong>and</strong>able that he is more likely to aim too high than too low), <strong>and</strong>waits to see what <strong>the</strong> buyers will do.... e sole way by which sellers canarrive at reliable knowledge about <strong>the</strong> valuations <strong>of</strong> consumers is <strong>the</strong> way<strong>of</strong> trial <strong>and</strong> error.Institutional forces work to postpone price changes o<strong>the</strong>rwise calledfor by small or transitory changes <strong>in</strong> supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> (1912/1981, p. 134).“Every change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> market data has its def<strong>in</strong>ite effects upon <strong>the</strong> market.It takes a def<strong>in</strong>ite length <strong>of</strong> time before all <strong>the</strong>se effects are consummated,i.e., before <strong>the</strong> market is completely adjusted to <strong>the</strong> new state <strong>of</strong> affairs”(Mises 1949/1963, p. 652).[C]hanges <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> factors which determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> formation <strong>of</strong> prices donot produce all <strong>the</strong>ir effects at once. A span <strong>of</strong> time must elapse beforeall <strong>the</strong>ir effects are exhausted. Between <strong>the</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> a new datum<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> perfect adjustment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market to it some time must pass....In deal<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> any change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> factors operat<strong>in</strong>g on<strong>the</strong> market, we must never forget that we are deal<strong>in</strong>g with events tak<strong>in</strong>gplace <strong>in</strong> succession, with a series <strong>of</strong> effects succeed<strong>in</strong>g one ano<strong>the</strong>r. Weare not <strong>in</strong> a position to know <strong>in</strong> advance how much time will have toelapse. (p. 246)Mises recognizes a certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>ertia <strong>of</strong> prices (1912/1981, pp. 133–136).Relatedly, he recognizes that flexible exchange rates tend to move ahead<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir purchas<strong>in</strong>g-power parities; relatively, prices <strong>of</strong> many goods<strong>and</strong> services are sluggish (1949/1963, pp. 455–456). Mitchell (1908/1966,pp. 259–283) observed <strong>the</strong> same phenomenon <strong>in</strong> detail <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> U.S. “greenback”period <strong>of</strong> 1862–1878. Mises also observes more <strong>of</strong> a historical element<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> money than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> any ord<strong>in</strong>ary good.


136 Part I: Economics[A] historically cont<strong>in</strong>uous component is conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> objective exchangevalue <strong>of</strong> money. e past value <strong>of</strong> money is taken over by <strong>the</strong>present <strong>and</strong> transformed by it.... Prices change slowly because <strong>the</strong> subjectivevaluations <strong>of</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>gs change slowly.... If rapid <strong>and</strong> erraticvaluations <strong>in</strong> prices were usually encountered <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> market, <strong>the</strong> conception<strong>of</strong> objective exchange value would not have atta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> significancethat it is actually accorded both by consumer <strong>and</strong> producer.In this sense, reference to an <strong>in</strong>ertia <strong>of</strong> prices is unobjectionable. (1912/1981,p. 133)It is so far as <strong>the</strong> money prices <strong>of</strong> goods are determ<strong>in</strong>ed by monetaryfactors, that a historically cont<strong>in</strong>uous component is <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m,without which <strong>the</strong>ir actual level could not be expla<strong>in</strong>ed. (p. 135) Without explicitly say<strong>in</strong>g so, <strong>the</strong>n, Mises clearly implies that money’s roleas unit <strong>of</strong> account contributes to <strong>the</strong> stick<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> prices. People are <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>habit <strong>of</strong> formulat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir subjective valuations <strong>of</strong> goods <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>money unit, <strong>and</strong> subjective valuations ord<strong>in</strong>arily do not change suddenly.Even if relatively objective developments do call for a change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> marketvalue <strong>of</strong> any ord<strong>in</strong>ary good or <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> money unit itself, people require timeto perceive <strong>and</strong> react to <strong>the</strong>se changes <strong>and</strong> to reformulate <strong>the</strong>ir valuations<strong>of</strong> goods <strong>in</strong> money (1912/1981, pp. 133–135; 1949/1963, p. 426). One might add, as Lerner (1952, pp. 191–193) did, that <strong>the</strong> most sweep<strong>in</strong>gsource <strong>of</strong> price stick<strong>in</strong>ess lies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> very nature <strong>of</strong> money. In a moneyeconomy, unlike a barter economy, people need not bo<strong>the</strong>r about all <strong>the</strong>real (relative) prices that might concern <strong>the</strong>m, for a th<strong>in</strong>g’s money price<strong>in</strong>dicates <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs that one might have <strong>in</strong>stead. A priceconveys <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> guides decisions, however, only if it is reasonablydependable. Imag<strong>in</strong>e how difficult decisions <strong>and</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation wouldbe if a th<strong>in</strong>g’s price today were only a poor clue to its price tomorrow.Substantial money <strong>and</strong> price <strong>in</strong>flation or deflation distorts relative prices<strong>and</strong> decisions <strong>and</strong> impairs coord<strong>in</strong>ation because not all money prices canbe equally flexible. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, stability <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> purchas<strong>in</strong>g power<strong>of</strong> money tends to re<strong>in</strong>force itself <strong>and</strong> deter accidental or r<strong>and</strong>om fluctuations;be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> general measure <strong>of</strong> value supports <strong>in</strong>stitutions, habits, Mises is only one <strong>of</strong> many economists who s<strong>in</strong>ce long ago have recognized pricestick<strong>in</strong>ess. e notion that attention to it is dist<strong>in</strong>ctively a contribution <strong>of</strong> Keynes is justwrong as history <strong>of</strong> economic thought. See my 1991/1997.


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 137<strong>and</strong> expectations that work to this effect. In short, thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g wage<strong>and</strong> price flexibility would keep money from serv<strong>in</strong>g its normal purposes;it could not survive. A degree <strong>of</strong> price stick<strong>in</strong>ess—or dependability—is nomystery. A lead<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>me <strong>of</strong> Mises’s <strong>the</strong>ory is that money is far from neutral <strong>in</strong>its effects on quantities, <strong>in</strong>comes, <strong>and</strong> relative prices (1949/1963, pp. 408ff.).Prices do not automatically set <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> proportion to <strong>the</strong> total quantity<strong>of</strong> money, as a naive <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantity-<strong>the</strong>ory equationmight suggest. Some changes occur relatively rapidly, o<strong>the</strong>rs after longdelays. People’s responses to ongo<strong>in</strong>g monetary <strong>and</strong> price <strong>in</strong>flation changeas experience accumulates <strong>and</strong> expectations change accord<strong>in</strong>gly. Mises’sdiscussion <strong>of</strong> differential price changes constitutes emphatic recognition<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> stick<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> many prices. is recognition is not a dist<strong>in</strong>ctivelyKeynesian notion, despite remarks by textbook authors neglectful <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>history <strong>of</strong> economic thought.Mises accepts <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> general equilibrium—<strong>the</strong> evenly rotat<strong>in</strong>geconomy, as he calls it—as a tool <strong>of</strong> analysis. Us<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong> no way entailssuppos<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong>f<strong>in</strong>al prices correspond<strong>in</strong>g to this imag<strong>in</strong>ary conception are ... identicalwith <strong>the</strong> market prices. e activities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> entrepreneurs or <strong>of</strong> any o<strong>the</strong>ractors on <strong>the</strong> economic scene are not guided by consideration <strong>of</strong> any suchth<strong>in</strong>gs as equilibrium prices <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> evenly rotat<strong>in</strong>g economy. (1949/1963,p. 329)Austrians are concerned with process—not merely with functionalrelations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical sense but with who does what, why, when,<strong>and</strong> how. Attention to process bars exclusive <strong>in</strong>fatuation with <strong>the</strong> equilibriumstate. (Austrian scorn for <strong>the</strong> neo-Walrasian br<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> generalequilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory is well known. It might well be better focused, however,than it habitually is.) Austrian economics recognizes <strong>the</strong> scope forentrepreneurship <strong>in</strong> disequilibrium. Recogniz<strong>in</strong>g disequilibrium is oneaspect <strong>of</strong> Austrian realism. Austrians are will<strong>in</strong>g to see <strong>the</strong> world as itactually is. ey are not sidetracked <strong>in</strong>to supposedly “rigorous” <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>gabout imag<strong>in</strong>ary worlds that diverge from reality <strong>in</strong> crucial respects.Austrians recognize that pure <strong>and</strong> perfect competition, like equilibrium,are abstractions <strong>and</strong> not reality. ese imag<strong>in</strong>ary extreme conditions do Roger Garrison objects to <strong>the</strong> term “sticky prices” on <strong>the</strong> grounds that stick<strong>in</strong>essimplies some sort <strong>of</strong> defect, as <strong>of</strong> a valve. Perhaps, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> term “dependable prices”would serve better.


138 Part I: Economicshave roles to play <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g, but economists should recognize when<strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong>applicable. In underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g money/macro phenomena <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>build<strong>in</strong>g bridges between macro <strong>and</strong> micro economics, it is essential torecognize that sellers are <strong>in</strong> general not pure price takers <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y arenot already sell<strong>in</strong>g all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir product or <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir labor that <strong>the</strong>y want tosell at <strong>the</strong> prevail<strong>in</strong>g price. In macroeconomics it is important to recognizethat most prices are set <strong>and</strong> not impersonally determ<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terplay<strong>of</strong> atomistic supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>.e Austrians’ concern for facts <strong>of</strong> reality is <strong>of</strong>ten overlooked because<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir supposed <strong>in</strong>sistence on a purely a priori method. is term, notablyas used by Ludwig von Mises, unfortunately <strong>in</strong>vites mis<strong>in</strong>terpretation. Soused, a priori suggests an un<strong>in</strong>tended sharp contrast with empirical. Misesdid not mean that all important propositions <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory can bespun out <strong>of</strong> factually empty logical truisms. He relied, ra<strong>the</strong>r, on axiomsfor which factual evidence constantly presses itself on us so abundantlythat we can hardly imag<strong>in</strong>e a world to which those axioms did not apply(cf. Rothbard 1957). Austrians do not—or should not—conf<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> honorificterm “empirical” to propositions dug out by arduous labor <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>doubtful general validity after all.In related respects, Austrians are more realistic than self-congratulat<strong>in</strong>g“empirical” researchers. ey open <strong>the</strong>ir eyes to what sorts <strong>of</strong> methodhave <strong>and</strong> what sorts have not brought important results. ey look at <strong>the</strong>facts bear<strong>in</strong>g on whe<strong>the</strong>r or not stable functions exist that quantitatively<strong>and</strong> dependably describe relations among economic magnitudes <strong>and</strong> thatmight be relied on for forecast<strong>in</strong>g. ey are at least as ready as o<strong>the</strong>r economiststo accept <strong>the</strong> facts that call <strong>in</strong>to question overambitious, activist,f<strong>in</strong>e-tun<strong>in</strong>g policies whose success presupposes know<strong>in</strong>g durable quantitativerelations., , What expla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> recessions that <strong>in</strong>terrupt prosperity from time to time? Each recession is a specific historical event. Researchers have <strong>the</strong> job <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g each one, ask<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m share some dom<strong>in</strong>antfeature <strong>and</strong> discard<strong>in</strong>g hypo<strong>the</strong>ses that do not fit <strong>the</strong> facts. It is I may seem to give unsuitably less attention to <strong>in</strong>flation than recession. e reason isnot complacency; on <strong>the</strong> contrary, I am someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> an anti<strong>in</strong>flation hawk. e reasonis that <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> money <strong>and</strong> price <strong>in</strong>flation is straightforward <strong>and</strong> well understood.Incomprehensibility is not <strong>the</strong> reason why impecunious governments so <strong>of</strong>ten disregard it.


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 139premature to start by suppos<strong>in</strong>g that one <strong>the</strong>ory fits all, just as it wouldbe to expect a s<strong>in</strong>gle cause <strong>of</strong> wars or revolutions or electoral l<strong>and</strong>slides.Macroeconomics is <strong>in</strong>herently a messier field than micro. Micro describesstraightforward pr<strong>in</strong>ciples that bear on decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g, coord<strong>in</strong>ation, <strong>and</strong>possible specific distortions <strong>of</strong> resource allocation. Macro studies whatmight go wrong on a large scale. Micro bears an analogy with describ<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> structure <strong>and</strong> function<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a healthy human body; macro resembles<strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> what might go wrong—diseases <strong>and</strong> wounds <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>numerablek<strong>in</strong>ds.Narrative <strong>and</strong> statistical history has conv<strong>in</strong>ced monetarists that mostrecessions exhibit a monetary disturbance—a shr<strong>in</strong>kage <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantity<strong>of</strong> money or, anyway, its downward deviation from a trend that wouldaccommodate real economic growth without a general fall <strong>in</strong> prices <strong>and</strong>wages. Monetarists can cite ample historical <strong>and</strong> statistical evidence frommany times <strong>and</strong> places. It is unnecessary to review this evidence here, butundue neglect warrants a plug <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> list <strong>of</strong> References for an <strong>in</strong>sightful <strong>and</strong>prescient article <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> monetarist tradition written by Harry GunnisonBrown just a few days before Frankl<strong>in</strong> Roosevelt took <strong>of</strong>fice at <strong>the</strong> depths<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Great Depression <strong>in</strong> 1933. In articles <strong>of</strong> 1989 <strong>and</strong> 1990, Christ<strong>in</strong>a<strong>and</strong> David Romer review recessions evidently caused by monetary policy<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States s<strong>in</strong>ce World War II.Money is not <strong>the</strong> only th<strong>in</strong>g, however, conceivably disrupt<strong>in</strong>g coord<strong>in</strong>ation.Severe “real” disturbances might overwhelm entrepreneurial effortsto cope with <strong>the</strong>m. It is <strong>in</strong>structive to ponder what would happen to totaloutput if <strong>the</strong> country’s telephone system (Hall 1991, p. 23) or, more starkly,if all <strong>of</strong> its electronic communications <strong>and</strong> data process<strong>in</strong>g were somehowto fail for several months.In historical fact, however, it is implausible to put special blame onsuch “real” disturbances for <strong>the</strong> major recessions <strong>and</strong> depressions actuallyexperienced. Instead <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g readily attributable to changes <strong>in</strong> productivecapacity, recessions <strong>and</strong> depressions exhibit what look like pervasive deficiencies<strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>, pervasive difficulties <strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g customers <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gjobs. A “real” <strong>the</strong>ory assum<strong>in</strong>g cont<strong>in</strong>uous market equilibrium is especiallyhard put to expla<strong>in</strong> eventual macroeconomic recoveries.Even a real disturbance as great as <strong>the</strong> shift from war to peace <strong>in</strong>1945–1946 brought a surpris<strong>in</strong>gly modest macroeconomic ripple, with lowunemployment despite demobilization. e two oil-price shocks <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>1970s might count as real causes <strong>of</strong> recession, but even <strong>the</strong>se had monetaryaspects. ey not only made old patterns <strong>of</strong> quantities <strong>and</strong> relative


140 Part I: Economicsprices wrong but also shrank real cash balances <strong>and</strong> reshuffled <strong>the</strong>ir ownership.Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, previous money <strong>and</strong> price <strong>in</strong>flation had helped trigger<strong>the</strong> oil shocks <strong>the</strong>mselves (<strong>and</strong> this <strong>in</strong>flation <strong>in</strong> turn arguably traced to abuilt-<strong>in</strong> bias <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Bretton Woods system).Ludwig von Mises aptly entitles one <strong>of</strong> his chapter sections “e Fallacies<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nonmonetary Explanations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Trade Cycle” (1949/1963,pp. 580–586; cf. pp. 554–555). He particularly criticizes “<strong>the</strong> two most popularvarieties <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se disproportionality doctr<strong>in</strong>es”: <strong>the</strong> durable-goods (orecho-effect) doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> acceleration pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. He judges <strong>the</strong>m hardto square with <strong>the</strong> general, economywide character <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess expansions<strong>and</strong> contractions (pp. 583, 585).e crisis <strong>and</strong> recession beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> 2007 had a conspicuous realelement—<strong>the</strong> collapse <strong>of</strong> a hous<strong>in</strong>g boom. In its background, however,lurked a monetary policy <strong>of</strong> arguably excessive liquidity <strong>and</strong> too-low <strong>in</strong>terestrates, as well as ill-considered government hous<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> mortgage policies<strong>and</strong> private f<strong>in</strong>ancial imprudence.is recession illustrates <strong>the</strong> contagion <strong>of</strong> distress through severalchannels. Insolvency or illiquidity <strong>of</strong> some <strong>in</strong>stitutions weakens o<strong>the</strong>rshold<strong>in</strong>g claims on <strong>the</strong>m. Consider an example. Consumers buy houses,putt<strong>in</strong>g up only a very small fraction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> purchase prices <strong>in</strong> money<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>and</strong> obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g mortgage loans for <strong>the</strong> rest. Now a f<strong>in</strong>ancier“packages” <strong>the</strong>se mortgages <strong>in</strong>to bonds. More specifically, he buys <strong>the</strong>semortgage claims from <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al lenders (unless he already owns <strong>the</strong>mby himself be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al lender). He gets <strong>the</strong> necessary funds onlyfractionally from resources <strong>of</strong> his own <strong>and</strong> issues bonds for <strong>the</strong> difference.His bonds are <strong>in</strong> turn bought by fur<strong>the</strong>r f<strong>in</strong>anciers, who also payonly a fraction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> purchase price <strong>in</strong> cash <strong>and</strong> obta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> rest by issu<strong>in</strong>gstill fur<strong>the</strong>r bonds. Bonds bought serve as collateral for <strong>the</strong> loansobta<strong>in</strong>ed (that is, fur<strong>the</strong>r bonds issued) to pay for <strong>the</strong> bond purchases.And so on. In short, loans are made with borrowed money obta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>turn mostly by borrow<strong>in</strong>g: bond sales f<strong>in</strong>ance bond purchases. At <strong>the</strong> end<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cha<strong>in</strong> are <strong>the</strong> saver-<strong>in</strong>vestors who pay <strong>in</strong> full, for example, <strong>in</strong>dividualswho <strong>in</strong>vest <strong>in</strong> bonds or bond mutual funds or participate <strong>in</strong> pensionfunds.At some stage <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> cha<strong>in</strong>, a f<strong>in</strong>ancier may issue bonds divided <strong>in</strong>totwo or more tranches, some appear<strong>in</strong>g safer by hav<strong>in</strong>g a primary claimon earn<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> ultimate repayment <strong>and</strong> lower tranches be<strong>in</strong>g riskier byhav<strong>in</strong>g only subord<strong>in</strong>ate claims. Upper-tranche ultra-safe bonds are apparentlymanufactured, <strong>the</strong>n, out <strong>of</strong> low-quality mortgage loans.


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 141Invest<strong>in</strong>g largely with borrowed money is “leverage.” “Deleverag<strong>in</strong>g”shook a multitiered structure <strong>of</strong> claims based on claims. e marketability<strong>of</strong> securities decl<strong>in</strong>ed as <strong>the</strong>ir actual values became unknown.Credit-default swaps are <strong>in</strong> effect <strong>in</strong>surance policies issued to cover<strong>the</strong> risk <strong>of</strong> default on bonds <strong>and</strong> so make <strong>the</strong> bonds more marketable.Ord<strong>in</strong>arily <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>surance providers need not expect hav<strong>in</strong>g to make goodon any substantial fraction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir policies at once, so <strong>the</strong>y hold liquidfunds amount<strong>in</strong>g to only a small fraction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir total potential liabilities.“Ord<strong>in</strong>arily,” for <strong>in</strong> times <strong>of</strong> crisis <strong>the</strong> credit-default swaps enter <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>crumbl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> leveraged cha<strong>in</strong>.e cha<strong>in</strong> is more fragile than one might suppose on <strong>the</strong> groundsthat, <strong>in</strong>directly <strong>and</strong> ultimately, houses largely back <strong>the</strong> bonds held by <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>vestors at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cha<strong>in</strong>. e nett<strong>in</strong>g-out <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>termediate stagesis not reassur<strong>in</strong>g, for f<strong>in</strong>ancial distress might strike any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> several <strong>in</strong>stitutions<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> break it.Even so, compounded leverage is not <strong>in</strong>herently fraudulent; for it canprovide <strong>the</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> sophisticated f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>termediation. It productivelyallocates <strong>the</strong> burdens <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> risk-bear<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> parties mostable <strong>and</strong> will<strong>in</strong>g to bear <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> prospective returns. Complexitybreeds ignorance, however; <strong>and</strong> unscrupulous operators may exploit it.Contagion marks booms <strong>and</strong> slumps. In times <strong>of</strong> exuberance, th<strong>in</strong>gsusable as collateral rise <strong>in</strong> price, permitt<strong>in</strong>g bigger loans. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,lenders grant larger loans relative to collateral. is exp<strong>and</strong>ed credit bidsup asset prices fur<strong>the</strong>r. And so on upwards until <strong>the</strong> spiral goes <strong>in</strong>to reverse.Lenders become more dem<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g. e troubles <strong>of</strong> operators hold<strong>in</strong>gdepreciat<strong>in</strong>g assets <strong>in</strong>fect <strong>the</strong>ir creditors. e multitiered leverage aggravates<strong>the</strong> downward spiral (Geanakoplos 2010).Mortgage foreclosures characterize just one channel <strong>of</strong> contagion.Houses st<strong>and</strong> empty, lawns go untrimmed, <strong>the</strong> neighborhood depreciates,house prices fall fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> trigger fur<strong>the</strong>r defaults, <strong>and</strong> holders <strong>of</strong>mortgage-backed bonds suffer.Structural contagion through <strong>the</strong>se channels, as one might call it, isjo<strong>in</strong>ed by expectational <strong>and</strong> psychological effects. e stock market is justone <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs register<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> perhaps <strong>in</strong>tensify<strong>in</strong>g optimism or pessimism.Investment fads <strong>and</strong> herd behavior are evident as people takeclues from one ano<strong>the</strong>r. After a bubble collapses, fear engenders morefear. Geanakoplos (2010) writes repeatedly <strong>of</strong> “scary bad news,” by whichhe means news that is not merely bad but that <strong>in</strong>tensifies itself by worsen<strong>in</strong>ggeneral uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty. Gorton (2008) emphasizes <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> its


142 Part I: Economicsabsence, as about <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>and</strong> location <strong>of</strong> risk. F<strong>in</strong>ancial complexityerodes <strong>in</strong>formation.Dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> recession that began <strong>in</strong> 2007, lenders held back from lend<strong>in</strong>g;banks accumulated huge excess reserves <strong>of</strong> base money newly createdby <strong>the</strong> Federal Reserve; <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors <strong>and</strong> consumers postponed spend<strong>in</strong>g.e dem<strong>and</strong> to hold money <strong>and</strong> near-money assets streng<strong>the</strong>ned relativeto <strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong> expenditure: <strong>the</strong> velocity <strong>of</strong> money fell. Uncerta<strong>in</strong>tywas at work accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>terpretations circulat<strong>in</strong>g widely toward <strong>the</strong>end <strong>of</strong> 2010. Bus<strong>in</strong>esses could hardly predict <strong>the</strong> impact <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mammothnew laws affect<strong>in</strong>g health care <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ance. Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty about whe<strong>the</strong>r<strong>the</strong> Bush-era tax cuts would be allowed to expire, extended, or modifiedcontributed to hesitation <strong>in</strong> hir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g major expenditures. To underst<strong>and</strong> what scope disordered money has for do<strong>in</strong>g damage, i<strong>the</strong>lps to recall money’s immensely valuable services when it works evenhalfway properly. It vastly facilitates <strong>the</strong> exchange <strong>of</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> servicesfor one ano<strong>the</strong>r. Indirect exchange through money takes place not onlyamong people work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> different sectors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy but also overtime. rough build<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>and</strong> draw<strong>in</strong>g down cash balances <strong>and</strong> throughcredit transactions, people can arrange to receive what o<strong>the</strong>r people produceei<strong>the</strong>r before or after <strong>the</strong>y deliver <strong>the</strong>ir own outputs. is <strong>in</strong>tertemporalaspect <strong>of</strong> money facilitates <strong>the</strong> pool<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> mobilization <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong>so promotes real capital formation, which, like specialization, enhancesproductivity.Money serves not only as <strong>the</strong> medium <strong>of</strong> exchange but also as <strong>the</strong>unit <strong>of</strong> account, <strong>the</strong> unit <strong>in</strong> which prices are quoted, bookkeep<strong>in</strong>g accomplished,contracts written, debts expressed, subjective evaluations formulated,benefits <strong>and</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> activities appraised, prospective <strong>and</strong> past pr<strong>of</strong>its<strong>and</strong> losses estimated <strong>and</strong> recorded, <strong>and</strong> taxes levied. e vital roles <strong>of</strong> marketprices, pr<strong>of</strong>its, <strong>and</strong> losses expressed <strong>in</strong> money received attention <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>debates over socialist economic calculation <strong>in</strong>itiated by Ludwig von Mises.When monetary disturbances require substantial changes <strong>in</strong> general levels<strong>of</strong> prices <strong>and</strong> wages, <strong>the</strong>n, whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong>se changes occur promptly, <strong>the</strong>functions <strong>of</strong> prices, pr<strong>of</strong>its, <strong>and</strong> losses <strong>in</strong> convey<strong>in</strong>g signals <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centivessuffer disruption. One notable glitch is <strong>the</strong> debt-deflation aspect <strong>of</strong> depressiondescribed by Irv<strong>in</strong>g Fisher (1933). Comparable effects occur whenprice <strong>in</strong>flation or deflation turns out substantially greater or slighter than


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 143people had allowed for <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir borrow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> lend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r plans.Previously scheduled debt <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest payments can become disruptivelyburdensome when debtors <strong>and</strong> so <strong>the</strong>ir creditors suffer disappo<strong>in</strong>tments<strong>of</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds o<strong>the</strong>r than or <strong>in</strong> addition to price-level or price-trend changes.Money is potentially a “loose jo<strong>in</strong>t,” as F.A. Hayek said (Garrison 1984,2001), between decisions to produce <strong>and</strong> sell th<strong>in</strong>gs on <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong>decisions to buy on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>. In accomplish<strong>in</strong>g exchanges, people(<strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess firms) rout<strong>in</strong>ely receive payments <strong>in</strong>to <strong>and</strong> make paymentsfrom hold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> money, a fact whose significance Mises well understood <strong>in</strong>develop<strong>in</strong>g his cash-balance approach to monetary <strong>the</strong>ory (1912/1981). esizes <strong>of</strong> cash balances desired are related to <strong>the</strong> sizes <strong>of</strong> people’s <strong>and</strong> firms’expected <strong>in</strong>ward <strong>and</strong> outward flows <strong>of</strong> payments (among o<strong>the</strong>r variables).If desired amounts <strong>of</strong> money exceed or fall short <strong>of</strong> actual amounts, <strong>the</strong>npeople try to adjust <strong>the</strong>ir hold<strong>in</strong>gs by modify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir behavior on <strong>the</strong>markets for goods <strong>and</strong> services <strong>and</strong> securities. As Mises wrote,A shortage <strong>of</strong> money means a difficulty <strong>in</strong> dispos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> commodities formoney.... Under <strong>the</strong> present organization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market, which leavesa deep gulf between <strong>the</strong> marketability <strong>of</strong> money on <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> marketability <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r economic goods on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, noth<strong>in</strong>gbut money enters <strong>in</strong>to consideration at all as a medium <strong>of</strong> exchange.(1912/1981, p. 157)eories <strong>of</strong> difficulty <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g contact with potential trad<strong>in</strong>g partnershelp illum<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong> decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> velocity <strong>of</strong> money <strong>in</strong> recessions(see <strong>the</strong> cited works <strong>of</strong> Clower, Leijonhufvud, <strong>and</strong> Hall, <strong>and</strong> particularlyClower 1990, p. 82). With many desired sales thwarted, people f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>mselves,more or less by default, hold<strong>in</strong>g more money than usual relative to<strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>comes <strong>and</strong> expenditures. e grim bus<strong>in</strong>ess scene, toge<strong>the</strong>r withuncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> precaution, counts aga<strong>in</strong>st act<strong>in</strong>g to get rid quickly <strong>of</strong> cashbalances that would o<strong>the</strong>rwise seem excessive.In some ways, as just implied, imbalance between money’s supply <strong>and</strong>dem<strong>and</strong> is self-aggravat<strong>in</strong>g. More generally, supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> stay <strong>in</strong>equilibrium less readily for money than for ord<strong>in</strong>ary goods <strong>and</strong> services.Because money is <strong>the</strong> one th<strong>in</strong>g rout<strong>in</strong>ely traded on all markets, its supply<strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> do not confront each o<strong>the</strong>r on a market <strong>of</strong> its own <strong>and</strong> cannotbe equilibrated with each o<strong>the</strong>r through a price adjustment <strong>of</strong> its own.Equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g processes do operate, but only <strong>in</strong>directly, over time, <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong> a piecemeal manner through trials <strong>and</strong> errors <strong>in</strong> adjust<strong>in</strong>g quantities<strong>and</strong> prices on <strong>in</strong>numerable specific markets. When an excess dem<strong>and</strong>


144 Part I: Economicsfor money requires widespread cuts <strong>in</strong> prices <strong>and</strong> wages, sellers <strong>and</strong> wagenegotiators <strong>in</strong> many or most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> markets for <strong>in</strong>dividual goods <strong>and</strong> serviceshave reason to delay cuts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own while wait<strong>in</strong>g for a clearerread<strong>in</strong>g on market conditions <strong>and</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g to see what o<strong>the</strong>r sellers—competitors,workers, suppliers—will do.Rapid cop<strong>in</strong>g with monetary disequilibrium is difficult because knowledgeis scattered <strong>in</strong> millions <strong>of</strong> separate m<strong>in</strong>ds—knowledge about tastes,resources, production possibilities, exchange opportunities, money <strong>and</strong>credit conditions, <strong>and</strong> conditions on specific markets. Because <strong>the</strong> marketis, among o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs, a mechanism for convey<strong>in</strong>g signals <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives,it would be <strong>in</strong>consistent both to recognize <strong>the</strong>se functions yet to suppose(as <strong>the</strong> rational-expectations <strong>the</strong>orists nearly do) that transactors somehowalready have <strong>the</strong> knowledge that <strong>the</strong> price system works to convey.e market process has no quick <strong>and</strong> easy substitute.Mises repeatedly emphasized <strong>the</strong> delayed <strong>and</strong> nonuniform responsesto money-supply changes (1912/1981, pp. 162–163, where he cites observations<strong>of</strong> David Hume <strong>and</strong> John Stuart Mill; Mises 1990, chaps. 4–6). “eessence <strong>of</strong> monetary <strong>the</strong>ory is <strong>the</strong> cognition that cash-<strong>in</strong>duced changes<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> money relation affect <strong>the</strong> various prices, wage rates, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terestrates nei<strong>the</strong>r at <strong>the</strong> same time nor to <strong>the</strong> same extent” (1949/1963, p. 555).Although Mises focuses his critical attention on money <strong>and</strong> credit expansion<strong>and</strong> its consequences, he recognizes <strong>the</strong> damage done to bus<strong>in</strong>esswhen a credit expansion ceases (p. 568). “Deflation <strong>and</strong> credit contractionno less than <strong>in</strong>flation <strong>and</strong> credit expansion are elements disarrang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>smooth course <strong>of</strong> economic activities” (p. 567). Mises alludes (p. 568) to<strong>the</strong> damage done by deflation <strong>and</strong> credit restriction required by Brita<strong>in</strong>’sreturn to <strong>the</strong> prewar gold parity <strong>of</strong> its currency after both <strong>the</strong> Napoleonicwars <strong>and</strong> World War I. Credit disruption accompanies or even seems to overshadow monetarydisruption <strong>in</strong> some episodes. Aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> current recession provides anexample. When <strong>the</strong> hous<strong>in</strong>g boom fed by cheap credit went <strong>in</strong>to reverse,spread<strong>in</strong>g fear made banks <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r lenders, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g those <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> commercial-papermarket, hesitant to lend. Some bus<strong>in</strong>esses, deprived <strong>of</strong>credit, had to curtail <strong>the</strong>ir operations, spread<strong>in</strong>g distress to <strong>the</strong>ir suppliers<strong>and</strong> laid-<strong>of</strong>f employees. O<strong>the</strong>rs that might still have obta<strong>in</strong>ed credit didnot seek it for lack <strong>of</strong> attractive opportunities to employ <strong>the</strong> money.


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 145Credit contraction may <strong>in</strong>deed count as a “real,” nonmonetary, factor<strong>in</strong> recession; but it still had monetary aspects. Velocity, as already mentioned,fell, <strong>and</strong> for any plausible concept <strong>and</strong> measure <strong>of</strong> money used <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> calculation. Income saved from consumption but not devoted to real<strong>in</strong>vestment or to nonmonetary assets was allocated to <strong>the</strong> one rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gasset, namely money, narrowly or broadly def<strong>in</strong>ed. If <strong>the</strong>re were no suchasset to latch onto, credit contraction could not have occurred, or not <strong>in</strong>any familiar way (Cover <strong>and</strong> Hooks 1989). MV=PQ, <strong>the</strong> familiar tautologicalequation <strong>of</strong> exchange, rema<strong>in</strong>s a useful check on what implies what. Perhaps more so than o<strong>the</strong>r schools, Austrian economists emphasize onebanal fact: economic plans <strong>and</strong> activities stretch out over time. (Dynamicgeneral-equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory does formally take account <strong>of</strong> time <strong>in</strong> its models,but not <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> way Austrians do.) is is one more reason why priceflexibility cannot keep markets cont<strong>in</strong>uously cleared. People cannot doeveryth<strong>in</strong>g at once; <strong>the</strong>y cannot set all prices at <strong>the</strong> same time <strong>and</strong> reviseall <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m equally <strong>of</strong>ten. Long-term contracts fix some prices; pr<strong>in</strong>cipal<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest on debt are <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> preset prices. A change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>general level <strong>of</strong> prices necessarily disrupts previous price relations.A more general po<strong>in</strong>t is that coord<strong>in</strong>ation requires <strong>in</strong>tertemporal aswell as <strong>in</strong>ter<strong>in</strong>dustry mesh<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> plans <strong>and</strong> activities. Roger Garrison(1984, 2001) identifies <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tersection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “market for time” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>“market for money” as <strong>the</strong> subject matter <strong>of</strong> macroeconomics. Moneyis not <strong>the</strong> only Hayekian “loose jo<strong>in</strong>t” <strong>in</strong> a market system. A merelyloose relation also holds between a def<strong>in</strong>ite assortment <strong>of</strong> capital goods<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> subsequent dem<strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>g consumer goods. islooseness permits maladies such as “over<strong>in</strong>vestment” or “under<strong>in</strong>vestment”or “mal<strong>in</strong>vestment.” Once committed to a certa<strong>in</strong> course, people cannot“<strong>in</strong>stantaneously <strong>and</strong> costlessly change that commitment; thus <strong>the</strong> passage<strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong> its irreversibility are matters <strong>of</strong> paramount importance <strong>in</strong>underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g economic activity” (Laidler 1975, p. 5).A fur<strong>the</strong>r l<strong>in</strong>k between <strong>the</strong> universals <strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong> money (so called byGarrison 1984, 2001) is that people hold money to cope with Keynes’s“dark forces <strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong> ignorance.” To <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong>y want topostpone consumption while keep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir options open about <strong>the</strong> tim<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> specific types <strong>and</strong> amounts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir future consumption <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment,people hold f<strong>in</strong>ancial claims, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g money. Keep<strong>in</strong>g options


146 Part I: Economicsopen is possible for <strong>in</strong>dividuals but is not possible for <strong>the</strong> economy as awhole (or is possible only to a lesser extent, through construction <strong>of</strong> versatilera<strong>the</strong>r than highly specialized capital goods). Private attempts to do<strong>the</strong> socially impossible—keep<strong>in</strong>g options open—epitomize <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tertemporal“loose jo<strong>in</strong>t.”, , Fundamentalist Keynesianism worried about <strong>the</strong> separation <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>vestment decisions. S<strong>in</strong>ce both types <strong>of</strong> decision concern <strong>the</strong> future, animbalance between desired sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> desired <strong>in</strong>vestment implies <strong>in</strong>tertemporaldiscoord<strong>in</strong>ation. e <strong>in</strong>terest rate (or array <strong>of</strong> rates) alone cannotensure sav<strong>in</strong>g/<strong>in</strong>vestment equilibrium, for <strong>in</strong>terest is not <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> thosetwo aggregate flow magnitudes. Instead, it is <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> loans, broadly<strong>in</strong>terpreted, or, more comprehensively, <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> “wait<strong>in</strong>g” performedthrough ownership <strong>of</strong> claims <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r assets.Imbalance implies monetary disequilibrium; yet <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate is not<strong>the</strong> equilibrator <strong>of</strong> money’s supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>, ei<strong>the</strong>r. To underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>relation between sav<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>vestment, <strong>and</strong> money, let us focus on <strong>the</strong> case<strong>of</strong> oversav<strong>in</strong>g, seen as pervasive deficiency <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for currently producedor producible goods <strong>and</strong> services. As follows from <strong>the</strong> two-sidedcharacter <strong>of</strong> markets <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> both actually accomplished <strong>and</strong> unsuccessfullyattempted transactions <strong>and</strong> as Walras’s Law states, supply-<strong>and</strong>-dem<strong>and</strong>imbalance for some th<strong>in</strong>gs implies imbalance <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> opposite directionfor o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs. (e aggregate value <strong>of</strong> all excess dem<strong>and</strong> quantities,due account taken <strong>of</strong> algebraic sign, is tautologically equal to zero.) In<strong>the</strong> case considered, excess supply (negative excess dem<strong>and</strong>) for currentlyproduced goods <strong>and</strong> services implies (positive) excess dem<strong>and</strong> for o<strong>the</strong>rth<strong>in</strong>gs. What might this o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>g or th<strong>in</strong>gs be?People who are try<strong>in</strong>g to save (<strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> fully spend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir current<strong>in</strong>comes on consumption) are by that very token try<strong>in</strong>g to acquire sav<strong>in</strong>gs(“sav<strong>in</strong>gs” with <strong>the</strong> s) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> real or f<strong>in</strong>ancial assets. Which assets?If <strong>the</strong> savers <strong>the</strong>mselves are buy<strong>in</strong>g labor <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r resources to constructnew capital goods, <strong>the</strong>y are not contribut<strong>in</strong>g to any deficiency <strong>of</strong> currenttotal spend<strong>in</strong>g. (H<strong>in</strong>dsight might later reveal <strong>the</strong> particular mix <strong>of</strong> capitalgoods constructed to be <strong>in</strong>appropriate, but that is a problem differentfrom oversav<strong>in</strong>g.) If, <strong>in</strong>stead, savers are acquir<strong>in</strong>g new stocks or bondsfrom issuers who use <strong>the</strong> monetary proceeds (<strong>the</strong> comm<strong>and</strong> over resourcesreleased from supply<strong>in</strong>g current consumption) to construct capital goods,


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 147aga<strong>in</strong> no oversav<strong>in</strong>g occurs. If savers are buy<strong>in</strong>g already exist<strong>in</strong>g physicalassets or securities, <strong>the</strong> question shifts to what <strong>the</strong>ir sellers are try<strong>in</strong>g todo with <strong>the</strong> proceeds. If those asset sellers are us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> proceeds for consumptionor new capital construction, aga<strong>in</strong> no oversav<strong>in</strong>g occurs. If <strong>the</strong>yare try<strong>in</strong>g to shift wealth <strong>in</strong>to o<strong>the</strong>r vehicles <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> question reappears<strong>of</strong> what <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r vehicles might be: what is <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g or th<strong>in</strong>gswhose excess dem<strong>and</strong> matches <strong>the</strong> deficiency <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for currently producedgoods <strong>and</strong> services?How, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, could <strong>the</strong> excess dem<strong>and</strong> for this someth<strong>in</strong>g persist?Consider how an excess dem<strong>and</strong> might work itself out. () e th<strong>in</strong>g’squantity might <strong>in</strong>crease, as with automobiles <strong>and</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> claims on f<strong>in</strong>ancial-<strong>in</strong>termediary<strong>in</strong>stitutions. () Its price might rise or its yield fall, aswith Old Masters, securities, <strong>and</strong> claims on f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>termediaries. () Ifits quantity <strong>and</strong> price are both rigid, frustrated dem<strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gmight divert itself onto o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs, with macroeconomic consequencesmuch <strong>the</strong> same as if <strong>the</strong> diverted dem<strong>and</strong> had run <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> substitutegoods <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place. () For only one th<strong>in</strong>g does none <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>seresponses to excess dem<strong>and</strong> operate, requir<strong>in</strong>g some quite different process.at th<strong>in</strong>g is money, <strong>the</strong> medium <strong>of</strong> exchange. (Even nearmoneyscan respond <strong>in</strong> quantity or price or yield.)In <strong>the</strong> current U.S. monetary system, <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong> money dependson <strong>the</strong> policy-determ<strong>in</strong>ed stock <strong>of</strong> government base money <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> circumstancesrepresented <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> textbook money-multiplier formula. Of <strong>the</strong>four supply-<strong>and</strong>-dem<strong>and</strong>-equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms, <strong>the</strong> first, <strong>the</strong> quantityresponse, is not free to work “automatically” (not apart from monetarypolicy, for exist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stitutions do not allow <strong>the</strong> actual quantity fullyto accommodate itself to changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for money at <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>gprice level). Mechanism 2, <strong>the</strong> price response, does not work becausemoney lacks a price <strong>of</strong> its own. Mechanism 3, diversion <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>, doesnot work because money supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> do not exhibit <strong>the</strong>ir imbalanceon a specific market from which excess dem<strong>and</strong> might be diverted.(Besides, what would diversion mean for <strong>the</strong> medium <strong>of</strong> exchange itself?)Because money is <strong>the</strong> medium <strong>of</strong> exchange, excess dem<strong>and</strong> for it is notclearly apparent. Everyone can obta<strong>in</strong> as much money as he th<strong>in</strong>ks he can“afford” to hold under his circumstances by restra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g his purchases, ifnot by eagerness <strong>in</strong> sell<strong>in</strong>g whatever he has for sale. (A depressed level<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come does affect how much money people th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong>y can “afford.”)<strong>Market</strong> difficulties appear to perta<strong>in</strong> to sales <strong>of</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> services, not tomoney.


148 Part I: EconomicsWith none <strong>of</strong> responses 1, 2, <strong>and</strong> 3 operat<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> market process <strong>of</strong>reequilibrat<strong>in</strong>g money’s supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> has to be <strong>the</strong> roundabout process<strong>of</strong> adjust<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>numerable prices <strong>and</strong> wages on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual marketsfor goods <strong>and</strong> services. For reasons already noted, prices <strong>and</strong> wages cannotimmediately jump to <strong>the</strong>ir new equilibrium level <strong>and</strong> pattern. Meanwhile,transactions, production, <strong>and</strong> employment suffer.e supposed problem <strong>of</strong> oversav<strong>in</strong>g boils down, <strong>the</strong>n, to monetary disequilibrium.Unsurpris<strong>in</strong>gly, what looks like oversav<strong>in</strong>g—a general deficiency<strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> pos<strong>in</strong>g an economywide impediment to transactions—isconnected with <strong>the</strong> medium <strong>of</strong> exchange, which is also, <strong>in</strong> our current system,<strong>the</strong> medium <strong>in</strong> which prices are correctly or <strong>in</strong>correctly set or adjustedor left unadjusted.Suitable monetary <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> policy might avoid macro discoord<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>and</strong> a general deficiency orexcess <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for current output. By <strong>the</strong>mselves, however, <strong>the</strong>y cannotensure both that a proper share <strong>of</strong> current <strong>in</strong>come is saved <strong>and</strong> devotedto capital formation <strong>and</strong> that resources are properly allocated among capital-constructionprojects by economic sectors <strong>and</strong> by degrees <strong>of</strong> remotenessfrom f<strong>in</strong>al consumption. Noth<strong>in</strong>g can ensure such ideal results—<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> very mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “proper” <strong>in</strong> this context is unclear. People do nothave perfect foresight, so some capital-construction projects are boundto turn out, <strong>in</strong> retrospect, to have been unwise, while o<strong>the</strong>rs will turnout to have been worth exp<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, noth<strong>in</strong>g guarantees that<strong>the</strong> proper share <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come will be saved <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vested or, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words,that “society” will discount <strong>the</strong> future at <strong>the</strong> proper rate. (ese are <strong>in</strong>herentlyfuzzy concepts anyway; <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong>, it is po<strong>in</strong>tless to blame reality forbe<strong>in</strong>g real.)Still, avoid<strong>in</strong>g monetary disruption means avoid<strong>in</strong>g a major obstacle to<strong>the</strong> function<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> price system. Undistorted by monetary <strong>in</strong>fluences,<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate is free to play its coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g role, along with o<strong>the</strong>r prices.A well function<strong>in</strong>g price system allows people to use <strong>the</strong>ir own decentralizedknowledge <strong>and</strong> judgments <strong>in</strong> allocat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir resources betweencurrent consumption <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment to achieve greater future consumption.Monolithic central decisions that might turn out monstrously wrongare avoided. Entrepreneurs whose judgments turn out consistently soundwill acquire greater control over resource allocation than those whosejudgments turn out consistently mistaken. Even if <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>herited array <strong>of</strong>capital goods does prove at any time to be what h<strong>in</strong>dsight deems a mistake—as<strong>in</strong>evitably it will to some extent—market signals <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 149will help promote an efficient use <strong>of</strong> this array. e bond <strong>and</strong> stock marketsplay a role <strong>in</strong> mobiliz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> facilitat<strong>in</strong>g recomb<strong>in</strong>ations<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>herited complex <strong>of</strong> capital goods. A stable unit <strong>of</strong> accountwould aid <strong>the</strong>se market processes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic calculation that <strong>the</strong>ypresuppose. Recogniz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> time element as <strong>the</strong>y do, Austrians give great attentionto capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment forgrowth <strong>of</strong> productivity <strong>and</strong> real <strong>in</strong>comes. Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g that branch <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>ory is essential to underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g even <strong>the</strong> basics <strong>of</strong> economics, especiallymicroeconomics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> a price system. Böhm-Bawerk <strong>and</strong>writers <strong>in</strong> his tradition have made <strong>in</strong>dispensable contributions here.Keynes saw <strong>in</strong>vestment spend<strong>in</strong>g as a strategic part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> total spend<strong>in</strong>gthat susta<strong>in</strong>s economic activity, but he did not treat what capital goodsare built or not built as a crucial issue.Monetarists certa<strong>in</strong>ly recognize <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>the</strong>ory. Unlike some Austrians, however, <strong>the</strong>y do not see it as a dom<strong>in</strong>antstr<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> fluctuations <strong>of</strong> boom <strong>and</strong> recession. Similarly,although a disequilibrium pattern <strong>of</strong> relative prices <strong>and</strong> wages is important<strong>in</strong> some contexts, it is not central to expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g cyclical fluctuations.e centerpiece <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> monetarist story, <strong>in</strong>stead, is a disequilibrium relationbetween <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al quantity <strong>of</strong> money <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> general level <strong>of</strong> prices<strong>and</strong> wages. Crucial here are <strong>the</strong> factors determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong> money<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for cash balances.Central-bank policy has much to do with determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong>money. Try<strong>in</strong>g to keep a target rate <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest below <strong>the</strong> “natural” rate thatwould o<strong>the</strong>rwise clear <strong>the</strong> credit market entails exp<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong>money, as Knut Wicksell expla<strong>in</strong>ed; <strong>and</strong> (less familiarly) try<strong>in</strong>g to keep atarget rate above <strong>the</strong> natural rate <strong>in</strong>volves shr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong> moneyor slow<strong>in</strong>g its growth. True as all this is, however, it does not elevate capital<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory to <strong>the</strong> crucial role specifically <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics thatsome Austrians would accord to it. - Partly for such reasons my enthusiasm for Austrian economics does notextend to a <strong>the</strong>ory propounded by Ludwig von Mises <strong>and</strong> F.A. Hayek


150 Part I: Economicsearly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> twentieth century <strong>and</strong> still recited by some Austrians as <strong>the</strong>dom<strong>in</strong>ant str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir macroeconomics. e <strong>the</strong>ory blames recessionon a preced<strong>in</strong>g policy <strong>of</strong> excessively easy money. Artificially low <strong>in</strong>terestrates falsify price signals, exaggerat<strong>in</strong>g how much sav<strong>in</strong>g is free<strong>in</strong>gresources from consumption for real <strong>in</strong>vestment. e false cheapness <strong>of</strong>credit lures entrepreneurs <strong>in</strong>to o<strong>the</strong>rwise unattractive long-term-oriented,<strong>in</strong>terest-sensitive projects. In time <strong>the</strong> scarcity <strong>of</strong> saved resources for complet<strong>in</strong>guncompleted projects or operat<strong>in</strong>g completed ones forces ab<strong>and</strong>on<strong>in</strong>gsome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. Dem<strong>and</strong>s for complementary <strong>in</strong>puts <strong>and</strong> factors <strong>of</strong>production, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g labor, fall <strong>of</strong>f. e downturn arrives. Noth<strong>in</strong>g can bedone about <strong>the</strong> misallocation <strong>and</strong> waste <strong>of</strong> resources except to restructuresome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mistaken projects for whatever alternative uses can be found.e lesson about not repeat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> easy money that may have caused suchdistress is <strong>of</strong>ten, sadly, not taken to heart.is scenario, although conceivable enough, f<strong>in</strong>ds little historical support.Overambitious <strong>in</strong>vestment projects are typically ab<strong>and</strong>oned or restructurednot for lack <strong>of</strong> real resources to complete <strong>and</strong> operate <strong>the</strong>mbut from disappo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gly weak dem<strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong>m <strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> goods <strong>and</strong>services <strong>in</strong>to whose production <strong>the</strong>y were meant to enter. Consider gluts<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> past several years <strong>of</strong> fiber-optic cable <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> houses <strong>and</strong> high-risecondom<strong>in</strong>iums.Str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle <strong>the</strong>ory may well belong <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>tool kit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories that researchers may draw on <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g historicalepisodes. Overemphasis on it, however, is an embarrassment that <strong>the</strong>Austrian school would well be rid <strong>of</strong>. (For a fuller critique, see Yeager1986/1997, pp. 229–235.) Excessively easy money can <strong>in</strong>deed do damage <strong>in</strong>various ways, but justified warn<strong>in</strong>gs aga<strong>in</strong>st it had best not be tarred byassociation with a questionable one.Not everyth<strong>in</strong>g said here is st<strong>and</strong>ard Austrian economics. It does fit <strong>in</strong>well, however, with several lead<strong>in</strong>g traits <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian school—itsemphasis on <strong>the</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation problem, its forthright perception <strong>of</strong> messyreality <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> scope it leaves for entrepreneurial activities, <strong>and</strong> its putt<strong>in</strong>gmoney <strong>and</strong> time at <strong>the</strong> center <strong>of</strong> macroeconomics. One fur<strong>the</strong>rtrait is concern for <strong>in</strong>stitutions. It contrasts <strong>in</strong> this respect with <strong>the</strong>hyper-free-marketry <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> New Classical <strong>and</strong> real-bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle schools,which have cultivated analysis <strong>of</strong> abstract models uncontam<strong>in</strong>ated by


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 151<strong>in</strong>stitutional detail. Austrians practice comparative-<strong>in</strong>stitutional analysis,which does not mean compar<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> real world unfavorably with <strong>the</strong> Walrasianvision <strong>of</strong> general equilibrium. When told that reality is unsatisfactory<strong>in</strong> this or that respect, Austrians are <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to ask, “Unsatisfactorycompared to what?” Like members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Public Choice school, Austriansknow better than automatically to regard government as superior toprivate enterprise <strong>in</strong> accomplish<strong>in</strong>g various tasks.e aggregate-dem<strong>and</strong>/aggregate-supply analysis still dom<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>textbooks almost <strong>in</strong>vites itchy-f<strong>in</strong>gered attempts to f<strong>in</strong>e-tune <strong>the</strong> macroeconomy.e Austrians’ concern with f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed specialization <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>task <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation directs attention, by contrast, to <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> whatframework <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> more or less steady policies, <strong>in</strong>stitutionalizedpolicies, can best allow market processes to operate.e Austrian concern with <strong>in</strong>stitutions shows up <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> debate overeconomic calculation under socialism <strong>and</strong> capitalism <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> discussions<strong>of</strong> monetary st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>and</strong> monetary reforms. It shows up <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> attentionthat Ludwig von Mises <strong>and</strong> Friedrich Hayek paid to history. Dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>gbetween <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> history, <strong>the</strong>y warned aga<strong>in</strong>st misconceiv<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> economics as numerical aspects <strong>of</strong> recent or earlier economic history.Aware <strong>of</strong> how important <strong>and</strong> how changeable <strong>in</strong>stitutions are, Austriansare skeptical that a country’s economic “structure” can be p<strong>in</strong>ned downeconometrically <strong>in</strong> functions <strong>of</strong> stable form <strong>and</strong> with stable coefficients.Noth<strong>in</strong>g can fully substitute for <strong>in</strong>sights from history. e large <strong>in</strong>stitutional <strong>and</strong> historical element <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics bars aspecific general <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> any well-specified model <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> macroeconomy.Emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g that element may seem anti<strong>the</strong>oretical, un<strong>in</strong>formative, <strong>and</strong>sloppy; but if that is <strong>the</strong> way th<strong>in</strong>gs are, suppos<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>rwise sabotagesunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g. Scarcely conceivable progress <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics mightsome day change that condition, but meanwhile we must acknowledge<strong>the</strong> contrast between micro- <strong>and</strong> macroeconomics. Devis<strong>in</strong>g a general<strong>the</strong>ory is as difficult for macroeconomics as for diseases <strong>and</strong> wounds <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> human body.In policy, also, a realistic macroeconomics might seem deficient. Unlikewhat a well-specified model might seem to do, it cannot gr<strong>in</strong>d out For an appeal for due modesty <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics by an em<strong>in</strong>ent ma<strong>in</strong>stream economist,see Summers 1991.


152 Part I: Economicsspecific recommendations, especially not quantitative ones. e best itcan recommend to policymakers is to avoid disrupt<strong>in</strong>g an economic environmentthat facilitates <strong>the</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> private plans. What historyparticularly warns aga<strong>in</strong>st is disruptions from excessively contractionaryor expansionary monetary policy. e case for dependability <strong>in</strong> monetarypolicy—for rules, not episode-to-episode discretion—deserves attention.Macroeconomics gives scant specific guidance for remedy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> fears<strong>and</strong> uncerta<strong>in</strong>ties <strong>of</strong> late 2010. It is true <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple that a monetary policyeven more expansionary than already adopted could revive spend<strong>in</strong>g by<strong>of</strong>fsett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> fall <strong>in</strong> money’s velocity—by gratify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> temporarily <strong>in</strong>tensifieddem<strong>and</strong> to hold money. Unlike many earlier recessions, however,<strong>the</strong> current one is not marked by monetary tightness. To ease money <strong>and</strong>credit fur<strong>the</strong>r would aggravate <strong>the</strong> “exit-strategy” problem for <strong>the</strong> FederalReserve, <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> how safely to reverse <strong>the</strong> great expansion <strong>of</strong> itsbalance sheet. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, such a short-run-oriented expedient mightwell destroy <strong>the</strong> Federal Reserve’s hard-won reputation as guardian <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>value <strong>of</strong> money.In summary, Austrian economics, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g macroeconomics, recognizeshow messy (“imperfect”) reality is, with so much depend<strong>in</strong>g on radicallydecentralized knowledge <strong>and</strong> decisions to be coord<strong>in</strong>ated somehow.Decisions are guided, not only by current conditions but also by chang<strong>in</strong>gexperience, <strong>the</strong>ories, entrepreneurial spirit (Keynes’s “animal spirits”),<strong>in</strong>tuitions, <strong>and</strong> hunches. Austrian emphasis on <strong>the</strong> subjective element isamply warranted. Fortunately, attention to <strong>the</strong> psychological contagion <strong>of</strong>speculative booms <strong>and</strong> paralyz<strong>in</strong>g fear is ga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g academic respectability.is cannot all be formalized <strong>and</strong> rigorized <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> way sought byma<strong>in</strong>stream economic models, with <strong>the</strong>ir functional forms <strong>and</strong> specificparameters <strong>in</strong>form<strong>in</strong>g ambitious <strong>and</strong> successful policy. Perhaps remarkable<strong>in</strong>tellectual advances will some day satisfy such aspirations. Until<strong>the</strong>n, however, <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> policy must rema<strong>in</strong> modest.e current disarray <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> exaggerations <strong>of</strong> latelyfashionable free-marketry give Austrian economists an opportunity toearn <strong>the</strong> attention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream. In bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>the</strong>ir broadtime-<strong>and</strong>-money orientation holds more promise than <strong>the</strong>ir specific application<strong>of</strong> capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory criticized above, which may haveseemed more plausible under certa<strong>in</strong> past historical-<strong>in</strong>stitutional conditionsthan it is <strong>in</strong> general. Austrian macroeconomics has much <strong>in</strong> common,<strong>and</strong> could develop still more <strong>in</strong> common, with monetarism, withwork like that <strong>of</strong> Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud <strong>and</strong> Howitt, <strong>and</strong> even with


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 153New Keynesianism. (We should not be afraid <strong>of</strong> mere labels, which havebeen especially misapplied <strong>in</strong> recent years anyway.)Ris<strong>in</strong>g Austrian economists might well f<strong>in</strong>d dissertation topics <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> areas <strong>of</strong> monetary history, monetary reform, alternative market <strong>in</strong>stitutions, property rights, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutional <strong>and</strong> entrepreneurial history.A search for historical episodes <strong>of</strong> depression or recession <strong>of</strong> entirelynonmonetary orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> character could be <strong>in</strong>structive, whe<strong>the</strong>r or notany actually turn up.Go<strong>in</strong>g beyond preservation <strong>and</strong> transmission <strong>of</strong> cherished truths, Austrianscan exploit <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>sights to help ga<strong>in</strong> new knowledge <strong>and</strong> sounderpublic policy. Macroeconomics as recommended here may <strong>of</strong>fer governmentsunfashionably little specific advice, little numerically def<strong>in</strong>ite, littlebeyond warn<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st monetary disorder <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong>st o<strong>the</strong>rwise contribut<strong>in</strong>gto uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> fear. But if that is <strong>the</strong> way th<strong>in</strong>gs are, whatelse can one say?Austrians can also po<strong>in</strong>t out <strong>the</strong> absurdity <strong>of</strong> our undef<strong>in</strong>ed fiat dollar,whose value rests precariously on noth<strong>in</strong>g better than <strong>the</strong> changeable policies<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Federal Reserve, badgered from all sides with contradictory,changeable, <strong>and</strong> short-run-oriented advice. ey have much to say abouthow this monetary anomaly abets irresponsible government, reflected <strong>in</strong>persistent budget deficits. It is unnecessary to identify sound money exclusivelywith a particular commodity st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> relatively brief historicalduration. As F.A. Hayek <strong>and</strong> several younger Austrian economists haveshown, several alternative monetary reforms are <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> practical<strong>in</strong>terest.Brown, Harry G. “Nonsense <strong>and</strong> Sense <strong>in</strong> Deal<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> Depression.” BGSInternational Exchange (Spr<strong>in</strong>g 1933): 97–107.Clower, Robert W. Money <strong>and</strong> <strong>Market</strong>s. Edited by Donald Walker. New York:Cambridge University Press, 1984.. “Keynes’s General eory: A Contemporary Perspective.” Greek EconomicReview 12, Supplement (Autumn 1990): 73–84. Peter Howitt recommends study<strong>in</strong>g how real-world <strong>in</strong>stitutions function very differentlyfrom <strong>the</strong> centralized Walrasian auction (1990, p. 51). “Fur<strong>the</strong>r progress will dependupon supply<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stitutional detail ... , <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ventory-hold<strong>in</strong>g, advertis<strong>in</strong>g, negotiat<strong>in</strong>g,<strong>in</strong>spection, <strong>and</strong> even price-quot<strong>in</strong>g services <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>termediaries <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r marketmak<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>of</strong> real life” (1990, p. 19).


154 Part I: EconomicsCover, James P., <strong>and</strong> Donald L. Hooks. “Credit versus Monetary eories<strong>of</strong> Macroeconomic Fluctuations.” Atlantic Economic Journal 17 ( June 1989):42–46.Eucken, Walter. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Economics. Translated by T.W. Hutchison.London: Hodge, 1950.Fisher, Irv<strong>in</strong>g. “e Debt-Deflation eory <strong>of</strong> Great Depressions.” Econometrica1 (October 1933): 337–357.Garrison, Roger W. “Time <strong>and</strong> Money: e Universals <strong>of</strong> Macroeconomiceoriz<strong>in</strong>g.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Macroeconomics 6 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g 1984): 197–213.. Time <strong>and</strong> Money: e Macroeconomics <strong>of</strong> Capital Structure. London: Routledge,2001.Geanakoplos, John. “Solv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Present Crisis <strong>and</strong> Manag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> LeverageCycle.” Federal Reserve Bank <strong>of</strong> New York Economic Policy Review 16, no. 1,Special <strong>Is</strong>sue (August 2010): 101–131.Gorton, Gary. “e Panic <strong>of</strong> 2007.” Paper delivered at Jackson Hole, August2008. http://www.kansascityfed.org/publicat/sympos/2008/gorton.08.04.08.pdf.Hall, Robert E. Booms <strong>and</strong> Recessions <strong>in</strong> a Noisy <strong>Economy</strong>. New Haven, Conn.:Yale University Press, 1991.Hansen, Gary D., <strong>and</strong> Edward C. Prescott. “Did Technology Shocks Cause <strong>the</strong>1990–1991 Recession?” American Economic Review 83 (May 1993): 280–286.Hansen, Gary D., <strong>and</strong> R<strong>and</strong>all Wright. “e Labor <strong>Market</strong> <strong>in</strong> Real Bus<strong>in</strong>essCycle eory.” Federal Reserve Bank <strong>of</strong> M<strong>in</strong>neapolis Quarterly Review 16(Spr<strong>in</strong>g 1992): 2–12.Hayek, F.A. “e Use <strong>of</strong> Knowledge <strong>in</strong> Society.” 1945. In Individualism <strong>and</strong> EconomicOrder, chap. 4. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1949.Howitt, Peter. e Keynesian Recovery <strong>and</strong> O<strong>the</strong>r <strong>Essays</strong>. Ann Arbor: University<strong>of</strong> Michigan Press, 1990.Laidler, David. <strong>Essays</strong> on Money <strong>and</strong> Inflation. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1975.Leijonhufvud, Axel. On Keynesian Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Economics <strong>of</strong> Keynes. NewYork: Oxford University Press, 1968.. Information <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation. New York: Oxford University Press, 1981.


Chapter : Macroeconomics <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation 155. “Whatever Happened to Keynesian Economics?” Paper delivered at aconference on e Legacy <strong>of</strong> Keynes, Gustavus Adolphus College, Sa<strong>in</strong>tPeter, M<strong>in</strong>nesota, 30 September <strong>and</strong> 1 October 1986.Lerner, Abba P. “e Essential Properties <strong>of</strong> Interest <strong>and</strong> Money.” QuarterlyJournal <strong>of</strong> Economics 66, no. 2 (May 1952): 172–193.Lucas, Robert E., Jr. Models <strong>of</strong> Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Cycles. Yrjo Jahnsson Lectures. Oxford<strong>and</strong> New York: Basil Blackwell, 1987.Mankiw, N. Gregory, <strong>and</strong> David Romer, eds. New Keynesian Economics. 2 vols.Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1991.Mises, Ludwig von. e eory <strong>of</strong> Money <strong>and</strong> Credit. 1912. Translated by H.E. Batson.Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 1981.. Human Action. 1949. Rev. ed. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press,1963.. Money, Method, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> Process. Selected by Margit von Mises,edited by Richard M. Ebel<strong>in</strong>g. Auburn, Ala., <strong>and</strong> Norwell, Mass.: Ludwigvon Mises Institute <strong>and</strong> Kluwer, 1990.Mitchell, Wesley C. Gold, Prices, <strong>and</strong> Wages Under <strong>the</strong> Greenback St<strong>and</strong>ard. 1908.New York: Kelley, 1966.O’Driscoll, Gerald P., Jr. Economics as a Coord<strong>in</strong>ation Problem. Kansas City:Sheed Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, 1977.Okun, Arthur M. Prices <strong>and</strong> Quantities: A Macroeconomic Analysis. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton,D.C.: Brook<strong>in</strong>gs, 1981.Romer, Christ<strong>in</strong>a D. <strong>and</strong> David H. Romer. “Does Monetary Policy Matter? ANew <strong>Test</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Spirit <strong>of</strong> Friedman <strong>and</strong> Schwartz.” NBER MacroeconomicsAnnual (1989): 121–170.. “New Evidence on <strong>the</strong> Monetary Transmission Mechanism.” Brook<strong>in</strong>gsPapers on Economic Activity, no. 1 (1990): 149–198.Rothbard, Murray N. “In Defense <strong>of</strong> ‘Extreme Apriorism’.” Sou<strong>the</strong>rn EconomicJournal 23 ( January 1957): 314–320.Stockman, Alan C. “Real Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Cycle eory: A Guide, an Evaluation, <strong>and</strong>New Directions.” Federal Reserve Bank <strong>of</strong> Clevel<strong>and</strong> Economic Review 24,no. 4 (1988): 24–47.


156 Part I: EconomicsStrong<strong>in</strong>, Steven. “Real Boats Rock: Monetary Policy <strong>and</strong> Real Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Cycles.”Federal Reserve Bank <strong>of</strong> Chicago Economic Perspectives 12 (November/December1988): 21–28.Summers, Lawrence H. “e Scientific Illusion <strong>in</strong> Empirical Macroeconomics.”Sc<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>avian Journal <strong>of</strong> Economics 93, no. 2 (1991): 129–148.Wickens, Michael. Macroeconomic eory: A Dynamic General Equilibrium Approach.Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press, 2008.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “e Significance <strong>of</strong> Monetary Disequilibrium.” 1986. In Yeager,e Flutter<strong>in</strong>g Veil, edited by George Selg<strong>in</strong>, 217–251. Indianapolis: LibertyFund, 1997.. “New Keynesians <strong>and</strong> Old Monetarists.” 1991. In e Flutter<strong>in</strong>g Veil,edited by George Selg<strong>in</strong>, 281–302. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1997.. “Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek on Calculation <strong>and</strong> Knowledge.” Review <strong>of</strong> AustrianEconomics 7, no. 2 (1994): 93–109.


e Keynesian Heritage<strong>in</strong> Economics * What difference has <strong>the</strong> General eory made? How do economic <strong>the</strong>ory<strong>and</strong> policy differ from what <strong>the</strong>y would have been if Keynes had neverlived?Keynes sold <strong>the</strong> economics pr<strong>of</strong>ession on concern with <strong>the</strong> macroproblems <strong>of</strong> employment <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>. is concern was not new.Even—or especially—among Chicago economists <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> early years <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Great Depression, it had already led to policy recommendations sound<strong>in</strong>gremarkably Keynesian (Davis 1971). But underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g was far from general,as one can verify by brows<strong>in</strong>g through Joseph Dorfman’s EconomicM<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> American Civilisation (1959) <strong>and</strong> by consider<strong>in</strong>g how experimental<strong>and</strong> eclectic anti-depression policy was. Keynes saw <strong>and</strong> provided whatwould ga<strong>in</strong> attention—harsh polemics, sardonic passages, bits <strong>of</strong> esoteric<strong>and</strong> shock<strong>in</strong>g doctr<strong>in</strong>e. It helps a doctr<strong>in</strong>e make a splash, as Harry Johnson(1971) suggested, to possess <strong>the</strong> right degree <strong>of</strong> difficulty—not somuch as to discourage those who would thrill at be<strong>in</strong>g revolutionaries,yet enough to allow those who th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong>y underst<strong>and</strong> it to regard <strong>the</strong>mselvesas an elite vanguard.If anyone should argue that pro-spend<strong>in</strong>g policies <strong>in</strong>spired by Keynesi<strong>and</strong>octr<strong>in</strong>es contributed to general prosperity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dustrialisedcountries for roughly two decades after World War II, I would concede<strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t. It took roughly that long for expectations to become attuned towhat was happen<strong>in</strong>g, for <strong>the</strong> Phillips unemployment/<strong>in</strong>flation trade-<strong>of</strong>f tobreak down, <strong>and</strong> for expansionary policies to waste <strong>the</strong>ir impact <strong>in</strong> price*From Keynes’s General eory: Fifty Years On, eds. John Burton et al. (London: Institute<strong>of</strong> Economic Affairs, 1986), 27–44; repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> A Critique <strong>of</strong> Keynesian Economics,ed. Walter Allan (New York: St. Mart<strong>in</strong>’s Press, 1993), 59–71.157


158 Part I: Economics<strong>in</strong>flation ra<strong>the</strong>r than ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> desired real stimulus. e longer-runeffects <strong>of</strong> Keynesianism are ano<strong>the</strong>r story. “ ”Even <strong>in</strong> its early years, Keynesianism may have been a misfortune. Sounderdevelopments <strong>in</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory might have ga<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>fluence had notKeynesianism crowded <strong>the</strong>m <strong>of</strong>f <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual scene. What Clark Warburtonhas called “monetary disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory” already had an honourabletradition, extend<strong>in</strong>g back at least as far as David Hume <strong>in</strong> 1752<strong>and</strong> P.N. Christiern<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> 1761. Even earlier <strong>in</strong> that century, a rudimentaryversion evidently found successful expression <strong>in</strong> policy <strong>in</strong> several Americancolonies (Lester 1939/1970, chaps. III, IV, <strong>and</strong> V). Warburton’s ownefforts to extend <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> statistical evidence for it <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1940s<strong>and</strong> 1950s were robbed <strong>of</strong> attention by <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>n-prevalent Keynesianism.A sound approach to macroeconomics, <strong>in</strong> my view, runs as follows(it largely overlaps what W.H. Hutt teaches <strong>in</strong> his own idiosyncratic term<strong>in</strong>ology).Fundamentally, beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> veil <strong>of</strong> money, people specialise<strong>in</strong> produc<strong>in</strong>g particular goods <strong>and</strong> services to exchange <strong>the</strong>m for <strong>the</strong>specialised outputs <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people. Any particular output thus constitutesdem<strong>and</strong> for o<strong>the</strong>r (non-compet<strong>in</strong>g) outputs. S<strong>in</strong>ce supply constitutesdem<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> that sense, <strong>the</strong>re can be no fundamental problem <strong>of</strong> deficiency<strong>of</strong> aggregate dem<strong>and</strong>. Even <strong>in</strong> a depression, men <strong>and</strong> women are will<strong>in</strong>gto work, produce, exchange, <strong>and</strong> consume. In particular, employersare will<strong>in</strong>g to hire more workers <strong>and</strong> produce more goods if only <strong>the</strong>ycould f<strong>in</strong>d customers, while unemployed workers are will<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> eager tobecome customers if only <strong>the</strong>y could be back at work earn<strong>in</strong>g money tospend.is doctr<strong>in</strong>e is not just a crude, Panglossian version <strong>of</strong> Say’s Law.It goes on to recognise that someth<strong>in</strong>g may be obstruct<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> transactionswhereby people might gratify unsatisfied desires to <strong>the</strong> benefit <strong>of</strong> allconcerned. It <strong>in</strong>quires <strong>in</strong>to what <strong>the</strong> obstruction might be. In Hutt’s version,villa<strong>in</strong>s are obstruct<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> market forces that would o<strong>the</strong>rwise movewages <strong>and</strong> prices to market-clear<strong>in</strong>g levels.Clark Warburton <strong>of</strong>fered a different emphasis. As he argued (e.g.,1966, selection 1, esp. pp. 26–27), a tendency towards equilibrium ra<strong>the</strong>r Pehr Niclas Christiern<strong>in</strong> (1725–1799) was a Swedish philosopher <strong>and</strong> economist at<strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Uppsala.


Chapter : e Keynesian Heritage <strong>in</strong> Economics 159than disequilibrium is <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> a market economy. Whenever,<strong>the</strong>refore, markets are quite generally <strong>and</strong> conspicuously fail<strong>in</strong>g toclear, some essentially exogenous disturbance must have occurred, a disturbancepervasive enough to resist quick, automatic correction. In adepression, what bars people from accomplish<strong>in</strong>g all <strong>the</strong> exchanges <strong>of</strong>each o<strong>the</strong>r’s goods <strong>and</strong> services that <strong>the</strong>y desire is a deficient real quantity<strong>of</strong> money. Such a deficiency could arise ei<strong>the</strong>r from shr<strong>in</strong>kage <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>money supply or from its failure to keep pace with <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for moneyassociated with real economic growth. Even <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> real money supplycould rema<strong>in</strong> adequate if people marked down <strong>the</strong>ir prices <strong>and</strong> wagessufficiently <strong>and</strong> promptly. Price <strong>and</strong> wage “stick<strong>in</strong>ess” is, however, sensiblefrom <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual decisionmakers, even though that stick<strong>in</strong>ess,<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> monetary disturbances, has pa<strong>in</strong>ful macroeconomicconsequences. (An adaptation <strong>of</strong> this account, draw<strong>in</strong>g on an analogybetween levels <strong>and</strong> trends <strong>of</strong> prices, can h<strong>and</strong>le <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> “stagflation.” Itis unnecessary to assume, as simplistic Keynesian analysis does, that <strong>in</strong>flation<strong>and</strong> depression are exact opposites associated respectively with toomuch <strong>and</strong> too little aggregate dem<strong>and</strong>.) Robert Clower (1965) <strong>and</strong> Axel Leijonhufvud (1968), <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r writers<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir tradition, have <strong>in</strong>terpreted Keynes as espous<strong>in</strong>g a good part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>ory just sketched out. (ey ignored its earlier expositors.) ey emphasisesuch concepts as <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Walrasian auctioneer, <strong>in</strong>complete<strong>and</strong> costly <strong>and</strong> imperfect <strong>in</strong>formation, false price signals, sluggish orpoorly coord<strong>in</strong>ated price adjustments, quantity adjustments besides priceadjustments, <strong>the</strong> dual-decision process (i.e., people’s decisions about try<strong>in</strong>gto buy or sell <strong>in</strong> some markets depend on whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong>y succeed<strong>in</strong> carry<strong>in</strong>g out desired transactions <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r markets), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> “<strong>in</strong>comeconstra<strong>in</strong>edprocess” (<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fectiousness <strong>of</strong> failure or success <strong>in</strong> accomplish<strong>in</strong>gtransactions). In brief, <strong>in</strong>formation gaps <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r frictions bar<strong>the</strong> swift, coord<strong>in</strong>ated, <strong>and</strong> appropriate readjustment <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terdependentyet separately decided prices. In <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> pervasive disturbances, notablymonetary disturbances, <strong>the</strong> price system cannot ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> or readily restoreequilibrium.Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud admit that Keynes did not explicitly statewhat <strong>the</strong>y suppose he meant. ey <strong>of</strong>fer excuses for him. In try<strong>in</strong>g to breakfree from orthodoxy, he was h<strong>and</strong>icapped by unavailability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> required


160 Part I: Economicsconcepts. e orthodox doctr<strong>in</strong>e he was attack<strong>in</strong>g had not yet been spelledout explicitly enough. Still, ample excuses for not hav<strong>in</strong>g done or saidsometh<strong>in</strong>g are not, after all, <strong>the</strong> same as actually hav<strong>in</strong>g done or said it. “”Despite Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud, much <strong>of</strong> what Keynes says <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Generaleory (1936) does <strong>in</strong>deed resemble <strong>the</strong> supposedly vulgar Keynesianism<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> textbooks. If Keynes really was a disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>orist, whydid he make so much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> equilibrium at underemployment?Why did he m<strong>in</strong>imise <strong>and</strong> almost deny <strong>the</strong> automatic forces conceivablywork<strong>in</strong>g, however sluggishly, towards full-employment equilibrium?Why did he repeatedly worry (as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory, p. 347) about“a chronic tendency throughout human history for <strong>the</strong> propensity to saveto be stronger than <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ducement to <strong>in</strong>vest”? “e desire <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualto augment his personal wealth by absta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g from consumption,”Keynes cont<strong>in</strong>ued (p. 348), “has usually been stronger than <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ducementto <strong>the</strong> entrepreneur to augment <strong>the</strong> national wealth by employ<strong>in</strong>g labouron <strong>the</strong> construction <strong>of</strong> durable assets.” Why did he say (p. 31) that a richcommunity would f<strong>in</strong>d it harder than a poor community to fill its sav<strong>in</strong>ggap with <strong>in</strong>vestment? Why did he argue (p. 105) that <strong>the</strong> more fully <strong>in</strong>vestmenthas already provided for <strong>the</strong> future, <strong>the</strong> less scope rema<strong>in</strong>s for mak<strong>in</strong>gstill fur<strong>the</strong>r provision? Keynes’s h<strong>in</strong>ts at <strong>the</strong> stagnation <strong>the</strong>sis <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>favour <strong>of</strong> government responsibility for total <strong>in</strong>vestment also suggest tha<strong>the</strong> worried about real factors mak<strong>in</strong>g for a chronic tendency for dem<strong>and</strong>to prove deficient. So does his emphasis on a “fundamental psychologicallaw” <strong>of</strong> consumption spend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> his h<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> favour <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come redistribution(p. 373) to raise <strong>the</strong> overall propensity to consume.His worries about excessive thrift date back to before <strong>the</strong> General eory.Recall, for example, his parable <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Treatise on Money (1930, vol. I:pp. 176–178) about <strong>the</strong> devastation wrought by a thrift campaign <strong>in</strong> aneconomy <strong>of</strong> banana plantations; he goes on to compare his own <strong>the</strong>orywith <strong>the</strong> over-sav<strong>in</strong>g or under-consumption <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> Mentor Bouniatian,J.A. Hobson, W.T. Foster <strong>and</strong> W. Catch<strong>in</strong>gs. Keynes’s banana parabledescribes too simple an economy to be amenable to <strong>in</strong>terpretationalong <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud. e parable does not evenmention money. Clearly Keynes was worry<strong>in</strong>g about over-sav<strong>in</strong>g as such.Keynes’s emphasis <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory on a def<strong>in</strong>ite multiplier relationbetween changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> total <strong>in</strong>come also suggests


Chapter : e Keynesian Heritage <strong>in</strong> Economics 161concern about difficulties more deep-seated than <strong>the</strong> Clower-Leijonhufvudanalysis describes. is analysis <strong>in</strong>terprets Keynes <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>dynamics <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come-constra<strong>in</strong>ed processes associated with deficiencies <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>formation, <strong>in</strong>adequately adjusted prices, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> attendant discoord<strong>in</strong>ation.It seems significant that W.H. Hutt, whose <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> cumulativedeterioration <strong>in</strong> a depression is remarkably similar to that <strong>of</strong> Clower <strong>and</strong>Leijonhufvud (Glazier 1970), believes he is expound<strong>in</strong>g a doctr<strong>in</strong>e quitedifferent from what he considers to be <strong>the</strong> crudities <strong>of</strong> Keynes.George Brockway (1986, p. 13) provides an extreme example <strong>of</strong> crude,popularised Keynesianism. Possibly Keynes’s greatest contribution washis demonstration that <strong>in</strong> a capitalist system (or <strong>in</strong> any system that isadvanced much beyond bare subsistence), glut is not only possible; it isalways imm<strong>in</strong>ent.Liquidity preference makes <strong>the</strong> economy unable “to buy <strong>and</strong> pay foreveryth<strong>in</strong>g it produces; hence a glut.” Brockway f<strong>in</strong>ds “disgust<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>stupid” <strong>the</strong> attempt be<strong>in</strong>g made <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States nowadays “to ‘balance’<strong>the</strong> budget <strong>and</strong> thus reduce government expenditures at <strong>the</strong> verymoment <strong>the</strong>y should be exp<strong>and</strong>ed.”“Was Keynes a ‘Keynesian’?” Contradict<strong>in</strong>g Leijonhufvud’s <strong>the</strong>sis, HerschelGrossman <strong>in</strong> effect answers “Yes”—<strong>and</strong> properly, <strong>in</strong> my view (Yeager1973): “Keynes’ th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g was both substantially <strong>in</strong> accord with that <strong>of</strong>his popularisers <strong>and</strong> similarly deficient” (Grossman 1972, p. 26). He providedno adequate microeconomic foundation for his macro-<strong>the</strong>ory. Histreatment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for labour, <strong>in</strong> particular, is <strong>in</strong>consistent with <strong>the</strong>Clower-Leijonhufvud <strong>in</strong>terpretation. Instead <strong>of</strong> focus<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> labourmarketconsequences <strong>of</strong> disequilibrium <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> market for current output,Keynes accepted <strong>the</strong> classical view that unemployment <strong>in</strong> a depressionderives from an excessive real wage rate. Keynes had <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d noth<strong>in</strong>g likeClower’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> consumption function <strong>and</strong> simply <strong>of</strong>feredan ad hoc formulation <strong>in</strong>stead. Nei<strong>the</strong>r Keynes’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs nor <strong>the</strong> ensu<strong>in</strong>gcontroversy <strong>and</strong> popularisation accomplished a shift away from a classicalanalytical with such writers as Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Clower.Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Allan Meltzer is ano<strong>the</strong>r economist who does not accept<strong>the</strong> Clower-Leijonhufvud <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory as emphasis<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> supposedly contagious failure <strong>of</strong> markets to clear because <strong>of</strong>sticky or malcoord<strong>in</strong>ated prices (Meltzer 1981, esp. pp. 49, 59; also Meltzer1983). Keynes was <strong>in</strong>deed concerned whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>vestment would be adequateto fill <strong>the</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs gap at full employment. Investment tended to be<strong>in</strong>adequate—not always, but on <strong>the</strong> average over time—because <strong>in</strong>vestors’


162 Part I: Economicslong-term expectations were bedevilled by uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty (non-quantifiablecont<strong>in</strong>gencies, not mere risks that might be estimated). Because expectationswere poorly rooted <strong>in</strong> objective, measurable circumstances, changes<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors’ “animal spirits” tended to be contagious. Because <strong>in</strong>vestmentthus fluctuated around a sub-optimal level, so did total output <strong>and</strong> employment.Some sort <strong>of</strong> government plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> large segments <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestmentseemed advisable as a remedy.For Keynes, as also <strong>in</strong>terpreted by Meltzer, <strong>the</strong>n, macroeconomic difficultieswere more real than monetary ones. Potted versions <strong>of</strong> Keynesian<strong>the</strong>ory underst<strong>and</strong>ably came to focus on those <strong>of</strong> its aspects that are relativelyeasy to build <strong>in</strong>to models—<strong>the</strong> consumption function, <strong>the</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gsgap to be filled by <strong>in</strong>vestment, <strong>the</strong> multiplier, <strong>and</strong> various <strong>in</strong>terest elasticitiesor <strong>in</strong>elasticities—ra<strong>the</strong>r than on <strong>the</strong> shapeless topic <strong>of</strong> hesitant <strong>and</strong>changeable expectations.Alan Codd<strong>in</strong>gton (1976, <strong>in</strong> Wood 1983, vol. IV: p. 227) commentedaptly on Clower’s suggestion that Keynes must have had <strong>the</strong> dual-decisionhypo<strong>the</strong>sis, <strong>in</strong> particular, “at <strong>the</strong> back <strong>of</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d”:e picture here seems to be one <strong>of</strong> Keynes with a m<strong>in</strong>d full <strong>of</strong> ideas,some <strong>of</strong> which he got onto <strong>the</strong> pages <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory, <strong>the</strong> task be<strong>in</strong>gto work out what <strong>the</strong> rema<strong>in</strong>der must have been. is is a problem <strong>of</strong>read<strong>in</strong>g not so much between <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es as <strong>of</strong>f <strong>the</strong> edge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> page.Early reviews <strong>and</strong> anniversary reviews <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory collected<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> volumes edited by Wood, especially volume II, provide little orno support for <strong>the</strong> Clower-Leijonhufvud <strong>in</strong>terpretation. More recent dissentersfrom that <strong>in</strong>terpretation, <strong>in</strong> articles also collected <strong>in</strong> Wood’s volumes,<strong>in</strong>clude Ivan Johnson, Rob<strong>in</strong> Jackman, <strong>and</strong> Victoria Chick.e dist<strong>in</strong>ctive feature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory, says Don Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>,is not simply its ... concern with changes <strong>in</strong> output, but <strong>the</strong> crucial rolethat it assigns to such changes as an equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g force with respect toaggregate dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> supply—or, equivalently, with respect to sav<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment.is is “what Keynes’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> effective dem<strong>and</strong> is all about” <strong>and</strong>what lends crucial significance to his “fundamental psychological law” <strong>of</strong>a marg<strong>in</strong>al propensity to consume less than one (Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong> 1975, <strong>in</strong> Wood1983, vol. I: p. 493). In letters to economists who had written major reviewarticles on <strong>the</strong> book, Keynes not only failed to reject <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation thatgave rise to <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard IS-LM apparatus but even criticised reviewers


Chapter : e Keynesian Heritage <strong>in</strong> Economics 163who gave <strong>in</strong>sufficient emphasis to its cornerstone, his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> effectivedem<strong>and</strong>.So <strong>the</strong>re is no basis for <strong>the</strong> ... contention ... that <strong>the</strong> message whichKeynes really meant to convey with his General eory has been distortedby this <strong>in</strong>terpretation. (Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong> 1981, <strong>in</strong> Wood 1983, vol. I: pp. 607–608) As a self-taught Keynesian who had read <strong>and</strong> re-read <strong>the</strong> General eorybefore tak<strong>in</strong>g any college courses <strong>in</strong> economics, <strong>and</strong> also as a selftaughtmonetarist, I long ago was enthusiastic about <strong>the</strong> apparently monetaristaspects <strong>of</strong> chapter 17 <strong>in</strong> particular. Later I became disillusioned.In describ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> “essential properties” that make money a prime c<strong>and</strong>idatefor be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> excess dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby caus<strong>in</strong>g depression, Keynesemphasises money’s yield. Its liquidity advantages <strong>in</strong> excess <strong>of</strong> carry<strong>in</strong>gcosts may well pose a target rate <strong>of</strong> return that new capital goods couldnot match, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> view <strong>of</strong> potential <strong>in</strong>vestors. As a result, <strong>in</strong>vestment maybe <strong>in</strong>adequate to fill <strong>the</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs gap. Keynes even considers whe<strong>the</strong>r assetso<strong>the</strong>r than money, such as l<strong>and</strong> or mortgages, might pose <strong>the</strong> same sort<strong>of</strong> troublesomely high target rate <strong>of</strong> return. He does not perceive <strong>the</strong> specialsnarl that results when <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> excess dem<strong>and</strong> is <strong>the</strong> medium <strong>of</strong>exchange, so that <strong>the</strong> supply <strong>of</strong> some goods <strong>and</strong> services can fail to constitutedem<strong>and</strong> for o<strong>the</strong>rs. He does not perceive <strong>the</strong> closely related difficultythat money, alone among all assets, has no price <strong>of</strong> its own <strong>and</strong> no market<strong>of</strong> its own. Keynes’s context <strong>of</strong>fered him an <strong>in</strong>vit<strong>in</strong>g opportunity to makeClower’s po<strong>in</strong>t (1967), if he really had it <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, about a possible hiatusbetween sales <strong>and</strong> purchases <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> one th<strong>in</strong>g used <strong>in</strong> practically alltransactions; yet he did not seize that opportunity. Keynes is not entirely consistent with himself throughout <strong>the</strong> Generaleory, but on <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>the</strong> book conveys a real, nonmonetary, <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong>macroeconomic disorder. It diverted economic research <strong>and</strong> policy awayfrom monetary disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory. at (sounder) <strong>the</strong>ory can expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> imbalances betweendem<strong>and</strong> for <strong>and</strong> supply <strong>of</strong> money when prices <strong>and</strong> wages are not For fur<strong>the</strong>r argument that Keynes was preoccupied with oversav<strong>in</strong>g as such ra<strong>the</strong>rthan with excess dem<strong>and</strong> for hold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> money, see Greidanus 1950, esp. pp. 202–203.


164 Part I: Economicssufficiently flexible promptly to absorb <strong>the</strong> full impact <strong>of</strong> a monetary disturbance.It recognises <strong>the</strong> utter reasonableness <strong>of</strong> that <strong>in</strong>flexibility from<strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual price-setters <strong>and</strong> wage negotiators. Althoughmyriad prices <strong>and</strong> wages are <strong>in</strong>terdependent, <strong>the</strong>y are necessarily set <strong>and</strong>adjusted piecemeal <strong>in</strong> a roundabout process. Whe<strong>the</strong>r a contemplatedtransaction can take place to <strong>the</strong> advantage <strong>of</strong> both potential parties maywell depend on prices besides those subject to <strong>the</strong> decisions <strong>of</strong> thoseparties.H.J. Davenport, to mention just one example from early twentiethcenturyAmerica, emphasised <strong>the</strong> monetary nature <strong>of</strong> depression.It rema<strong>in</strong>s difficult to f<strong>in</strong>d a market for products, simply because eachproducer is attempt<strong>in</strong>g a feat which must <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> average be an impossibility—<strong>the</strong>sell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> goods to o<strong>the</strong>rs without a correspond<strong>in</strong>g buy<strong>in</strong>g fromo<strong>the</strong>rs.... [T]he prevail<strong>in</strong>g emphasis is upon money, not as <strong>in</strong>termediatefor present purposes, but as a commodity to be kept.... [T]he psychology<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> time stresses not <strong>the</strong> goods to be exchanged through <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>termediarycommodity, but <strong>the</strong> commodity itself. e halfway house becomesa house <strong>of</strong> stopp<strong>in</strong>g.... Or to put <strong>the</strong> case <strong>in</strong> still ano<strong>the</strong>r way: <strong>the</strong> situationis one <strong>of</strong> withdrawal <strong>of</strong> a large part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> money supply at <strong>the</strong>exist<strong>in</strong>g level <strong>of</strong> prices; it is a change <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> entire dem<strong>and</strong> schedule <strong>of</strong>money aga<strong>in</strong>st goods. (1913, pp. 319–320)Davenport also recognised (p. 299) that <strong>the</strong> depression would be milder<strong>and</strong> shorter if prices could fall evenly all along <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e. In reality, however,not all prices fall with equal speed. Wages fall only slowly <strong>and</strong> with pa<strong>in</strong>fulstruggle, <strong>and</strong> entrepreneurs may be caught <strong>in</strong> a cost-price squeeze. Exist<strong>in</strong>gnom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>debtedness also poses resistance to adjustments. Monetary disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory not only has a long <strong>and</strong> venerable historybut was at times <strong>the</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ant view on macroeconomics (cf. Warburton’swrit<strong>in</strong>gs). Much evidence supports it, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g statistical evidence<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort that present-day monetarists produce. Unfortunately, that promis<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> analysis was largely crowded out fora long time by such Keynesian concepts as <strong>the</strong> IS-LM apparatus, which Fur<strong>the</strong>r quotations from <strong>and</strong> citations to pre-Keynesian writ<strong>in</strong>gs on <strong>the</strong> prevalence<strong>and</strong> reasonableness <strong>of</strong> price <strong>and</strong> wage stick<strong>in</strong>ess can be found <strong>in</strong> my “e Keynesian Diversion”(1973).


Chapter : e Keynesian Heritage <strong>in</strong> Economics 165for some years trivialised <strong>the</strong> confrontation between Keynesians <strong>and</strong> monetarists<strong>in</strong>to supposed differences <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion about <strong>in</strong>terest elasticities. Iconfess that personal experience has made me even more weary <strong>of</strong> suchconcepts. While a visit<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>of</strong>essor at George Mason University <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>fall <strong>of</strong> 1983, I not only had to clean <strong>the</strong> blackboard after my classes, as apr<strong>of</strong>essor should; I also had to clear away what <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>considerate pr<strong>of</strong>essorbefore me had left on <strong>the</strong> board. rough <strong>the</strong> entire semester, more <strong>of</strong>tenthan not, it seemed to me, what was left was <strong>the</strong> Keynesian cross diagramillustrat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> simple-m<strong>in</strong>ded Keynesian multiplier.I blame <strong>the</strong> Keynesians for l<strong>in</strong>ger<strong>in</strong>g notions that government budgetdeficits, apart from how <strong>the</strong>y are f<strong>in</strong>anced, unequivocally “stimulate”<strong>the</strong> economy. Examples <strong>of</strong> tak<strong>in</strong>g this for granted are Abrams <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs(1983) <strong>and</strong> Eisner <strong>and</strong> Pieper (1984). e latter authors even argue, <strong>in</strong>effect, that partial repudiation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> U.S. government debt through itsdecl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al market value as <strong>in</strong>terest rates rise, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n througherosion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> dollar itself, should count as a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> government revenue,mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> real budget deficit <strong>and</strong> its real stimulatory effect slighter than<strong>the</strong>y superficially appear to be.Buchanan <strong>and</strong> Wagner (1977) argue that <strong>the</strong> Keynesian justification <strong>of</strong>budget deficits <strong>in</strong> specific circumstances has been illegitimately extendedby politicians <strong>in</strong>to a reason for complacency about deficits even <strong>in</strong> a muchwidenedrange <strong>of</strong> circumstances.Although Keynes advocated government deficits to boost total spend<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> a slack economy, he also called for government surpluses to restra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>flation dur<strong>in</strong>g booms. But politicians have selectively recalled <strong>the</strong>irKeynesian <strong>the</strong>ory, perennially <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> spend<strong>in</strong>g rationale while convenientlyignor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> restra<strong>in</strong>t Keynes envisioned. (Bendt 1984, p. 5)Perhaps, as is <strong>of</strong>ten said, Keynes was over-confident <strong>of</strong> his ability toturn public op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>and</strong> policy choices around when his own assessmentschanged. -I conjecture that Keynesianism, followed by disillusionment with it, hasprovoked an <strong>in</strong>tellectual overreaction. I refer to doctr<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> “equilibrium Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Hayek recounted just such an expression by Keynes <strong>of</strong> his belief <strong>in</strong> hispowers <strong>of</strong> persuasion <strong>in</strong> a conversation <strong>the</strong>y had “a few weeks before his [Keynes’s] death.”In Hayek 1966/1978, p. 103.


166 Part I: Economicsalways,” which tend to be associated with <strong>the</strong> rational-expectations orNew Classical school, <strong>and</strong> which treat disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ories with scorn. Why should stick<strong>in</strong>esses persist <strong>and</strong> contracts go unrevised, obstruct<strong>in</strong>gexchanges, when rational market participants would adjust pricespromptly <strong>and</strong> completely to levels at which mutually advantageous transactionscould proceed? Equilibrium-always <strong>the</strong>orists do not see fluctuations<strong>in</strong> output <strong>and</strong> employment as reflect<strong>in</strong>g chang<strong>in</strong>g degrees <strong>of</strong> disequilibrium.ey suggest, <strong>in</strong>stead, that markets are still clear<strong>in</strong>g, but withtransactors sometimes respond<strong>in</strong>g to distorted or misperceived prices. Perceptions<strong>of</strong> relative prices <strong>and</strong> relative wages are likely to go awry whenprice <strong>in</strong>flation occurs at an unexpectedly high or unexpectedly low rate. In<strong>the</strong> sense that workers <strong>and</strong> producers are still operat<strong>in</strong>g “on <strong>the</strong>ir supplycurves,” equilibrium, though distorted, cont<strong>in</strong>ues to prevail. Even this distortionwould supposedly be absent if people fully expected <strong>and</strong> allowedfor <strong>the</strong> underly<strong>in</strong>g changes <strong>in</strong> monetary policy, as self-<strong>in</strong>terest would lead<strong>the</strong>m to do to <strong>the</strong> extent that is cost-effectively possible.Exaggerated notions <strong>of</strong> how nearly perfect markets are possess astrange appeal for some <strong>the</strong>orists. Anyway, <strong>the</strong>se exaggerations, toge<strong>the</strong>rwith <strong>the</strong> exegetical writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud, have given perceptiveKeynesians an opportunity to shift <strong>the</strong>ir ground gracefully, with anironic result: someth<strong>in</strong>g like <strong>the</strong> venerable monetary-disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory,which Keynesianism had crowded out, now f<strong>in</strong>ds itself labelled “Keynesian”by leaders <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> over-reaction. e very title, “Second oughtson Keynesian Economies,” <strong>of</strong> an article by Robert Barro (1979), a recanteddisequilibrium <strong>the</strong>orist, suggests <strong>the</strong> apparent notion that <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>gwage <strong>and</strong> price stick<strong>in</strong>ess are Keynesian. Kenneth Arrow (1980, p. 149)casually refers to “Disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>orists, ... stemm<strong>in</strong>g from Keynes.”Stanley Fischer (<strong>in</strong> Fischer 1980, p. 223) refers to “Keynesian disequilibriumanalysis.” James Tob<strong>in</strong> (1980a, p. 789) refers to “<strong>the</strong> Keynesian message”as deal<strong>in</strong>g with disequilibrium <strong>and</strong> sluggishness <strong>of</strong> adjustment.Frank Hahn (1980, p. 137) notes “<strong>the</strong> present <strong>the</strong>oretical disillusionmentwith Keynes” (which, he conjectures, will be reversed). ArthurOkun’s posthumous book (1981) spell<strong>in</strong>g out much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> price<strong>and</strong> wage stick<strong>in</strong>ess is widely regarded as Keynesian. In a new textbook,Hall <strong>and</strong> Taylor (1986, pp. 13–14, 325) report that Lucas 1975 <strong>and</strong> 1980, Lucas <strong>and</strong> Sargent 1978, <strong>and</strong> Willes 1980 are examples <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>gsto this effect. Comments <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g such writ<strong>in</strong>gs pretty much as I do <strong>in</strong>cludeArrow 1980, Buiter 1980, <strong>and</strong> Tob<strong>in</strong> 1980a <strong>and</strong> 1980b. Also Barro 1984, esp. chap. 19.


Chapter : e Keynesian Heritage <strong>in</strong> Economics 167Keynes’s idea was to look at what would happen if prices were “sticky”....Macro-economic models that assume flexible prices <strong>and</strong> wages bear <strong>the</strong>name classical, because it was this assumption that was used by <strong>the</strong> classicaleconomists <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> early twentieth century.... In <strong>the</strong> 1930s, JohnMaynard Keynes began to emphasise <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> wage <strong>and</strong> pricerigidities.Really! A manuscript once sent me by <strong>the</strong> authors even referred to <strong>the</strong>elasticities approach to balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments analysis as Keynesian.Among advanced th<strong>in</strong>kers, or leaders <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> overreaction, “Keynesian”apparently serves as a loose synonym for out <strong>of</strong> fashion <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reforewrong. More generally, though, Keynes enjoys automatic charity. It iswidely taken for granted that such a th<strong>in</strong>g as Keynesian economics exists<strong>and</strong> makes sense. Discussion concerns just what it is to which <strong>the</strong> label“Keynesian” properly applies. Pro- <strong>and</strong> anti-Keynesians alike could welluse better care <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> labels <strong>and</strong> more respect for <strong>the</strong> history<strong>of</strong> thought.’ I do not want to seem too negative. Much can be said <strong>in</strong> Keynes’s favour.He actively pursued <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> arts, public service, <strong>and</strong> many o<strong>the</strong>rfields. He made contributions <strong>in</strong> analys<strong>in</strong>g Indian currency <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ance,<strong>in</strong> assess<strong>in</strong>g economic conditions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> peace settlements after WorldWar I, <strong>in</strong> probability <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> monetary history <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>stitutions. He wrote charm<strong>in</strong>g biographical <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r essays. His contributions<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Tract <strong>of</strong> 1923 ran soundly along l<strong>in</strong>es later called monetarist.Despite un<strong>in</strong>tended <strong>in</strong>fluences that his later doctr<strong>in</strong>es may havehad, Keynes himself was a lifelong <strong>and</strong> eloquent opponent <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>flation(Humphrey 1981).Here, however, our concern is ma<strong>in</strong>ly with <strong>the</strong> General eory. In writ<strong>in</strong>git, Keynes was no doubt moved by a benevolent, if perhaps patrician,humanitarianism—he meant well. Assum<strong>in</strong>g that a first-best (monetarist)diagnosis <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> policy response to <strong>the</strong> depression <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1930s wassomehow not <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> cards, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> policies seem<strong>in</strong>gly recommended by<strong>the</strong> General eory would have been a good second-best approach. In <strong>the</strong>United States, however, what brought recovery was not policies <strong>in</strong>spiredby Keynes but an almost accidental monetary expansion, unfortunately<strong>in</strong>terrupted <strong>in</strong> 1936–1937, <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ally wartime monetary expansion. eideas <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory took several years to filter down through <strong>the</strong>


168 Part I: Economicsacademic world <strong>and</strong> did not ga<strong>in</strong> major <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> policy arena untilafter <strong>the</strong> war. ose policy ideas may well have been beneficial <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> shortrun, but <strong>the</strong>ir long-run harmfulness started becom<strong>in</strong>g evident <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1960s,<strong>and</strong> more so <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1970s.Why, even today, after so much academic dissection <strong>of</strong> Keynesianideas <strong>and</strong> so much sorry experience with <strong>the</strong>ir results <strong>in</strong> practice, does<strong>the</strong> Keynes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory rema<strong>in</strong> for many a fasc<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> evenheroic figure? e disorganisation, obscurities, <strong>and</strong> contradictions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>book, toge<strong>the</strong>r with its apparent pr<strong>of</strong>undity <strong>and</strong> novelty, actually keepdraw<strong>in</strong>g attention to it. Writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> 1946, Paul Samuelson found itnot unlikely that future historians <strong>of</strong> economic thought will concludethat <strong>the</strong> very obscurity <strong>and</strong> polemical character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eoryultimately served to maximize its long-run <strong>in</strong>fluence. (Wood 1983, vol. II:p. 193)Different economists can read <strong>the</strong>ir own favourite ideas <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> Generaleory. Left-w<strong>in</strong>gers, delighted to learn that no mechanism exists tokeep sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment equal at full employment, can use that supposedfundamental flaw as one more stick to beat <strong>the</strong> capitalist systemwith. Right-w<strong>in</strong>g Keynesians (e.g., Polanyi 1948) rejoice that an easy repairwill preserve <strong>and</strong> streng<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> system.James Schles<strong>in</strong>ger (1956, <strong>in</strong> Wood 1983, vol. II: p. 281) suggested thatwhat makes Keynes so satisfy<strong>in</strong>g is not his <strong>the</strong>oretical structure but his“emotional attractiveness.” For many economists whose views were shapedby <strong>the</strong> events <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1930s, he “represents <strong>the</strong> Proper Attitude TowardSocial Problems.” For <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>the</strong> symbolic Keynes will reta<strong>in</strong> his presentposition <strong>of</strong> veneration, for he is <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g embodiment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Dreams<strong>of</strong> eir Youth—<strong>the</strong> reform<strong>in</strong>g fervor <strong>of</strong> ancient days.e discussions, research, <strong>and</strong> attitudes evoked by <strong>the</strong> General eory <strong>of</strong>fermuch to admire. Even as propag<strong>and</strong>a for a short-run policy stance, <strong>the</strong>book may have had merit (as I said above, with heavy qualifications). Butdoes it deserve last<strong>in</strong>g admiration as a scientific performance? Even from Although I am not directly acqua<strong>in</strong>ted with <strong>the</strong> James Joyce <strong>in</strong>dustry, I suspect thatUlysses <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory are alike <strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g employment for academic labourers <strong>of</strong>a certa<strong>in</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d. My own admittedly lame excuse is that I have never written on Keynesexcept by <strong>in</strong>vitation.


Chapter : e Keynesian Heritage <strong>in</strong> Economics 169students writ<strong>in</strong>g exam<strong>in</strong>ation papers under time constra<strong>in</strong>t <strong>and</strong> stress, weteachers expect adequately clear exposition; <strong>and</strong> a student’s protests about“what he meant...”—about what was “at <strong>the</strong> back <strong>of</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d,” to adopt aphrase from Keynes’s sympa<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>in</strong>terpreters—do not suffice to get hisgrade revised upward. Keynes, likewise, hardly deserves credit for wha<strong>the</strong> supposedly may have meant but did not know how to say. If, morethan 50 years later, scholars are still disput<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> central message <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>General eory, that very fact should count aga<strong>in</strong>st ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>in</strong> favour<strong>of</strong> Keynes’s claim to scientific stature. Whatever <strong>the</strong> General eory was, itwas not great science. It was largely a dress<strong>in</strong>g-up <strong>of</strong> old fallacies. Worse,for many years it crowded better science <strong>of</strong>f <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual scene.If Keynes had never written, I conjecture, experience <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> GreatDepression would have prodded economists towards rediscover<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>perfect<strong>in</strong>g monetary-disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory. Researchers like Clark Warburtonwould have ga<strong>in</strong>ed respectful attention earlier. Whatever one maysay favourably about Keynes’s work, it did divert attention away from <strong>the</strong>oriesthat st<strong>and</strong> up better to factual experience <strong>and</strong> critical <strong>in</strong>spection.Abrams, Richard K., Richard Froyen, <strong>and</strong> Roger N. Waud. “e State <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Federal Budget <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> State <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>.” Economic Inquiry 21 (October1983): 485–503.Arrow, Kenneth J. “Real <strong>and</strong> Nom<strong>in</strong>al Magnitudes <strong>in</strong> Economics.” e PublicInterest, Special <strong>Is</strong>sue (1980): 139–150.Barro, Robert J. “Second oughts on Keynesian Economies.” American EconomicReview 69 (May 1979): 54–59.. Macroeconomics. New York: Wiley, 1984.Bendt, Douglas L. “Leash<strong>in</strong>g Federal Spend<strong>in</strong>g.” e Chase Economic Observer 4(March/April 1984): 3–5.Brockway, George P. “Chok<strong>in</strong>g to Death on Cream.” New Leader 69 ( January1986): 12–13.Buchanan, James M., <strong>and</strong> Richard E. Wagner. Democracy In Deficit: e <strong>Political</strong>Legacy <strong>of</strong> Lord Keynes. New York: Academic Press, 1977.Buiter, Willem. “e Macroeconomics <strong>of</strong> Dr. Pangloss: A Critical Survey <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>New Classical Macroeconomics.” Economic Journal 90 (March 1980): 34–50.


170 Part I: EconomicsChristiern<strong>in</strong>, Pehr Niclas. Summary <strong>of</strong> Lectures on <strong>the</strong> High Price <strong>of</strong> ForeignExchange <strong>in</strong> Sweden. 1761. In e Swedish Bullionist Controversy, translated<strong>and</strong> edited by Robert V. Eagly, 41–99. Philadelphia: American PhilosophicalSociety, 1971.Clower, Robert W. “e Keynesian Counterrevolution: A eoretical Appraisal.”In e eory <strong>of</strong> Interest Rates, edited by F.H. Hahn <strong>and</strong> F.P.R. Brechl<strong>in</strong>g,103–125. London: Macmillan, 1965.. “A Reconsideration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Micro-foundations <strong>of</strong> Monetary eory.”Western Economic Journal 6 (December 1967): 1–9.Davenport, Herbert J. e Economics <strong>of</strong> Enterprise. New York: Macmillan, 1913.Davis, J. Ronnie. e New Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Old Economists. Ames: Iowa StateUniversity Press, 1971.Dorfman, Joseph. e Economic M<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> American Civilization. Vol. 5. New York:Vik<strong>in</strong>g Press, 1959.Eisner, Robert, <strong>and</strong> Paul J. Pieper. “A New View <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Federal Debt <strong>and</strong> BudgetDeficits.” American Economic Review 74 (March 1984): 11–29.Fischer, Stanley, ed. Rational Expectations <strong>and</strong> Economic Policy. Chicago: University<strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1980.Glazier, Evelyn M. eories <strong>of</strong> Disequilibrium: Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud Comparedto Hutt. MA <strong>the</strong>sis, University <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia, 1970.Greidanus, Tjardus. e Value <strong>of</strong> Money. 2ⁿ ed. London: Staples Press, 1950.Grossman, Herschel I. “Was Keynes a ‘Keynesian’? A Review Article.” Journal <strong>of</strong>Economic Literature 10 (March 1972): 26–30.Hahn, Frank. “General Equilibrium eory.” e Public Interest, Special <strong>Is</strong>sue(1980): 123–138.Hall, Robert E., <strong>and</strong> John B. Taylor. Macroeconomics. New York: Norton, 1986.Hayek, F.A. “Personal Recollections <strong>of</strong> Keynes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘Keynesian Revolution’.”1966. In A Tiger by <strong>the</strong> Tail, 2ⁿ ed. London: IEA, 1978.Hume, David. “Of Money.” 1752. In Writ<strong>in</strong>gs on Economics, edited by EugeneRotwe<strong>in</strong>, 33–46. Madison: University <strong>of</strong> Wiscons<strong>in</strong> Press, 1970.Humphrey, omas M. “Keynes on Inflation.” Federal Reserve Bank <strong>of</strong> RichmondEconomic Review 67 ( January/February 1981): 3–13.


Chapter : e Keynesian Heritage <strong>in</strong> Economics 171Hutt, W.H. Keynesianism—Retrospect <strong>and</strong> Prospect. Chicago: Regnery, 1963.. A Rehabilitation <strong>of</strong> Say’s Law. A<strong>the</strong>ns: Ohio University Press, 1974.. e Keynesian Episode: A Reassessment. Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1979.Johnson, Harry G. “e Keynesian Revolution <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Monetarist Counter-Revolution.” American Economic Review 61 (May 1971): 1–14.Keynes, John Maynard. A Tract on Monetary Reform. London: Macmillan, 1923.. A Treatise on Money. 2 vols. London: Macmillan, 1930.. e General eory <strong>of</strong> Employment, Interest <strong>and</strong> Money. London <strong>and</strong> NewYork: Macmillan <strong>and</strong> Harcourt Brace, 1936.Leijonhufvud, Axel. On Keynesian Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Economics <strong>of</strong> Keynes. NewYork: Oxford University Press, 1968.Lester, Richard A. Monetary Experiments: Early American <strong>and</strong> Recent Sc<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>avian.1939. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted Newton Abbot, U.K.: David & Charles Repr<strong>in</strong>ts, 1970.Lucas, Robert E., Jr. “An Equilibrium Model <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Cycle.” Journal <strong>of</strong><strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> 83 (December 1975): 1113–1144.. “Methods <strong>and</strong> Problems <strong>in</strong> Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Cycle eory.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Money,Credit, <strong>and</strong> Bank<strong>in</strong>g 12, Pt. 2 (November 1980): 696–715.Lucas, Robert E., Jr., <strong>and</strong> omas J. Sargent. “After Keynesian Macroeconomics.”In After <strong>the</strong> Phillips Curve: Persistence <strong>of</strong> High Inflation <strong>and</strong> HighUnemployment, 49–72. Boston: Federal Reserve Bank <strong>of</strong> Boston, 1978.Meltzer, Allan H. “Keynes’s General eory: A Different Perspective.” Journal <strong>of</strong>Economic Literature 19 (March 1981): 34–64.. “Interpret<strong>in</strong>g Keynes.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic Literature 21 (March 1983):66–78.Okun, Arthur. Prices <strong>and</strong> Quantities. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.: Brook<strong>in</strong>gs Institution,1981.Polanyi, Michael. Full Employment <strong>and</strong> Free Trade. Cambridge, U.K.: CambridgeUniversity Press, 1948.Tob<strong>in</strong>, James. “Are New Classical Models Plausible Enough to Guide Policy?”Journal <strong>of</strong> Money, Credit, <strong>and</strong> Bank<strong>in</strong>g 12, Pt. 2 (November 1980a): 788–799.. Asset Accumulation <strong>and</strong> Economic Activity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell,1980b.


172 Part I: EconomicsWarburton, Clark. Depression, Inflation, <strong>and</strong> Monetary Policy. Baltimore: JohnsHopk<strong>in</strong>s Press, 1966.. “Monetary Disequilibrium eory <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> First Half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> TwentiethCentury.” History <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> 13 (Summer 1981): 285–299.. Book-length manuscript on <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> monetary-disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory,available <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> library <strong>of</strong> George Mason University, Fairfax, Virg<strong>in</strong>ia.Willes, Mark H. “‘Rational Expectations’ as a Counterrevolution.” e PublicInterest, Special <strong>Is</strong>sue (1980): 81–96.Wood, John Cunn<strong>in</strong>gham, ed. John Maynard Keynes: Critical Assessments. 4 vols.London: Croom Helm, 1983.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “e Keynesian Diversion.” Western Economic Journal 11 ( June1973): 150–163.


Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes *William H. Hutt’s career <strong>in</strong>volved work on three cont<strong>in</strong>ents. Born <strong>in</strong> London<strong>in</strong> 1899, he studied at <strong>the</strong> London School <strong>of</strong> Economics. From 1928to 1965, <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Cape Town <strong>in</strong> South Africa was his academicbase. He subsequently emigrated to <strong>the</strong> United States, teach<strong>in</strong>g at severalAmerican universities. He died <strong>in</strong> 1988.Hutt was a wide-rang<strong>in</strong>g scholar. Like John Maynard Keynes, he contributedto topics beyond monetary <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> macroeconomics (see, forexample, Reynolds 1986). In Economists <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Public <strong>and</strong> <strong>Political</strong>ly Impossible... ?, he waxed philosophical, explor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> proper role <strong>of</strong> academiceconomists <strong>in</strong> debates over public policy. He counselled academics to cherish<strong>the</strong>ir ivory-tower purity, avoid<strong>in</strong>g even <strong>the</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> speak<strong>in</strong>g forpolitical parties or <strong>in</strong>dustries or o<strong>the</strong>r private <strong>in</strong>terests, <strong>in</strong> order to preserve<strong>the</strong>ir scientific authority. ey should not compromise <strong>in</strong> hope <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>fluential. Hutt was “sufficient <strong>of</strong> a realist to know that <strong>the</strong> chances <strong>of</strong> ...exercis<strong>in</strong>g any <strong>in</strong>fluence on policy are small.” “Every true economist <strong>in</strong> thisage must be satisfied with great hopes <strong>and</strong> small expectations” (1952a, p. 53,quot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> preface to his own eory <strong>of</strong> Idle Resources). When an economistdoes consider political feasibility <strong>and</strong> so recommends a policy o<strong>the</strong>rthan <strong>the</strong> one he considers best on grounds <strong>of</strong> economics (<strong>and</strong> avowablevalue judgments), <strong>the</strong>n he should clearly state <strong>the</strong> amateur political assessmentunderly<strong>in</strong>g his recommendation, <strong>and</strong> also state <strong>the</strong> policy he trulyconsiders best. Keynes, unlike Hutt, relished active <strong>in</strong>volvement outsideacademia. He wrote much on policy issues, was confident <strong>of</strong> his ability tosway public op<strong>in</strong>ion first one way <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n ano<strong>the</strong>r (as he mentioned <strong>in</strong> aconversation recalled by F.A. Hayek, 1979, pp. 101–102), <strong>and</strong> was <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>edto develop <strong>the</strong>ory to bolster exist<strong>in</strong>g policy <strong>in</strong>tuitions. As its title suggests,however, this chapter concentrates on work for which Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes*From Perspectives on <strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong> Economic ought, vol. 6, Selected Papers from<strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong> Economics Conference, 1989, ed. William J. Barber (Aldershot, U.K., <strong>and</strong>Brookfield, Vt.: Elgar, 1991).173


174 Part I: Economicsare best known <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y treat <strong>the</strong> same topics—<strong>the</strong>ir moneymacro<strong>the</strong>ories. As <strong>the</strong> General eory <strong>in</strong> particular shows, Keynes believed <strong>in</strong> a deepseated,recurrent tendency toward deficiency <strong>of</strong> effective dem<strong>and</strong>, caus<strong>in</strong>gunemployment <strong>and</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> potential output. Keynes had no particularcompla<strong>in</strong>t about how <strong>the</strong> price mechanism would allocate resources,given adequate total dem<strong>and</strong>. Especially <strong>in</strong> wealthy communities, however,private <strong>in</strong>vestment tended to be <strong>in</strong>adequate to absorb all <strong>the</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gthat would be attempted at full employment. Although Keynes <strong>and</strong> hisfollowers sometimes identified <strong>the</strong> difficulty as characteristic <strong>of</strong> a monetaryeconomy as opposed to a barter economy, <strong>the</strong>y did not trace deficiency<strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> to an unstable <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ten wrong quantity <strong>of</strong> money.Even though Keynes waffled a bit on <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> monetary disorder(notably <strong>in</strong> chapter 17 <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory), he def<strong>in</strong>itely was not a monetarist<strong>in</strong> today’s sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word. Monetary disequilibrium, if it occurred,reflected real troubles; he saw market failure, particularly failures centred<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> labour <strong>and</strong> stock <strong>and</strong> bond markets. He believed that on averageover time, bus<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>in</strong>vestment was <strong>in</strong>adequate for full employment <strong>and</strong>was prone to fluctuate with <strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess confidence, which <strong>in</strong> turnwas subject to sudden change because estimates <strong>of</strong> prospective yield hadto be made us<strong>in</strong>g limited knowledge. Keynes alluded to waves <strong>of</strong> optimism<strong>and</strong> pessimism, an antisocial fetish <strong>of</strong> liquidity, <strong>and</strong> “dark forces <strong>of</strong>time <strong>and</strong> ignorance” envelop<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> future (1936, pp. 153–155). For suchreasons, he thought that an acceptable approximation to full employmentrequired susta<strong>in</strong>ed government action to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> adequate total spend<strong>in</strong>g.(To avoid repeat<strong>in</strong>g myself <strong>in</strong> detail, <strong>and</strong> for documentation, I referto my chapter .)’ Hutt’s macroeconomics is more disaggregative <strong>and</strong> micro-oriented. Huttadopts a Say’s Law, or goods-aga<strong>in</strong>st-goods, approach. People specialize<strong>in</strong> produc<strong>in</strong>g particular goods <strong>and</strong> services to trade <strong>the</strong>m away for <strong>the</strong> specializedoutputs <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people. Incomes created <strong>in</strong> particular l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong>production are <strong>the</strong> sources <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> outputs <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r l<strong>in</strong>es: supply<strong>of</strong> some th<strong>in</strong>gs constitutes dem<strong>and</strong> for o<strong>the</strong>r (non-compet<strong>in</strong>g) th<strong>in</strong>gs.


Chapter : Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes 175Fundamentally, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong>re can be no deficiency <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>. Any apparentproblem <strong>of</strong> that sort traces to impediments to <strong>the</strong> exchange <strong>of</strong> goods<strong>and</strong> services for each o<strong>the</strong>r. Impediments to exchange discourage <strong>the</strong> production<strong>of</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> services dest<strong>in</strong>ed for exchange <strong>and</strong> discourage <strong>the</strong>employment <strong>of</strong> labour <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r productive factors. Diagnos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>seimpediments is Hutt’s overrid<strong>in</strong>g concern.Say’s Law, as Hutt <strong>in</strong>terprets <strong>and</strong> extends it, expla<strong>in</strong>s how cuts <strong>in</strong>production <strong>in</strong> some sectors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy entail cuts <strong>in</strong> real dem<strong>and</strong>sfor <strong>the</strong> outputs <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sectors <strong>and</strong> so cuts <strong>in</strong> production <strong>in</strong> those o<strong>the</strong>rsectors also. e rot is cumulative; disequilibrium is <strong>in</strong>fectious; a multiplierprocess operates, although not <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mechanistic way suggested byKeynes’s spuriously precise formulas. In <strong>the</strong> opposite <strong>and</strong> more cheerfuldirection, anyth<strong>in</strong>g promot<strong>in</strong>g recovery <strong>of</strong> production <strong>in</strong> some sectors promotesrecovery <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sectors also.But what are <strong>the</strong> impediments to exchange <strong>and</strong> production that trigger<strong>the</strong> downward movement <strong>and</strong> whose alleviation triggers cumulativerecovery? Hutt po<strong>in</strong>ts to wrong prices. Prices too high to clear <strong>the</strong> marketsfor <strong>the</strong> outputs <strong>of</strong> some sectors cause cutbacks <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir production<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir dem<strong>and</strong>s for <strong>the</strong> outputs <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sectors. What might o<strong>the</strong>rwisehave been equilibrium prices for <strong>the</strong> outputs <strong>of</strong> those o<strong>the</strong>r sectorsare now too high; <strong>and</strong> unless adjusted downwards, <strong>the</strong>y impede exchanges<strong>and</strong> production fur<strong>the</strong>r. Hutt blames wrong pric<strong>in</strong>g, not any <strong>in</strong>adequacy<strong>of</strong> “spend<strong>in</strong>g.” Instead <strong>of</strong> determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> volume <strong>of</strong> exchanges, spend<strong>in</strong>ggets determ<strong>in</strong>ed: <strong>the</strong> flow <strong>of</strong> money transferred <strong>in</strong> lubricat<strong>in</strong>g transactionsdepends on <strong>the</strong>ir physical volume <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> money prices at which thosereal transactions are evaluated. It is fallacious to suppose, with <strong>the</strong> Keynesians,that <strong>in</strong>come is created by transfers <strong>of</strong> money (Hutt 1979, pp. 90, 381).Hutt does not flatly assert that monetary disorder never plays any role atall <strong>in</strong> frustrat<strong>in</strong>g exchanges <strong>and</strong> production. His view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> moneywill require fur<strong>the</strong>r attention later <strong>in</strong> this chapter. Meanwhile, we maynote his remark that “Money is relevant to ‘effective dem<strong>and</strong>’ only becauseunanticipated <strong>in</strong>flation can, <strong>in</strong> a very crude way, cause certa<strong>in</strong> prices whichhave been forced above market-clear<strong>in</strong>g levels (caus<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>refore nonuseor underuse <strong>of</strong> men <strong>and</strong> assets) to become market-clear<strong>in</strong>g values, <strong>the</strong>rebyreleas<strong>in</strong>g ‘withheld’ potential productive capacity <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g ‘effectivedem<strong>and</strong>’ <strong>in</strong> our sense <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> Keynes’ sense” (Hutt 1977, p. 36, emphasis <strong>in</strong>orig<strong>in</strong>al).Hutt scorns <strong>the</strong> fundamentalist Keynesianism that broods about adequacyor <strong>in</strong>adequacy <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>, about <strong>the</strong> propensity to consume out <strong>of</strong>


176 Part I: Economicsreal <strong>in</strong>come, <strong>and</strong> about a sav<strong>in</strong>gs gap that grows with <strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong> wealth<strong>and</strong> so supposedly becomes all <strong>the</strong> harder to fill with real <strong>in</strong>vestmentspend<strong>in</strong>g, especially as real capital formation supposedly leaves fewer <strong>and</strong>fewer attractive opportunities for still fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>vestment. Sav<strong>in</strong>g, as such,cannot pose a problem. People cannot save without acquir<strong>in</strong>g some assetsor o<strong>the</strong>r. If this process, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> associated f<strong>in</strong>ancial transactions,results <strong>in</strong> real capital formation, well <strong>and</strong> good; opportunities for fur<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>vestment still are not foreclosed. Complementarities exist among capitalgoods; hav<strong>in</strong>g more <strong>of</strong> some exp<strong>and</strong>s pr<strong>of</strong>itable opportunities to constructmore <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, sectors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy employ<strong>in</strong>gadditional capital goods enjoy <strong>in</strong>creased productivity <strong>and</strong> real <strong>in</strong>comes,which <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s for <strong>the</strong> outputs <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sectors <strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong>resources to produce <strong>the</strong>m. If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, savers nei<strong>the</strong>r acquirereal assets <strong>the</strong>mselves nor acquire securities by transferr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir comm<strong>and</strong>over resources to entrepreneurs who will construct assets, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y mustbe try<strong>in</strong>g to build up <strong>the</strong>ir hold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> money. Yet Keynes, says Hutt, triedto put <strong>the</strong> blame on an excessive propensity to save as such, obscur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>liquidity-preference or dem<strong>and</strong>-for-money aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> disequilibrium.(is charge, it seems to me, overlooks chapter 17 <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> General eory.What Keynes might better be charged with is vagueness, along with <strong>in</strong>consistencyamong different parts <strong>of</strong> his book.)Actually, says Hutt (1979, p. 295), “sav<strong>in</strong>g preference <strong>and</strong> liquiditypreference are as unrelated as dem<strong>and</strong>s for monocles <strong>and</strong> bubble gum.”Even when an <strong>in</strong>tensified dem<strong>and</strong> for money balances is contribut<strong>in</strong>g tomacroeconomic disequilibrium, <strong>the</strong> blame should fall not on this particularchange <strong>in</strong> preferences but on <strong>the</strong> failure <strong>of</strong> prices to accommodate it.With prices <strong>in</strong>sufficiently flexible, any change <strong>in</strong> technology or resourcesor preferences, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g not only a streng<strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g but even a weaken<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs preference or <strong>of</strong> liquidity preference, can impede market clear<strong>in</strong>g,exchanges, <strong>and</strong> production. Diagnosis must thus focus on how wellor poorly <strong>the</strong> pric<strong>in</strong>g process is work<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> why. In emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fectiousness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> failure <strong>of</strong> some markets to clear(<strong>and</strong>, more cheerfully, <strong>the</strong> cumulative character <strong>of</strong> recovery when someprices <strong>in</strong>itiate adjustment to market-clear<strong>in</strong>g levels), Hutt’s doctr<strong>in</strong>e parallelsa l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> advance <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics pioneered by Robert Clower(1965, 1967) <strong>and</strong> Axel Leijonhufvud (1968) <strong>and</strong> followed by such o<strong>the</strong>r


Chapter : Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes 177economists as Donald Tucker (1971) <strong>and</strong> Robert Barro <strong>and</strong> Herschel Grossman(1971, 1976). eir approach features such concepts as absence <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> (supposed) Walrasian auctioneer, <strong>in</strong>complete <strong>and</strong> costly <strong>and</strong> imperfect<strong>in</strong>formation, false price signals, sluggish price adjustments, quantitychanges as well as price adjustments, <strong>the</strong> duality <strong>of</strong> people’s decisionsabout particular transactions accord<strong>in</strong>g to whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y do or do not meetfrustration <strong>in</strong> accomplish<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r desired transactions, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>comeconstra<strong>in</strong>edprocess (<strong>the</strong> counterpart <strong>of</strong> Hutt’s <strong>in</strong>fectiousness <strong>of</strong> disequilibrium<strong>and</strong> recovery).Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud <strong>of</strong>fered <strong>the</strong>ir approach as spell<strong>in</strong>g out whatKeynes “really meant” or “had at <strong>the</strong> back <strong>of</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d” while writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>General eory. In this <strong>the</strong>y were wrong, <strong>in</strong> my op<strong>in</strong>ion. Actually, <strong>the</strong>ywere <strong>in</strong>dependently resurrect<strong>in</strong>g an older approach from which <strong>the</strong> Keynesianrevolution had diverted attention (Yeager 1973; cf. Grossman 1972).Hutt believes that his own remarkably similar doctr<strong>in</strong>e st<strong>and</strong>s poles apartfrom what he considers <strong>the</strong> crudities <strong>of</strong> Keynes. In a <strong>the</strong>sis on eories<strong>of</strong> Disequilibrium: Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud Compared to Hutt, Mrs. EvelynMarr Glazier notes but does not actually tackle <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> whomore correctly underst<strong>and</strong>s what Keynes really meant. She does, however,show that <strong>the</strong> three economists named <strong>in</strong> her title “agree more on some<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fundamental issues <strong>of</strong> disequilibrium than <strong>the</strong>y do on <strong>the</strong> history<strong>of</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>es” (p. 3).Hutt differs from Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud more <strong>in</strong> emphasis thanon substance. He puts less emphasis than <strong>the</strong>y do on reasons why a considerabledegree <strong>of</strong> price <strong>and</strong> wage stick<strong>in</strong>ess is underst<strong>and</strong>able <strong>and</strong> rational.He does not recognize why, after a disturbance, it naturally takes time toachieve a new equilibrium level <strong>and</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ated pattern <strong>of</strong> prices because<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>completeness <strong>and</strong> costl<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> delays <strong>in</strong> obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g up-to-dateknowledge <strong>of</strong> market conditions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terdependence yet separate<strong>and</strong> sequential sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> revision <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual prices <strong>and</strong> wages. (Onthis latter po<strong>in</strong>t, see Cagan 1980 <strong>and</strong> Yeager 1986.)Hutt notes that Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud stress “<strong>the</strong> imperfections <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> communication process as a cause <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> hiatus” thatmoney poses between desires to sell <strong>and</strong> desires to buy.But <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> communication or <strong>in</strong>formation required for <strong>the</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy takes <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> market pressures; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>sepressures are exerted through loss-avoidance, pr<strong>of</strong>it-seek<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>centives.Faced with such market signals as shr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g or accumulat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ventories,entrepreneurs react by chang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> rates <strong>of</strong> liquidation <strong>of</strong> different


178 Part I: Economics<strong>in</strong>ventories via <strong>the</strong> price changes which <strong>the</strong>y forecast will effect <strong>the</strong> desiredresults. (Hutt 1974, p. 102, emphasis <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al) In passages where he seems about to recognize <strong>the</strong> natural aspect <strong>of</strong> price<strong>and</strong> wage stick<strong>in</strong>ess (for example, 1974, pp. 40–41), Hutt does not followthrough. He regrets <strong>the</strong> less than <strong>in</strong>stantaneous operation <strong>of</strong> marketpressures <strong>and</strong> returns to <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>me that wrong prices <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r economicsectors “merely” make price cuts necessary for market clear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a particularsector (1974, pp. 40–41, 89–90). He notes that if an entrepreneurcorrectly expects a decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for his product to prove temporary,<strong>the</strong>n lett<strong>in</strong>g its <strong>in</strong>ventory grow will turn out to have been a wise <strong>in</strong>vestment.If he proves wrong, <strong>the</strong>n he will have withheld supplies, <strong>and</strong> hismisbehaviour has depressive effects on o<strong>the</strong>r sectors. <strong>Market</strong> processes,however, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> natural selection <strong>of</strong> entrepreneurs, will generallyachieve quick adjustment <strong>of</strong> prices to market-clear<strong>in</strong>g levels if only <strong>the</strong>yare allowed to work (pp. 44–45, 97). Even if government policy aimed atprevent<strong>in</strong>g misbehaviour <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pric<strong>in</strong>g process, it admittedly could notsucceed completely. “ere would always be defects <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> draft<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>required legislation, as well as error <strong>in</strong> enforcement <strong>and</strong> judicial <strong>in</strong>terpretations”(pp. 41–42). So say<strong>in</strong>g, Hutt aga<strong>in</strong> blames imperfect policy ra<strong>the</strong>rthan natural conditions. Entrepreneurial pessimism or timidity <strong>in</strong> depressionshas always been “a consequence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> price mechanism hav<strong>in</strong>g beenprevented from fulfill<strong>in</strong>g its co-ord<strong>in</strong>ative role” (p. 99). Note <strong>the</strong> word“prevented.”Hutt blames government for not suppress<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> basic reason—villa<strong>in</strong>y—whyprices <strong>and</strong> wages do not clear markets <strong>and</strong> assure cont<strong>in</strong>uouscoord<strong>in</strong>ation. He perceives villa<strong>in</strong>y—but <strong>the</strong> word is m<strong>in</strong>e, not his—on<strong>the</strong> part <strong>of</strong> labour unions, bus<strong>in</strong>ess monopolists, <strong>and</strong> government itself.Villa<strong>in</strong>y <strong>in</strong>cludes such th<strong>in</strong>gs as union control over wages, m<strong>in</strong>imum-wagelaws, overgenerous unemployment compensation, <strong>and</strong> monopoly <strong>and</strong> collusion.Hutt recognizes that <strong>the</strong> victims <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>correct pric<strong>in</strong>g are not necessarily<strong>the</strong> villa<strong>in</strong>s. Villa<strong>in</strong>ous pric<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> particular factors <strong>and</strong> outputs canreduce <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s for o<strong>the</strong>r outputs, render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir unchanged priceswrong <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir producers idle (for example, Hutt 1974, p. 88). However,he is <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to criticize even <strong>the</strong>se victims <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs’ malpric<strong>in</strong>g for notadapt<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> changed situation by adjust<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir own prices promptly<strong>and</strong> steeply enough (1974, p. 83).


Chapter : Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes 179roughout his many writ<strong>in</strong>gs (for example, 1973) Hutt denouncesunion wage scales <strong>and</strong> strikes. Even <strong>the</strong> mere possibility <strong>of</strong> strikes detersproductive <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>and</strong> so <strong>the</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> real <strong>in</strong>comes. Even for me, nogreat admirer <strong>of</strong> unions, his repeated fulm<strong>in</strong>ations aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong>m becomedownright bor<strong>in</strong>g.Hutt’s book <strong>of</strong> 1944, conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g proposals for postwar Brita<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> particular,fur<strong>the</strong>r expounds his diagnosis by display<strong>in</strong>g his passion for reconstruct<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> world along idealized competitive l<strong>in</strong>es. Drastic antitrustlaws would prohibit strikes, lockouts, <strong>and</strong> boycotts; contracts or conspiraciesto restra<strong>in</strong> output, trade, or exchange or to take part <strong>in</strong> collusivemonopolies; price discrim<strong>in</strong>ation; amalgamations, mergers, <strong>and</strong> hold<strong>in</strong>gcompanies; acquisition by a corporation <strong>of</strong> shares or debentures <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rcorporations or purchase, as a go<strong>in</strong>g concern, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> assets <strong>of</strong> competitors;<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g directorates. A State Trad<strong>in</strong>g Board would have<strong>the</strong> right to compete with private enterprise, to expropriate property, toimpose schemes for coord<strong>in</strong>ation, synchronization, <strong>and</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ardizationupon groups <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent firms, to determ<strong>in</strong>e hours <strong>and</strong> conditions <strong>of</strong>labour <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> circumstances, to certify quality, <strong>and</strong> to issue cease-<strong>and</strong>desistorders. A Labour Security Board might require young people toaccept specified tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g or apprenticeship <strong>and</strong> might penalize failure toattend regularly <strong>and</strong> perform with due diligence. A Resources UtilizationCommission would require State corporations <strong>and</strong> owners <strong>of</strong> public utilitiesto practise marg<strong>in</strong>al-cost pric<strong>in</strong>g, unless aggregate receipts would beless than fixed cost plus avoidable cost. Hutt gave a def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>alcost <strong>and</strong> added: “In <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> this def<strong>in</strong>ition recourse may behad to <strong>the</strong> text-books <strong>of</strong> economics” (1944, quotation from p. 62).I doubt that Hutt would still, late <strong>in</strong> his career, have advocated suchdrastic steps toward mak<strong>in</strong>g reality conform to textbook chapters on pure<strong>and</strong> perfect competition. In <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g years he, like so many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>rest <strong>of</strong> us, presumably learned much about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrelations between economicfreedom <strong>and</strong> human freedom <strong>in</strong> general; he presumably became disenchantedabout turn<strong>in</strong>g to government for solutions to market failures.But his book <strong>of</strong> 1944 rema<strong>in</strong>s symptomatic <strong>of</strong> an orientation that Huttapparently did hold throughout his career—a concern to trace macroeconomicdifficulties to impediments to <strong>the</strong> ideal work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> markets <strong>and</strong>to seek remedies through microeconomic reconstructions. In his book <strong>of</strong>1974 (pp. 101–102) he still suggested that antitrust action, if not pervertedby demagogic vote-seek<strong>in</strong>g, would be an appropriate <strong>and</strong> important <strong>in</strong>gredient<strong>of</strong> policy for full employment. Pre-Keynesian economists whom he


180 Part I: Economicsadmired believed “that unless government performed its classical role <strong>the</strong>rewas an automatic tendency for groups act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> collusion to price <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>putsor outputs <strong>in</strong> such a way that a cumulative tendency for economies to run downcould be set <strong>in</strong> motion” (1974, p. 120, emphasis <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al).Hutt <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Clower-Leijonhufvud school differ, as we have seen, <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ir relative emphases on villa<strong>in</strong>y <strong>and</strong> reasonable behaviour <strong>in</strong> expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gwage <strong>and</strong> price stick<strong>in</strong>ess. (I do not want to suggest, however, that<strong>the</strong> latter school stresses rigidity or even stick<strong>in</strong>ess as <strong>the</strong> ultimate source<strong>of</strong> discoord<strong>in</strong>ation. Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud probe more deeply <strong>in</strong>to<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tricate <strong>and</strong> prolonged grop<strong>in</strong>g necessary to enlist scattered knowledge<strong>and</strong> achieve a new market-clear<strong>in</strong>g level <strong>and</strong> pattern <strong>of</strong> prices aftera major shock. On this dist<strong>in</strong>ction, see, <strong>in</strong> particular, Leijonhufvud 1981,pp. 111–112.) Ano<strong>the</strong>r po<strong>in</strong>t on which emphases differ concerns <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> money <strong>in</strong> economicdiscoord<strong>in</strong>ation. Clower <strong>in</strong> particular (for example, 1967) emphasizesthat goods do not exchange for goods directly: money is <strong>the</strong> medium<strong>of</strong> exchange, <strong>and</strong> if people have difficulty obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g money by sell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irown goods or services, that very fact keeps <strong>the</strong>m from express<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irdem<strong>and</strong>s for o<strong>the</strong>r people’s goods <strong>and</strong> services.Hutt is sceptical <strong>of</strong> this notion <strong>of</strong> money as a hiatus between sell<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> buy<strong>in</strong>g.[W]hen a person buys, he normally dem<strong>and</strong>s with money’s worth, notwith money. He dem<strong>and</strong>s with money only when he happens to be reduc<strong>in</strong>ghis <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> it (i.e., not concurrently replenish<strong>in</strong>g his moneyhold<strong>in</strong>gs), for he can always obta<strong>in</strong> money costlessly by realiz<strong>in</strong>g his <strong>in</strong>putsor outputs (services or assets) as <strong>the</strong>ir money’s worth.... [T]he acquisition <strong>and</strong>spend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> money ... is costless. It follows that money is as <strong>in</strong>cidental (<strong>and</strong>as important) as cash registers <strong>and</strong> cashiers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> supply<strong>in</strong>gprocess. (1974, pp. 67–68, emphasis <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al; cf. pp. 57–60)In this passage Hutt seems to be suppos<strong>in</strong>g a unified budget constra<strong>in</strong>t,<strong>in</strong> contrast with <strong>the</strong> realistic split constra<strong>in</strong>t described by Clower (1967).He also seems to suppose that all goods <strong>and</strong> services are extremely liquidor readily marketable at <strong>the</strong>ir full values. His downplay<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong>money as medium <strong>of</strong> exchange may be associated with his def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>quantity <strong>of</strong> money very broadly so as to <strong>in</strong>clude what he calls <strong>the</strong> “pure


Chapter : Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes 181money equivalent” <strong>of</strong> nearmoneys <strong>and</strong> nonmoneys (Hutt 1974, pp. 17–18;1979, chap. 8).e possible frustration <strong>of</strong> transactions through failure <strong>of</strong> communications<strong>and</strong> market signals does not basically trace to <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> money.e hiatus arises from <strong>the</strong> remoteness <strong>of</strong> wage-earner <strong>and</strong> wage-earner,<strong>of</strong> entrepreneur <strong>and</strong> entrepreneur. ese remotenesses are <strong>in</strong>evitable consequences<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> extreme division <strong>of</strong> labour that <strong>the</strong> pric<strong>in</strong>g system <strong>and</strong>money make possible. Except <strong>in</strong> this sense, <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> money has noth<strong>in</strong>gwhatever to do with <strong>the</strong> problem. (ese sentences closely paraphrase1974, pp. 58–59.)Yet one would expect someone who expounds <strong>the</strong> tremendous services<strong>of</strong> money as eloquently as Hutt does (for example, 1974, p. 60) torecognize <strong>the</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>gly great scope for damage if <strong>the</strong> real quantity<strong>of</strong> money comes to deviate seriously from <strong>the</strong> total <strong>of</strong> real cash balancesdem<strong>and</strong>ed. One would expect that recognition from <strong>the</strong> author <strong>of</strong> “eYield on Money Held” (1956), an absolutely fundamental contributionto monetary <strong>the</strong>ory. (Hutt expla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> straightforward senses <strong>in</strong> whichbus<strong>in</strong>ess cash balances are productive <strong>and</strong> consumers’ cash balances affordutility. A brilliant exposition <strong>and</strong> extension by Selg<strong>in</strong>, 1987, makes fur<strong>the</strong>rdiscussion here unnecessary.)Yet Hutt says he does not underst<strong>and</strong> why <strong>the</strong> tastes, market processes,<strong>and</strong> so forth that determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> purchas<strong>in</strong>g power <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moneyunit should <strong>in</strong>duce “<strong>in</strong>come constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> withhold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>supplies <strong>and</strong> hence <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s, except <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense that, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> presence<strong>of</strong> downward cost <strong>and</strong> price rigidities, deflation will aggravate <strong>the</strong> cumulativewithhold<strong>in</strong>g process—just as unanticipated <strong>in</strong>flation will mitigate orreverse it” (1974, p. 62, emphasis <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al). Whe<strong>the</strong>r Hutt realizes it ornot, <strong>the</strong> exception he makes is a mammoth one. He also appears to recognize<strong>the</strong> damage that an <strong>in</strong>appropriate quantity <strong>of</strong> money can do whenhe quotes Leijonhufvud, with apparent agreement, concern<strong>in</strong>g “recurrentattacks <strong>of</strong> central bank perversity” (1974, p. 73, quot<strong>in</strong>g Leijonhufvud 1968,p. 399, where, however, Leijonhufvud capitalizes <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itial letters <strong>of</strong> “CentralBank”).Yet Hutt shies away from recogniz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> money <strong>in</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>esscycles <strong>and</strong> from appreciat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> monetary-disequilibrium hypo<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>of</strong>David Hume, Clark Warburton, Milton Friedman, Karl Brunner, AllanMeltzer, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r monetarists. In an oblique reference to <strong>the</strong> monetaryaspect <strong>of</strong> depression, Hutt did go so far as to say that <strong>the</strong> classicalorthodoxy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1920s <strong>and</strong> 1930s had warned aga<strong>in</strong>st “<strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong>


182 Part I: Economicsan <strong>in</strong>flationary situation which, requir<strong>in</strong>g subsequent deflationary ratificationif contractual monetary obligations were to be honored, would eventuallyprecipitate depression through predictable resistances to <strong>the</strong> necessaryprice adjustments” (Hutt 1974, p. 118, emphasis <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al). In severalplaces, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, Hutt appears to advocate a policy <strong>of</strong> accommodat<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong> money to <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> to hold it at a stable price level.Even so, he backs away from trac<strong>in</strong>g macroeconomic disorder to money.When he comes as close as he ever does to compar<strong>in</strong>g monetary disturbances<strong>and</strong> price rigidities as sources <strong>of</strong> disruption, he almost always putshis emphasis on <strong>the</strong> rigidities (for example, 1974, p. 69). e nonmonetaryview <strong>of</strong> depression, he says, “is truly <strong>the</strong> explanation <strong>of</strong> all depression.When deflation is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itiat<strong>in</strong>g factor (under downward cost or pricerigidity), <strong>the</strong> economy still runs through <strong>the</strong> cumulative consequences <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> withdrawal <strong>of</strong> supplies <strong>of</strong> non-money” (1974, p. 73 n., emphasis <strong>in</strong>orig<strong>in</strong>al).[D]epression is due to <strong>the</strong> chronic, cont<strong>in</strong>uous boost<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> costs <strong>in</strong> occupations<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dustries where <strong>the</strong> unions tend to be strongest—becausedem<strong>and</strong>s for <strong>the</strong>ir outputs happen to be most <strong>in</strong>elastic <strong>and</strong> consumers<strong>the</strong>refore most easily exploited. In <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>flation it would havebeen perceived how <strong>the</strong> withdrawal <strong>of</strong> labour <strong>and</strong> output by over-pric<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> such activities reduces <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s for <strong>the</strong> outputs <strong>of</strong> lesseasily exploitable occupations <strong>and</strong> activities. (1975, p. 113; footnotes omittedhere)But one might well expect Hutt to expla<strong>in</strong> why a “chronic” <strong>and</strong> “cont<strong>in</strong>uous”problem manifests itself <strong>in</strong> only occasional depressions, withhealthy growth <strong>and</strong> occasional booms <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g. Later Hutt says that<strong>in</strong>flation, if unanticipated, can improve price/cost ratios <strong>in</strong> many sectors<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy. But this crude remedy attracts resources <strong>in</strong>to unsusta<strong>in</strong>ablek<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> production <strong>and</strong> “creates such basic distortions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pric<strong>in</strong>gmechanism that we must <strong>of</strong>ten blame <strong>the</strong> attempt to spend depression<strong>in</strong>to prosperity for aggravat<strong>in</strong>g prospective <strong>and</strong> realised unemployment” (1975,pp. 113–114, emphasis <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al).Hutt touches on certa<strong>in</strong> crucial questions about money without giv<strong>in</strong>gsufficiently explicit answers. In some passages he takes such pa<strong>in</strong>s topenetrate beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> veil <strong>of</strong> money that he practically denies money’s rout<strong>in</strong>ebut momentously important function as <strong>the</strong> medium <strong>of</strong> exchange;he actually says that people are buy<strong>in</strong>g goods <strong>and</strong> services with moneyonly when, untypically, <strong>the</strong>y are act<strong>in</strong>g to reduce <strong>the</strong>ir cash balances (1979,


Chapter : Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes 183pp. 238, 295). When <strong>in</strong>flation appears to be stimulat<strong>in</strong>g a depressed economy—aphenomenon supposedly beloved <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Keynesians—does <strong>the</strong>stimulus come from <strong>the</strong> monetary expansion as such, with prices lagg<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong> money <strong>and</strong> flow <strong>of</strong> spend<strong>in</strong>g thus grow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> realterms, or from <strong>the</strong> price <strong>in</strong>flation itself, which may be rectify<strong>in</strong>g wrong relativeprices, especially by erod<strong>in</strong>g excessively high real wage rates? OftenHutt appears to give <strong>the</strong> latter answer, suggest<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> trick <strong>of</strong> gett<strong>in</strong>greal wages down <strong>in</strong> a relatively politically feasible way is <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong>Keynesian employment policy. Interpreters disagree, but o<strong>the</strong>rs have alsotaken Keynes to mean just that. It would be ironic if Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes,when agree<strong>in</strong>g, agree on an erroneous po<strong>in</strong>t.In a malcoord<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>and</strong> depressed economy, does <strong>the</strong> trouble necessarilystem from wrong relative prices, such as excessive real wages, ormight it stem <strong>in</strong>stead ma<strong>in</strong>ly from prices <strong>and</strong> wages that, although notbadly out <strong>of</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e with one ano<strong>the</strong>r, are generally too high (or conceivablytoo low) <strong>in</strong> relation to <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al quantity <strong>of</strong> money? In some passages(September 1953, p. 224; 1979, pp. 147, 282–283, <strong>and</strong> passim) Huttemphasizes unstable price rigidities <strong>and</strong> people’s postponement <strong>of</strong> purchaseswhile wait<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> rigidities to break down <strong>and</strong> prices to fall,seem<strong>in</strong>g to imply that <strong>the</strong> particular price level would not matter if itspermanent rigidity were obviat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se expectations <strong>and</strong> postponements.In o<strong>the</strong>r passages (1979, pp. 185–186, 207, <strong>and</strong> passim) he seems to advocatea policy <strong>of</strong> flexibly accommodat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al quantity <strong>of</strong> money to<strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g price level, as if he were <strong>in</strong>deed concerned about <strong>the</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>fulnecessity <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwise adjust<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> price <strong>and</strong> wage level to <strong>the</strong> moneysupply.Hutt anticipated some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soundest parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present-day doctr<strong>in</strong>e<strong>of</strong> rational expectations. He emphasizes that when <strong>in</strong>flation hascome to be generally expected <strong>and</strong> allowed for, it becomes purposeless.Unemployment becomes almost a normal accompaniment <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>flation,even accelerat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>flation (1977, pp. 37–38; cf. p. 252). In <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rpassages, however, it is unclear whe<strong>the</strong>r he sees <strong>the</strong> underly<strong>in</strong>g moneysupplyexpansion itself or <strong>in</strong>stead sees <strong>the</strong> result<strong>in</strong>g price <strong>in</strong>flation as whatmay <strong>in</strong>itially stimulate or recoord<strong>in</strong>ate an economy (although eventuallybecom<strong>in</strong>g futile). Apparently he means <strong>the</strong> latter: price <strong>in</strong>flation maybe a way—an <strong>in</strong>ferior, temporary, Keynesian way—<strong>of</strong> improv<strong>in</strong>g coord<strong>in</strong>ationby <strong>in</strong>flat<strong>in</strong>g down excessively high real wage rates. He does notforthrightly grapple with <strong>the</strong> monetarist po<strong>in</strong>t that depression may occurnot so much because relative prices <strong>and</strong> wages are wrong as because <strong>the</strong>


184 Part I: Economicswhole wage <strong>and</strong> price level is too high <strong>in</strong> relation to <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al quantity<strong>of</strong> money or, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words, because <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al money supply hasbecome too small for <strong>the</strong> wage <strong>and</strong> price level.’ Readers must wish that Hutt had done what he did not do, namely systematicallypresent <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>es he considered rivals <strong>of</strong> his own <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>irstrongest versions, criticize <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> adequate detail, <strong>and</strong> show just how<strong>the</strong>y fail where his succeeds. We know Hutt disliked Keynesianism; itwould be <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to know <strong>in</strong> some detail what he thought about monetaristreason<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> evidence.Hutt’s failure to make his position clear on crucial issues, toge<strong>the</strong>r with<strong>the</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g style that is largely responsible, br<strong>in</strong>gs to m<strong>in</strong>d his own compla<strong>in</strong>t(for example, <strong>in</strong> 1979, Prologue) about how little scholarly dialoguehis work had elicited, particularly from Keynesians. (Consider, also, <strong>the</strong>harsh review <strong>of</strong> Hutt 1974 by Herschel Grossman, 1976, someone who Ith<strong>in</strong>k would be sympa<strong>the</strong>tic to much <strong>of</strong> Hutt’s message if it were presentedclearly.)Hutt’s exposition is a collection <strong>of</strong> discursive <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ten cryptic remarks.Strewn over hundreds <strong>of</strong> pages (<strong>in</strong> 1979, for example), <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> no readily<strong>in</strong>telligible order, we f<strong>in</strong>d bits <strong>of</strong> positive analysis, jabs at Keynesianism,historical allusions, policy proposals, <strong>and</strong> autobiographical asides. Hutthad a habit <strong>of</strong> latch<strong>in</strong>g onto remarks by o<strong>the</strong>r writers as <strong>the</strong>y were apparentlycast up at r<strong>and</strong>om by his own read<strong>in</strong>g, even if those writers were notlead<strong>in</strong>g or typical authorities or controversialists on <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ts at issue,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir remarks as pegs onto which to str<strong>in</strong>g his own observations.is habit gave his writ<strong>in</strong>g an unnecessarily polemical tone. (AsPejovich 1978 noted, Hutt had a normative bent <strong>and</strong> seemed not particularlyconcerned with non-normative analysis <strong>of</strong> allocations generated byalternative <strong>in</strong>stitutional arrangements.)Strewn through Hutt’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs are echoes <strong>of</strong> long-st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g obsessions,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>of</strong> course, his obsession with labour unions. Ano<strong>the</strong>rconcerns Brita<strong>in</strong>’s return to <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>in</strong> 1925 at <strong>the</strong> prewar parity,requir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ternal deflation if that parity were to rema<strong>in</strong> workable.Repeatedly, though <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>in</strong> cryptic language, Hutt <strong>of</strong>fered apologeticsfor that policy. He might even have been right, but <strong>the</strong> way that <strong>the</strong>seapologetics kept <strong>in</strong>trud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> unlikely places <strong>and</strong> with a moraliz<strong>in</strong>g toneis characteristic <strong>of</strong> his style.


Chapter : Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes 185Ano<strong>the</strong>r characteristic is lengthy brood<strong>in</strong>g over <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> terms<strong>and</strong> concepts. Hutt once recorded his “strong dislike for mere ‘term<strong>in</strong>ological<strong>in</strong>novation’” (September 1953, p. 215), but this is a dislike that he managedto overcome. Some wag once said that he wrote <strong>in</strong> Huttite. Hutt<strong>of</strong>fered lengthy <strong>and</strong> sometimes obscure def<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>of</strong> such concepts asmarket-clear<strong>in</strong>g prices for <strong>in</strong>puts (1977, p. 105), competition (1977, p. 154;1974, pp. 15–16), exploitation (1977, p. 218 n.), money (1977, p. 254), <strong>and</strong>some n<strong>in</strong>e or ten varieties <strong>of</strong> idleness (throughout his 1977). Presumablyout <strong>of</strong> aversion to <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g with aggregates <strong>and</strong> averages, Hutt avoided<strong>the</strong> term “price level,” say<strong>in</strong>g “scale <strong>of</strong> prices” <strong>in</strong>stead (for example, September1953, p. 217; 1979, p. 214).Hutt used one term so much that I, anyway, became accustomed to it:“withheld capacity.” is term suggests that people who, <strong>in</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary language,are hav<strong>in</strong>g a hard time f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g jobs or customers are withhold<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>ir capacity to work or produce by <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g on wages or prices abovemarket-clear<strong>in</strong>g levels. So do<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>y are withhold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir dem<strong>and</strong>s for<strong>the</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> services <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby caus<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r prices<strong>and</strong> wages, if unchanged, to be excessive. is term<strong>in</strong>ological allusion tovilla<strong>in</strong>y serves to shunt aside analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> reasons for price<strong>and</strong> wage stick<strong>in</strong>ess, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g ways that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terdependence <strong>of</strong> wages<strong>and</strong> prices narrows <strong>the</strong> reasonable options available to <strong>in</strong>dividual pricesetters<strong>and</strong> wage negotiators. His term<strong>in</strong>ology helps Hutt to damn realityfor be<strong>in</strong>g real. Yet he himself briefly recognized (for example, 1977,pp. 136 n., 204) that resistance to wage <strong>and</strong> price adjustments can be “<strong>in</strong>dividuallyrational” although “collectively irrational.”His term<strong>in</strong>ology would permit him, if pressed, to defend propositionsthat are startl<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong>ir face.e withhold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> capacity which is capable <strong>of</strong> provid<strong>in</strong>g currently valuableservices is always a case <strong>of</strong> restra<strong>in</strong>t on freedom. (1979, p. 371 n.)[T]he labor <strong>of</strong> all able-bodied persons was dem<strong>and</strong>ed throughout <strong>the</strong>depression years. It was not supplied. (1979, p. 169)[W]hat is usually called “unemployed labor” could be more realisticallycalled “unsupplied labor.” (1974, p. 79)Individuals actively “prospect<strong>in</strong>g” for remunerative jobs are employed.(italicized section head<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> 1977, p. 83)[In <strong>the</strong>] phrase “excess supply” <strong>of</strong> labor ... <strong>the</strong> word “excess” ... couldmore appropriately be “deficient” or “<strong>in</strong>sufficient”! (1974, p. 86)


186 Part I: Economics[T]he phrase “will<strong>in</strong>gness to dem<strong>and</strong>” ... simply means “will<strong>in</strong>gness tosupply”! (1974, p. 27)[W]hen <strong>the</strong>re is a “shortage” or ration<strong>in</strong>g, we usually say that “dem<strong>and</strong>exceeds supply,” although what we really mean is that, at <strong>the</strong> price asked,more would be dem<strong>and</strong>ed if more were supplied. Hence I cannot conceive<strong>of</strong> any situation <strong>in</strong> which ... <strong>the</strong> value <strong>and</strong> amount dem<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>any market fails to equal <strong>the</strong> value <strong>and</strong> amount supplied.... [P]eoplewho would be prepared to dem<strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> price asked if <strong>the</strong>y could get<strong>the</strong> goods are prevented from dem<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g. (1974, pp. 80–81)[C]onsumption is always <strong>the</strong> exterm<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> power to dem<strong>and</strong>. efailure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Keynesians to underst<strong>and</strong> this simple truth lies at <strong>the</strong> root<strong>of</strong> what I believe to be <strong>the</strong> most outrageous <strong>in</strong>tellectual error <strong>of</strong> this age.(1979, p. 341)Hutt <strong>of</strong>ten covered himself aga<strong>in</strong>st challenge by qualify<strong>in</strong>g apparentlyegregious propositions with cryptic phrases that are hardly underst<strong>and</strong>ableunless <strong>the</strong> reader is already familiar with his term<strong>in</strong>ology <strong>and</strong> allusions. Forexample,It is quite wrong to assume that unfavorable prospects can deter net accumulations,o<strong>the</strong>rwise than through <strong>the</strong> discouragement <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g preference,or—<strong>in</strong>directly—through <strong>the</strong> encouragement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> withhold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>capacity (although such prospects certa<strong>in</strong>ly do <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>the</strong> form takenby accumulation). (1979, p. 349)A similar habit was to mention government policies not always straightforwardlybut ra<strong>the</strong>r with reference to <strong>the</strong> results that Hutt would expect<strong>the</strong>m to have. us, <strong>in</strong> an historical context: “not a s<strong>in</strong>gle governmentalstep toward multiply<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> wages flow was taken” (italicized <strong>in</strong> 1979,p. 61), mean<strong>in</strong>g, approximately, that <strong>the</strong> government did not act aga<strong>in</strong>st<strong>the</strong> unions. Besides his term<strong>in</strong>ology, tone, <strong>and</strong> paradox-monger<strong>in</strong>g, o<strong>the</strong>r circumstanceshelp expla<strong>in</strong> why Hutt’s work has received less attention thanKeynes’s. Although <strong>the</strong> General eory was not Keynes’s best-writtenbook, it does conta<strong>in</strong> flashes <strong>of</strong> clever writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> appeal<strong>in</strong>g new concepts<strong>and</strong> term<strong>in</strong>ology. Keynes presented his message as revolutionary,<strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g young or adaptable economists <strong>the</strong> opportunity to march at <strong>the</strong>


Chapter : Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes 187vanguard <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ession. Keynes’s <strong>the</strong>ory had political appeal. It cameas a rationalization (whe<strong>the</strong>r sound or unsound) <strong>of</strong> policies that wouldhave been beneficial under <strong>the</strong> exceptional circumstances <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mid-1930s.Hutt, though, was recommend<strong>in</strong>g micro-oriented policies that wouldhave stepped on toes <strong>and</strong> whose desired benefits would not have comequickly.Hutt always ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed that he was expound<strong>in</strong>g old, orthodox doctr<strong>in</strong>e;but, although allud<strong>in</strong>g to Edw<strong>in</strong> Cannan <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> London Schooltradition, he did not build on his predecessors’ work <strong>in</strong> adequate detail,<strong>and</strong> he neglected to forge l<strong>in</strong>ks with pre-Keynesian monetary-disequilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory. So he put himself at a double-barreled disadvantage—confess<strong>in</strong>gthat his message was basically old stuff, while not clearly show<strong>in</strong>ghow he was extend<strong>in</strong>g it. Keynes’s <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>in</strong> contrast, appealed toacademic economists by conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g concepts <strong>and</strong> gimmicks <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g possibilitiesfor research <strong>and</strong> publication, for class lectures <strong>and</strong> exam<strong>in</strong>ationquestions. (On this matter <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal dynamic <strong>of</strong> a field <strong>of</strong> study, seeCol<strong>and</strong>er 1986.) ’ Although I do th<strong>in</strong>k that Hutt created unnecessary difficulties for its acceptance,I do not mean to disparage his message itself. Apparent macro disorderscan <strong>in</strong>deed trace partly to micro distortions, particularly <strong>in</strong> prices <strong>and</strong>wages. Because market transactions are voluntary <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> short side determ<strong>in</strong>es<strong>the</strong> actual quantity traded <strong>in</strong> any market, frustration <strong>of</strong> transactions<strong>and</strong> so <strong>of</strong> production can cumulate <strong>in</strong> a quasi-multiplier process. Downwardcumulativeness is particularly severe if money <strong>and</strong> credit undergo an<strong>in</strong>duced or secondary deflation (although I do wish that Hutt had beenmore emphatic <strong>in</strong> recogniz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> money). Like F.A. Hayek <strong>and</strong>o<strong>the</strong>rs, Hutt was magnificently right <strong>in</strong> his strictures aga<strong>in</strong>st chronically<strong>in</strong>flationary policies as supposed cures <strong>of</strong> unemployment.Because <strong>of</strong> Hutt’s style <strong>and</strong> tone, his writ<strong>in</strong>gs are unlikely to persuadereaders who lack <strong>the</strong> background <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> will necessary to underst<strong>and</strong>his eccentrically phrased message. For two reasons I myself have beenturned <strong>of</strong>f by Hutt’s style less than most readers probably would be. First,when I came across Hutt’s work decades ago, I happened to be predisposed<strong>in</strong> favour <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> message he was try<strong>in</strong>g to convey. Second, I wasprivileged <strong>in</strong> 1955 to attend a two-week conference at which he was one<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> speakers. Later, when he served as visit<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>of</strong>essor at <strong>the</strong>


188 Part I: EconomicsUniversity <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia, we were colleagues. His analytical message, hishumanitarian concern for those suffer<strong>in</strong>g from restrictions on economicopportunity, his <strong>in</strong>tellectual force <strong>and</strong> zeal, <strong>and</strong> his <strong>in</strong>tegrity came acrossbetter when he had ample opportunity to present his message <strong>in</strong> personthan when he <strong>of</strong>fered it <strong>in</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g alone.Whe<strong>the</strong>r he realized it or not, Hutt was preach<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> already saved.Do<strong>in</strong>g so, however, is far from po<strong>in</strong>tless. Sympa<strong>the</strong>tic readers can f<strong>in</strong>dmuch <strong>in</strong> his work to fortify <strong>the</strong>ir underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> how <strong>the</strong> real worldworks <strong>and</strong> could be made to work better. ey can f<strong>in</strong>d much to deepen<strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> fallacies <strong>of</strong> Keynesian doctr<strong>in</strong>es whose former dom<strong>in</strong>ancehas still not been entirely expunged. Teachers able to give sympa<strong>the</strong>ticexpositions can make good use <strong>of</strong> Hutt’s work <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir classes. Itmay serve as <strong>the</strong> focus <strong>of</strong> fruitful controversy among sympa<strong>the</strong>tic readers.Barro, Robert J., <strong>and</strong> Herschel I. Grossman. “A General Disequilibrium Model<strong>of</strong> Income <strong>and</strong> Employment.” American Economic Review 61 (March 1971):82–93.. Money, Employment, <strong>and</strong> Inflation. New York: Cambridge UniversityPress, 1976.Cagan, Philip. “Reflections on Rational Expectations.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Money, Credit,<strong>and</strong> Bank<strong>in</strong>g 12, Pt. 2 (November 1980): 826–832.Clower, Robert W. “e Keynesian Counterrevolution: A eoretical Appraisal.”In e eory <strong>of</strong> Interest Rates, edited by F.H. Hahn <strong>and</strong> F.P.R. Brechl<strong>in</strong>g,103–125. London: Macmillan, 1965.. “A Reconsideration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Micr<strong>of</strong>oundations <strong>of</strong> Monetary eory.”Western Economic Journal 6 (December 1967): 1–8.Col<strong>and</strong>er, David C. “e Evolution <strong>of</strong> Keynesian Economics.” Unpublishedmanuscript dated 14 October 1986. Prepared for presentation at GlendonCollege, York University, Conference on Keynes <strong>and</strong> Public Policy after FiftyYears, 1986.Friedman, Milton, <strong>and</strong> Anna J. Schwartz. A Monetary History <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States,1867–1960. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press, 1963.Glazier, Evelyn M. eories <strong>of</strong> Disequilibrium: Clower <strong>and</strong> Leijonhufvud Comparedto Hutt. MA esis, University <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia, 1970.


Chapter : Hutt <strong>and</strong> Keynes 189Grossman, Herschel I. “Was Keynes a ‘Keynesian’?” Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic Literature10 (1972): 26–30.. Review <strong>of</strong> A Rehabilitation <strong>of</strong> Say’s Law, by W.H. Hutt. e ManchesterSchool <strong>of</strong> Economic <strong>and</strong> Social Studies 44 ( June 1976): 196–197.Hayek, F.A. A Tiger by <strong>the</strong> Tail. San Francisco: Cato Institute, 1979.Hutt, W.H. Economists <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Public. London: Jonathan Cape, 1936.. Plan for Reconstruction. New York: Oxford University Press, 1944.. “e Nature <strong>of</strong> Money.” South African Journal <strong>of</strong> Economics 20 (March1952a): 50–64.. “e Notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Volume <strong>of</strong> Money.” South African Journal <strong>of</strong> Economics20, no. 3 (September 1952b): 231–241.. “e Notion <strong>of</strong> Money <strong>of</strong> Constant Value.” Parts I <strong>and</strong> II. South AfricanJournal <strong>of</strong> Economics 21 (September <strong>and</strong> December 1953): 215–226 <strong>and</strong> 341–353.. “e Significance <strong>of</strong> Price Flexibility.” South African Journal <strong>of</strong> Economics22 (March 1954): 40–51.. “e Yield from Money Held.” In On Freedom <strong>and</strong> Free Enterprise,edited by M. Sennholz, 196–216. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>, 1956.. Keynesianism—Retrospect <strong>and</strong> Prospect. Chicago: Regnery, 1963.. <strong>Political</strong>ly Impossible ... ? London: Institute <strong>of</strong> Economic Affairs, 1971.. e Strike-reat System. New Rochelle, N.Y.: Arl<strong>in</strong>gton House, 1973.. A Rehabilitation <strong>of</strong> Say’s Law. A<strong>the</strong>ns: Ohio University Press, 1974.. e eory <strong>of</strong> Collective Barga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, 1930–1975. 1930. London: Institute <strong>of</strong>Economic Affairs, 1975.. e eory <strong>of</strong> Idle Resources: A Study <strong>in</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ition. 1939. 2ⁿ ed. Indianapolis:Liberty Press, 1977.. e Keynesian Episode: A Reassessment. Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1979.Keynes, John M. e General eory <strong>of</strong> Employment, Interest <strong>and</strong> Money. NewYork: Harcourt Brace, 1936.Leijonhufvud, Axel. On Keynesian Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Economics <strong>of</strong> Keynes. NewYork: Oxford University Press, 1968.


190 Part I: Economics. Information <strong>and</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ation. New York: Oxford University Press, 1981.Pejovich, Svetozar. Review <strong>of</strong> Economic Forces at Work, by Armen Alchian, <strong>and</strong>e eory <strong>of</strong> Idle Resources, by W.H. Hutt. Modern Age 22 (W<strong>in</strong>ter 1978):92–94.Reynolds, Morgan O., ed. W.H. Hutt: An Economist for <strong>the</strong> Long Run. Chicago<strong>and</strong> Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.: Gateway Editions, 1986.Selg<strong>in</strong>, George A. “e Yield on Money Held Revisited: Lessons for Today.”<strong>Market</strong> Process 5, no. 1 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g 1987): 18–24.Tucker, Donald P. “Macroeconomic Models <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Dem<strong>and</strong> for Money under<strong>Market</strong> Disequilibrium.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Money, Credit, <strong>and</strong> Bank<strong>in</strong>g 3 (February1971): 57–83.Warburton, Clark. Depression, Inflation, <strong>and</strong> Monetary Policy. Baltimore: JohnsHopk<strong>in</strong>s Press, 1966.. “Monetary Disequilibrium eory <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> First Half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> TwentiethCentury.” History <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> 13 (Summer 1981): 285–299.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “e Keynesian Diversion.” Western Economic Journal 11 ( June1973): 150–163.. “e Significance <strong>of</strong> Monetary Disequilibrium.” Cato Journal 6 (Fall1986): 369–399.


e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> GoldSt<strong>and</strong>ard * Bills were pend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> parliaments <strong>of</strong> Austria <strong>and</strong> Hungary <strong>in</strong> 1892to put those countries on <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard. In Austria, Deputy AntonMenger, a lawyer <strong>and</strong> bro<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economist Carl Menger, was chosento sum up <strong>the</strong> pro-gold-st<strong>and</strong>ard position at certa<strong>in</strong> stages <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> debates.Anton Menger tried to refute <strong>the</strong> objection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> critics that gold, like<strong>the</strong> paper gulden, could be unstable <strong>in</strong> value—perhaps even more unstable.His economist bro<strong>the</strong>r, although also <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, recognizedthat it had some “undeniable disadvantages,” <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>stability<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> gold <strong>and</strong> especially its rise <strong>in</strong> value <strong>in</strong> recent decades.e paper gulden, he recognized, had been satisfactorily stable <strong>in</strong> value fordomestic bus<strong>in</strong>ess (Menger 1893/1936, p. 123). By <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> gold <strong>and</strong>value <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gulden, Carl Menger, as well as <strong>the</strong> actual critics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> goldst<strong>and</strong>ard, clearly meant purchas<strong>in</strong>g power.Anton Menger evidently did not underst<strong>and</strong> this. He suffered notmerely from a money illusion but from a pound-sterl<strong>in</strong>g illusion specifically.Anyone can see how stable gold has been, he told critics, if <strong>the</strong>ywould take <strong>the</strong> trouble to look at a statistical table <strong>of</strong> its price on <strong>the</strong> Londonmarket from 1878 to 1891. He conceded that some fluctuations hadoccurred.Do you know how large <strong>the</strong>se were? e greatest change amounted to0.13 per cent. What a difference? In one year our money notes have*From a conference talk pr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> A Retrospective on <strong>the</strong> Classical Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard,1821–1931, eds. Michael Bordo <strong>and</strong> Anna Schwartz (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Pressfor National Bureau <strong>of</strong> Economic Research, 1984), 651–669. Cf. Menger 1893/1936, pp. 147, 196, 233–234.191


192 Part I: Economicschanged <strong>in</strong> money-value by about ten per cent, while gold, over <strong>the</strong>course <strong>of</strong> a period <strong>of</strong> 12 to 13 years, has changed only by 0.13 per cent.Under such circumstances <strong>the</strong>re is no doubt at all that <strong>the</strong>re can be noquestion at all <strong>of</strong> compar<strong>in</strong>g banknotes with gold <strong>in</strong> regard to <strong>the</strong> function<strong>of</strong> measure <strong>of</strong> value. (Austria, Parliament, Chamber <strong>of</strong> Deputies1892, p. 7182) Evidently, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> economic underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> his bro<strong>the</strong>r Carl hadnot automatically rubbed <strong>of</strong>f onto Deputy Anton Menger.I thought I might say someth<strong>in</strong>g tonight about <strong>the</strong> image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> goldst<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> late n<strong>in</strong>eteenth century. I’ll look at it from <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>of</strong> legislators, economists, <strong>and</strong> pamphleteers <strong>in</strong> countries that werecontemplat<strong>in</strong>g a move onto gold, namely, Austria-Hungary <strong>and</strong> Russia.ese countries had fiat paper moneys, hav<strong>in</strong>g been <strong>in</strong>flated <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>irtraditional silver st<strong>and</strong>ards several decades earlier by paper-money issuesto cover <strong>the</strong> expenses <strong>of</strong> wars <strong>and</strong> revolutions. Automatic regulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> money supply was one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> advantagesmost strongly argued <strong>in</strong> Austria <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard. In countrieswith a sound monetary system, Carl Menger expla<strong>in</strong>ed, money flowsout if commodity prices rise <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> if prices fall appreciably <strong>in</strong> relation to<strong>the</strong>ir normal level. It was a defect <strong>of</strong> Austria’s isolated monetary systemthat flows <strong>of</strong> money <strong>and</strong> gold could not fill temporary gaps <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> balance<strong>of</strong> payments, so that balance had to be ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed entirely <strong>in</strong> goods<strong>and</strong> securities. Domestic bus<strong>in</strong>ess suffered because its chang<strong>in</strong>g needs formoney confronted an <strong>in</strong>adequately elastic paper-money supply. “We lack<strong>the</strong> mechanically operat<strong>in</strong>g, regulat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>flow <strong>of</strong> moneyonto our markets; for this reason, we have apa<strong>the</strong>tic, <strong>in</strong>sensitive commoditymarkets; prices <strong>in</strong> Austria are not calculated precisely, as <strong>in</strong> Engl<strong>and</strong> orHoll<strong>and</strong>; we have apa<strong>the</strong>tic markets, which paralyzes <strong>the</strong> spirit <strong>of</strong> enterprise”(Menger 1893/1936, p. 294). e quotation is from <strong>the</strong> 14 July 1892 transcript. Menger had previously used <strong>the</strong>same argument on 25 May, p. 6192. ese <strong>in</strong>clude some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> expert witnesses testify<strong>in</strong>g before commissions convoked<strong>in</strong> Vienna <strong>and</strong> Budapest <strong>in</strong> March 1892 <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> St. Petersburg <strong>in</strong> March/April 1896. SeeAustria, Währungs-Enquête Commission 1892; Imperatorskoe Voljnoe .EkonomicheskoeObshchestvo 1896. Cf. Menger 1893/1936, pp. 138–139, 226–227.


Chapter : e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard 193Carl Menger recognized that <strong>the</strong> typical European currency was not agold currency but a “gold-plated” one. It had a core <strong>of</strong> paper, surroundedby layers <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>or co<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> silver <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n with an outer layer <strong>of</strong> goldplat<strong>in</strong>g. is arrangement was good enough for him, provided <strong>the</strong> plat<strong>in</strong>gwas strong enough to resist <strong>the</strong> acid test <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial crisis. What hewanted was stable exchange rates (p. 247).In Hungary, <strong>Is</strong>tván Tisza expressed similar ideas: A paper-moneycountry experiences no significant <strong>in</strong>flows <strong>and</strong> outflows <strong>of</strong> money. “Ingold-st<strong>and</strong>ard countries, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> size <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> need for gold isdecisive.” Rich or populous countries need more media <strong>of</strong> exchange, pooror less populous ones need less.e relation between quantity <strong>and</strong> need must be such that <strong>in</strong> both places<strong>the</strong>y are equal; <strong>and</strong> money even goes from <strong>the</strong> richest country to <strong>the</strong> poorestif <strong>the</strong>re is relatively greater need for it <strong>the</strong>re, for <strong>the</strong>n it can be turnedto better account <strong>the</strong>re; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> elements <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> balance <strong>of</strong> payments willnecessarily change as <strong>the</strong> relation between <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> need forgold requires.... e tendency <strong>of</strong> balances <strong>of</strong> payments will always be... to equalize <strong>the</strong> relation between dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> supply <strong>in</strong> all countries<strong>and</strong> give all as much gold as <strong>the</strong>y need <strong>in</strong> relation to <strong>the</strong> needs <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs.(Tisza 1890, pp. 92–93)Its Austrian supporters saw <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard less as a transmitter <strong>of</strong>foreign disturbances than as a means <strong>of</strong> cushion<strong>in</strong>g domestic disturbancesby l<strong>in</strong>kage with <strong>the</strong> presumably more stable world economy. Franz Perlwrote <strong>in</strong> 1887 that<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> isolation <strong>in</strong> which our currency places us, we are left to our ownresources whenever credit is shaken; that <strong>in</strong>ternational flow <strong>of</strong> moneywhich st<strong>and</strong>s helpfully at <strong>the</strong> side <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r money markets <strong>in</strong> times <strong>of</strong>need is lack<strong>in</strong>g to us; our securities, which only <strong>in</strong> rare cases have a realabode abroad, return to us at <strong>the</strong> least sign <strong>of</strong> mistrust; we lack thatequilibrat<strong>in</strong>g help. (1887, p. 64, cit<strong>in</strong>g Alfred von L<strong>in</strong>dheim)Deputy Anton Menger also believed that bus<strong>in</strong>ess crises were “veryconsiderably <strong>in</strong>tensified” by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ability <strong>of</strong> money to flow <strong>in</strong>to <strong>and</strong> out<strong>of</strong> Austria, a monetary isl<strong>and</strong>. e value <strong>of</strong> Austrian money rested onlyon a very dangerous basis, its scarcity, for a country should have enoughmoney <strong>and</strong> not too little (Austria, Parliament, Chamber <strong>of</strong> Deputies 1892,pp. 7182–7183).


194 Part I: EconomicsAno<strong>the</strong>r deputy (Eim) po<strong>in</strong>ted out that <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a paper moneydepended on <strong>the</strong> need for money <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>in</strong> circulation. elatter could be controlled, but <strong>the</strong> need for money could hardly be calculated.us, <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> paper money “is subject to cont<strong>in</strong>ual changes,which depend on <strong>the</strong> most various circumstances, <strong>of</strong>ten on chance, <strong>in</strong>deedeven on speculation” (Austria, Parliament, Chamber <strong>of</strong> Deputies 1892,p. 6989).e economist Julius L<strong>and</strong>esberger likewise saw it as a grave defect<strong>of</strong> a system <strong>of</strong> purely fiduciary money that it could not work well “unlessit were cont<strong>in</strong>uously possible to ascerta<strong>in</strong> most reliably <strong>the</strong> need <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>whole economy for means <strong>of</strong> circulation at all times <strong>and</strong> to regulate <strong>the</strong>monetary circulation correspond<strong>in</strong>gly. To this, however, <strong>the</strong> resources <strong>of</strong>science are not adequate today” (L<strong>and</strong>esberger 1892, p. 68). Russian supporters <strong>of</strong> gold also argued that that st<strong>and</strong>ard made a country’smoney supply appropriately elastic. Under a paper system, by contrast,<strong>the</strong> money supply supposedly did not respond appropriately <strong>and</strong>automatically to <strong>the</strong> chang<strong>in</strong>g need for means <strong>of</strong> circulation; yet it wasimpossible to calculate <strong>and</strong> deliberately meet that need. In a gold-st<strong>and</strong>ardcountry, though, a deficiency <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> domestic money supply would remedyitself through a balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments surplus <strong>and</strong> an <strong>in</strong>flow <strong>of</strong> gold,<strong>and</strong> a superabundance <strong>of</strong> money would remedy itself through a deficit <strong>and</strong>an outflow. Each country would automatically come to hold <strong>the</strong> quantity<strong>of</strong> metallic money appropriate to its wealth <strong>and</strong> transactions, without anyone’shav<strong>in</strong>g to try to estimate <strong>the</strong> required quantity. Opponents <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard sometimes argued that <strong>the</strong> sacrificesrequired to get onto gold would prove to have been <strong>in</strong> va<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> case Austria-Hungary should get <strong>in</strong>to ano<strong>the</strong>r war. e pro-gold reply was that <strong>the</strong>country should have hard money <strong>in</strong> peacetime to save <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong>paper-money issues—<strong>the</strong> state’s “note credit”—for wartime. With <strong>the</strong>country hav<strong>in</strong>g a depreciated paper money even <strong>in</strong> time <strong>of</strong> peace, saidPerl (1887, p. 29), every economist <strong>and</strong> patriot must shudder to th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong>what would happen <strong>in</strong> time <strong>of</strong> war or fear <strong>of</strong> war. L<strong>and</strong>esberger thus seemed to imply that if <strong>the</strong> supply <strong>of</strong> a fiat money could be regulatedappropriately, exchange-rate fluctuations would not count decisively aga<strong>in</strong>st thatsystem. Some people, he noted, even considered <strong>the</strong> fluctuations a desirable <strong>in</strong>sulatoraga<strong>in</strong>st price deflation <strong>in</strong> gold countries. ese arguments are reported <strong>in</strong> Vlasenko 1963, pp. 85–86; Raffalovich 1896, p. 369;Trakhtenberg 1962, pp. 174ff.; <strong>and</strong> F<strong>in</strong>ance M<strong>in</strong>ister Witte’s bill to authorize contracts <strong>in</strong>gold currency, quoted <strong>in</strong> Saenger 1927, p. 16.


Chapter : e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard 195In Russia, also, gold-st<strong>and</strong>ard opponents argued that monetary reformwould not be worth <strong>the</strong> trouble, s<strong>in</strong>ce a new war would only make <strong>the</strong>paper money irredeemable aga<strong>in</strong>. e reply was that irredeemable papermoney should be abolished now so that new issues could be put <strong>in</strong>to circulationif <strong>the</strong> occasion arose. e currency reform could be a “reconstruction<strong>of</strong> war material” (Schultze-Gävernitz 1899, p. 462). Start<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> goldst<strong>and</strong>ard, <strong>the</strong> government would have better wartime f<strong>in</strong>ancial alternativesthan if it started from irredeemability.Early <strong>in</strong> 1879, when <strong>the</strong> world-market price <strong>of</strong> silver had sunk so lowthat <strong>the</strong> Austrian gulden was aga<strong>in</strong> worth as much as its supposed silvercontent, or even slightly more, <strong>the</strong> co<strong>in</strong>age <strong>of</strong> silver on private accountthreatened to <strong>in</strong>flate <strong>the</strong> money supply <strong>and</strong> price level. e Austrian <strong>and</strong>Hungarian governments responded by clos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir m<strong>in</strong>ts to <strong>the</strong> freeco<strong>in</strong>age <strong>of</strong> silver. at action had been taken <strong>in</strong> a legally very <strong>in</strong>formalway, however, leav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> possibility that <strong>the</strong> silver st<strong>and</strong>ard would comealive aga<strong>in</strong>. For some years <strong>the</strong> gulden floated at a value above that <strong>of</strong> itssupposed silver content.By 1890, a different aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> loose l<strong>in</strong>k rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g between <strong>the</strong>gulden <strong>and</strong> silver—one work<strong>in</strong>g through speculation about domestic redemption<strong>and</strong> co<strong>in</strong>age policy <strong>and</strong> American silver-purchase policy—cameto <strong>the</strong> fore, provid<strong>in</strong>g one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> strongest motives to reform. e Austrianf<strong>in</strong>ancial press <strong>and</strong> Parliament seemed preoccupied with <strong>the</strong> progress <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> Sherman Silver Purchase Bill <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> U.S. Congress, <strong>and</strong> unusual dayto-dayjumps <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> silver <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> gulden’s exchange rate weregenerally attributed to news from Wash<strong>in</strong>gton.F<strong>in</strong>ance M<strong>in</strong>ister Ste<strong>in</strong>bach warned Parliament on 14 May 1892 thatforces support<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> oppos<strong>in</strong>g free co<strong>in</strong>age <strong>of</strong> silver <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United Stateswere almost evenly balanced; powerful <strong>in</strong>fluences on <strong>the</strong> Austrian currencycould come from that direction. “e rate fluctuations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> year 1890,which you all remember, gentlemen, have brought us a small foretaste <strong>of</strong>what would happen if silver co<strong>in</strong>age were made free today <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates <strong>of</strong> North America” (Austria, Parliament, Chamber <strong>of</strong> Deputies1892, p. 5930).Ano<strong>the</strong>r aspect <strong>of</strong> legal untid<strong>in</strong>ess was <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> four dist<strong>in</strong>cttypes or concepts <strong>of</strong> gulden: () <strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary fiat gulden (“gulden <strong>of</strong> Austriancurrency”), <strong>in</strong> which currency <strong>and</strong> bank deposits were denom<strong>in</strong>ated<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> which most prices <strong>and</strong> debts were expressed; () <strong>the</strong> silver gulden,<strong>in</strong> which some bonds <strong>and</strong> preferred stocks were still denom<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>and</strong>which could aga<strong>in</strong> become separated from <strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary gulden if silver


196 Part I: Economicsrose sufficiently <strong>in</strong> market value; () a gold gulden worth two-<strong>and</strong>-ahalfFrench francs, <strong>in</strong> which some bonds <strong>and</strong> customs payments wereexpressed; <strong>and</strong> () ano<strong>the</strong>r gold gulden, worth 1.2 percent less, which hadsome slight application <strong>in</strong> government account<strong>in</strong>g; it was <strong>the</strong> gold equivalent<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard silver gulden at <strong>the</strong> 15.5:1 bimetallic ratio <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong>Monetary Union. As Josef Kreibig later observed, “if <strong>the</strong>re was one drasticpro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> a reform, it was this peculiar splitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>monetary unit” (Kreibig 1899, pp. 61–62). Dom<strong>in</strong>ant Hungarian <strong>in</strong>terests switched <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> gold around 1889–1890.Earlier <strong>the</strong>y had opposed it out <strong>of</strong> fear that it meant appreciation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>paper gulden to equality with <strong>the</strong> two-<strong>and</strong>-a-half-franc gold gulden, hamper<strong>in</strong>gagricultural exports. But as <strong>the</strong> Hungarians came to realize that<strong>the</strong> gulden would not be pegged upward at that rate <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> goldst<strong>and</strong>ard might mean resistance to fur<strong>the</strong>r appreciation, or even a partialreversal <strong>of</strong> recent appreciation, <strong>the</strong> sentiment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> country’s export-<strong>and</strong>import-compet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terests shifted. It seems that <strong>the</strong> experts, so considered by <strong>the</strong> Establishment, werealmost all <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard. Be<strong>in</strong>g an expert (<strong>and</strong> so be<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>vited to testify before <strong>the</strong> commissions mentioned <strong>in</strong> footnote 3) apparentlypresupposed, almost by def<strong>in</strong>ition, advocacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard.None <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> major Austrian political parties, as a party, opposed <strong>the</strong> goldst<strong>and</strong>ard, although many <strong>in</strong>dividual deputies did. Even proponents <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard recognized that a large opposition existed—<strong>and</strong> thatopponents might possibly outnumber proponents—but outside <strong>the</strong> most<strong>in</strong>fluential circles. e masses had supposedly become accustomed to <strong>the</strong>exist<strong>in</strong>g currency situation <strong>and</strong> were apa<strong>the</strong>tic about reform. Among <strong>the</strong>articulate, though, advocacy <strong>of</strong> gold dom<strong>in</strong>ated. A pro-paper pamphleteersuggested a version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fable <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> emperor’s clo<strong>the</strong>s: even peoplewho did not underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed disadvantages <strong>of</strong> paper money <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> supposed advantages <strong>of</strong> gold never<strong>the</strong>less jo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> progold chorus<strong>in</strong> order not to seem unenlightened (Gruber 1892, pp. 114–115). Vienna Board <strong>of</strong> Trade 1887, p. 388; Kamitz 1949, pp. 147–148; Aktiönar, 22 June 1890,first supplement, dispatch from Prague; Sil<strong>in</strong> 1913, pp. 394, 395, 399, quoted <strong>and</strong> paraphrasedat length <strong>in</strong> Trakhtenberg 1962, pp. 265–266. Tisza 1890, esp. pp. 93–95, expla<strong>in</strong>ed<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>correctness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> earlier fears <strong>and</strong> argued that <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard would serve Hungarian<strong>in</strong>terests.


Chapter : e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard 197Even so, opposition consumed most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> time <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> parliamentarydebates. is was underst<strong>and</strong>able: <strong>the</strong> government’s position took <strong>the</strong>form <strong>of</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite bills, <strong>and</strong> only so much could be said <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir favor withoutrepetition, while opposition views were aired <strong>in</strong> great variety. Only am<strong>in</strong>ority <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> opponents forthrightly favored reta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g fiat paper money.Most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m wanted bimetallism, or thought that <strong>the</strong> time was not ripefor <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, or believed that action should await some sort <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>ternational agreement, or wanted a gold st<strong>and</strong>ard different from what<strong>the</strong> government’s bills would <strong>in</strong>troduce, or engaged <strong>in</strong> nit-pick<strong>in</strong>g aboutsuch issues as <strong>the</strong> emperor’s titles on <strong>the</strong> new gold co<strong>in</strong>s. e only amendmentadopted was one exp<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g his titles from Imperator et Rex to along list <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g K<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Bohemia, K<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Gallicia, <strong>and</strong> end<strong>in</strong>g withApostolic K<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Hungary.Some pamphleteers did state <strong>the</strong> case for reta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a fiat paper moneywith float<strong>in</strong>g exchange rates—a case centered around <strong>the</strong> greater importance<strong>of</strong> domestic than <strong>of</strong> exchange-rate stability <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong>a measure <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>sulation from foreign deflation <strong>and</strong> crises. Josef Neupauerpredicted that “a slow <strong>and</strong> steady <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> means <strong>of</strong> circulation willwithout doubt encourage <strong>the</strong> spirit <strong>of</strong> enterprise, <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong> more rema<strong>in</strong>without <strong>in</strong>fluence on <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian money as <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>the</strong> populationgrows <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole economy develops.” He proposed that <strong>the</strong> newmoney necessary to accompany real economic growth be put <strong>in</strong>to circulationthrough purchase <strong>of</strong> securities on <strong>the</strong> Bourse. He even hazarded aguess about <strong>the</strong> proper rate <strong>of</strong> annual <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> money supply—4 percent(Neupauer 1892, p. 26 <strong>and</strong> passim).Dom<strong>in</strong>ant trends <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion were apparently quite different <strong>in</strong> Russia.e discussions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Imperial Free Economic Society <strong>in</strong> St. Petersburg<strong>in</strong> March/April 1896 serve as evidence that advocacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> goldst<strong>and</strong>ard was not part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conventional wisdom among economists <strong>and</strong>lead<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>kers. Even advocates <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard acknowledged thatapathy toward <strong>the</strong> reform was quite general. Schulze-Gävernitz referredto those discussions to justify his assertion that “<strong>the</strong> State carried out <strong>the</strong>currency reform aga<strong>in</strong>st public op<strong>in</strong>ion, with few exceptions, aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong>press, aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> tough resistance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> public” (Schulze-Gävernitz 1899,pp. 461–462, 470–471). Austria, Währungs-Enquête Commission 1892; Imperatorskoe Voljnoe .EkonomicheskoeObshchestvo 1896.


198 Part I: EconomicsF<strong>in</strong>ance M<strong>in</strong>ister Sergei Witte also testified to <strong>the</strong> climate <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion.As he said, nearly <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g Russia was <strong>in</strong>itially opposed tohis reform. Even he, while new <strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong>fice, contemplated ab<strong>and</strong>on<strong>in</strong>g hispredecessors’ work <strong>of</strong> mov<strong>in</strong>g toward <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard. e opposition to <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard was so strong <strong>in</strong> Russia that <strong>in</strong>order to enact it, <strong>the</strong> Tsar had to bypass <strong>the</strong> usual legislative procedure,which <strong>in</strong>volved various committees. Support<strong>in</strong>g his f<strong>in</strong>ance m<strong>in</strong>ister, <strong>the</strong>Tsar enacted it piecemeal by autocratic decrees. Before turn<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> noneconomic reasons for adoption <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard,particularly <strong>in</strong> Austria, I want to emphasize that <strong>the</strong> economic reasonsdid not <strong>in</strong>clude poor performance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fiat paper currency (seeYeager 1969, pp. 61–89). Exchange-rate fluctuations were not extreme bypresent-day st<strong>and</strong>ards, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> paper currency was not suffer<strong>in</strong>g price<strong>in</strong>flation. (In fact, <strong>the</strong> price trend had been downward s<strong>in</strong>ce about 1871,though less steeply downward than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold-st<strong>and</strong>ard world.)Yet Deputy Anton Menger compla<strong>in</strong>ed. He said that importers <strong>and</strong>exporters were able to perceive seasonal tendencies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> exchangerate—very feeble tendencies, so far as <strong>the</strong> figures show—<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it from<strong>the</strong>m by shrewdly tim<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir purchases <strong>and</strong> sales <strong>of</strong> foreign exchange.is sounds like stabiliz<strong>in</strong>g speculation to us—hardly grounds for compla<strong>in</strong>t.Yet Menger implied, without articulat<strong>in</strong>g his compla<strong>in</strong>t explicitly,that <strong>the</strong> ga<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shrewd traders were necessarily com<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> expense<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> country as a whole (Austria, Parliament, Chamber <strong>of</strong> Deputies 1892,p. 7473). e gold st<strong>and</strong>ard would put a stop to that.Apart from <strong>the</strong> economics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> matter, <strong>the</strong> fluctuat<strong>in</strong>g exchange ratewas widely viewed as a symbol <strong>of</strong> disorder <strong>and</strong> backwardness, whereasbe<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard—<strong>the</strong> most modern monetary system—was<strong>the</strong> mark <strong>of</strong> a civilized country. Vienna’s lead<strong>in</strong>g newspaper deplored <strong>the</strong>monarchy’s confused monetary system—with silver as <strong>the</strong> basic metal,with irredeemable paper notes <strong>in</strong> circulation, <strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> gulden’s valueexposed to <strong>the</strong> vicissitudes <strong>of</strong> wild <strong>in</strong>ternational speculation—“while allcivilized states have long s<strong>in</strong>ce assured <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>of</strong> a stable measure <strong>of</strong> Witte 1921, pp. 59–60; cf. Von Laue 1963; Crisp 1967, p. 211; Migul<strong>in</strong> 1899–1904,pp. 130–131. Witte 1921, pp. 59, 61; Von Laue 1963, pp. 141–144; Migul<strong>in</strong> 1899–1904, pp. 284–286;Trakhtenberg 1962, p. 267; Russia, F<strong>in</strong>ance M<strong>in</strong>istry 1902, vol. 2: pp. 422–425.


Chapter : e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard 199value, a money as steady <strong>in</strong> value as possible” (Neue Freie Presse, 7 September1890). Considerations <strong>of</strong> prestige were at work. In <strong>the</strong> Hungarian CurrencyInquiry <strong>of</strong> 1892, Koloman Szell, a former f<strong>in</strong>ance m<strong>in</strong>ister <strong>and</strong> future primem<strong>in</strong>ister, declaimed about “<strong>the</strong> stigma <strong>of</strong> a paper economy, unworthy <strong>of</strong>a civilized nation” (quoted <strong>in</strong> Gruber 1892, p. 117). e Currency Committee<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian Parliament observed <strong>in</strong> 1892 that “considerations<strong>of</strong> state [had] <strong>in</strong>fluenced <strong>the</strong> decision <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> government” to proceed withgold-st<strong>and</strong>ard legislation. Twenty years before, Austria had not been alone<strong>in</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g paper money; s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> United States, Italy, <strong>and</strong> even littleRumania had gone onto <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard. Russia, <strong>the</strong> only o<strong>the</strong>r majorpower still with a paper st<strong>and</strong>ard, was already mak<strong>in</strong>g preparations forgo<strong>in</strong>g onto gold. “Every year it detracts more from <strong>the</strong> State prestige <strong>of</strong>Austria that it still belongs to <strong>the</strong> countries with an unregulated currency”(Austria, Parliament, Chamber <strong>of</strong> Deputies 1892, Beilage no. 491, p. 8).Deputy Dr. Foregger rem<strong>in</strong>ded his colleagues that <strong>the</strong> “scrap-<strong>of</strong>-papereconomy” degraded Austria economically to a second-rate power. “Wedemonstrate that our Empire does not have <strong>the</strong> strength to <strong>in</strong>troduceamong us, too, <strong>the</strong> means <strong>of</strong> payment, hard money, that holds sway <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>civilized world. We <strong>the</strong>reby <strong>in</strong>cessantly damage our credit, our economicflexibility <strong>and</strong> competitiveness.” Lack <strong>of</strong> foreign confidence extended beyond<strong>the</strong> economic sphere <strong>in</strong>toall o<strong>the</strong>r sides <strong>of</strong> our <strong>in</strong>ternational relations; it lessens respect for us,esteem for us; it lessens our power position. We must <strong>the</strong>refore makeall efforts to br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> strength <strong>of</strong> our Monarchy <strong>in</strong>to full effect aga<strong>in</strong>by regulat<strong>in</strong>g our monetary system.... We cannot have a separate, an<strong>in</strong>sular, currency cont<strong>in</strong>ue: if we want to take part <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> competition <strong>of</strong>civilized nations, we too must accept <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational means <strong>of</strong> payment,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational measure <strong>of</strong> value is just nowadays gold. (Austria,Parliament, Chamber <strong>of</strong> Deputies 1892, pp. 7132–7133)e “scrap <strong>of</strong> paper” to which Dr. Foregger alluded was itself a source<strong>of</strong> dismay. e state currency notes (as dist<strong>in</strong>guished from <strong>the</strong> notes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Austro-Hungarian Bank) were thought <strong>of</strong> as an actual debt to be paid <strong>of</strong>fsooner or later. is view found support not only <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>kage <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> legallypermissible quantities <strong>of</strong> state notes <strong>and</strong> treasury bills (Sal<strong>in</strong>ensche<strong>in</strong>e) Earlier (1 November 1884) <strong>the</strong> same newspaper had exclaimed, “What enthusiasm itwould stir up if at last <strong>the</strong> warmly longed-for moment had arrived to raise Austria onto<strong>the</strong> height <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> civilized states!”


200 Part I: Economicsunder a ceil<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong>ir comb<strong>in</strong>ed amount but also <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>scriptionon <strong>the</strong> notes <strong>the</strong>mselves, which acknowledged each note as “a part <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> common float<strong>in</strong>g debt <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austro-Hungarian Monarchy” (“common”here mean<strong>in</strong>g shared by <strong>the</strong> two governments). e term “float<strong>in</strong>gdebt” sounds more om<strong>in</strong>ous <strong>in</strong> German than <strong>in</strong> English—schwebendeSchuld—convey<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> impression <strong>of</strong> a “hover<strong>in</strong>g guilt” still to be expiated.One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> purposes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> monetary reform bills <strong>of</strong> 1892, <strong>the</strong> Austriangovernment said, was to abolish <strong>the</strong>se state notes, which had been issuedunder <strong>the</strong> compulsion <strong>of</strong> “shatter<strong>in</strong>g political events” (Austria, Parliament,Chamber <strong>of</strong> Deputies, Beilage no. 436). e reference was to monetary<strong>in</strong>flation dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Austro-Prussian War <strong>of</strong> 1866. e yearn<strong>in</strong>g to banishan ever-present rem<strong>in</strong>der <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> humiliation <strong>of</strong> Königgrätz was an oldone. On 1 November 1884 <strong>the</strong> Neue Freie Presse said that “redeem<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>float<strong>in</strong>g debt” was “an old duty <strong>of</strong> honor <strong>of</strong> Austria.” On 1 January 1892<strong>the</strong> newspaper lamented “<strong>the</strong> dismal legacy <strong>of</strong> revolution <strong>and</strong> wars, <strong>the</strong>irredeemable notes, <strong>the</strong>se hateful sta<strong>in</strong>s on <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> Austria.... epaper gulden is ... [a] sad monument that has been erected <strong>in</strong> our budgetto rem<strong>in</strong>d us <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> suffer<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past.”Even <strong>the</strong> analytical Carl Menger “most decidedly” rejected “<strong>the</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion<strong>of</strong> those who deny Austria-Hungary <strong>the</strong> right to reshape her currencyon <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>of</strong> that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> civilized nations. It should not be <strong>in</strong>terpretedas immodesty if we too wish to be counted among <strong>the</strong> ‘nations les plusavancées dans la civilisation,’ among <strong>the</strong> nations that are already ‘ready forgold,’ <strong>and</strong> not among <strong>the</strong> peoples ‘<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r currency area,’ which shouldcontent <strong>the</strong>mselves with silver currency” (Menger 1893/1936, pp. 172–173).Among its advocates <strong>in</strong> Russia, <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard “had become, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mid-n<strong>in</strong>eties, more than ever a matter <strong>of</strong> national respectability <strong>and</strong> economicadvantage.... For Russia (as for any civilized country at that time)it was a prerequisite for sound credit <strong>and</strong> economic progress <strong>in</strong> general.Above all it would encourage more foreign <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> Russian <strong>in</strong>dustry”(Von Laue 1963, p. 139).A.N. Gurjev was one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economists who held such a view. Forhim, restoration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ruble to a metallic basis had political <strong>and</strong> culturalas well as economic significance:Membership <strong>in</strong> worldwide civilization is unth<strong>in</strong>kable without membership<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> worldwide monetary economy.... A country with an isolatedmonetary economy cannot enter <strong>in</strong>to stable cultural <strong>in</strong>tercourse if it isseparated from civilized peoples by <strong>the</strong> whole complex <strong>of</strong> economic evilsconnected with <strong>the</strong> disorder <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> monetary system. (Gurjev 1896, p. 163)


Chapter : e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard 201F<strong>in</strong>ally, we have <strong>the</strong> judgment <strong>of</strong> an em<strong>in</strong>ent Austrian economist <strong>of</strong>a later generation. Modern economists will be quite unable to underst<strong>and</strong>,said Joseph Schumpeter, why countries such as Austria-Hungary,Russia, <strong>and</strong> Italy imposed hardships on <strong>the</strong>mselves to adopt gold paritiesfor <strong>the</strong>ir currencies. No important economic <strong>in</strong>terests clamored forthat policy. Noneconomic considerations were decisive. Gold symbolizedsound practice <strong>and</strong> honor <strong>and</strong> decency. “Perhaps this explanation raisesmore problems than it solves. at it is true is certa<strong>in</strong>” (Schumpeter 1954,p. 770). Now, <strong>in</strong> preparation for com<strong>in</strong>g to a conclusion, I want to return to myearlier <strong>the</strong>mes. ese <strong>the</strong>mes concern <strong>the</strong> appeal or <strong>the</strong> desirability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>gold st<strong>and</strong>ard.As we know, some prom<strong>in</strong>ent economists <strong>and</strong> politicians nowadaysare recommend<strong>in</strong>g a return to <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard—or <strong>the</strong> adoption <strong>of</strong> whateverit is that <strong>the</strong>y are market<strong>in</strong>g under that label. My response is notthat we must not turn back <strong>the</strong> clock. at hackneyed slogan betrays aprov<strong>in</strong>cialism about one’s own time, a shallow meliorism, a moral futurism.Nor is my message that we can’t turn back <strong>the</strong> clock. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, mymessage is a rem<strong>in</strong>der <strong>of</strong> what it is that we would have to turn back to. Itis a rem<strong>in</strong>der <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> entire situation <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard flourished.More exactly, perhaps, <strong>the</strong> gold-st<strong>and</strong>ard world is an idealized past state<strong>of</strong> affairs.e few, very few, decades dur<strong>in</strong>g which <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational gold st<strong>and</strong>ardflourished <strong>of</strong>fered almost uniquely favorable conditions. M<strong>in</strong>t parsamong gold st<strong>and</strong>ard currencies, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g arbitrarily chosen,expressed an equilibrium that had evolved gradually between <strong>the</strong>mselves<strong>and</strong> national price levels. Mildly ris<strong>in</strong>g world prices after 1896 facilitatedrelative adjustments <strong>of</strong> prices <strong>and</strong> wages, while <strong>the</strong> uptrend did not lastlong enough—until war destroyed <strong>the</strong> system—to dissipate its possiblebenefits by becom<strong>in</strong>g embodied <strong>in</strong> expectations. Relative calm <strong>in</strong> social<strong>and</strong> political affairs <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> excessively ambitious governmentprograms <strong>and</strong> excessive taxation all favored confidence <strong>in</strong> monetary stability.e age <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard was an age <strong>of</strong> peace, relatively. e Neue Freie Presse (Vienna) <strong>and</strong> Aktiönar (Berl<strong>in</strong>), both evident organs <strong>of</strong> liberalbourgeois thought, repeatedly stressed that peace was good for bus<strong>in</strong>ess.


202 Part I: EconomicsHugh Rock<strong>of</strong>f suggested that <strong>the</strong> tolerably good performance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>gold st<strong>and</strong>ard before World War I h<strong>in</strong>ged on favorable conditions thatno longer prevail: a corps <strong>of</strong> dedicated gold prospectors work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> unexploredareas; absence <strong>of</strong> political <strong>in</strong>terference (a laissez-faire atmosphere);patience with <strong>the</strong> long <strong>and</strong> uncerta<strong>in</strong> lags <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> response <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold supplyto <strong>the</strong> chang<strong>in</strong>g dem<strong>and</strong> for money.By <strong>and</strong> large, people (<strong>in</strong> countries that happened to be on <strong>the</strong> goldst<strong>and</strong>ard, anyway) were freer from government control than <strong>in</strong> any agebefore or s<strong>in</strong>ce—freer to transact bus<strong>in</strong>ess, to make <strong>in</strong>vestments, to transferfunds, to travel. ere is a certa<strong>in</strong> charm <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> rem<strong>in</strong>iscences <strong>of</strong> anold German banker <strong>of</strong> how, dur<strong>in</strong>g his student days at Heidelberg, he<strong>and</strong> some friends, one <strong>of</strong> whom had just come <strong>in</strong>to an <strong>in</strong>heritance, left on<strong>the</strong> impulse <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moment for a tour <strong>of</strong> Italy, where <strong>the</strong> banker <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>first town <strong>the</strong>y stopped at considered it an honor to cash <strong>in</strong> gold co<strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> large check written by <strong>the</strong> young stranger. ere is similar charm<strong>in</strong> Jules Verne’s story <strong>of</strong> Ph<strong>in</strong>eas Fogg, who left on short notice for hiseighty-day tour <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world, pay<strong>in</strong>g his expenses from a carpetbag full <strong>of</strong>Bank <strong>of</strong> Engl<strong>and</strong> notes, accepted everywhere. e civility <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternationalityprevalent dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> age <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard have such charm forus nowadays that it seems almost sacrilege to ask whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se benefitsresulted from <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard or, <strong>in</strong>stead, coexisted with it by mereco<strong>in</strong>cidence.e gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, <strong>in</strong> short, evokes <strong>the</strong> “good old days.” is associationis well illustrated by two quotations, <strong>the</strong> first from Benjam<strong>in</strong> M.Anderson, a lifelong champion <strong>of</strong> gold, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> second from John MaynardKeynes, his generation’s lead<strong>in</strong>g critic <strong>of</strong> that st<strong>and</strong>ard.ose who have an adult’s recollection <strong>and</strong> an adult’s underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> world which preceded <strong>the</strong> first World War look back upon it witha great nostalgia. ere was a sense <strong>of</strong> security <strong>the</strong>n which has nevers<strong>in</strong>ce existed. Progress was generally taken for granted.... We had hada prolonged period <strong>in</strong> which decade after decade had seen <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gpolitical freedom, <strong>the</strong> progressive spread <strong>of</strong> democratic <strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>the</strong>steady lift<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> life for <strong>the</strong> masses <strong>of</strong> men....In f<strong>in</strong>ancial matters <strong>the</strong> good faith <strong>of</strong> governments was taken forgranted.... No country took pride <strong>in</strong> debas<strong>in</strong>g its currency as a cleverf<strong>in</strong>ancial expedient. (Anderson 1949, pp. 3–4, 6)What an extraord<strong>in</strong>ary episode <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic progress <strong>of</strong> man that agewas which came to an end <strong>in</strong> August, 1914! ... [A]ny man <strong>of</strong> capacity or


Chapter : e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard 203character at all exceed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> average [could escape from <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>gclass] <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> middle <strong>and</strong> upper classes, for whom life <strong>of</strong>fered, at alow cost <strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> least trouble, conveniences, comforts <strong>and</strong> amenitiesbeyond <strong>the</strong> compass <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> richest <strong>and</strong> most powerful monarchs <strong>of</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r ages. e <strong>in</strong>habitant <strong>of</strong> London could order by telephone, sipp<strong>in</strong>ghis morn<strong>in</strong>g tea <strong>in</strong> bed, <strong>the</strong> various products <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole earth,<strong>in</strong> such quantity as he might see fit, <strong>and</strong> reasonably expect <strong>the</strong>ir earlydelivery upon his doorstep; he could at <strong>the</strong> same moment <strong>and</strong> by <strong>the</strong>same means adventure his wealth <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural resources <strong>and</strong> new enterprises<strong>of</strong> any quarter <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world, <strong>and</strong> share, without exertion or eventrouble, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir prospective fruits <strong>and</strong> advantages.... He could secureforthwith ... cheap <strong>and</strong> comfortable means <strong>of</strong> transit to any countryor climate without passport or o<strong>the</strong>r formality, could despatch his servantto <strong>the</strong> neighbor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>fice <strong>of</strong> a bank for such supply <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> preciousmetals as might seem convenient, <strong>and</strong> could <strong>the</strong>n proceed abroad t<strong>of</strong>oreign quarters, without knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir religion, language, or customs,bear<strong>in</strong>g co<strong>in</strong>ed wealth upon his person, <strong>and</strong> would consider himselfgreatly aggrieved <strong>and</strong> much surprised at <strong>the</strong> least <strong>in</strong>terference. But,most important <strong>of</strong> all, he regarded this state <strong>of</strong> affairs as normal, certa<strong>in</strong>,<strong>and</strong> permanent, except <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r improvement, <strong>and</strong> anydeviation from it as aberrant, sc<strong>and</strong>alous, <strong>and</strong> avoidable. (Keynes 1920,pp. 10–12)Rem<strong>in</strong>iscences like <strong>the</strong>se re<strong>in</strong>force my impression that <strong>the</strong> outbreak<strong>of</strong> World War I was a momentous turn<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>and</strong> a great tragedy <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world—a tragedy all <strong>the</strong> more poignant because <strong>the</strong> warbroke out so accidentally. e build<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Sarajevo near which <strong>the</strong> assass<strong>in</strong>was st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g when he fired <strong>the</strong> fateful shots bears a plaque say<strong>in</strong>g tha<strong>the</strong>re, on 28 June 1914, Gavrilo Pr<strong>in</strong>cip carried out an act express<strong>in</strong>g resistanceto tyranny <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> will to freedom. e <strong>in</strong>scription says noth<strong>in</strong>gabout <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itiation <strong>of</strong> a cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> events that may, even yet, carry to <strong>the</strong>destruction <strong>of</strong> Western civilization. It says noth<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> start <strong>of</strong> ourpresent age <strong>of</strong> wars, <strong>of</strong> globally expansionist tyrannies, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> perversion<strong>of</strong> democratic government <strong>in</strong>to an <strong>in</strong>strument whereby each <strong>in</strong>terestgroup seeks to plunder society <strong>in</strong> general, to <strong>the</strong> un<strong>in</strong>tended net loss <strong>of</strong>practically all.If I were asked for my recommendation, <strong>the</strong>refore, I would not merelyrecommend go<strong>in</strong>g back to <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard. By itself, apart from restoration<strong>of</strong> its preconditions, that would hardly be a constructive step. Mynostalgia is for <strong>the</strong> whole pre-1914 climate, not for one specific facet <strong>of</strong> it.I recommend repeal<strong>in</strong>g World War I, root <strong>and</strong> branch. If only we could!


204 Part I: Economics Repeal<strong>in</strong>g World War I would have to <strong>in</strong>clude restor<strong>in</strong>g certa<strong>in</strong> attitudesthat seem to have been more prevalent <strong>in</strong> public affairs before 1914 than<strong>the</strong>y are now. ose attitudes favored limitations on <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>of</strong> governmentactivity <strong>and</strong> restra<strong>in</strong>t on seek<strong>in</strong>g special advantage through <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>strumentality <strong>of</strong> government. Broadly speak<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>se were liberal attitudes<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century sense. ese attitudes have now beenunderm<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> ways analyzed, <strong>in</strong> part, by Ortega y Gasset <strong>in</strong> e Revolt<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Masses (1930).Nowadays, we have tyranny <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> nondemocratic countries <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> democratic countries, democracy perverted <strong>in</strong> such a way that politicaldecisions are made out <strong>of</strong> short-run expediency <strong>and</strong> without due regardfor long-run consequences. But <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold-st<strong>and</strong>ard era, as Lars Jonungsays, “<strong>the</strong> democratic system had not been fully developed.” (Peter L<strong>in</strong>dertdetects signs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> perversion <strong>of</strong> democracy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United K<strong>in</strong>gdom,however, even before World War I.)Without a return to liberal attitudes <strong>and</strong> self-restra<strong>in</strong>ts, a restored goldst<strong>and</strong>ard would not work well <strong>and</strong> would hardly endure. After all, <strong>the</strong>gold st<strong>and</strong>ard is simply a particular set <strong>of</strong> rules for policy regard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>monetary system; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>se rules are no more <strong>in</strong>herently self-enforc<strong>in</strong>gthan any o<strong>the</strong>r set <strong>of</strong> monetary rules. Michele Fratianni has been tell<strong>in</strong>gus <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> read<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> Italian politicians to throw out <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard,<strong>and</strong> Peter L<strong>in</strong>dert has noted <strong>the</strong> propensity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>and</strong> keycurrencysystems to collapse when shocked. (Even today, before we havegone back to a supposed gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, <strong>the</strong>re is plenty <strong>of</strong> reason for suspect<strong>in</strong>gthat what some <strong>of</strong> its supporters are advocat<strong>in</strong>g is not a real buta pseudo gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, to echo a dist<strong>in</strong>ction made by Milton Friedman,1961, pp. 66–79.)Maybe some hope is to be found <strong>in</strong> constitutional restra<strong>in</strong>ts on governmenttax<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> spend<strong>in</strong>g, maybe <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> depoliticization <strong>of</strong> money.It would be outside my assignment to discuss <strong>the</strong>se possibilities tonight.My purpose, ra<strong>the</strong>r, has been to set our exam<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> classical goldst<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conditions <strong>and</strong> attitudes that apparentlyprevailed at <strong>the</strong> time.Given <strong>the</strong> required attitudes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> related restra<strong>in</strong>ts on government,<strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard is not <strong>the</strong> only set <strong>of</strong> monetary arrangements that wouldfunction tolerably well. Economists can easily imag<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> have proposed,monetary arrangements that would function better.


Chapter : e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard 205e required attitudes were illustrated <strong>in</strong> Austria even while <strong>the</strong> countrywas still on fiat paper money. e government <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial pressrepeatedly agonized even over budget deficits that would seem delightfullysmall to us today. Although <strong>the</strong> price level was generally steady or eventrend<strong>in</strong>g mildly downward (except dur<strong>in</strong>g wars <strong>and</strong> immediately afterward),<strong>the</strong> government <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> press worried about <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> moneyas reflected <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> exchange rate. (Nowadays, attention would more suitablyfocus on a price <strong>in</strong>dex.) e Neue Freie Presse took exchange rates <strong>of</strong>120 guldens or higher for ten pounds sterl<strong>in</strong>g as a particularly om<strong>in</strong>ouswarn<strong>in</strong>g.I will conclude with three quotations from that newspaper.London: 120! A cannon shot cannot shock us more than this figure; <strong>and</strong>it also forms an urgent warn<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> many f<strong>in</strong>ance m<strong>in</strong>isters <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Monarchy to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> moderation, to retrench, to resume <strong>the</strong> policy <strong>of</strong>soundness.... When <strong>the</strong> exchange rates, this manometer <strong>of</strong> credit, rise,<strong>the</strong>n it is better to reef <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sails a bit. <strong>Is</strong> it really our fate eternally tobear <strong>the</strong> mark <strong>of</strong> shame <strong>of</strong> a disordered currency? Will <strong>the</strong>re never comea chancellor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> treasury who will have <strong>the</strong> will <strong>and</strong> also <strong>the</strong> power torestore <strong>the</strong> most important basis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy? (14 October 1883)e price <strong>of</strong> foreign bills is <strong>the</strong> loudest <strong>and</strong> gravest accusation aga<strong>in</strong>st<strong>the</strong> government.... [When <strong>the</strong> opposition parties] want to depict <strong>the</strong>sad condition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> state with one stroke, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y need only unfold<strong>the</strong> Cursblatt [sic] <strong>and</strong> say: <strong>in</strong>gs have gone pretty far <strong>in</strong> Austria whenone franc equals half <strong>of</strong> our gulden on <strong>the</strong> world market.... what <strong>the</strong>ghosts were for poor Macbeth, <strong>the</strong> foreign exchanges are for [F<strong>in</strong>anceM<strong>in</strong>ister] Dunajewski; <strong>in</strong>deed, we are conv<strong>in</strong>ced that he <strong>of</strong>ten wakesup at night, terrified, <strong>and</strong> suddenly perceives a figure before him thatmock<strong>in</strong>gly hisses at him: London 126.50! (26 April 1885)To <strong>in</strong>troduce my f<strong>in</strong>al quotation, I should expla<strong>in</strong> that <strong>the</strong> Austrianpolice from time to time confiscated issues <strong>of</strong> publications conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g articlesconsidered too critical <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> government. e Neue Freie Presse occasionallycarried a notice on its front page say<strong>in</strong>g that its preced<strong>in</strong>g issue hadbeen confiscated. (To compensate its subscribers, <strong>the</strong> newspaper wouldei<strong>the</strong>r repr<strong>in</strong>t <strong>the</strong> confiscated issue without <strong>the</strong> <strong>of</strong>fend<strong>in</strong>g material or elsemake <strong>the</strong> next issue especially large.) In one <strong>of</strong> its editorials denounc<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> confiscations, <strong>the</strong> paper compla<strong>in</strong>ed about discrim<strong>in</strong>ation, as well:Unlike itself, <strong>the</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial Coursblatt <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Vienna Bourse had never beenconfiscated. Yet its latest issue quoted London exchange at 120.95. “Andif we were to write our f<strong>in</strong>gers sore, we could not portray <strong>the</strong> situation


206 Part I: Economicsmore precisely. Confiscate <strong>the</strong> Cursblatt [sic], Mr. Attorney General” (26February 1882).Anderson, Benjam<strong>in</strong> M. Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Public Welfare. New York: D. VanNostr<strong>and</strong>, 1949.Austria. Parliament. Chamber <strong>of</strong> Deputies. Stenographisches Protokoll, XI session,1892.. Währungs-Enquête Commission. Stenographische Protokolle über dievom 8. bis 17. März abgehaltenen Sitzungen. Vienna: K. k. H<strong>of</strong>- und Staatsdruckerei,1892.Crisp, Olga. “Russia, 1860–1914.” In Bank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Early Stages <strong>of</strong> Industrialization,edited by Rondo Cameron et al. New York: Oxford University Press,1967.Friedman, Milton. “Real <strong>and</strong> Pseudo Gold St<strong>and</strong>ards.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Law <strong>and</strong> Economics4 (October 1961): 66–79.Gruber, Robert. Nationales oder <strong>in</strong>ternationales Geld? Die Qu<strong>in</strong>tessenz der Währungsfrage.Vienna: Lesk und Schwidernoch, 1892.Gurjev, Aleks<strong>and</strong>r Nikolaevich. Reforma Denezhnago Obrashchenija. St. Petersburg:Kirshbaum, 1896.Imperatorskoe Voljnoe .Ekonomicheskoe Obshchestvo. Reforma denezhnagoobrashchenija. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted from <strong>the</strong> society’s Trudy 3. St. Petersburg: Demakov,1896.Kamitz, Re<strong>in</strong>hard. “Die österreichische Geld- und Währungspolitik von 1848bis 1948.” In Hundert Jahre österreichischer Wirtschaftsentwicklung, 1848–1948,edited by Hans Mayer. Vienna: Spr<strong>in</strong>ger, 1949.Keynes, John Maynard. e Economic Consequences <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Peace. New York: HarcourtBrace & World, 1920.Kreibig, Josef Clemens. Unser Währungs- und Münzwesen während der letztenfünfzig Jahre. Vienna, 1899.L<strong>and</strong>esberger, Julius. Über die Goldprämien-Politik der Zettelbanken. Vienna:Manz, 1892.


Chapter : e Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gold St<strong>and</strong>ard 207Menger, Carl. Collected Works <strong>of</strong> Carl Menger. Vol. 4, Schriften über Geld<strong>the</strong>orie undWährungspolitik. 1893. London: London School <strong>of</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>Political</strong>Science, 1936.Migul<strong>in</strong>, P.P. Russkij gosudarstvennyj kredit, 1769–1899. Vols. 2–3. Kharkov: PechatnoeDelo, 1899–1904.Neupauer, Josef Ritter von. Die Schäden und Gefahren der Valutaregulirung für dieStaatsf<strong>in</strong>anzen, die Volkswirthschaft und die Kriegsbereitschaft. Vienna: Leskund Schwidernoch, 1892.Ortega y Gasset, José. La Rebelión de las Masas. Madrid: Revista de Occidente,1930.Perl, Franz. Zur Frage der Valutaregulirung <strong>in</strong> Oesterreich-Ungarn. Zurich:Verlags-Magaz<strong>in</strong>, 1887.Raffalovich, Arthur. “Histoire du rouble-crédit.” Journal de la Société de Statistiquede Paris 37 (October 1896): 369.Russia. F<strong>in</strong>ance M<strong>in</strong>istry. M<strong>in</strong>isterstvo f<strong>in</strong>ansov, 1802–1902. St. Petersburg: .EkspeditsijaZagotovlenija Gosudarstvennykh Bumag, 1902.Saenger, Max. Die Wittesche Währungsreform. Vienna <strong>and</strong> Leipzig: Deuticke,1927.Schulze-Gävernitz, Gerhard von. Volkswirtschaftliche Studien aus Russl<strong>and</strong>. Leipzig:Duncker & Humblot, 1899.Schumpeter, Joseph. History <strong>of</strong> Economic Analysis. New York: Oxford UniversityPress, 1954.Sil<strong>in</strong>, N. Avstro-vengerskij bank. Moscow, 1913.Sowell, omas. Knowledge <strong>and</strong> Decisions. New York: Basic Books, 1980.Tisza, <strong>Is</strong>tván. “Valutánk rendezéséröl.” Budapesti Szemle 62, no. 160 (1890).Trakhtenberg, Iosif Adoljfovich. Denezhnoe Obrashchenie i Kredit pri Kapitalizme.Moscow: Izdateljstvo Akademii Nauk SSSR, 1962.Vienna Board <strong>of</strong> Trade (H<strong>and</strong>els- und Gewerbekammer <strong>in</strong> Wien). Bericht überden H<strong>and</strong>el, die Industrie und die Verkehrsverhältnisse <strong>in</strong> Nieder-Oesterreichwährend des Jahres 1886. Vienna, 1887.Vlasenko, Vasilij Evtikhievich. Teorii deneg v Rossii, Konets XIX-dooktjabrskijperiod XX v. Kiev: Izdateljstvo Kievskogo Universiteta, 1963.


208 Part I: EconomicsVon Laue, eodore H. Sergei Witte <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Industrialization <strong>of</strong> Russia. NewYork: Columbia University Press, 1963.Wicksell, Knut. Interest <strong>and</strong> Prices. 1898. Translated by R.F. Kahn. New York:Augustus M. Kelley, 1965.Witte, Sergej Juljevich. e Memoirs <strong>of</strong> Count Witte. Edited <strong>and</strong> translated byAbraham Yarmol<strong>in</strong>sky. Garden City: Doubleday Page, 1921.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong>. “Fluctuat<strong>in</strong>g Exchange Rates <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> N<strong>in</strong>eteenth Century: <strong>the</strong>Experiences <strong>of</strong> Austria <strong>and</strong> Russia.” In Monetary Problems <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> International<strong>Economy</strong>, edited by R.A. Mundell <strong>and</strong> A.K. Swoboda. Chicago: University<strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1969.


L<strong>and</strong>, Money, <strong>and</strong> CapitalFormation * What service, if any, do l<strong>and</strong>owners perform for <strong>the</strong> rents <strong>the</strong>y collect?L<strong>and</strong>, narrowly <strong>in</strong>terpreted as sheer space <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> associated pure gifts <strong>of</strong>nature, is just <strong>the</strong>re, available to render services regardless <strong>of</strong> ownership<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> owners’ work. Partly with such a thought <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, Henry Georgeproposed tax<strong>in</strong>g away most pure l<strong>and</strong> rent. Even some fervent defenders<strong>of</strong> private ownership <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> collection <strong>of</strong> rent give <strong>in</strong>complete <strong>and</strong>thus feeble accounts <strong>of</strong> service performed. e l<strong>and</strong>owner, accord<strong>in</strong>g toMurray Rothbard,f<strong>in</strong>ds, br<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>to use, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n allocates, l<strong>and</strong> sites to <strong>the</strong> most valueproductivebidders.... [I]t is not just <strong>the</strong> physical good that is be<strong>in</strong>g sold,but a whole bundle <strong>of</strong> services along with it—among which is <strong>the</strong> service<strong>of</strong> transferr<strong>in</strong>g ownership from seller to buyer, <strong>and</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g so efficiently.Ground l<strong>and</strong> does not simply exist; it must be served to <strong>the</strong> user....e l<strong>and</strong>owner earns <strong>the</strong> highest ground rents by allocat<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>and</strong> sitesto <strong>the</strong>ir most value-productive uses, i.e., to those uses most desired byconsumers....e view that br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g sites <strong>in</strong>to use <strong>and</strong> decid<strong>in</strong>g upon <strong>the</strong>ir location[sic] is not really “productive” is a vestige from <strong>the</strong> old classical view that aservice which does not tangibly “create” someth<strong>in</strong>g physical is not “really”productive. Actually, this function is just as productive as any o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong>a particularly vital function it is. To hamper <strong>and</strong> destroy this functionwould wreck <strong>the</strong> market economy. (Rothbard 1962, vol. II: pp. 813–814;attached endnotes on vol. II: pp. 929–930, are omitted here.)*From Economic Policy <strong>in</strong> an Orderly Framework: Liber Amicorum for Gerrit Meijer,eds. J.G. Backhaus et al. (Münster: Lit Verlag, 2003), 455–469. An omitted <strong>in</strong>troduction conta<strong>in</strong>s complimentary remarks about Gerrit Meijer, <strong>the</strong>honoree <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Festschrift.209


210 Part I: Economicsis is Rothbard’s ma<strong>in</strong> explanation <strong>of</strong> what <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong>owner does. It istrue that elsewhere (vol. II: pp. 503, 509) he briefly likens rental returns onl<strong>and</strong> values to <strong>in</strong>terest, but he does not develop this comparison <strong>and</strong> apparentlyei<strong>the</strong>r does not see its full significance or considers its significancetoo obvious to need spell<strong>in</strong>g out.A fuller account recognizes that l<strong>and</strong>owners, like owners <strong>of</strong> capitalgoods, stocks, <strong>and</strong> bonds, are perform<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> service <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g, as GustavCassel (1903/1956) called it, <strong>in</strong>sightfully <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g it as an <strong>in</strong>dependentfactor <strong>of</strong> production. Instead <strong>of</strong> sell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir assets <strong>and</strong> spend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>proceeds on consumption or o<strong>the</strong>r current purposes <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> neveraccumulat<strong>in</strong>g sav<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se forms <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place, <strong>the</strong> owners are ty<strong>in</strong>gup wealth over time <strong>and</strong> are wait<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> future <strong>in</strong>comes <strong>and</strong> maturityor sale values that <strong>the</strong>ir assets will yield. So do<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>y free resourceso<strong>the</strong>rwise allocated to consumption for construction <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance <strong>of</strong>mach<strong>in</strong>es, build<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r capital goods (<strong>and</strong> for formation <strong>of</strong> humancapital); <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>reby contribute to productivity <strong>and</strong> economic growth.L<strong>and</strong>owners are perform<strong>in</strong>g essentially <strong>the</strong> same service as recipients <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> strict sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term.Arbitrage <strong>of</strong> various k<strong>in</strong>ds tends to press annual net rents, expressedas percentages <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> values, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rates on loans toward equality(subject to st<strong>and</strong>ard qualifications about differences <strong>in</strong> risk, maturity,liquidity, <strong>and</strong> so forth). e uniform rate toward which <strong>the</strong>se tendenciespress may be seen as <strong>the</strong> reward or price <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> general, wait<strong>in</strong>g performed<strong>in</strong> various ways by delay<strong>in</strong>g consumption, ty<strong>in</strong>g up one’s sav<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>in</strong> claims or assets, <strong>and</strong> so free<strong>in</strong>g resources for capital formation.But just how does wait<strong>in</strong>g through acquir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> hold<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>and</strong> operate?Suppose that people become more thrifty <strong>and</strong> devote <strong>the</strong>ir thrift tobuy<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>and</strong>. eir purchases tend to raise l<strong>and</strong> prices <strong>and</strong> reduce percentageyields on l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong>, through arbitrage, to raise asset prices <strong>and</strong> reducepercentage yields generally, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate. e decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> targetyields encourages bus<strong>in</strong>ess firms to <strong>in</strong>vest <strong>the</strong> freed resources <strong>in</strong> realcapital formation, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> rise <strong>in</strong> real <strong>in</strong>vestment contributes to <strong>the</strong> generaldecl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> rates <strong>of</strong> return. e <strong>in</strong>creased <strong>in</strong>vestment embodies <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>creased thrift.Conversely, a decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> thrift restra<strong>in</strong>s real <strong>in</strong>vestment. If l<strong>and</strong>owners,becom<strong>in</strong>g less thrifty, decide to sell <strong>the</strong>ir hold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> spend <strong>the</strong> proceeds But <strong>the</strong>se different rates <strong>of</strong> yield are not identical just because <strong>the</strong>y tend to be equal <strong>in</strong>equilibrium. Expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g this equality is part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economist’s job, which is only impededby mak<strong>in</strong>g rent returns conceptually identical to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate narrowly def<strong>in</strong>ed.


Chapter : L<strong>and</strong>, Money, <strong>and</strong> Capital Formation 211on consumption, net rents expressed as percentages <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> depressed l<strong>and</strong>values would rise. Arbitrage would communicate this rise <strong>in</strong> yields to <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> more specific sense. Investment <strong>in</strong> time-consum<strong>in</strong>gproduction processes would suffer, as is already obvious from <strong>the</strong> reducedfree<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> resources for such <strong>in</strong>vestments.Wait<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>n, is <strong>the</strong> social function (along with o<strong>the</strong>rs mentionedby Rothbard) for which <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong>owner is “rewarded.” Say<strong>in</strong>g so merelynotes a parallel with <strong>the</strong> receipt <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest; it is not meant to justify <strong>the</strong>private ownership <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> receipt <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> rent. Maurice Allais has evenexpressed some worries (exam<strong>in</strong>ed below) about private l<strong>and</strong>ownership<strong>and</strong> rent collection. Ano<strong>the</strong>r way <strong>in</strong> which placement <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> l<strong>and</strong> can affect <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terestrate <strong>and</strong> real capital formation is <strong>in</strong>structive. Foreigners’ purchase <strong>of</strong>l<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> our country does so. e transaction, counted as “capital <strong>in</strong>flow,”contributes toward a balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments surplus on capital account <strong>and</strong>deficit on current account. Dur<strong>in</strong>g a period <strong>of</strong> adjustment, imports <strong>of</strong>goods <strong>and</strong> services exceed exports: our people ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> additional realresources embodied <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> net imports. e foreigners perform wait<strong>in</strong>gfor our country by surrender<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se resources currently <strong>and</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g for<strong>the</strong> yields on <strong>the</strong>ir newly purchased l<strong>and</strong>. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> foreign purchasetends to bid up l<strong>and</strong> prices, slightly reduc<strong>in</strong>g percentage yields <strong>and</strong>,through arbitrage, <strong>the</strong> general <strong>in</strong>terest rate as well. In this way, capital<strong>in</strong>flow through foreign purchases <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> promotes domestic capital formationmuch <strong>the</strong> same as would capital <strong>in</strong>flow through purchase <strong>of</strong> securities.is example re<strong>in</strong>forces <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> domestic sav<strong>in</strong>g devoted tobuy<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>and</strong>. One dist<strong>in</strong>ction between l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> man-made capital goods holds <strong>in</strong> degreeif not <strong>in</strong> essence. e supply <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> given by nature <strong>in</strong> fixed quantities ishighly price-<strong>in</strong>elastic, while quantities <strong>of</strong> most capital goods can respondto price. In some circumstances, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> desire to accumulate wealth<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> (wealth, not mere acreage) can be met through meregrowth <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> market value <strong>of</strong> a fixed amount, while accumulation <strong>of</strong> wealth


212 Part I: Economicsas capital goods ord<strong>in</strong>arily presupposes an <strong>in</strong>crease at least partly <strong>in</strong> physicalquantity. Maurice Allais f<strong>in</strong>ds this dist<strong>in</strong>ction important (1947, vol. II:chap. IX <strong>and</strong> passim; passages on this <strong>and</strong> related topics reviewed beloware widely scattered <strong>in</strong> his two volumes).People’s overall will<strong>in</strong>gness to wait, if it were somehow predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed,would promote capital formation all <strong>the</strong> more if people did not have <strong>the</strong>option <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g through ownership <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> particular. Accumulation<strong>of</strong> wealth <strong>in</strong> bid-up l<strong>and</strong> values partially gratifies <strong>the</strong> overall will<strong>in</strong>gness towait, leav<strong>in</strong>g less <strong>of</strong> that will<strong>in</strong>gness for satisfaction <strong>in</strong> ways that ultimatelyresult <strong>in</strong> capital formation.Allais’s po<strong>in</strong>t serves a deeper underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest,but no policy conclusions immediately follow. It concerns how <strong>the</strong> tastefor wait<strong>in</strong>g is gratified. It does not contradict recognition that wait<strong>in</strong>g performedthrough l<strong>and</strong>ownership makes <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate lower <strong>and</strong> capitalconstruction <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance greater than <strong>the</strong>se would be if <strong>the</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>gso performed did not occur at all, not even through ownership <strong>of</strong> wealth<strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r forms.It does seem plausible that wait<strong>in</strong>g is more attractive <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reforemore abundant overall with than without <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong>ownership option. Allaisseems to take <strong>the</strong> overall supply <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g tacitly for granted, however,<strong>and</strong> to suppose that if thrift could not f<strong>in</strong>d an outlet <strong>in</strong> l<strong>and</strong>ownership, itwould all seek an outlet <strong>in</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> capital goods, ei<strong>the</strong>r directly orthrough securities, fur<strong>the</strong>r lower<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>and</strong> promot<strong>in</strong>g realcapital formation.e opportunity to accumulate wealth as privately owned l<strong>and</strong> cutstwo ways. On <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, it broadens <strong>the</strong> opportunities open to savers,<strong>the</strong>reby improv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> overall attractiveness <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> so presumably<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g its total performance (assum<strong>in</strong>g, anyway, a “normal” ra<strong>the</strong>rthan “backbend<strong>in</strong>g” response to its rewards). On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong>ownershipoption diverts some fraction <strong>of</strong> total wait<strong>in</strong>g away from capitalformation <strong>in</strong>to accumulation <strong>of</strong> private wealth <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> socially ra<strong>the</strong>rfictitious form <strong>of</strong> bid-up l<strong>and</strong> values. e <strong>in</strong>elasticity <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>’s supplyis relevant: streng<strong>the</strong>ned dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>creases its quantity much less thanits market value (<strong>and</strong> not merely nom<strong>in</strong>al price but value relative too<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs). It is not obvious whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> absolute volume <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>gdevoted to capital formation is larger or smaller than it would be if<strong>the</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> values did not accrue to private owners. Allais evidentlybelieves that it is smaller, which is why he wants to restra<strong>in</strong> thataccrual.


Chapter : L<strong>and</strong>, Money, <strong>and</strong> Capital Formation 213A loose analogy holds here with creation <strong>and</strong> destruction <strong>of</strong> trade asanalyzed by <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> customs unions. A union opens some tradeamong member countries that trade barriers had formerly blocked, butit also diverts to with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> union some trade formerly carried on with<strong>the</strong> outside world. In <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> specific facts, one cannot concludewhich dom<strong>in</strong>ates—<strong>the</strong> benefits from trade creation or <strong>the</strong> damage fromtrade diversion. In <strong>the</strong> present context, similarly, it is not obvious whicheffect <strong>of</strong> private l<strong>and</strong>ownership prevails—<strong>the</strong> encouragement <strong>of</strong> total wait<strong>in</strong>gor <strong>the</strong> diversion <strong>of</strong> some wait<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to accumulation <strong>of</strong> socially fictitiouswealth.is remark about encouragement <strong>and</strong> diversion needs to be sharpened.Real resources cannot be diverted <strong>in</strong>to accumulation <strong>of</strong> fictitiouswealth; what can be diverted, ra<strong>the</strong>r, is <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness to postpone consumption<strong>and</strong> accumulate <strong>and</strong> hold wealth. It is thus <strong>in</strong>exact <strong>in</strong> this contextto worry over any diversion <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g apart <strong>and</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ct from itsdecrease. Allais’s worry must mean that <strong>the</strong> propensity to save or waitis gratified <strong>and</strong> sopped up by accumulation <strong>of</strong> wealth that, though genu<strong>in</strong>efrom <strong>the</strong> private po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view, is fictitious from <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong>society as a whole. is fictitious wealth—values created by competitionto own l<strong>and</strong> that would physically exist anyway—makes <strong>the</strong> economywidepropensity to save slighter (as I <strong>in</strong>terpret his view) than it would o<strong>the</strong>rwisebe. (e concepts <strong>of</strong> supply or diversion <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> possible waste<strong>of</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness to supply it speak fur<strong>the</strong>r, by <strong>the</strong> way, <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> view<strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g as a factor <strong>of</strong> production.)Emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> divergence <strong>of</strong> viewpo<strong>in</strong>ts fur<strong>the</strong>r clarifies Allais’spo<strong>in</strong>t. By own<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual is transferr<strong>in</strong>g consumption from<strong>the</strong> present to <strong>the</strong> future for himself but not for society except—<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>exception is important—<strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as substitution <strong>and</strong> arbitrage promotecapital-goods accumulation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like because <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g as such ra<strong>the</strong>rthan because <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g performed through l<strong>and</strong>ownership <strong>in</strong> particular.rough l<strong>and</strong>ownership, wait<strong>in</strong>g can be done from <strong>the</strong> private po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong>view that is not wait<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> social po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view. (Wait<strong>in</strong>g performedthrough l<strong>and</strong>ownership <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwise not performed at all, however, doespromote capital-goods construction through substitution <strong>and</strong> arbitrage,so that <strong>the</strong> damage done through diversion <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to l<strong>and</strong>ownershipis partially <strong>and</strong> conceivably even more than fully <strong>of</strong>fset.)A reductio ad absurdum helps convey Allais’s po<strong>in</strong>t. If sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> realcapital formation were to br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al productivity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate extremely low, capitaliz<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>and</strong> rents at that rate


214 Part I: Economicswould make l<strong>and</strong> values extremely high. As l<strong>and</strong>ed wealth grew from <strong>the</strong>private po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view, it would deter sav<strong>in</strong>g through a positive effect on <strong>the</strong>propensity to consume. us <strong>the</strong> tentatively supposed great sav<strong>in</strong>g, capitalaccumulation, <strong>and</strong> reduction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al productivity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate would not go to such an extreme <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place. An<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> wealth from <strong>the</strong> private though not from <strong>the</strong> social po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong>view does tend to check sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> real capital formation. at particularcheck would be absent if savers were denied <strong>the</strong> opportunity to acquirel<strong>and</strong>. Some examples <strong>of</strong> change may re<strong>in</strong>force <strong>the</strong> analysis. Suppose that peoplebecome more thrifty <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong>itially direct <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>creased propensityto wait to l<strong>and</strong>ownership. L<strong>and</strong> rises <strong>in</strong> price, mak<strong>in</strong>g more monetarywealth available to be accumulated as l<strong>and</strong>. From <strong>the</strong> social po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong>view, however, this <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> opportunities for wait<strong>in</strong>g is spurious. e<strong>in</strong>creased propensity to wait will go partly <strong>in</strong>to hold<strong>in</strong>g an unaugmentedphysical amount <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> at higher prices ra<strong>the</strong>r than predom<strong>in</strong>antly <strong>in</strong>tohold<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>creased amount <strong>of</strong> capital goods.Suppose that although <strong>the</strong> overall degree <strong>of</strong> thrift has not changed,wealth-owners’ preferences about <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> wealth <strong>the</strong>y hold doesshift—toward l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> away from capital goods <strong>and</strong> securities issued t<strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>ance <strong>the</strong>m. e bid-up level <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> prices <strong>in</strong>creases <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>of</strong>l<strong>and</strong>ed wealth from <strong>the</strong> private po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view—this is a matter <strong>of</strong> arithmetic—butnot from <strong>the</strong> social po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view. is socially fictitiouswealth helps satisfy its owners’ desire for accumulated sav<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> thuscompetes with satisfy<strong>in</strong>g that desire through f<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> construction <strong>of</strong>new real wealth with resources diverted from current consumption. isis not to say that <strong>the</strong> fictitious l<strong>and</strong>ed wealth reduces <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness tosave or wait as described by a schedule or function. Instead, l<strong>and</strong>ed wealthfrom <strong>the</strong> private po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view forms part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wealth argument <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>sav<strong>in</strong>g function. e more wealth people already hold, <strong>the</strong> weaker is <strong>the</strong>ir<strong>in</strong>centive to accumulate still more. e effect <strong>in</strong> question is <strong>the</strong> so-calledwealth or Pigou or real-balance effect (an effect reviewed below <strong>in</strong> connectionwith how <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> money also affects <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate, sav<strong>in</strong>g,<strong>and</strong> real capital formation). Assets from which dem<strong>and</strong> has shifted away presumably decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> price, but <strong>the</strong>yare <strong>of</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds associated with capital formation.


Chapter : L<strong>and</strong>, Money, <strong>and</strong> Capital Formation 215Suppose a change <strong>in</strong> policy. A new tax (or, almost equivalently, somesort <strong>of</strong> new social stigma) makes l<strong>and</strong>ownership less attractive than before.e old rate <strong>of</strong> return on l<strong>and</strong> is <strong>in</strong>adequate. L<strong>and</strong>owners try to sell <strong>the</strong>irhold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> shift <strong>in</strong>to securities until, at its reduced price, l<strong>and</strong> bearsa percentage rate <strong>of</strong> return sufficiently higher than <strong>the</strong> rate on bonds tocompensate for <strong>the</strong> new disadvantages <strong>of</strong> own<strong>in</strong>g it. Nei<strong>the</strong>r l<strong>and</strong> itselfnor its services have become any more or less abundant than before, <strong>and</strong>noth<strong>in</strong>g obvious works unambiguously to raise or reduce <strong>the</strong> prices <strong>of</strong> itsservices. Still, <strong>the</strong> development that made people want to sell l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> buybonds depresses <strong>the</strong> bond <strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>and</strong> promotes real capital formation.With <strong>the</strong>ir prices reduced, <strong>the</strong> unchanged physical quantities <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>absorb less <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> overall propensity to wait or save, assumed to rema<strong>in</strong>unchanged.e follow<strong>in</strong>g question might seem to discredit Allais’s analysis. If<strong>the</strong> overall propensity to save or wait has not <strong>in</strong>creased, where do <strong>the</strong>additional resources for capital-goods construction come from? How doadditional resources get released from provid<strong>in</strong>g current consumption? Toanswer, we must dist<strong>in</strong>guish between <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>of</strong> thrift, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words,<strong>the</strong> propensity to save or wait, expressible as a function <strong>of</strong> several variables,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> actual volume <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g or wait<strong>in</strong>g performed. (Compare<strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>the</strong> schedule <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>amount dem<strong>and</strong>ed or <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>the</strong> Keynesian consumptionfunction <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> actual volume <strong>of</strong> consumption.) e answer is that<strong>the</strong> reduced attractiveness <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> as an outlet for <strong>the</strong> propensity to saveaffects <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> that propensity at <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> such a way fewerresources do <strong>in</strong>deed go <strong>in</strong>to current consumption <strong>and</strong> more <strong>in</strong>to capitalformation.Two ways <strong>of</strong> analyz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> new tax or stigma attachedto l<strong>and</strong>ownership might seem to contradict each o<strong>the</strong>r. On <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>,penaliz<strong>in</strong>g wait<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a particular form would presumably help make aggregatewait<strong>in</strong>g less attractive, scarcer, <strong>and</strong> costlier. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>tax or stigma would reduce <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong>-wealth deterrent to sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> so promotesatisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> propensity to save through f<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> construction<strong>of</strong> real wealth.e difference <strong>in</strong> possible conclusions traces to differences <strong>in</strong> tacitassumptions. One str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> analysis assumes that <strong>the</strong> penalty on wait<strong>in</strong>gperformed through own<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>and</strong> deters wait<strong>in</strong>g overall. It assumes relativelyslight substitutability among forms <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g: not all <strong>the</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>gdisplaced from one particular form, l<strong>and</strong>, switches to o<strong>the</strong>rs; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> total


216 Part I: Economicsvolume goes down. Ano<strong>the</strong>r str<strong>and</strong>, Allais’s, tacitly assumes high substitutability:<strong>the</strong> propensity to save will be satisfied <strong>in</strong> some form or o<strong>the</strong>r;<strong>and</strong> if satisfy<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong> a socially fictitious way is made less attractive, morewill be satisfied through real capital formation.is second str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> analysis tacitly supposes that l<strong>and</strong> simply exists.If it can be created <strong>and</strong> destroyed, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> argument is stronger fortreat<strong>in</strong>g it like any o<strong>the</strong>r capital good. If l<strong>and</strong> does not, <strong>in</strong> fact, go onyield<strong>in</strong>g a stream <strong>of</strong> services that rema<strong>in</strong>s unimpaired forever despite <strong>the</strong>conditions <strong>of</strong> ownership, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> signals <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives transmitted by<strong>the</strong> price system can usefully guide <strong>the</strong> exploitation <strong>and</strong> conservation <strong>of</strong>depletable resources, whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong>y are straightforwardly replaceable.Restrict<strong>in</strong>g private ownership <strong>of</strong> resources <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>comes from <strong>the</strong>mwould impair <strong>the</strong>se signals <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives. Anthony Scott (1955) developsthis po<strong>in</strong>t at length. He fur<strong>the</strong>r argues, among o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs, thatnoth<strong>in</strong>g is sacred about conserv<strong>in</strong>g depletable resources <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir orig<strong>in</strong>al,nature-given form; man-made capital goods can <strong>of</strong>ten sensibly replace<strong>the</strong>m. Because <strong>in</strong>vestments <strong>in</strong> resource conservation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> man-madecapital goods are essentially similar, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g greater stocks <strong>of</strong> naturalresources means hav<strong>in</strong>g less man-made capital goods—given <strong>the</strong> totalvolume <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestable sav<strong>in</strong>g.None <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> above cancels what was said near <strong>the</strong> start <strong>of</strong> this paperabout how people’s will<strong>in</strong>gness to acquire <strong>and</strong> hold l<strong>and</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r than spend<strong>the</strong> proceeds <strong>of</strong> its sale on current consumption does tend to hold down<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>and</strong> promote capital formation. Nor does anyth<strong>in</strong>g cancel<strong>the</strong> reservation, largely attributable to Allais, that, given <strong>the</strong> propensity topostpone current consumption, conceived <strong>of</strong> as a function <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong>wealth, <strong>the</strong> opportunity to accumulate private wealth <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>,as compared with its absence, does tend to absorb <strong>the</strong> propensity to wait<strong>in</strong> such a way as to impede capital formation.Allais is not <strong>the</strong> only economist to mention l<strong>and</strong> (as well as money; seea later section) <strong>in</strong> an analysis <strong>of</strong> unproductive diversion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gnessto save; so does Maxwell J. Fry (1988, p. 17). e total market value <strong>of</strong>wealth, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> collectibles, appears with positivesign as an argument <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy’s consumption function <strong>and</strong> with anegative sign <strong>in</strong> its sav<strong>in</strong>g function. O<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs equal, <strong>the</strong> larger thiswealth term is, <strong>the</strong> larger is <strong>the</strong> volume <strong>of</strong> consumption out <strong>of</strong> a givenreal <strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> smaller <strong>the</strong> volume <strong>of</strong> resources released by sav<strong>in</strong>g forreal <strong>in</strong>vestment. e more people satisfy <strong>the</strong>ir desire to hold sav<strong>in</strong>gs byhold<strong>in</strong>g wealth <strong>of</strong> a privately genu<strong>in</strong>e but socially spurious k<strong>in</strong>d, such as


Chapter : L<strong>and</strong>, Money, <strong>and</strong> Capital Formation 217<strong>the</strong> bid-up value <strong>of</strong> collectibles <strong>and</strong> l<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> less <strong>the</strong>y satisfy <strong>the</strong>ir desiresfor sav<strong>in</strong>gs by hold<strong>in</strong>g capital goods (or securities issued to f<strong>in</strong>ance capitalgoods). As just suggested, a similar worry applies to collectibles—Old Masters,antiques, rare co<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> stamps, <strong>and</strong> similarly durable <strong>and</strong> nonreproducibleassets. If a change <strong>in</strong> tastes or circumstances streng<strong>the</strong>ns <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for<strong>the</strong>m (perhaps as hedges aga<strong>in</strong>st ongo<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>flation), <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensified bidd<strong>in</strong>graises <strong>the</strong>ir prices. eir <strong>in</strong>creased value—not merely nom<strong>in</strong>al valuebut value relative to o<strong>the</strong>r goods <strong>and</strong> services—is an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> wealthfor <strong>in</strong>dividual holders, but it corresponds to no physical <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> wealthfrom <strong>the</strong> social po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view. Never<strong>the</strong>less, this socially fictitious wealthtends to satisfy <strong>and</strong> absorb <strong>the</strong> propensity to accumulate sav<strong>in</strong>gs. is OldMasters wealth effect makes <strong>the</strong> volume <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g smaller than it wouldo<strong>the</strong>rwise be, releas<strong>in</strong>g fewer resources for capital-goods construction. Incontrast, a streng<strong>the</strong>ned desire to save <strong>and</strong> accumulate wealth <strong>in</strong> bondstends to lower <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>and</strong> promote real capital formation; <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial assets (<strong>and</strong> liabilities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> bond-issuers) is matchedby an <strong>in</strong>creased quantity <strong>of</strong> real assets.is parable <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Old Masters is an analytical device <strong>and</strong> not a h<strong>in</strong>t ata policy proposal. It rem<strong>in</strong>ds us, though, <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> severe <strong>in</strong>flation:disruption <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial markets <strong>and</strong> diversion <strong>of</strong> people’s propensityto save away from f<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> construction <strong>of</strong> real capital equipment.... Allais applies his argument about <strong>the</strong> sidetrack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> thrift not only tol<strong>and</strong> but also to money. Of course, <strong>the</strong> very existence <strong>of</strong> money <strong>in</strong>fluences<strong>the</strong> real fundamentals; <strong>the</strong> contrast with a barter economy is sharp. But aPigou or wealth or real-balance effect (Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong> 1965, 1987/1992) can have<strong>the</strong> regretted consequences. Money, <strong>and</strong> especially a rise <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> purchas<strong>in</strong>gpower <strong>of</strong> a given nom<strong>in</strong>al money supply, may constitute wealth oran <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> wealth from <strong>the</strong> private if not <strong>the</strong> social po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view <strong>and</strong>so may <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>the</strong> overall propensity to consume <strong>and</strong> reduce <strong>the</strong> overallpropensity to save.e real-balance effect is probably most familiar <strong>in</strong> refutation <strong>of</strong> Keynesianworries about too great a propensity to save, which <strong>in</strong> turn are


218 Part I: Economicsprobably more familiar than Allais’s quite different worry. e effect <strong>of</strong>monetary wealth on <strong>the</strong> propensity to save can <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple solve any supposedproblem <strong>of</strong> unemployment <strong>and</strong> idle productive capacity due to oversav<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> deficiency <strong>of</strong> effective dem<strong>and</strong>. In <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> any o<strong>the</strong>rsolution, price <strong>and</strong> wage deflation would eventually make <strong>the</strong> real value<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al money supply adequate to support a full-employment volume<strong>of</strong> effective dem<strong>and</strong>. (For familiar reasons, <strong>of</strong> course, this “automatic”solution is not <strong>the</strong> easiest or best one.)More important <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> present context, <strong>the</strong> real-balance effect illum<strong>in</strong>atesAllais’s worry. Sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> real capital formation may be curtailednot just from a deflationary <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> real value <strong>of</strong> a given nom<strong>in</strong>almoney supply but even from <strong>the</strong> availability <strong>of</strong> money as an alternative tohold<strong>in</strong>g capital goods <strong>and</strong> stocks <strong>and</strong> bonds. ( James Tob<strong>in</strong>’s version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>argument, 1965, is better known than Allais’s.)e reason for this worry about money is similar to <strong>the</strong> reason forworry about l<strong>and</strong>. If people can postpone consumption by hold<strong>in</strong>g moneyor l<strong>and</strong> or Old Masters as well as by hold<strong>in</strong>g man-made capital goodsor securities that f<strong>in</strong>ance <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>the</strong>n part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir propensity to save orwait is diverted from channel<strong>in</strong>g resources <strong>in</strong>to capital-goods construction.Money is wealth from <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual owner,<strong>and</strong> hold<strong>in</strong>g it contributes to satiat<strong>in</strong>g his overall propensity to save orwait; but it is not wealth <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same way <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> same extent for <strong>the</strong>economy at large.e phrase “<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same way <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> same extent” is a hedge. Evenfrom <strong>the</strong> social po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view, money is not mere fictitious wealth. It elim<strong>in</strong>ates<strong>the</strong> frustrations <strong>and</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> barter. It facilitates f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>termediation<strong>and</strong> capital formation. It renders services to its holders. A largercash balance permits less attention to synchroniz<strong>in</strong>g payment <strong>in</strong>flows <strong>and</strong>outflows <strong>and</strong> less use <strong>of</strong> labor <strong>and</strong> materials <strong>in</strong> manag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> holder’s cashposition. What renders <strong>the</strong>se services is real <strong>and</strong> not merely nom<strong>in</strong>al cashbalances. Real money is peculiar <strong>in</strong> that its quantity is determ<strong>in</strong>ed on <strong>the</strong>dem<strong>and</strong> side. ere is no way <strong>of</strong> simply supply<strong>in</strong>g more real money to aneconomy unless holders are somehow <strong>in</strong>duced to dem<strong>and</strong> more <strong>of</strong> it (as<strong>the</strong>y would be <strong>in</strong>duced when nom<strong>in</strong>al money expansion helps restore adepressed economy to full employment). (An exception is ra<strong>the</strong>r trivial:monetary <strong>in</strong>flation can <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>the</strong> real money stock temporarily untilprices have caught up.) e just-mentioned hedge applies to l<strong>and</strong> as wellas to money. L<strong>and</strong> is socially useful, <strong>of</strong> course, as are Old Masters. But<strong>the</strong>y have a socially fictitious wealth aspect also.


Chapter : L<strong>and</strong>, Money, <strong>and</strong> Capital Formation 219Suppos<strong>in</strong>g a certa<strong>in</strong> type <strong>of</strong> change <strong>of</strong> tastes helps us underst<strong>and</strong> thisdivergence between private <strong>and</strong> social viewpo<strong>in</strong>ts. Although people rema<strong>in</strong>as will<strong>in</strong>g as before to postpone consumption by hold<strong>in</strong>g assets, <strong>the</strong>y desireto hold more <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir wealth as money <strong>and</strong> less <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r forms. e result<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>itial excess dem<strong>and</strong> for cash balances (<strong>and</strong> deficient dem<strong>and</strong> for goods<strong>and</strong> services) tends to deflate prices <strong>and</strong> wages. e correspond<strong>in</strong>g rise <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> real value <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unchanged total nom<strong>in</strong>al money supply is an <strong>in</strong>crease<strong>in</strong> real wealth for <strong>in</strong>dividual holders, but it is less fully so from <strong>the</strong> socialpo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view. Yet this <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> private real monetary goes toward satisfy<strong>in</strong>gpeople’s will<strong>in</strong>gness to postpone consumption <strong>and</strong> accumulate wealth;it makes <strong>the</strong> propensity to consume higher <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> propensity to save lowerthan <strong>the</strong>y would o<strong>the</strong>rwise be. Fewer real resources are released from provid<strong>in</strong>gcurrent consumption <strong>and</strong> made available for capital-goods construction.e more <strong>of</strong> this quasi-fictitious wealth people hold, <strong>the</strong> less realwealth (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g capital goods) <strong>the</strong>y want to accumulate. In short, <strong>the</strong>availability <strong>of</strong> wealth <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> cash balances diverts some <strong>of</strong> people’spropensity to wait away from <strong>the</strong> accumulation <strong>and</strong> construction <strong>of</strong> realcapital goods.Allais accord<strong>in</strong>gly regrets <strong>the</strong> opportunity open to savers to accumulate<strong>the</strong>ir sav<strong>in</strong>gs partly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> money. e problem would be worsewhen price-level deflation was actually reward<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> hold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> moneyra<strong>the</strong>r than physical assets (or securities f<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m). Growth <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>real value <strong>of</strong> money would be ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g effective dem<strong>and</strong> for currentoutput by satiat<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>creased dem<strong>and</strong> for real cash balances, that is, bystimulat<strong>in</strong>g consumption <strong>and</strong> partially neutraliz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> public’s propensityto save.Allais’s proposed remedy provides fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to his reason<strong>in</strong>g.He suggested stamped money (as Silvio Gesell, 1934, did but for a differentpurpose). e tax thus imposed on cash balances would prod peopleto accumulate wealth <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r forms, such as capital goods or securities.Almost equivalently, a policy <strong>of</strong> chronic mild price <strong>in</strong>flation would discouragemoney-hold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> channel propensities to save <strong>and</strong> accumulate<strong>in</strong>to socially more productive directions. Allais even suggested splitt<strong>in</strong>gapart <strong>the</strong> unit <strong>of</strong> account <strong>and</strong> medium <strong>of</strong> exchange. e “franc,” <strong>the</strong> unit<strong>of</strong> account, would be def<strong>in</strong>ed so as to have a stable value. e “circul,”or medium <strong>of</strong> exchange, would cont<strong>in</strong>uously depreciate aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> stablefranc, discourag<strong>in</strong>g hold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> circul-denom<strong>in</strong>ated banknotes <strong>and</strong>deposits. Use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> circul as unit <strong>of</strong> account would be “flatly forbidden”(1947, vol. II: pp. 579–585 <strong>and</strong> passim).


220 Part I: EconomicsAllais focused on what he considered beneficial allocation effects <strong>of</strong>mild <strong>in</strong>flation. What amounts to a tax on real cash balances motivates peopleto allocate a given volume <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g less toward <strong>the</strong>m <strong>and</strong> more towardreal capital formation. e <strong>in</strong>flationary erosion <strong>of</strong> wealth held as cash balancesfur<strong>the</strong>r promotes sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as people try to recoup this lostwealth (Mundell 1963; 1971, chap. 2). On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> realbalanceservices would itself tend to hamper economic activity (cf. Short1979).As for whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness to wait is used productively or is diverted,securities resemble or represent capital goods <strong>and</strong> contrast withmoney. Ultimately, securities can be bought only if <strong>the</strong>y are issued; <strong>and</strong>, by<strong>and</strong> large, <strong>the</strong>y are issued more to f<strong>in</strong>ance real <strong>in</strong>vestment than to f<strong>in</strong>anceconsumption. If ei<strong>the</strong>r Allais’s tax or ongo<strong>in</strong>g price-level <strong>in</strong>flation prodspeople away from money balances <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>to securities, f<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>g capitalconstruction becomes cheaper <strong>and</strong> more attractive for companies. eresult<strong>in</strong>g larger stock <strong>of</strong> capital goods, while tend<strong>in</strong>g to raise <strong>the</strong> productivity<strong>of</strong> complementary factors <strong>of</strong> production, tends to reduce those goods’own marg<strong>in</strong>al productivity <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al productivity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment,<strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e with <strong>the</strong> depressed <strong>in</strong>terest rate.Despite but not contrary to Allais’s analysis, an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> overallthrift<strong>in</strong>ess, even if <strong>in</strong>itially directed toward acquir<strong>in</strong>g larger real moneybalances, does tend to promote capital formation, although less so than<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> effect that worried Allais. Don Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>’s apparatus<strong>of</strong> CC-BB-LL curves (1965, chaps. IX–XI) is useful <strong>in</strong> show<strong>in</strong>g how.Although his apparatus, unsupplemented, does not dist<strong>in</strong>guish betweenconsumer goods <strong>and</strong> capital goods, it does yield conclusions about changes<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rate (<strong>and</strong> price level) that <strong>in</strong> turn suggest effects on capital-goodsconstruction. A shift <strong>of</strong> preferences away from goods—fromcurrent consumption, specifically—toward hold<strong>in</strong>g money tends to lower<strong>the</strong> rate <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>and</strong> thus promote capital construction, although moreslightly than if <strong>the</strong> shift had been <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> bonds. (A shift <strong>of</strong> preferencesaway from money hold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> bonds would alsotend to lower <strong>the</strong> rate <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>and</strong> promote capital construction, asPat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>’s apparatus also illustrates, <strong>in</strong> agreement with Allais’s analysis.)Even when oriented toward money, <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness to postpone consumption<strong>and</strong> accumulate wealth favors capital formation, though <strong>in</strong> a lesserdegree than when oriented to capital goods directly or to securities forf<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m. In a sense, money itself can be a vehicle <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>termediation,a means <strong>of</strong> convey<strong>in</strong>g comm<strong>and</strong> over resources from savers to


Chapter : L<strong>and</strong>, Money, <strong>and</strong> Capital Formation 221real <strong>in</strong>vestors (a role <strong>of</strong> money expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> McK<strong>in</strong>non 1973, Shaw 1973,<strong>and</strong> Yeager 1997). is possibility h<strong>in</strong>ges on <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particularmonetary system.Allais’s objection to nontaxed <strong>and</strong> non<strong>in</strong>flationary money is best <strong>in</strong>terpreted,<strong>the</strong>n, not as deny<strong>in</strong>g money’s f<strong>in</strong>ancial-<strong>in</strong>termediary function butas emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g that certa<strong>in</strong> types <strong>of</strong> money perform that function imperfectly.Allais himself recognized that creat<strong>in</strong>g new money <strong>in</strong> ways thattended to favor real <strong>in</strong>vestment, as through bank-credit expansion for thatpurpose, could more or less neutralize <strong>the</strong> anti-capital-formation effectthat he worried about (1947, vol. I: chap. VIII, esp. pp. 338–340). e veryissue <strong>of</strong> new money to meet a streng<strong>the</strong>ned dem<strong>and</strong> for money (<strong>in</strong>stead<strong>of</strong> lett<strong>in</strong>g price deflation <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>the</strong> real value <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g nom<strong>in</strong>alsupply) could help convey to real <strong>in</strong>vestors <strong>the</strong> comm<strong>and</strong> over resourcesreleased by savers acquir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> new money.is effect is a mild version <strong>of</strong> “forced sav<strong>in</strong>g” (cf. Hansson 1992),although <strong>the</strong> term may be <strong>in</strong>exact <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mild <strong>and</strong> non<strong>in</strong>flationary caseconsidered here. In <strong>the</strong> prototypical case, new money loaned to <strong>in</strong>vestorsenables <strong>the</strong>m to bid resources away from o<strong>the</strong>r people, who are forcedto consume less as <strong>in</strong>flation shr<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>the</strong> purchas<strong>in</strong>g powers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<strong>in</strong>comes, money hold<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r nom<strong>in</strong>al claims. In <strong>the</strong> presentmild case, new money appears merely <strong>in</strong> amounts that meet a grow<strong>in</strong>gdem<strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g price level (for example, a grow<strong>in</strong>g dem<strong>and</strong> forreal money balances associated with economic growth). e manner <strong>in</strong>which additional real <strong>and</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al money comes <strong>in</strong>to circulation moreor less corrects for <strong>the</strong> consumption-promot<strong>in</strong>g divergence between <strong>the</strong>private <strong>and</strong> social views <strong>of</strong> money as wealth. An <strong>in</strong>creased will<strong>in</strong>gnessto wait, even by way <strong>of</strong> hold<strong>in</strong>g money, does <strong>the</strong>n promote capital construction.is result can arise from <strong>the</strong> mere existence <strong>and</strong> not just <strong>the</strong> expansion<strong>of</strong> money that is matched on <strong>the</strong> asset sides <strong>of</strong> its issuers’ balance sheetsby loans to real <strong>in</strong>vestors. As new <strong>in</strong>vestment-related loans replace oldones be<strong>in</strong>g paid <strong>of</strong>f, even with <strong>the</strong>ir total amount unchanged, <strong>the</strong> moneymatch<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m cont<strong>in</strong>ues serv<strong>in</strong>g as a vehicle <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>termediation. e cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>gopportunity to hold sav<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> that form promotes ra<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>and</strong>eters wait<strong>in</strong>g devoted to ma<strong>in</strong>tenance or replacement <strong>of</strong> capital goods.Like o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>struments <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>termediation, money helps hold down <strong>the</strong>spread between <strong>the</strong> effective <strong>in</strong>terest rates (nom<strong>in</strong>al rates plus <strong>and</strong> m<strong>in</strong>uspecuniary <strong>and</strong> nonpecuniary advantages <strong>and</strong> costs) that lenders receive<strong>and</strong> that borrowers pay.


222 Part I: Economicse alternative method <strong>of</strong> accommodat<strong>in</strong>g a streng<strong>the</strong>ned dem<strong>and</strong>for real money balances <strong>in</strong> a growth context works through price-leveldeflation. Allais’s worry does apply to that method. It applies most straightforwardlyto money based on a commodity, like gold, whose productionuses up real resources, to government fiat money <strong>of</strong> fixed nom<strong>in</strong>al quantity,<strong>and</strong> to bank money fully backed by such gold or such fiat money. It alsoapplies to money created to f<strong>in</strong>ance consumption (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g governmentbudget deficits).In short, Allais’s worry about <strong>the</strong> pro-consumption/anti-sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence<strong>of</strong> wealth held <strong>in</strong> real money balances is not refuted by a different considerationpull<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> opposite direction. Allais himself recognized it:existence <strong>and</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for money provide opportunities for<strong>the</strong> non<strong>in</strong>flationary creation <strong>of</strong> new money to f<strong>in</strong>ance <strong>in</strong>vestment projects.It is not clear that <strong>the</strong> effect that concerned Allais is quantitativelyimportant. Relative to <strong>the</strong> volumes <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial<strong>in</strong>termediation rout<strong>in</strong>ely accomplished anyway, only presumably small volumesmight be frustrated by absence <strong>of</strong> suitable growth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>almoney <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Allais’s measures to deter money-hold<strong>in</strong>g. Still, that effectwas worth describ<strong>in</strong>g because <strong>of</strong> its parallel with <strong>the</strong> similar <strong>and</strong> supposedlyworrisome effect <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>. As is evident from his arguments summarized above, Allais, along withsome o<strong>the</strong>r economists, th<strong>in</strong>ks that <strong>the</strong> market-determ<strong>in</strong>ed overall rate<strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> capital formation is too low. An excessive market rate <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terest reflects <strong>and</strong> implements an <strong>in</strong>adequate degree <strong>of</strong> concern for <strong>the</strong>future. A person’s choices between consumption today <strong>and</strong> consumptionten or twenty years later are made by <strong>the</strong> present person only. e futureperson, who might well prefer a more future-oriented allocation, has nosay <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> matter. e state knows better <strong>and</strong> might legitimately imposeforced sav<strong>in</strong>g through taxation (1947, vol. I: pp. 220 n., 221–225; vol. II:pp. 592–593; similar thoughts are scattered widely through both volumes;on <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ “telescopic faculty” be<strong>in</strong>g “defective” or “perverted,” comparePigou 1932/1950, pp. 24–26; <strong>and</strong> Scott 1955, chap. 8, “A Social Rate <strong>of</strong>Time Preference”). On all this, remember that Allais was writ<strong>in</strong>g back <strong>in</strong>1947, before <strong>the</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong> subsequent experience with governmenteconomic <strong>and</strong> budgetary policies <strong>and</strong> before <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> publicchoice <strong>the</strong>ory.


Chapter : L<strong>and</strong>, Money, <strong>and</strong> Capital Formation 223Private ownership <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> has a social function. In free<strong>in</strong>g resources fromserv<strong>in</strong>g current consumption while wait<strong>in</strong>g for l<strong>and</strong>’s periodic rents <strong>and</strong>future sell<strong>in</strong>g price, <strong>the</strong> owner is supply<strong>in</strong>g a productive service. It is essentially<strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g for which lenders receive <strong>in</strong>terest. On <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> volumes <strong>of</strong> this service <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> result<strong>in</strong>g real capitalformation would be still greater if private <strong>and</strong> social viewpo<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>edwealth did not diverge <strong>and</strong> if <strong>the</strong> Pigou or wealth effect did not deter sav<strong>in</strong>g.Quite similar remarks apply to some o<strong>the</strong>r vehicles <strong>of</strong> wait<strong>in</strong>g, notablycollectibles <strong>and</strong> money.e entire forego<strong>in</strong>g discussion serves an analytical purpose only <strong>and</strong>is not meant, by itself, ei<strong>the</strong>r to justify or to condemn <strong>the</strong> private collection<strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> rents. It does not claim that <strong>the</strong> effects described are quantitativelyimportant <strong>and</strong> detectable amidst all <strong>the</strong> constantly occurr<strong>in</strong>g changes <strong>in</strong>economic conditions. For this <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r reasons, <strong>the</strong> discussion does notrecommend any particular policy. Policy proposals are mentioned to helpclarify <strong>the</strong> analysis that underp<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong>m.Allais, Maurice. Économie et Intérêt. 2 vols. Paris: Imprimerie Nationale, 1947.Cassel, Gustav. e Nature <strong>and</strong> Necessity <strong>of</strong> Interest. 1903. New York: Augustus M.Kelley, 1956.Fry, Maxwell J. Money, Interest, <strong>and</strong> Bank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Economic Development. Baltimore:Johns Hopk<strong>in</strong>s University Press, 1988.Gesell, Silvio. e Natural Economic Order. San Antonio, Tex.: Free <strong>Economy</strong>Publish<strong>in</strong>g, 1934.Hansson, Björn. “Forced Sav<strong>in</strong>g.” In e New Palgrave Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Money &F<strong>in</strong>ance, edited by Peter Newman, Murray Milgate, <strong>and</strong> John Eatwell, vol. 2:140–142. New York: Stockton Press, 1992.McK<strong>in</strong>non, Ronald I. Money <strong>and</strong> Capital <strong>in</strong> Economic Development. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton,D.C.: Brook<strong>in</strong>gs Institution, 1973.Mundell, Robert. “Inflation <strong>and</strong> Real Interest.” Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> 71( June 1963): 280–283.. Monetary eory. Pacific Palisades, Calif.: Goodyear, 1971.


224 Part I: EconomicsPat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Don. Money, Interest, <strong>and</strong> Prices. 2ⁿ ed. New York: Harper & Row,1965.. “Real Balances.” 1987. In e New Palgrave Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Money &F<strong>in</strong>ance, edited by Peter Newman, Murray Milgate, <strong>and</strong> John Eatwell, vol. 3:295–298. New York: Stockton Press, 1992.Pigou, A.C. e Economics <strong>of</strong> Welfare. 1932. 4 ed. London: Macmillan, 1950.Rothbard, Murray N. Man, <strong>Economy</strong>, <strong>and</strong> State. 2 vols. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. VanNostr<strong>and</strong>, 1962.Scott, Anthony. Natural Resources: e Economics <strong>of</strong> Conservation. Toronto: University<strong>of</strong> Toronto Press, 1955.Shaw, Edward S. F<strong>in</strong>ancial Deepen<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Economic Development. New York:Oxford University Press, 1973.Short, Eugenie Dudd<strong>in</strong>g. “A New Look at Real Money Balances as a Variable <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> Production Function.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Money, Credit, <strong>and</strong> Bank<strong>in</strong>g 11 (August1979): 326–339.Tob<strong>in</strong>, James. “Money <strong>and</strong> Economic Growth.” Econometrica 33 (October 1965):671–684.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “Injection Effects <strong>and</strong> Monetary Intermediation.” In e Flutter<strong>in</strong>gVeil, edited by George Selg<strong>in</strong>. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1997.


Tacit Preachments are<strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d * Some years ago I gave a talk on “e Curse <strong>of</strong> Methodology.” at unfortunatetitle appeared to deny that methodology comes <strong>in</strong> good varietiesas well as bad. Still, good methodology is mostly countermethodology,which strives to free work<strong>in</strong>g economists from methodological pressures.e worst preachments, which were <strong>and</strong> rema<strong>in</strong> my ma<strong>in</strong> target, are<strong>the</strong> pervasive, tacit, dimly identified k<strong>in</strong>d. Countermethodology can drag<strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> open, expos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m to <strong>in</strong>spection <strong>and</strong>, when appropriate,to ridicule. As if to ward <strong>of</strong>f this exposure, however, <strong>the</strong> practitioners <strong>of</strong>tacit methodology appear to taboo explicit method-talk. I <strong>of</strong>fer this <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r remarks about <strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong> academic economicsnot as confident assertions but as conjectures <strong>and</strong> as possible explanations<strong>of</strong> what we do observe. We have an opportunity to confess our suspicions<strong>and</strong> to compare <strong>and</strong> check <strong>the</strong>m out. I quote <strong>and</strong> paraphrase scholarswhose writ<strong>in</strong>gs document my po<strong>in</strong>ts or who share my perceptions <strong>and</strong>I also use footnotes all more extensively than precepts <strong>of</strong> good writ<strong>in</strong>gstyle might o<strong>the</strong>rwise recommend. Invok<strong>in</strong>g respectable company itselfproves noth<strong>in</strong>g, but it assuages my uneas<strong>in</strong>ess.In part, admittedly, I’ll be express<strong>in</strong>g personal pique. Even some experienceswith explicit methodologiz<strong>in</strong>g prod me. ey <strong>in</strong>clude all too many“Austrian” sem<strong>in</strong>ars at two or three universities <strong>in</strong> which discussion rout<strong>in</strong>elydegenerated from <strong>the</strong> substantive to <strong>the</strong> methodological. I have seendissertation-writers (at <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia) badgered about what<strong>the</strong>ir models might be or what hypo<strong>the</strong>ses <strong>the</strong>y were test<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>and</strong> have*From Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic Methodology 2, no. 1 ( June 1995): 1–33. “[M]ethod-talk is asserted to be taboo <strong>in</strong> economics, when <strong>in</strong> fact it is surpassed <strong>in</strong>its ubiquity only by discussion <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people’s salaries” (Mirowski 1992, p. 236).225


226 Part I: Economicsexperienced some badger<strong>in</strong>g myself ). I have heard all too much praise <strong>of</strong>methodological articles that did not rise above po<strong>in</strong>tless pr<strong>of</strong>undity. Some economists, <strong>the</strong>n, though a m<strong>in</strong>ority, are fasc<strong>in</strong>ated with methodology.Why? Could <strong>the</strong>y be delighted with <strong>the</strong>ir own breadth <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g,as <strong>in</strong> epistemology <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> science? Could <strong>the</strong>y believethat such pr<strong>of</strong>undity <strong>and</strong> wisdom must have great significance, somehow,for <strong>the</strong>ir own field? Perhaps it helps make a splash to propose import<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>to economics, even without reference to any genu<strong>in</strong>e questions orproblems, ideas <strong>and</strong> techniques lifted from o<strong>the</strong>r fields. Examples <strong>in</strong>cludenotions <strong>of</strong> Newtonian <strong>and</strong> Bergsonian time, concepts <strong>of</strong> hermeneutics,psychological notions, <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical techniques from eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g.Far be it from me to taboo such borrow<strong>in</strong>gs, but <strong>the</strong> test should benot whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y confer a supposed cachet on <strong>the</strong> borrowers but whe<strong>the</strong>r<strong>the</strong>y fur<strong>the</strong>r genu<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>vestigations. Nor do I want to lecture methodologistsaga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> pleasure <strong>of</strong> wallow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir favorite pr<strong>of</strong>undities—notunless <strong>the</strong>y expect o<strong>the</strong>r people admir<strong>in</strong>gly to jo<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>.Methodologists get a h<strong>and</strong>le on o<strong>the</strong>r people as teachers, dissertationsupervisors, journal editors <strong>and</strong> referees, conference organizers, participants<strong>in</strong> tenure <strong>and</strong> promotion decisions, writers <strong>of</strong> letters <strong>of</strong> recommendation,<strong>and</strong> members <strong>of</strong> fellowship <strong>and</strong> research committees. People <strong>in</strong>such roles almost necessarily issue advice or apply requirements. osepeople may deserve some advice <strong>in</strong> turn, even though it may sound likemethodology itself.Donald McCloskey (1985, esp. pp. 24–26) dist<strong>in</strong>guishes three levels<strong>of</strong> methodology. e bottom level, unobjectionable <strong>and</strong> necessary, consists<strong>of</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g nuts <strong>and</strong> bolts like how to construct an Edgeworth box,run a regression, <strong>and</strong> punctuate a sentence. e top level, “Sprachethik,”also unobjectionable, calls for constructive dialogue. Scholars should try tocommunicate clearly <strong>and</strong> avoid shout<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r tricks <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>timidation.On <strong>the</strong> middle level we f<strong>in</strong>d pronouncements about ma<strong>the</strong>matics,econometrics, model<strong>in</strong>g, empiricism, armchair <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g, methodological<strong>in</strong>dividualism, use <strong>of</strong> aggregates <strong>and</strong> averages, use <strong>of</strong> questionnaires,experimentation, <strong>and</strong> so on. Methodologists discuss whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> supposedmethods <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural sciences belong <strong>in</strong> economics, whe<strong>the</strong>r Paul Samuelson was avowedly jok<strong>in</strong>g, but probably only half-jok<strong>in</strong>g, when hereported a negative correlation between <strong>the</strong> fruitfulness <strong>of</strong> scientific discipl<strong>in</strong>es <strong>and</strong> “<strong>the</strong>irpropensity to engage <strong>in</strong> methodological discussion.... [S]<strong>of</strong>t sciences spend time <strong>in</strong> talk<strong>in</strong>gabout method because Satan f<strong>in</strong>ds tasks for idle h<strong>and</strong>s to do. Nature does abhor avacuum, <strong>and</strong> hot air fills up more space than cold” (1963, <strong>in</strong> Caldwell 1984, p. 188).


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 227economics is more like physics or biology, whe<strong>the</strong>r notions from anthropology<strong>and</strong> literary criticism <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r discipl<strong>in</strong>es should be imported,<strong>and</strong> what should be regarded as <strong>the</strong> Lakatosian hard core <strong>of</strong> economics.Such middle-level methodologiz<strong>in</strong>g is presumptuous <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficious. Anyone who has refereed for journals knows that hitch<strong>in</strong>g ont<strong>of</strong>ads, rout<strong>in</strong>e orig<strong>in</strong>ality, unnecessary polemics, pretentiousness, tedium,<strong>and</strong> bad writ<strong>in</strong>g abound. Methodology will hardly remedy <strong>the</strong>se defectsbecause, for one th<strong>in</strong>g, no s<strong>in</strong>gle best method is available. e academicdivision <strong>of</strong> labor leaves no presumption that all researchers should tackle<strong>the</strong> same problems <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same way. e methodologist “undertakes to second-guess <strong>the</strong> scientific community”; he“claims prescience,” “pretends to know how to achieve knowledge before <strong>the</strong> knowledgeto be achieved is <strong>in</strong> place,” <strong>in</strong>sists on “an artificially narrowed range <strong>of</strong> argument,” <strong>and</strong>“lay[s] down legislation for science on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> epistemological convictions held with avehemence <strong>in</strong>versely proportional to <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> evidence that <strong>the</strong>y work” (McCloskey1985, pp. 20, 36, 53, 139).e particular examples <strong>of</strong> exhortation <strong>and</strong> taboo mentioned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> text are more m<strong>in</strong>ethan McCloskey’s. K. Klappholz <strong>and</strong> J. Agassi deplore “<strong>the</strong> illusion that <strong>the</strong>re can exist <strong>in</strong> any sciencemethodological rules <strong>the</strong> mere adoption <strong>of</strong> which will hasten its progress” <strong>and</strong> warnaga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> “belief that, if only economists adopted this or that methodological rule, <strong>the</strong>road ahead would at least be cleared (<strong>and</strong> possibly <strong>the</strong> traffic would move briskly alongit).” ey will heed only <strong>the</strong> general “exhortation to be critical <strong>and</strong> always ready to subjectone’s hypo<strong>the</strong>ses to critical scrut<strong>in</strong>y.” Additional rules to re<strong>in</strong>force this general maxim are“likely to be futile <strong>and</strong> possibly harmful” (1959, pp. 60, 74).e physicist P.W. Bridgman liked to say that<strong>the</strong>re is no scientific method as such, but that <strong>the</strong> most vital feature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> scientist’sprocedure has been merely to do his utmost with his m<strong>in</strong>d, no holds barred. ismeans <strong>in</strong> particular that no special privileges are accorded to authority or to tradition,that personal prejudices <strong>and</strong> predilections are carefully guarded aga<strong>in</strong>st, thatone makes cont<strong>in</strong>ued check to assure oneself that one is not mak<strong>in</strong>g mistakes, <strong>and</strong>that any l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>quiry will be followed that appears at all promis<strong>in</strong>g.... e so-calledscientific method is merely a special case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> method <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence, <strong>and</strong> any apparentlyunique characteristics are to be expla<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject matterra<strong>the</strong>r than ascribed to <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> method itself. (Bridgman 1955, p. 544)I th<strong>in</strong>k that <strong>the</strong> objectives <strong>of</strong> all scientists have this <strong>in</strong> common—that <strong>the</strong>y are alltry<strong>in</strong>g to get <strong>the</strong> correct answer to <strong>the</strong> particular problem <strong>in</strong> h<strong>and</strong>.... What appearsto [<strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g scientist] as <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> situation is that he is not consciouslyfollow<strong>in</strong>g any prescribed course <strong>of</strong> action, but feels complete freedom to utilize anymethod or device whatever which <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular situation before him seems likelyto yield <strong>the</strong> correct answer. In his attack on his specific problem he suffers no <strong>in</strong>hibitions<strong>of</strong> precedent or authority, but is completely free to adopt any course that his<strong>in</strong>genuity is capable <strong>of</strong> suggest<strong>in</strong>g to him. No one st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> outside can predict


228 Part I: EconomicsWhe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> natural <strong>and</strong> social sciences are fundamentally similar orfundamentally different is a po<strong>in</strong>tless concern. What does “fundamental”mean? All sciences seek propositions <strong>of</strong> generality <strong>and</strong> depth (Bauer 1959),seek uniformity amidst superficial diversity, <strong>and</strong> try to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>itiallypuzzl<strong>in</strong>g phenomena as examples <strong>of</strong> familiar or potentially familiar generalizations,so that curiosity rests (evok<strong>in</strong>g Machlup’s “aha!”). Success <strong>in</strong>prediction streng<strong>the</strong>ns <strong>the</strong> scientist’s hunch that he has found <strong>the</strong> correctexplanation <strong>of</strong> some phenomenon. All sciences presumably <strong>in</strong>volve whatKarl Popper called “conjectures <strong>and</strong> refutations.” All presumably presupposesimilar ideals <strong>of</strong> scientific <strong>in</strong>tegrity <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> openness to critical exam<strong>in</strong>ation.On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, any two sciences differ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir specific subjectmatters <strong>and</strong> so <strong>in</strong> what k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> empirical observation enter <strong>in</strong>to arous<strong>in</strong>gcuriosity, <strong>in</strong>spir<strong>in</strong>g conjectures, <strong>and</strong> sift<strong>in</strong>g hypo<strong>the</strong>ses. Human purposiveness<strong>and</strong> free choice play a role <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> social sciences that <strong>the</strong>y cannot play<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural sciences. Whe<strong>the</strong>r this makes <strong>the</strong> two fields fundamentallydifferent is a mere semantic question. Here are some signs <strong>of</strong> poorly articulated methodological th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g:• Rout<strong>in</strong>e questions such as: What hypo<strong>the</strong>sis are you test<strong>in</strong>g? Howcould it be falsified? What is your model?what <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual scientist will do or what method he will follow ... <strong>the</strong>re are asmany scientific methods as <strong>the</strong>re are <strong>in</strong>dividual scientists. (pp. 82–83)Question<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> assumption <strong>of</strong> one or a few best methods, Fritz Machlup identifies <strong>the</strong>harmfulattitude <strong>of</strong> snubb<strong>in</strong>g, disparag<strong>in</strong>g, excommunicat<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> prohibit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>ghabits <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> preach<strong>in</strong>g a methodology that implies that <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong>ferior<strong>in</strong> scientific workmanship. [Machlup’s footnote below.]Good “scientific method” must not proscribe any technique <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>quiry deemed usefulby an honest <strong>and</strong> experienced scholar. e aggressiveness <strong>and</strong> restrictiveness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>various methodological beliefs which social scientists have developed—<strong>in</strong> subconsciousattempts to compensate for <strong>the</strong>ir feel<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>feriority vis-a-vis <strong>the</strong> alleged“true scientist”—are deplorable. Attempts to establish a monopoly for one method,to use moral suasion <strong>and</strong> public defamation to exclude o<strong>the</strong>rs, produce harmfulrestra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> research <strong>and</strong> analysis, seriously retard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir progress.[Footnote:] ... I have not said anyth<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g habits <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>and</strong>have not questioned anybody’s scientific workmanship. I have dealt with <strong>the</strong>ir claims<strong>of</strong> exclusive possession <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> one <strong>and</strong> only scientific method. (Machlup 1956/1978,p. 344 <strong>in</strong> chap. 13)


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 229• e prestige <strong>of</strong> falsifiability, with misconceptions about it be<strong>in</strong>g re<strong>in</strong>forcedby <strong>the</strong> slogan aga<strong>in</strong>st test<strong>in</strong>g a <strong>the</strong>ory by its assumptions to <strong>the</strong>degree that downright false propositions share <strong>in</strong> its supposed prestige.(A warn<strong>in</strong>g is valid, however, aga<strong>in</strong>st ostensibly empirical propositionsso constructed as to enjoy built-<strong>in</strong> immunity to any adverse evidence.)• e prestige <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> polar extremes <strong>of</strong> abstract, high-power <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> empirical work, with what counts as “empirical” be<strong>in</strong>g practicallyconf<strong>in</strong>ed to statistics.• e associated idea that familiar, dependable facts are by that verytoken unimportant.• Knee-jerk <strong>in</strong>sistence on certa<strong>in</strong> styles <strong>of</strong> argumentation <strong>and</strong> particularlyon “rigor” (about which I’ll have more to say).• e prestige <strong>of</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> frontier.Examples abound <strong>of</strong> methodological preconceptions practically foreorda<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gconclusions or shield<strong>in</strong>g shaky argument or dubious assumptionsfrom scrut<strong>in</strong>y. ey <strong>in</strong>clude (<strong>in</strong> my op<strong>in</strong>ion) <strong>the</strong> “Austrian” <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle, <strong>the</strong> “pure-time-preference” <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest, London-School skepticism <strong>of</strong> cost-oriented bus<strong>in</strong>ess regulation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>of</strong> anyobjective content <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> very concept <strong>of</strong> cost, <strong>the</strong> rational-expectationsschool’s <strong>in</strong>sistence on equilibrium model<strong>in</strong>g, Milton Friedman’s Marshalli<strong>and</strong>em<strong>and</strong> curve, <strong>and</strong> widespread m<strong>in</strong>dless recitation <strong>of</strong> Friedman’s sloganabout not test<strong>in</strong>g a <strong>the</strong>ory by its assumptions.In macroeconomics, <strong>the</strong> shift <strong>of</strong> fashion from monetarism to its newclassicalversion <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n on to real bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycles appears to exhibit amethodological basis (as well as some factors discussed later). David Laidler(1990) <strong>and</strong> Karl Brunner (1989) have diagnosed as much, mention<strong>in</strong>gan impatience with disequilibrium analysis <strong>and</strong> a shift <strong>of</strong> priorities awayfrom empirical evidence toward supposed first pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, micr<strong>of</strong>oundations,<strong>and</strong> rigor. e new classical macroeconomics, or rational-expectations/equilibriumalwaysschool, provides examples. (Citations <strong>and</strong> fuller discussion appear<strong>in</strong> my 1986, pp. 386–393.) e Lucas supply function (Lucas 1973) dealswith cyclical fluctuations <strong>in</strong> aggregate output on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> methodologicalpreconception that sellers are respond<strong>in</strong>g to prices only, ra<strong>the</strong>r


230 Part I: Economicsthan also to how readily <strong>the</strong>y are f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g customers. Notions <strong>of</strong> pure competitionlurk below <strong>the</strong> surface: <strong>the</strong> seller can sell all he desires at <strong>the</strong> go<strong>in</strong>gprice.eorists <strong>in</strong> this camp seem to believe that monetary expansion, forexample, <strong>and</strong> unexpected monetary expansion <strong>in</strong> particular, can have animpact on real variables only through price changes—unexpected <strong>and</strong>mis<strong>in</strong>terpreted changes—<strong>and</strong> not directly, as by giv<strong>in</strong>g sellers more customers.e rival monetary-disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory can <strong>in</strong>terpret recoveryfrom depression <strong>in</strong> a more straightforward way than is available to a <strong>the</strong>oristunwill<strong>in</strong>g to recognize disequilibrium <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place.e idea seems to be afoot <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> circles (or was for a while) thatequilibrium model<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g—<strong>the</strong> technically advanced th<strong>in</strong>g—tobe do<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics. Robert Lucas <strong>and</strong> admirers (Lucas 1980,pp. 697, 708; Willes 1980, pp. 90, 92) recommended <strong>the</strong>ir br<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> equilibriumeconomics for employ<strong>in</strong>g technical advances <strong>in</strong> model<strong>in</strong>g that simplywere unavailable a few years earlier.Lucas <strong>and</strong> Sargent (1978, p. 58) appeared to congratulate <strong>the</strong>mselveson <strong>the</strong> “dramatic development” that <strong>the</strong> very mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term “equilibrium”had undergone. Sargent (<strong>in</strong>terviewed <strong>in</strong> Klamer 1983, pp. 67–68)expressed satisfaction with “fancier” notions <strong>of</strong> equilibrium, “much morecomplicated” notions <strong>of</strong> market-clear<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> “fancy new k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> equilibriummodels.” Well, to recommend destabiliz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> words,subvert<strong>in</strong>g communication, is <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> methodologiz<strong>in</strong>g that needs tobe dragged <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> open <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>spected.Suggest<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> sheer commitment to a cherished <strong>the</strong>oreticaltradition, Herschel Grossman (1983, p. 240) wrote:e position that strict application <strong>of</strong> neoclassical maximization postulatesis relevant to macroeconomic developments only <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> “long-run”may seem reasonable from an empirical st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t, but it puts neoclassicaleconomics <strong>in</strong> a defensive position. It suggests <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> ageneral <strong>in</strong>ability <strong>of</strong> neoclassical economics to account for short-run economicphenomena.Yet despite <strong>the</strong> apparent implication here, disequilibrium is not <strong>in</strong>compatiblewith <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ efforts to maximize.e idea seems to be <strong>in</strong> circulation that an economist who talks aboutdisequilibrium is really talk<strong>in</strong>g not about market failure but about his ownfailure as a model-builder. It is methodologically unfashionable to speak<strong>of</strong> prices <strong>and</strong> quantities that are not at <strong>the</strong>ir equilibrium values but are only


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 231tend<strong>in</strong>g toward <strong>the</strong>m at speeds specified only <strong>in</strong> ad hoc ways. In this connection,Lucas (1980) scorns models conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g “free parameters.” Observ<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g about disequilibrium processes <strong>in</strong> a straightforward <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>refore relatively nonma<strong>the</strong>matical manner can be stigmatized as casual<strong>and</strong> loose, so <strong>the</strong>y escape due attention.Equilibrium-always <strong>the</strong>orists presumably know as well as anyone elsethat atomistic competition is <strong>and</strong> must be <strong>the</strong> exception ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong>rule <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> real world, that sellers are typically not sell<strong>in</strong>g as much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>iroutput or labor as <strong>the</strong>y would like to sell at prevail<strong>in</strong>g prices, that mostprices <strong>and</strong> wages are not determ<strong>in</strong>ed impersonally but are consciouslydecided upon (even though decided with an eye on supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>),<strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r circumstances cause or reveal price stick<strong>in</strong>ess. But<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orists do not know <strong>the</strong>se facts <strong>of</strong>ficially, not <strong>in</strong> a methodologicallyreputable way.ey are <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to recite <strong>the</strong> slogan that (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> paraphrase <strong>of</strong> Willes1980, p. 91) “<strong>the</strong>ories cannot be judged by <strong>the</strong> realism <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir assumptions,”a slogan reasonable enough <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> contexts <strong>and</strong> under certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretations,yet much abused. Actually, it is necessary to dist<strong>in</strong>guish atleast between simplify<strong>in</strong>g assumptions that abstract from unimportantdetails <strong>and</strong> assumptions on which <strong>the</strong> conclusions crucially depend. (AlanMusgrave, 1981, makes enlighten<strong>in</strong>g dist<strong>in</strong>ctions between negligibility,doma<strong>in</strong>, <strong>and</strong> heuristic assumptions.)What assumptions are acceptable simplifications <strong>and</strong> what ones arecrucial to <strong>the</strong> conclusions depends on <strong>the</strong> question at h<strong>and</strong>. “[A]n ecologistconcerned about pollution may treat <strong>the</strong> Black Sea as a closed body<strong>of</strong> water, <strong>the</strong> Straits <strong>of</strong> Marmara be<strong>in</strong>g sufficiently narrow for that. Butsomeone consider<strong>in</strong>g how to ship goods from London to Odessa shouldnot” (Mayer 1993, p. 38). In <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> long-run effects on relativeprices <strong>and</strong> quantities <strong>of</strong> a specified change <strong>in</strong> wants, resources, technology,or taxes, it is convenient to assume that competition is pure <strong>and</strong> thatmarkets clear. <strong>in</strong>gs are different <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics, whose very subjectmatter is <strong>the</strong> lapses that do sometimes occur from a high degree <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>of</strong> radically decentralized decisions <strong>and</strong> activities. When one is<strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g how <strong>and</strong> why separate but <strong>in</strong>terdependent markets fall short<strong>of</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g to perfection, it is fatuous to <strong>in</strong>sist that <strong>the</strong>y are always <strong>in</strong> equilibriumanyway. More generally, it is fatuous to work with assumptionsthat rule out <strong>the</strong> questions to be faced. (It is important, by <strong>the</strong> way, asKarl Popper taught, to have a question or problem to work on, not a meretopic; Bartley 1990, p. 159.)


232 Part I: EconomicsRobert Clower <strong>and</strong> Paul Krugman are among <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ority <strong>of</strong> economistswho have spoken out emphatically aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> methodology-drivenexcesses <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> equilibrium-always approach. “[T]he approaches <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Keynesians, monetarists, <strong>and</strong> new classical economists to monetary <strong>the</strong>ory<strong>and</strong> macroeconomics will get us exactly nowhere,” Clower writes, “becauseeach is founded, one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r, on <strong>the</strong> conventional but empiricallyfallacious assumption that <strong>the</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> economic activitiesis costless.” While established value <strong>the</strong>ory has <strong>in</strong>disputable merits, “forsome purposes, such as <strong>the</strong> fruitful analysis <strong>of</strong> ongo<strong>in</strong>g processes <strong>of</strong> monetaryexchange, models <strong>of</strong> a very different k<strong>in</strong>d may be required” (1984,“Afterword,” p. 272).e “Lucas Project,” as Paul Krugman calls it, tried “to build bus<strong>in</strong>esscycle<strong>the</strong>ory on maximiz<strong>in</strong>g micr<strong>of</strong>oundations.... e ramshackle, ad hoc<strong>in</strong>tellectual structures <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1950s <strong>and</strong> 1960s were ruthlessly cleared away,mak<strong>in</strong>g room for <strong>the</strong> erection <strong>of</strong> a new structure to be based on securemicr<strong>of</strong>oundations. Unfortunately, that structure never got built” (Krugman1993, pp. 15–16). e Lucas Project “destroy[ed] <strong>the</strong> old regime butfailed to create a workable new macroeconomics.... e true believers <strong>in</strong>equilibrium bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycles shifted to real-bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle <strong>the</strong>ory” (p. 16).“[R]ational-expectations macroeconomics ... collapsed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> itsown <strong>in</strong>ternal contradictions,” leav<strong>in</strong>g macroeconomics <strong>in</strong> “a terrible state”(p. 18).In Krugman’s view, “<strong>the</strong> effort to expla<strong>in</strong> away <strong>the</strong> apparent real effects<strong>of</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al shocks is silly, even if one restricts oneself to domestic evidence.Once one confronts <strong>in</strong>ternational evidence, however, it becomes an act <strong>of</strong>almost pathological denial” (1993, p. 17). Krugman mentions tight correlationbetween nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>and</strong> real exchange rates (p. 16). F<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ternationalmacroeconomics <strong>in</strong> a pa<strong>in</strong>ful dilemma, Krugman alludes to fads<strong>and</strong> tacit methodologiz<strong>in</strong>g: “to write a macroeconomic model with stickyprices is pr<strong>of</strong>essionally dangerous, but to write one without such rigiditiesis empirically ridiculous” (p. 17). “It’s easy to be cynical about <strong>the</strong> motivations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> people who write <strong>the</strong>se papers.You don’t progress as an economics pr<strong>of</strong>essor by solv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> real problems <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> real economy,at least not <strong>in</strong> any direct way. Instead, you progress by conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g your colleaguesthat you are clever. In an ideal world you would demonstrate your cleverness by develop<strong>in</strong>gbl<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gly orig<strong>in</strong>al ideas or produc<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>itive evidence about how <strong>the</strong> economyactually works. But most <strong>of</strong> us can’t do that, at least not consistently. So pr<strong>of</strong>essors lookfor more surefire approaches. And thus <strong>the</strong> most popular economic <strong>the</strong>ories among <strong>the</strong>pr<strong>of</strong>essors tend to be those that best allow for <strong>in</strong>genious elaboration without fundamental


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 233 - : One broad message <strong>of</strong> omas Mayer’s book <strong>of</strong> 1993 is that academic economicsis driven not only by economic reality but also by features <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>game itself. Economists attuned to <strong>the</strong> academic game “frequently act asthough <strong>the</strong> strength <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir whole argument is equal to <strong>the</strong> strength <strong>of</strong> itsstrongest l<strong>in</strong>k” (1993, p. x). (is strongest-l<strong>in</strong>k analogy recurs repeatedly<strong>and</strong> appropriately, as on pp. 57–63, 80, 127–130. I myself have long used it,for it is an obvious one.) One form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> bias toward excessive formalization“is to lavish tender lov<strong>in</strong>g care on those steps <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> argument thatare rigorous, while pay<strong>in</strong>g little attention to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r steps” (p. 66). Arelated str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> tacit methodology is reductionism—<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sistence thatall macroeconomics be reduced to microeconomics (pp. 90–97; compare<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sistence that psychology be reduced to chemistry <strong>and</strong> ultimately tophysics).“Rigor” is <strong>of</strong>ten taken as self-evidently crucial to respectable economics.At a department meet<strong>in</strong>g years ago, discussion <strong>of</strong> a proposed course<strong>in</strong> portfolio management did not concern what <strong>of</strong> substance <strong>the</strong> studentsmight learn, or how its subject matter might relate to <strong>the</strong> body <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>novation—ways to show that you are smart by putt<strong>in</strong>g old w<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> new bottles, usuallywith fancier ma<strong>the</strong>matical labels” (Krugman 1994, p. 8).“[T]he technicality <strong>and</strong> difficulty <strong>of</strong> Lucas’s [bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle] <strong>the</strong>ory ... was, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world<strong>of</strong> academic economics, an asset ra<strong>the</strong>r than a liability. It is cynical but true to say that<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> academic world <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories that are most likely to attract a devoted follow<strong>in</strong>gare those that best allow a clever but not very orig<strong>in</strong>al young man to demonstrate hiscleverness. is has been true <strong>of</strong> deconstructionist literary <strong>the</strong>ory; it has equally been true<strong>of</strong> equilibrium bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle <strong>the</strong>ory. It turned out that Lucas’s <strong>in</strong>itial <strong>the</strong>ory naturally ledto <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> a whole new set <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical <strong>and</strong> statistical techniques. A firstset <strong>of</strong> Lucas disciples made academic reputations develop<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se techniques; later waves<strong>of</strong> students <strong>in</strong>vested large amounts <strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong> effort learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>and</strong> were loath toconsider <strong>the</strong> possibility that <strong>the</strong> view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy to which <strong>the</strong>ir specialized tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gwas appropriate might be wrong. Indeed, Lucas himself has <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> end seemed more<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> his techniques than <strong>in</strong> what he does with <strong>the</strong>m” (Krugman 1994, p. 52).In Krugman’s view, political bias also helped make rational-expectations macroeconomicsattractive (1994, pp. 52–53).Mayer also testifies to tacit methodology at work: “New classicals expla<strong>in</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>esscycles as mostly due to supply shocks because a dem<strong>and</strong>-side explanation is <strong>in</strong>consistentwith <strong>the</strong>ir chosen Walrasian market clear<strong>in</strong>g paradigm” (1993, p. 116).Mirowski (1992, pp. 241–247) <strong>and</strong> McCloskey (1992, p. 266) tell <strong>the</strong> story <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> suppression<strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>vited conference paper by Lawrence Summers (an em<strong>in</strong>ent economist,certa<strong>in</strong>ly, associated with New Keynesianism) because <strong>of</strong> frankness about methodologysimilar to that <strong>of</strong> Krugman <strong>and</strong> Mayer. Summers had entitled his paper “e ScientificIllusion <strong>in</strong> Macroeconomics” (published elsewhere <strong>in</strong> 1991).


234 Part I: Economicseconomic <strong>the</strong>ory or to o<strong>the</strong>r courses <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> curriculum, or whe<strong>the</strong>r it mightduplicate exist<strong>in</strong>g courses. No, <strong>the</strong> overrid<strong>in</strong>g concern was with whe<strong>the</strong>r<strong>the</strong> prospective <strong>in</strong>structor would teach <strong>the</strong> course with due “rigor,” mean<strong>in</strong>g,<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context, teach it as an application <strong>of</strong> advanced ma<strong>the</strong>matics.Rigor does have its proper place. In ma<strong>the</strong>matics or formal logic—<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>se <strong>of</strong> course can enter <strong>in</strong>to an economist’s work—one does not wantlapses from due rigor; one does not tolerate ei<strong>the</strong>r mistakes or steps <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>argument where crude appeal to <strong>in</strong>tuition substitutes for logical entailment.Yet even <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics, excessive or premature <strong>in</strong>sistence on rigorcan impede progress (Lakatos 1976). Davis <strong>and</strong> Hersh identify a myth<strong>of</strong> totally rigorous <strong>and</strong> formalized ma<strong>the</strong>matics (1986, section on “Ma<strong>the</strong>matics<strong>and</strong> Rhetoric,” pp. 57–73). No one knows exactly what constitutesa ma<strong>the</strong>matical pro<strong>of</strong>. All pro<strong>of</strong>s fall short <strong>of</strong> complete formal logic <strong>and</strong>so <strong>of</strong> comm<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g absolute confidence. A ma<strong>the</strong>matical pro<strong>of</strong> written <strong>in</strong>complete logical detail would be unreadable <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>comprehensible. “Pr<strong>of</strong>essedlyrigorous pro<strong>of</strong>s usually have holes that are covered over by <strong>in</strong>tuition”(p. 69; an example follows). Pro<strong>of</strong> simply means pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong> enoughdetail to conv<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tended audience. e competent ma<strong>the</strong>maticianknows where his audience should focus <strong>the</strong>ir skepticism. ere he willsupply sufficient detail, abbreviat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> rest. Most ma<strong>the</strong>matical articles,Davis <strong>and</strong> Hersh add, do not get close scrut<strong>in</strong>y from ei<strong>the</strong>r referees orjournal readers.Garrett Hard<strong>in</strong> identifies such a th<strong>in</strong>g as “ma<strong>the</strong>matical machismo”(1986, p. 39). Arrogant numeracy can do harm. Lord Kelv<strong>in</strong> said, “[W]henyou cannot measure it <strong>in</strong> numbers, your knowledge is <strong>of</strong> a meagre <strong>and</strong>unsatisfactory k<strong>in</strong>d” (quoted <strong>in</strong> Hard<strong>in</strong> 1986, p. 39). Yet Kelv<strong>in</strong> radicallyunderestimated <strong>the</strong> age <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> earth, predicted that man would never fly <strong>in</strong>craft heavier than air, <strong>and</strong> predicted that any metal cooled almost to absolutezero would become an electric <strong>in</strong>sulator (p. 40). Many contributionsto science, as by Darw<strong>in</strong>, Pasteur, Kekulé, Harvey, Virchow, Pavlov, <strong>and</strong>Sherr<strong>in</strong>gton, have been much more qualitative than quantitative (p. 41).Even more so than ma<strong>the</strong>matical pro<strong>of</strong>s, knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> real worldsimply cannot be totally rigorous; <strong>in</strong>duction is not deduction.In Karl Brunner’s view, <strong>the</strong> new-classical <strong>and</strong> “M<strong>in</strong>nesota” school<strong>of</strong> macroeconomics, with its <strong>in</strong>sistence on beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> supposedbeg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g, commits what he called <strong>the</strong> “Cartesian fallacy.”e Cartesian tradition <strong>in</strong>sisted that all statements be derived froma small set <strong>of</strong> “first pr<strong>in</strong>ciples.” “Cogito ergo sum” <strong>and</strong> everyth<strong>in</strong>g else


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 235follows.... Anyth<strong>in</strong>g not derived from “first pr<strong>in</strong>ciples” does not countas knowledge. You are not allowed to talk about money if you have notderived from “first pr<strong>in</strong>ciples” a specification <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> items which aremoney. is methodological position is quite untenable <strong>and</strong> conflicts with<strong>the</strong> reality <strong>of</strong> our cognitive progress over history. Science rarely progressesby work<strong>in</strong>g “down from first pr<strong>in</strong>ciples”; it progresses <strong>and</strong> exp<strong>and</strong>s <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r way. We beg<strong>in</strong> with empirical regularities <strong>and</strong> go backward to more<strong>and</strong> more complicated hypo<strong>the</strong>ses <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories. Adherence to <strong>the</strong> Cartesianpr<strong>in</strong>ciple would condemn science to stagnation. ere are, moreover,as Karl Popper properly emphasized, no first pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. (Karl Brunner<strong>in</strong>terviewed <strong>in</strong> Klamer 1983, p. 195; compare Brunner 1989, pp. 225–227.)e Cartesian fallacy appears l<strong>in</strong>ked with what W.W. Bartley III(1984) called “justificationism.” An <strong>of</strong>ten unrecognized trait runn<strong>in</strong>gthrough <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> philosophy, justificationism is <strong>the</strong> expectation thatall propositions be justified (demonstrated, proved, warranted) by appealto some authority, whe<strong>the</strong>r reason <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> style <strong>of</strong> Descartes, empiricalobservation, div<strong>in</strong>e revelation, or some o<strong>the</strong>r def<strong>in</strong>itive source. But no<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g propositions can be justified <strong>in</strong> such a way. e dem<strong>and</strong> forjustification is a piece <strong>of</strong> ancient methodology carried forward uncritically<strong>in</strong>to modern discussion (1984, p. 221 <strong>in</strong> particular). Bartley rejectsjustificationism <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Popperian process <strong>of</strong> conjectures <strong>and</strong> refutations.Scientists <strong>in</strong>vent laws <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>and</strong> devise ways <strong>of</strong> w<strong>in</strong>now<strong>in</strong>gout wrong ones. It is reasonable to accept, tentatively, laws <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>oriesnot yet rejected on logical or empirical grounds <strong>and</strong> not yet displacedby more attractive alternatives. Accept<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> that way is not <strong>the</strong>same, however, as hold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m to have been justified or proved; for positivejustification is downright impossible. We cannot criticize all <strong>of</strong> ourbeliefs all at <strong>the</strong> same time. Criticism <strong>of</strong> particular propositions or <strong>the</strong>oriesmust employ o<strong>the</strong>rs—notably, st<strong>and</strong>ard logic—taken as valid for <strong>the</strong>purpose at h<strong>and</strong>. But none <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se is exempt from criticism <strong>in</strong> all contexts.Although we cannot criticize everyth<strong>in</strong>g at once, noth<strong>in</strong>g is properlyimmune aga<strong>in</strong>st any criticism <strong>in</strong> all circumstances <strong>and</strong> contexts. (See<strong>the</strong> many pages on justification <strong>and</strong> justificationism cited <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dex toBartley 1984.) : Years ago a graduate-student advisee reported to me <strong>the</strong> expectations <strong>of</strong>ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> his advisors: he must build his dissertation around a model.


236 Part I: Economics“Why?” <strong>the</strong> student asked. “I don’t know,” was <strong>the</strong> reported reply, “you’vejust got to have a model.” e o<strong>the</strong>r advisor reportedly went on to say thatif <strong>the</strong> student expected to get his dissertation past certa<strong>in</strong> members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>department, he would have to do work <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>y expected.Such sermoniz<strong>in</strong>g seldom appears <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>t <strong>and</strong> fully articulated, whichis why it can be so <strong>in</strong>sidious. Although <strong>in</strong>fluential, it escapes critical exam<strong>in</strong>ation.I wish economists would drag it <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> open by recount<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irexperiences with it. (Mayer makes a good beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> his 1993, chap. 9,entitled “Model or Die.”)One little episode <strong>in</strong>volved me directly. Dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> discussion periodat a conference, I remarked that a particular monetary reform would elim<strong>in</strong>ate<strong>the</strong> contagion <strong>of</strong> bank runs, <strong>and</strong> I briefly expla<strong>in</strong>ed why. Dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>fur<strong>the</strong>r discussion, <strong>and</strong> at greater length dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> c<strong>of</strong>fee break, ano<strong>the</strong>rconferee objected that if I <strong>and</strong> my coauthor expected anyone to underst<strong>and</strong>what we were say<strong>in</strong>g, we would have to argue <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> a model<strong>of</strong> bank runs, complete with specification <strong>of</strong> 100 persons, 47 commodities(or whatever <strong>the</strong> numbers might be), <strong>and</strong> so forth. If I had thought fast onmy feet, I would have pressed <strong>the</strong> question “Why?”. I would have askedmy <strong>in</strong>terlocutor to make his methodological sermon explicit <strong>and</strong> supportit with reasons. Unfortunately, <strong>the</strong> conversation w<strong>and</strong>ered <strong>of</strong>f.Months later, <strong>in</strong> conversation with Donald McCloskey, I wonderedabout <strong>the</strong> claims <strong>of</strong> some economists not to underst<strong>and</strong> arguments presentedoutside <strong>of</strong> formal models. McCloskey conjectured that <strong>the</strong>y meanwhat <strong>the</strong>y say: some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m are so wrapped up <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own models<strong>and</strong> favorite symbols that <strong>the</strong>y actually cannot underst<strong>and</strong> arguments presented<strong>in</strong> an unexpected language, English.Peter N. Irel<strong>and</strong> (1994) provides ano<strong>the</strong>r example <strong>of</strong> what bo<strong>the</strong>rs me.After mak<strong>in</strong>g sensible remarks about relations between money <strong>and</strong> economicgrowth, he goes on to give his argument supposed rigor with ma<strong>the</strong>matics<strong>and</strong> numerical simulations. He elaborates a model <strong>of</strong> a large number<strong>of</strong> identical, <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely lived households possess<strong>in</strong>g perfect foresight. Eachconsists <strong>of</strong> a worker <strong>and</strong> a shopper. Production functions have specific specialproperties. Perfect competition prevails. A cash-<strong>in</strong>-advance constra<strong>in</strong>tapplies to purchases made without <strong>the</strong> assistance <strong>of</strong> a f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>termediary.Yet if <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r special assumptions spelled out <strong>in</strong> great detail(about transactions costs <strong>and</strong> so forth) are not necessary for <strong>the</strong> conclusionsreached, what is <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m? And if <strong>the</strong>y are necessary, is itnot a great lapse from <strong>the</strong> trumpeted rigor to convey <strong>the</strong> impression that<strong>the</strong> conclusions reached apply to <strong>the</strong> messy real world anyway?


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 237In <strong>the</strong> same journal issue, Steve Williamson <strong>and</strong> R<strong>and</strong>all Wright(1994) expla<strong>in</strong> how money, besides provid<strong>in</strong>g its familiar services, cutsdown <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation requirements <strong>of</strong> exchange, giv<strong>in</strong>g transactors a betterchance than <strong>the</strong>y would have under barter to w<strong>in</strong>d up with high-qualitygoods. e authors’ model assumes away <strong>the</strong> non<strong>in</strong>formational difficulties<strong>of</strong> barter, leav<strong>in</strong>g no role for money <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> private <strong>in</strong>formation.Time is discrete <strong>and</strong> goes on forever. e population is a cont<strong>in</strong>uum<strong>of</strong> immortal agents who can produce both good <strong>and</strong> bad commoditiesat positive <strong>and</strong> zero utility cost, respectively. Consumption <strong>of</strong> money,<strong>of</strong> a bad commodity, or <strong>of</strong> one’s own output yields zero utility, whileconsumption <strong>of</strong> someone else’s good output does yield utility. Detailedassumptions about proportions <strong>of</strong> good <strong>and</strong> bad commodities, probabilities<strong>of</strong> encounters, <strong>and</strong> so forth create <strong>the</strong> opportunity for numerous equations<strong>and</strong> graphs add<strong>in</strong>g noth<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> central message, as far as I cansee, except spurious rigor. e authors give no reason for suppos<strong>in</strong>g thatwhat is rigorously true <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir concocted world is equally true <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> realworld.Robert Frank has done much <strong>in</strong>sightful writ<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tersection <strong>of</strong>economics, psychology, <strong>and</strong> ethics. His article <strong>of</strong> 1987, however, providesan example <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> merely decorative use <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical code, as dist<strong>in</strong>guishedfrom bona fide manipulation requir<strong>in</strong>g symbols. One footnote(1987, p. 595) even promises “a more reader-friendly version” <strong>of</strong> his model<strong>in</strong> a <strong>the</strong>n-forthcom<strong>in</strong>g book. Well, why wasn’t he friendly to his currentreaders? Bénassy’s article <strong>of</strong> 1993, which I admire for its actual substance, issimilarly discourteous <strong>in</strong> its use <strong>of</strong> symbols. Bénassy actually dist<strong>in</strong>guishesbetween certa<strong>in</strong> concepts by whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> identical double-subscripted lettersrepresent<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m are topped by a macron or by an only slightly wavytilde; this is a subtlety likely to escape a reader not wield<strong>in</strong>g a magnify<strong>in</strong>gglass. I suspect that he, like Frank, Irel<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Williamson <strong>and</strong> Wright,was bow<strong>in</strong>g to tacit methodological pressures.As Mayer’s strongest-l<strong>in</strong>k (or most-rigorous-l<strong>in</strong>k) pr<strong>in</strong>ciple suggests,a display <strong>of</strong> technique can plaster over much. Robert Solow was stay<strong>in</strong>gwith<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bounds <strong>of</strong> permissible exaggeration when he wrote (1985,p. 330) that a modern economist, dropped with his computer from a timemach<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>to any old time <strong>and</strong> place, will soonhave maximized a familiar-look<strong>in</strong>g present-value <strong>in</strong>tegral, made a fewfamiliar log-l<strong>in</strong>ear approximations, <strong>and</strong> run <strong>the</strong> obligatory familiar regression.e familiar coefficients will be poorly determ<strong>in</strong>ed, but about onetwentieth<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m will be significant at <strong>the</strong> 5 percent level, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r


238 Part I: Economicsn<strong>in</strong>eteen do not have to be published. With a little judicious selectionhere <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re, it will turn out that your data are just barely consistentwith your <strong>the</strong>sis adviser’s hypo<strong>the</strong>sis ... , modulo an <strong>in</strong>formationasymmetry, any old <strong>in</strong>formation asymmetry, don’t worry, you’ll th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong>one.Walter Eucken (1948, Pt. II, esp. pp. 192–193) criticized two ra<strong>the</strong>ropposite trends <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. Often <strong>the</strong> question is asked how th<strong>in</strong>gs wouldgo <strong>in</strong> an a priori model built with little reference to reality. e very fram<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> question excludes reality. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, Eucken cont<strong>in</strong>ues,analysis may work with crude, sweep<strong>in</strong>g concepts like “capitalism,” “laissezfaire,” or “socialism.” But both a priori models <strong>and</strong> imprecise “blanket”concepts can be <strong>of</strong> little help <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g reality.James Tob<strong>in</strong> (1980, p. 86) comments on overlapp<strong>in</strong>g-generations models<strong>of</strong> money. Long before, economists had already po<strong>in</strong>ted out how acommon medium <strong>of</strong> payment facilitates multilateral trade, whereas barterwould restrict transactions.e <strong>in</strong>sight tells us why <strong>the</strong> social <strong>in</strong>stitution <strong>of</strong> money has been observedthroughout history even <strong>in</strong> primitive societies. An <strong>in</strong>sight is not amodel, <strong>and</strong> it does not satisfy <strong>the</strong> tra<strong>in</strong>ed scholarly consciences <strong>of</strong> modern<strong>the</strong>orists who require that all values be rooted, explicitly <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matically,<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> market valuations <strong>of</strong> maximiz<strong>in</strong>g agents. But I must say <strong>in</strong> allirreverent c<strong>and</strong>or that as yet I do not feel significantly better enlightenedthan by <strong>the</strong> traditional <strong>in</strong>sight.Let me quote two physicists. Pierre Duhem (1954, esp. chap. IV) doesnot deny <strong>the</strong> usefulness <strong>of</strong> models. He recommends “<strong>in</strong>tellectual liberalism.”“Discovery is not subject to any fixed rule.... e best means <strong>of</strong>promot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> science is to permit each form <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectto develop itself by follow<strong>in</strong>g its own laws <strong>and</strong> realiz<strong>in</strong>g fully its type”(1954, pp. 98–99). Duhem questions <strong>the</strong> claim that provid<strong>in</strong>g a “mechanicalor algebraic model” for each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> chapters <strong>of</strong> physics satisfies all<strong>the</strong> legitimate wishes <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g (p. 100). Perhaps <strong>the</strong> most fruitfulprocedure <strong>in</strong> physics has been <strong>the</strong> search for analogies between dist<strong>in</strong>ctcategories <strong>of</strong> phenomena, but we should not confuse it with model<strong>in</strong>g(pp. 95–97). e use <strong>of</strong> mechanical models “has not brought to <strong>the</strong> progress<strong>of</strong> physics that rich contribution boasted for it.” Its contribution “seemsquite meager when we compare it with <strong>the</strong> opulent conquests <strong>of</strong> abstract<strong>the</strong>ories. e dist<strong>in</strong>guished physicists who have recommended <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong>models have used it [that method] far less as a means <strong>of</strong> discovery than asa method <strong>of</strong> exposition” (p. 99).


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 239Ronald Giere (1988, esp. chap. 3, “Models <strong>and</strong> eories”) describesmodels as stylizations or idealizations about which propositions hold morerigorously true than <strong>the</strong>y ever could about <strong>the</strong>ir possible counterparts <strong>in</strong>reality (cf. Hausman 1992, pp. 75–82, 273). F = ma <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r general “laws”<strong>of</strong> mechanics are not really empirical claims but more like general schemasthat need to be filled <strong>in</strong> (Giere 1988, p. 76). If <strong>the</strong> laws <strong>of</strong> motion, suchas <strong>the</strong> law <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pendulum, were to give a literally true <strong>and</strong> exact description<strong>of</strong> even <strong>the</strong> simplest <strong>of</strong> physical phenomena, <strong>the</strong>y would have to be<strong>in</strong>credibly more complex than any that could ever be written down. enonuniformity <strong>of</strong> gravity near <strong>the</strong> earth’s surface, <strong>the</strong> gravitational force <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> moon, nonl<strong>in</strong>earities <strong>in</strong> air resistance, <strong>and</strong> so forth would all have to betaken <strong>in</strong>to account. Idealization <strong>and</strong> approximation are <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong>empirical science (pp. 76–78). Hooke’s law “states that <strong>the</strong> force exerted bya spr<strong>in</strong>g is proportional to <strong>the</strong> amount it is stretched,” <strong>the</strong> constant <strong>of</strong> proportionalitybe<strong>in</strong>g “<strong>in</strong>terpreted as a measure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> stiffness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> spr<strong>in</strong>g”(p. 68). Such a statement presupposes certa<strong>in</strong> “idealizations,” such as that<strong>the</strong> spr<strong>in</strong>g is without mass <strong>and</strong> subject to no frictional forces, that <strong>the</strong>force-displacement is l<strong>in</strong>ear, that <strong>the</strong> attached mass is subject to no frictionalforces, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> wall is rigid, so <strong>the</strong> wall recoil due to motion <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> mass may be neglected (Giere, pp. 69–70). In mechanics, “e equationstruly describe <strong>the</strong> model because <strong>the</strong> model is def<strong>in</strong>ed as someth<strong>in</strong>gthat exactly satisfies <strong>the</strong> equations” (p. 79). (e physicist Henri Po<strong>in</strong>carérepeatedly <strong>in</strong>sisted on similar po<strong>in</strong>ts about <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> stylizations <strong>and</strong> conventions<strong>in</strong> science; see Yeager 1994, esp. pp. 161–162, <strong>and</strong> Po<strong>in</strong>caré’s writ<strong>in</strong>gscited <strong>the</strong>re.)Unlike a model, a <strong>the</strong>oretical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis is ... a statement assert<strong>in</strong>g somesort <strong>of</strong> relationship between a model <strong>and</strong> a designated real system (orclass <strong>of</strong> real systems).... e general form <strong>of</strong> a <strong>the</strong>oretical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis isthus: Such-<strong>and</strong>-such identifiable real system is similar to a designatedmodel <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicated respects <strong>and</strong> degrees. (Giere 1988, pp. 80–81)Lucas <strong>and</strong> Sargent (1978, p. 52) say <strong>in</strong> effect that anyone utter<strong>in</strong>g anyproposition <strong>of</strong> economics must, whe<strong>the</strong>r he realizes it or not, be work<strong>in</strong>gwith some sort <strong>of</strong> model <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d. It may be vague or clear, poor or good;but if <strong>the</strong> economist does not set forth his model explicitly, he is just hid<strong>in</strong>git from pr<strong>of</strong>essional scrut<strong>in</strong>y <strong>and</strong> criticism.<strong>Is</strong> it true, though, that one is necessarily work<strong>in</strong>g with a model? If <strong>the</strong>term “model” is stretched to cover any piece <strong>of</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>n it seemsa mere equivocation to <strong>in</strong>sist after all on a model <strong>in</strong> a narrower sense. If


240 Part I: Economics“model” means a complete set <strong>of</strong> equations specific enough to be ready foreconometric estimation, <strong>the</strong> answer is pretty clearly that <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orist isnot necessarily work<strong>in</strong>g with one. He may not want to restrict himself toany specific model because he believes that suitable ones differ widely <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ir details across times <strong>and</strong> places. Consider a model <strong>of</strong> our solar system.For some purposes we are <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> system’s specific, historicallyaccidental, features; <strong>and</strong> for such purposes, a detailed model is necessary.But for o<strong>the</strong>r purposes we want to emphasize propositions <strong>of</strong> wider application,such as those <strong>of</strong> gravity; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n it would be po<strong>in</strong>tless to be tieddown to a model <strong>of</strong> a particular solar system.Similarly <strong>in</strong> economics, propositions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort we hope to developmay not perta<strong>in</strong> to an economic system <strong>of</strong> one specific structure; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>na specific model may be mere clutter. As Ludwig von Mises once remarked(orally) about an econometric <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> watermelon market,none <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fundamental propositions <strong>of</strong> economics depends on <strong>the</strong> existence<strong>of</strong> such a commodity as watermelons. Nor, one might add, does anydepend on <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> such a country as <strong>the</strong> United States <strong>of</strong> America.In many contexts, by <strong>the</strong> same token, we are concerned with propositionsapplicable widely enough not to st<strong>and</strong> or fall on <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong>railroads or labor unions or negotiable certificates <strong>of</strong> deposit. What sort<strong>of</strong> model it may be legitimate to <strong>in</strong>sist on, if on any at all, thus dependson <strong>the</strong> purpose at h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> conceived scope <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> propositionsunder <strong>in</strong>vestigation.e <strong>in</strong>vestigator might recognize that he cannot produce a ma<strong>the</strong>maticalor econometric model with specific details yet wide applicability.He might be concerned, <strong>in</strong>stead, with <strong>the</strong> characteristics that any plausiblyrelevant model would have—if one <strong>in</strong>sists on speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> models. Hemight be seek<strong>in</strong>g Bauer’s “propositions <strong>of</strong> generality <strong>and</strong> depth.” Examples<strong>in</strong> economics <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> dim<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g marg<strong>in</strong>al returns,<strong>the</strong> law <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> money. ey enter <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>construction <strong>of</strong> widely different specific models. e <strong>in</strong>vestigator mightlegitimately be more concerned with such propositions <strong>the</strong>mselves thanwith one or ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir particular embodiments. Before one cansensibly construct a model, one must have some idea <strong>of</strong> what observedor conjectured or even merely postulated features <strong>of</strong> reality one is try<strong>in</strong>gto embody <strong>in</strong> it. One needs to know what relations <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terdependenceor cause <strong>and</strong> effect one is try<strong>in</strong>g to exhibit. In that sense, propositions(<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>the</strong>y employ) are logically prior to models. (Kosko1993, pp. 165, 169, 177, makes sensible remarks about models <strong>and</strong> about


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 241<strong>the</strong> frequent usefulness <strong>of</strong> “model-free estimation or approximation” <strong>and</strong>“model freedom.”)Far be it from me to taboo model<strong>in</strong>g, which can be a way <strong>of</strong> stimulat<strong>in</strong>g,organiz<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> present<strong>in</strong>g one’s thoughts. A burst <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>sistenceon model<strong>in</strong>g may even be justified if it is provoked by someone’s argumentthat is too vague, is phrased <strong>in</strong> idiosyncratic language, or rests onunstated assumptions. If so, challeng<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orist to put his argument<strong>in</strong>to graphs or equations may force him to make his assumptions <strong>and</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>gexplicit. More generally, translat<strong>in</strong>g an argument from one style<strong>in</strong>to ano<strong>the</strong>r may serve as a check on one’s reason<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> improve communication.(omas Hobbes made a noteworthy case for <strong>the</strong> translationtest <strong>in</strong> 1651/1968, chaps. 8 <strong>and</strong> 46.) While translation can <strong>in</strong>deedbe beneficial, <strong>the</strong> logical priority <strong>of</strong> propositions over models embody<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>m casts doubt on <strong>in</strong>sistence on model<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>the</strong> only legitimate wayto develop <strong>and</strong> communicate propositions. What warrant, <strong>the</strong>n, does acritic have for accus<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>vestigator <strong>of</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g disreputablycryptic—namely, work<strong>in</strong>g with a model while protect<strong>in</strong>g it from <strong>in</strong>spection—whenhe may not be work<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> model<strong>in</strong>g stage at all? e recent vogue <strong>of</strong> real-bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle models has produced econometricstudies purportedly discredit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> more traditional focus on moneyas a source <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess fluctuations. Econometric studies enjoy <strong>the</strong> recommendations<strong>of</strong> explicit <strong>and</strong> tacit methodology both. ey enjoy <strong>the</strong>reputation <strong>of</strong> com<strong>in</strong>g to grips with reality by high-powered techniques,<strong>in</strong> contrast with commonplace <strong>and</strong> mostly qualitative observations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>role <strong>of</strong> money over <strong>the</strong> centuries <strong>and</strong> throughout <strong>the</strong> world <strong>and</strong> also <strong>in</strong>contrast with questions about <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> barriers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> channelsthrough which money plausibly would affect output. Jones <strong>and</strong> Newman 1992 is a good example. e authors argue that technologicalprogress <strong>in</strong>creases potential output but may reduce current output by mak<strong>in</strong>g currentknowledge obsolete <strong>and</strong> disrupt<strong>in</strong>g current adaptations. ey adopt <strong>the</strong> metaphor<strong>of</strong> goods concealed <strong>in</strong> holes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ground <strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite amounts each period. Progress<strong>in</strong>creases <strong>the</strong> amounts <strong>of</strong> goods available but reshuffles <strong>the</strong>ir locations, mak<strong>in</strong>g knowledgega<strong>in</strong>ed from past searches obsolete. A ma<strong>the</strong>matical formulation <strong>of</strong> this metaphor, withparameters express<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> probability <strong>of</strong> technological shocks <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir effects on productivity,does illum<strong>in</strong>ate questions <strong>of</strong> welfare <strong>and</strong> its distribution <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> possible policytrade<strong>of</strong>fs.


242 Part I: EconomicsAn article by Hansen <strong>and</strong> Prescott (1993) provides a partial exceptionto <strong>the</strong> observation that real-bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle <strong>the</strong>orists do not identify <strong>the</strong>“real” shocks that <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>ory presupposes. Ultimately, though, <strong>the</strong> partialnature <strong>of</strong> that exception supports <strong>the</strong> observation. Without explicitly say<strong>in</strong>gso, Hansen <strong>and</strong> Prescott convey <strong>the</strong> impression that <strong>the</strong>y are answer<strong>in</strong>g“yes” to <strong>the</strong> question posed by <strong>the</strong>ir title, “Did Technology Shocks Cause<strong>the</strong> 1990–1991 Recession?”, thus <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g that episode <strong>in</strong> support <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<strong>the</strong>ory. In <strong>the</strong>ir conclud<strong>in</strong>g paragraph (p. 286) <strong>the</strong>y say: “Of course, iftechnology shocks cont<strong>in</strong>ue to be above average, <strong>the</strong> United States willexperience a boom; if <strong>the</strong> shocks <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> com<strong>in</strong>g year are below average,we can expect a recession.” Earlier (e.g., p. 284), <strong>the</strong>y say that <strong>the</strong>ir modeleconomy had a recession roughly match<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> actual economy <strong>in</strong>tim<strong>in</strong>g, magnitude, <strong>and</strong> duration.Hansen <strong>and</strong> Prescott’s method was to construct a model economy,modified from <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard real-bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle model <strong>and</strong> calibrated withfigures from <strong>the</strong> real world. ey calculate supposed productivity or technologyparameters from employment data <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r macroeconomicfigures. ey f<strong>in</strong>d that fluctuations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> model <strong>and</strong> actual economiesmatch each o<strong>the</strong>r fairly well, except for stronger <strong>and</strong> more rapid reactionsto productivity shocks <strong>and</strong> faster recovery from <strong>the</strong> recession <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>model than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> real world. (Robert Clower’s “major objection to <strong>the</strong>new classical economics,” comes to m<strong>in</strong>d: “it equates <strong>the</strong>oretical progresswith improved econometric performance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical models ra<strong>the</strong>r thanwith enhanced underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> way <strong>in</strong> which decentralized economicsystems work.” 1984, p. 272.)Lack<strong>in</strong>g space to describe <strong>the</strong>ir procedures <strong>in</strong> detail, Hansen <strong>and</strong>Prescott never<strong>the</strong>less convey <strong>the</strong> impression that sophisticated techniquewent <strong>in</strong>to reach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir results, as if that very fact recommends <strong>the</strong>m.Despite entitl<strong>in</strong>g one section “What Are ese Technology Shocks?”(pp. 280–282), <strong>the</strong> authors do not actually name <strong>the</strong> supposed causes<strong>of</strong> recession. At most <strong>the</strong>y h<strong>in</strong>t that antipollution regulations may havebeen <strong>in</strong>volved. is style <strong>of</strong> exposition—convey<strong>in</strong>g impressions ra<strong>the</strong>rthan muster<strong>in</strong>g explicit evidence <strong>and</strong> argument—requires comment thatI never<strong>the</strong>less refra<strong>in</strong> from provid<strong>in</strong>g here, except to po<strong>in</strong>t out anexample <strong>of</strong> tacit cheerleaders for rigor argu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> quite a nonrigorousway.Philip Cagan reviews studies that manage to avoid detect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence<strong>of</strong> monetary changes on output (1989, followed by comments byRobert Rasche <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs). Cagan criticizes <strong>the</strong> regression techniques


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 243commonly employed, “Granger-causality” tests, <strong>and</strong> particularly vectorautoregressionstudies, for <strong>the</strong> way <strong>the</strong>y h<strong>and</strong>le correlations among <strong>the</strong>“<strong>in</strong>dependent” variables, because <strong>of</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> data (prewhiten<strong>in</strong>g,trend removal, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r purifications <strong>of</strong> time-series data <strong>in</strong> waysthat throw away some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> association that may exist), <strong>and</strong> because<strong>the</strong>se methods are test<strong>in</strong>g for specific (e.g., l<strong>in</strong>ear or log-l<strong>in</strong>ear) relations<strong>and</strong> rigid relations among <strong>the</strong> variables, whereas money exerts its effectswith “long <strong>and</strong> variable lags.” e filter<strong>in</strong>g techniques employed removemuch <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cyclical movements <strong>in</strong> money, <strong>and</strong> monetary <strong>in</strong>fluences aremasked by <strong>in</strong>novations <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rates, <strong>in</strong> turn reflect<strong>in</strong>g monetary policy.(Michael Bordo, editor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> volume, adds that observation.) eVAR technique for deal<strong>in</strong>g with spurious correlation elim<strong>in</strong>ates importantmonetary changes. By remov<strong>in</strong>g all serial <strong>and</strong> cross correlations fromeconomic series, VAR <strong>in</strong> effect removes all but short-run blips <strong>in</strong> money,los<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> relatively susta<strong>in</strong>ed monetary changes that do tendto affect bus<strong>in</strong>ess activity.Cagan also criticizes <strong>the</strong> treatment <strong>of</strong> money’s endogeneity. (Monetaristsknow that connections between monetary changes <strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>essactivity can run <strong>and</strong> evidently have run <strong>in</strong> both directions.) If <strong>the</strong> FederalReserve could override <strong>the</strong> endogeneity <strong>of</strong> money <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby make outputbehave differently than it behaves <strong>in</strong> fact, <strong>the</strong>n money does count.ere is a difference between be<strong>in</strong>g endogenous with no <strong>in</strong>dependenteffect <strong>and</strong> a mutual dependence which policy can affect. ose who denymonetary effects on output may be aware <strong>of</strong> this po<strong>in</strong>t but cont<strong>in</strong>ue toneglect it. Even if money had been <strong>in</strong> some sense completely endogenous<strong>in</strong> 1929–1933, <strong>the</strong> Federal Reserve could have overridden that endogeneity<strong>and</strong> saved <strong>the</strong> economy from devastation.I can only raise, not answer, a few fur<strong>the</strong>r questions about supposedeconometric evidence. <strong>Is</strong> it really <strong>in</strong>formative to run correlations withtime-series figures taken not only from periods <strong>of</strong> cyclical or “abnormal”change <strong>in</strong> output, money, prices, <strong>and</strong> so forth but also from periods <strong>of</strong>stead<strong>in</strong>ess or relatively steady growth (or relatively undisturbed moneysupply-<strong>and</strong>-dem<strong>and</strong>relations), as if all <strong>the</strong>se figures, taken <strong>in</strong>discrim<strong>in</strong>ately,constituted observations on a s<strong>in</strong>gle universe? In o<strong>the</strong>r words,can one really exam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> compare <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> monetary <strong>and</strong> nonmonetarydisturbances by jumbl<strong>in</strong>g toge<strong>the</strong>r numbers from periods bo<strong>the</strong>xperienc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> not experienc<strong>in</strong>g such disturbances? e issue is notreally what calculated parameters describe ill-def<strong>in</strong>ed average-over-timerelations among various macroeconomic variables. e issue, <strong>in</strong>stead, is


244 Part I: Economics<strong>the</strong> how <strong>the</strong> phenomena <strong>of</strong> recession <strong>and</strong> recovery may be causally relatedto contemporaneous <strong>and</strong> earlier events. If one would ra<strong>the</strong>r not f<strong>in</strong>d or see someth<strong>in</strong>g—like monetary disturbances<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir consequences—ways are available. e story comes tom<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> Admiral Nelson putt<strong>in</strong>g his telescope to his bl<strong>in</strong>d eye at <strong>the</strong> battle<strong>of</strong> Copenhagen.More fundamentally, what reason is <strong>the</strong>re to suppose that a def<strong>in</strong>ite“structure” <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy, describable by def<strong>in</strong>ite functions <strong>and</strong> def<strong>in</strong>itecoefficients, exists <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place as an object amenable to econometric<strong>in</strong>vestigation? Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, even if a ma<strong>the</strong>matically formulated systemwere determ<strong>in</strong>istic, with known <strong>and</strong> fixed parameters, <strong>the</strong> simplest k<strong>in</strong>ds<strong>of</strong> nonl<strong>in</strong>earity could render even its qualitative behavior after several ormany “rounds” extremely sensitive to parameter sizes <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>itial conditions.Still fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> real system be<strong>in</strong>g modeled, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g isolated,is exposed to <strong>in</strong>numerable perturbations (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g “noneconomic”ones) that <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple require be<strong>in</strong>g taken <strong>in</strong>to account. In such a system,numerical prediction is impossible (except, perhaps, for short-run extrapolation);<strong>the</strong> best that can be done is qualitative prediction, or recognition<strong>of</strong> patterns. Similar remarks apply to attempts to characterize <strong>the</strong> “processes”supposedly at work <strong>in</strong> real economies—whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong>y haveunit roots, <strong>and</strong> so forth.ese are among <strong>the</strong> lessons for economics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> recently popularma<strong>the</strong>matical <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> “chaos” or “catastrophe.” (See Ekel<strong>and</strong> 1988, whobr<strong>in</strong>gs E.N. Lorenz’s “butterfly effect” <strong>and</strong> Henri Po<strong>in</strong>caré’s reservationsabout quantitative model<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> story.) I do not want to be misunderstood,however, as issu<strong>in</strong>g methodological taboos <strong>of</strong> my own. Econometricresearch <strong>in</strong>to recent or earlier economic history can <strong>in</strong>deed be <strong>in</strong>formative,<strong>and</strong> its techniques are worth cultivat<strong>in</strong>g for applications outside aswell as with<strong>in</strong> economics. I merely want to question <strong>in</strong>sistence on <strong>the</strong>mas both obligatory <strong>and</strong> decisive across practically <strong>the</strong> whole broad range<strong>of</strong> economics. Especially where human action is <strong>the</strong> subject matter, muchcan be said for observations described <strong>and</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g conducted largely <strong>in</strong> William Poole (1994, pp. 60–62) makes a related po<strong>in</strong>t: an optimal policy shouldabolish any observable relation between money growth <strong>and</strong> GDP growth. He <strong>of</strong>fers ananalogy about try<strong>in</strong>g to determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> relation between a car’s speed <strong>and</strong> its gasol<strong>in</strong>e consumptionby muddl<strong>in</strong>g toge<strong>the</strong>r observations made at moments when <strong>the</strong> car was go<strong>in</strong>guphill, go<strong>in</strong>g downhill, <strong>and</strong> proceed<strong>in</strong>g on level ground, even though <strong>the</strong> driver was try<strong>in</strong>gto hold <strong>the</strong> car’s speed steady throughout.


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 245<strong>the</strong> terms that people <strong>the</strong>mselves use when <strong>the</strong>y perceive <strong>and</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k about<strong>and</strong> cope with reality. Cheerleaders for rigor tacitly imply that only numbers constitute reallyrespectable evidence. Everyth<strong>in</strong>g else is anecdote; <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> economist’squip, “a historian is one who believes that <strong>the</strong> plural <strong>of</strong> anecdote is data”(Brennan <strong>and</strong> Lomasky 1993, p. 90). Yet Brennan <strong>and</strong> Lomasky, undeterred,denythat <strong>the</strong> world is describable exhaustively by numbers or that broad brushdescriptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> political l<strong>and</strong>scape have noth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> relevance to contributeto <strong>the</strong> collection <strong>of</strong> evidence.... Anecdote does ... have a role toplay, <strong>and</strong> a good feel for <strong>the</strong> whole story is a crucial prerequisite for properempirical judgment.... More than “fitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> facts” is required <strong>of</strong> a <strong>the</strong>ory;it must also genu<strong>in</strong>ely expla<strong>in</strong>, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>telligible,<strong>the</strong> facts it fits. (1993, pp. 90–91; compare Higgs 1987, pp. 31–32)e history <strong>of</strong> science shows, with Copernicus <strong>and</strong> Darw<strong>in</strong> as examples,that <strong>the</strong>ory can play a powerful role <strong>in</strong> organiz<strong>in</strong>g underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>geven before it can provide quantitative predictions. e Wealth <strong>of</strong> Nationsconta<strong>in</strong>s little quantitative detail but had great impact “as a way <strong>of</strong> see<strong>in</strong>ghow th<strong>in</strong>gs fit toge<strong>the</strong>r qualitatively.” Quantitative prediction, though areasonable goal for science, is not <strong>the</strong> test <strong>of</strong> a new <strong>the</strong>ory (Margolis 1982,pp. 10–11).If an economist is not will<strong>in</strong>g to analyze nonquantitative evidencesuch as executive orders, statutes, court decisions, <strong>and</strong> regulatory directives,writes Robert Higgs (1987, p. 32), <strong>the</strong>n perhaps he should ab<strong>and</strong>onhis pretensions <strong>in</strong> this field <strong>of</strong> study.... e keys lost elsewhere will neverbe found under <strong>the</strong> lamp post, not even with <strong>the</strong> aid <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most powerfulfloodlights. e spectacle <strong>of</strong> economists br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir awesome ma<strong>the</strong>matical<strong>and</strong> statistical techniques to bear on <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> irrelevantor mislead<strong>in</strong>g data can only disgust those for whom <strong>the</strong> desire to underst<strong>and</strong>reality takes precedence over <strong>the</strong> desire to impress <strong>the</strong>ir colleagueswith analytical pyrotechnics. Higgs fur<strong>the</strong>r rem<strong>in</strong>ds us that people do not act merely out <strong>of</strong> self-<strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>narrow sense <strong>of</strong> homo oeconomicus. Sometimes <strong>the</strong>y act from loyalty to a cherished ideology<strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> satisfaction <strong>of</strong> shared membership <strong>in</strong> a set <strong>of</strong> noble, right-m<strong>in</strong>ded persons (1987,pp. 42–43).


246 Part I: EconomicsRob<strong>in</strong> W<strong>in</strong>ks collected several historical essays under a suggestivetitle, e Historian as Detective (1969). Like a detective try<strong>in</strong>g to solvea murder case, a good researcher <strong>of</strong> historical questions does not letmethodological prejudice or <strong>in</strong>timidation narrow <strong>the</strong> range <strong>of</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong>clues he is will<strong>in</strong>g to sift. He is will<strong>in</strong>g to undertake episode-by-episodeanalysis, or any o<strong>the</strong>r k<strong>in</strong>d that appears promis<strong>in</strong>g. Economists, we mayhope, will become equally open-m<strong>in</strong>ded even about novel evidence <strong>and</strong>argument. e disparagers <strong>of</strong> money-oriented macroeconomics take few pa<strong>in</strong>s to l<strong>in</strong>kup <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>ories with earlier <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> facts that <strong>the</strong>y appeared toaccount for. (Yet <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural sciences this is st<strong>and</strong>ard practice. Kepler’sastronomy accounted for <strong>the</strong> observations that <strong>the</strong> Ptolemaic <strong>the</strong>ory hadalready accommodated. E<strong>in</strong>ste<strong>in</strong>’s relativistic mechanics assimilates Newtonianmechanics as giv<strong>in</strong>g an excellent account <strong>of</strong> a special case, whichhappens to be <strong>the</strong> world <strong>of</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary human observation.) Instead, <strong>the</strong>disparagers <strong>of</strong> money cont<strong>in</strong>ue t<strong>in</strong>ker<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>ir “real” models, “calibrat<strong>in</strong>g”<strong>the</strong>m, <strong>in</strong>geniously striv<strong>in</strong>g for verisimilitude.So do<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>y disregard or flout <strong>the</strong> method <strong>of</strong> multiple compet<strong>in</strong>ghypo<strong>the</strong>ses. Actually, this is not a specific method or technique, noris it a tissue <strong>of</strong> methodological exhortations <strong>and</strong> taboos; ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is abroad approach or attitude toward research. e biophysicist John R. Platt(1964), echo<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> re<strong>in</strong>forc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> geologist T.C. Chamberl<strong>in</strong> (1897/n.d.),persuasively argues for develop<strong>in</strong>g rival hypo<strong>the</strong>ses <strong>and</strong> seek<strong>in</strong>g ways torule each one out, see<strong>in</strong>g which one or more, if any, st<strong>and</strong> up to <strong>the</strong> challenges<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> best evidence obta<strong>in</strong>able.e contrast<strong>in</strong>g approach or attitude is simply to seek arguments <strong>and</strong>evidence <strong>in</strong> defense <strong>of</strong> one’s own favorite hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. “[I]n numerous areasthat we call science,” Platt observes (p. 352), “we have come to like ourhabitual ways, <strong>and</strong> our studies that can be cont<strong>in</strong>ued <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>itely. Wemeasure, we def<strong>in</strong>e, we compute, we analyze, but we do not exclude.And this is not <strong>the</strong> way to use our m<strong>in</strong>ds most effectively or to make<strong>the</strong> fastest progress <strong>in</strong> solv<strong>in</strong>g scientific questions.” A researcher with aparental affection for his own favorite <strong>the</strong>ory, Chamberl<strong>in</strong> had already On “argument from <strong>in</strong>timidation,” see passages from Ayn R<strong>and</strong>’s works repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong>B<strong>in</strong>swanger 1986, pp. 32–34.


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 247observed (1897/n.d., p. 840), searches especially for phenomena that supportit. Unwitt<strong>in</strong>gly he presses <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> facts to fit each o<strong>the</strong>r.Chamberl<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> effect advocated substitut<strong>in</strong>g discussion for debate.e two are different <strong>in</strong> spirit. e debater seeks <strong>the</strong> decision <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>judges for his already adopted conclusion; a discussant searches for truth(F.A. Harper <strong>in</strong> a “publisher’s note” to <strong>the</strong> repr<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> Chamberl<strong>in</strong>’s article).“e conflict <strong>and</strong> exclusion <strong>of</strong> alternatives that is necessary to sharp <strong>in</strong>ductive<strong>in</strong>ference has been all too <strong>of</strong>ten a conflict between men, each withhis s<strong>in</strong>gle Rul<strong>in</strong>g eory. But whenever each man beg<strong>in</strong>s to have multiplework<strong>in</strong>g hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, it becomes purely a conflict between ideas. Itbecomes much easier <strong>the</strong>n for each <strong>of</strong> us to aim every day at conclusive dispro<strong>of</strong>s—atstrong <strong>in</strong>ference—without ei<strong>the</strong>r reluctance or combativeness.”Researchers become excited at see<strong>in</strong>g how <strong>the</strong> detective story will turn out(Platt 1964, p. 350). e forego<strong>in</strong>g views require qualification. Not every researcher needbe test<strong>in</strong>g several hypo<strong>the</strong>ses. Division <strong>of</strong> labor can be fruitful. Someresearchers may legitimately work to give one particular hypo<strong>the</strong>sis itsbest possible shot. It may be <strong>in</strong>structive for <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs to seewhat persistence <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>genuity can do toward salvag<strong>in</strong>g even a hypo<strong>the</strong>sisthat does <strong>in</strong>deed seem preposterous on its face. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, somemay flourish <strong>in</strong> a sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centive structure <strong>of</strong> rivalry not merely Platt <strong>in</strong>sightfully warns <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> researcher who is method-oriented ra<strong>the</strong>r than problem-oriented.[A]nyone who asks <strong>the</strong> question about scientific effectiveness will also conclude thatmuch <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>maticiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> physics <strong>and</strong> chemistry today is irrelevant if notmislead<strong>in</strong>g....e great value <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical formulation is that when an experiment agrees witha calculation to five decimal places, a great many alternative hypo<strong>the</strong>ses are pretty wellexcluded.... But when <strong>the</strong> fit is only to two decimal places, or one, it may be a trapfor <strong>the</strong> unwary; it may be no better than any rule-<strong>of</strong>-thumb extrapolation, <strong>and</strong> someo<strong>the</strong>r k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> qualitative exclusion might be more rigorous for test<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> assumptions<strong>and</strong> more important to scientific underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g than <strong>the</strong> quantitative fit....Measurements <strong>and</strong> equations are supposed to sharpen th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g, but, <strong>in</strong> my observation,<strong>the</strong>y more <strong>of</strong>ten tend to make <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g noncausal <strong>and</strong> fuzzy. ey tendto become <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> scientific manipulation <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> auxiliary tests <strong>of</strong> crucial<strong>in</strong>ferences.Many—perhaps most—<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> great issues <strong>of</strong> science are qualitative, not quantitative,even <strong>in</strong> physics <strong>and</strong> chemistry. Equations <strong>and</strong> measurements are useful when<strong>and</strong> only when <strong>the</strong>y are related to pro<strong>of</strong>; but pro<strong>of</strong> or dispro<strong>of</strong> comes first <strong>and</strong> is <strong>in</strong>fact strongest when it is absolutely conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g without any quantitative measurement.(1964, pp. 351–352)


248 Part I: Economicsamong ideas but among persons. Differences not merely <strong>of</strong> abilities, tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g,<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terests but even <strong>of</strong> temperaments may be put to good use. Butto <strong>the</strong> extent that some economists do work <strong>in</strong>geniously at protect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irfavorite <strong>the</strong>ories, <strong>the</strong> task falls all <strong>the</strong> more to o<strong>the</strong>rs to perform <strong>the</strong> necessaryconfrontations.Not only real-bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle <strong>the</strong>orists but monetarists must face <strong>the</strong>objections voiced by Chamberl<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Platt. Still, monetarism is not irrefutable<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> disreputable sense <strong>of</strong> enjoy<strong>in</strong>g built-<strong>in</strong> protection aga<strong>in</strong>st anyadverse evidence. Observations are readily conceivable that would <strong>in</strong>deedrefute it. If <strong>the</strong>se are merely conceivable, not actual, <strong>and</strong> if <strong>the</strong>y wouldrun counter to manifest facts about <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> money <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> everydayactivities <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess firms, well, a <strong>the</strong>ory is scarcely atfault for recogniz<strong>in</strong>g those facts.e method <strong>of</strong> compet<strong>in</strong>g multiple hypo<strong>the</strong>ses scarcely requires thatno question ever be settled, not even tentatively, <strong>and</strong> that multiple hypo<strong>the</strong>sesalways rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> active contention on all topics. It would be no sc<strong>and</strong>alif a strong consensus eventually developed on <strong>the</strong> monetary (or nonmonetary)nature <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycles. What would be a scientific sc<strong>and</strong>alwould be to grant certa<strong>in</strong> questions perpetual immunity to ever be<strong>in</strong>greopened, no matter what new evidence <strong>and</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g might bedeveloped.-Countermethodology, which I dist<strong>in</strong>guish favorably from methodology,does not mean that “anyth<strong>in</strong>g goes.” It <strong>in</strong> no way exempts any argumentor supposed evidence from critical <strong>in</strong>spection. Critics should po<strong>in</strong>t outspecific defects, however,—slips <strong>in</strong> logic <strong>and</strong> errors <strong>of</strong> fact—ra<strong>the</strong>r thanjust sneer broadly at <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> some methods but not o<strong>the</strong>rs.Despite Donald McCloskey’s lack <strong>of</strong> enthusiasm for what he calls“fallacy-monger<strong>in</strong>g” (1985, pp. 48–49), it can be useful to identify <strong>and</strong>classify specific types <strong>of</strong> unsatisfactory argument. McCloskey is emphatically<strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> scholarly dialogue, conversation, or rhetoric. Well, dialogueconsists largely <strong>of</strong> critical exam<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> arguments <strong>and</strong> evidence<strong>and</strong> supposed <strong>in</strong>ferences, <strong>and</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g acqua<strong>in</strong>ted with <strong>and</strong> alert to frequenttypes <strong>of</strong> fallacy can help <strong>in</strong> this exam<strong>in</strong>ation. McCloskey himself warnsaga<strong>in</strong>st some particular types, such as confusion between statistical significance<strong>and</strong> substantive significance <strong>of</strong> coefficients <strong>in</strong> fitted equations(1986; also 1992, p. 267). Identify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> categoriz<strong>in</strong>g fallacies is not at all


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 249<strong>the</strong> same th<strong>in</strong>g as issu<strong>in</strong>g methodological <strong>in</strong>junctions <strong>and</strong> taboos. Ra<strong>the</strong>r,it resembles <strong>the</strong> bottom-level, nuts-<strong>and</strong>-bolts methodology acceptable toMcCloskey.Now, what are some types <strong>of</strong> fallacy—<strong>and</strong>, to broaden our target, types<strong>of</strong> irrelevance—found <strong>in</strong> economic discourse?• St<strong>and</strong>ard fallacies that textbooks warn aga<strong>in</strong>st, such as <strong>the</strong> fallacy <strong>of</strong>composition (<strong>and</strong> reverse fallacies <strong>of</strong> composition).• e Ricardian Vice (so called by Schumpeter 1954, pp. 668, 1171): “<strong>the</strong>habit <strong>of</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g simple relations between aggregates that <strong>the</strong>nacquire a spurious halo <strong>of</strong> causal importance, whereas all <strong>the</strong> reallyimportant (<strong>and</strong>, unfortunately, complicated) th<strong>in</strong>gs are be<strong>in</strong>g bundledaway <strong>in</strong> or beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>se aggregates,” <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words, “<strong>the</strong> habit <strong>of</strong> pil<strong>in</strong>ga heavy load <strong>of</strong> practical conclusions upon a tenuous groundwork,which was unequal to it yet seemed <strong>in</strong> its simplicity not only attractivebut also conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g.”• “Austrian-style disquisitions on <strong>the</strong> foundations <strong>of</strong> human knowledge<strong>and</strong> conduct <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like,” an irrelevancy characteristic <strong>of</strong> FrankKnight’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs, accord<strong>in</strong>g to LeRoy <strong>and</strong> S<strong>in</strong>gell (1987, p. 402).• Similarly, nonsubstantive brood<strong>in</strong>g over <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> concepts, asover <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> entrepreneurship.• Assum<strong>in</strong>g constancy <strong>of</strong> magnitudes that simply cannot rema<strong>in</strong> constant<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r magnitudes considered (Buchanan1958).• Failure to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>and</strong> overall po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> viewor, relatedly, failure to make, when relevant, Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>’s dist<strong>in</strong>ctionbetween <strong>in</strong>dividual experiments <strong>and</strong> market experiments (1965, chap. 1<strong>and</strong> appendix).• Failures to dist<strong>in</strong>guish when necessary between actual <strong>and</strong> desiredchanges <strong>in</strong> hold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> money, between an excess dem<strong>and</strong> for or supply<strong>of</strong> home money on <strong>the</strong> foreign-exchange market <strong>and</strong> an excessdem<strong>and</strong> for or supply <strong>of</strong> domestic cash balances, <strong>and</strong> between dem<strong>and</strong>for assets denom<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> a particular currency <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> forhold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> that currency as a medium <strong>of</strong> exchange.• e real-bills fallacy, which keeps turn<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>in</strong> new disguises.


250 Part I: Economics• Tacitly suppos<strong>in</strong>g that lack <strong>of</strong> tight short-run correlation betweenchanges <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> magnitudes discredits <strong>the</strong> broad relation that st<strong>and</strong>ard<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong>dicates between <strong>the</strong>ir levels. (Nowadays <strong>the</strong> technique<strong>of</strong> co<strong>in</strong>tegration is cultivated as a means <strong>of</strong> overcom<strong>in</strong>g this fallacy.)• Mere eloquence that crowds out quantitative considerations. Hard<strong>in</strong>duly condemns decisions dom<strong>in</strong>ated by sheer eloquence, whereas <strong>the</strong>numerate outlook shows a concern for how big, how important, phenomena<strong>and</strong> effects are (1986, esp. pp. 42–44). Fritz Machlup (1956/1978, chap. 13) listed several signs <strong>of</strong> an “<strong>in</strong>ferioritycomplex <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> social sciences,” <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Behaviorism, Operationism,Metromania, Predictionism, Experimentomania, <strong>and</strong> Ma<strong>the</strong>matosis.Pressure to resemble <strong>the</strong> physical sciences does seem to be a k<strong>in</strong>d<strong>of</strong> tacit methodologiz<strong>in</strong>g.Ano<strong>the</strong>r, apparently, is attunement to fads.In science, as everywhere else, <strong>the</strong>re are few true creators, people ableto leave <strong>the</strong> beaten track <strong>and</strong> to come up with new ideas. It is very tempt<strong>in</strong>gto deem a problem <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g because half <strong>the</strong> people you know arework<strong>in</strong>g on it. But truly deep <strong>and</strong> difficult problems promise no easyreturns, <strong>and</strong> do not attract people eager to publish. Po<strong>in</strong>caré makes a dist<strong>in</strong>ctionbetween problems that nature sets up <strong>and</strong> problems that one setsup (Ekel<strong>and</strong> 1988, p. 25).What one might call frontiersmanship is a related attitude. Conjecturablyit tends to crowd out due attention to history, both <strong>of</strong> subjectmatter <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> research <strong>and</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> one’s field. In macroeconomics,older <strong>and</strong> more straightforward doctr<strong>in</strong>es, whatever <strong>the</strong>ir merits, were,well, remote from <strong>the</strong> frontier. O<strong>the</strong>r fields appeared more suitable for<strong>the</strong> academic game. On <strong>the</strong> supposed frontier, bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle researchers,whe<strong>the</strong>r belong<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> new-classical or <strong>the</strong> “real” school, tend to neglecthistorical episodes help<strong>in</strong>g to support (or to discredit) <strong>the</strong> monetaristexplanation <strong>of</strong> cycles. ey also neglect or slight <strong>the</strong> fact that competentobservers <strong>in</strong> widely diverse times <strong>and</strong> places saw reason to be persuaded<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> monetary nature <strong>of</strong> cycles. Yet this widespread perception surelycounts for someth<strong>in</strong>g, especially s<strong>in</strong>ce it does not st<strong>and</strong> alone but complementsa variety <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r evidence.Also at work <strong>in</strong> contemporary macroeconomics is an attitude that Ido not want to label; it can exhibit itself. Referr<strong>in</strong>g to New Keynesian


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 251economics <strong>in</strong> particular (which, be<strong>in</strong>g mislabeled, has close though <strong>in</strong>adequatelyappreciated aff<strong>in</strong>ities with monetarism), Robert G. K<strong>in</strong>g mentionsmacroeconomists work<strong>in</strong>g “on <strong>the</strong> banks <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Charles River,” whoseproduct he disparages <strong>in</strong> contrast with “that <strong>of</strong> macroeconomists at <strong>the</strong>universities where <strong>the</strong> cutt<strong>in</strong>g-edge research has been done over <strong>the</strong> pastdecade.” e latter consists <strong>of</strong> dynamic general equilibrium microeconomicmodels <strong>of</strong> macroeconomic phenomena. “It is what most graduate studentsare now learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> what most undergraduates will soon learn. In twodecades or less, it will be hard to f<strong>in</strong>d a macroeconomist whose first reactionsto policy problems will not be conditioned by susta<strong>in</strong>ed exposure to[it]” (K<strong>in</strong>g 1990, p. 162). In a later article, K<strong>in</strong>g reproaches New Keynesiansfor attempts at “market<strong>in</strong>g” a version <strong>of</strong> macroeconomics resembl<strong>in</strong>ga Ford P<strong>in</strong>to. “e danger is that macroeconomists <strong>and</strong> policy-makers willpay too much attention to <strong>the</strong> new Keynesian advertis<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> assumefor too long that <strong>the</strong> old product is a sound one” (K<strong>in</strong>g 1993, conclud<strong>in</strong>gsentence). e state <strong>of</strong> academic economics is far from wholly bad; progress doesoccur. Critics, though, see grounds for compla<strong>in</strong>t. An article chosen atr<strong>and</strong>om out <strong>of</strong> any economics journal, James Buchanan f<strong>in</strong>ds, is unlikely“to have a social productivity greater than zero. Most modern economistsare simply do<strong>in</strong>g what o<strong>the</strong>r economists are do<strong>in</strong>g while liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>f a form<strong>of</strong> dole that will simply not st<strong>and</strong> critical scrut<strong>in</strong>y” (1979, pp. 90–91). Morerecently a young academic superstar has said much <strong>the</strong> same:In America’s academic system, pr<strong>of</strong>essors <strong>of</strong> economics get tenure <strong>and</strong>build reputations that give <strong>the</strong>m o<strong>the</strong>r academic perks by publish<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong>so <strong>the</strong>y publish immense amounts—thous<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> papers each year, <strong>in</strong>scores <strong>of</strong> obscure journals. Most <strong>of</strong> those papers aren’t worth read<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong>many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m are pretty much impossible to read <strong>in</strong> any case, because<strong>the</strong>y are loaded with dense ma<strong>the</strong>matics <strong>and</strong> denser jargon. (Krugman1994, p. 8)“Academic programs almost everywhere,” Buchanan cont<strong>in</strong>ues, “arecontrolled by rent-recipients who simply try to ape <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream work<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir peers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e” (Buchanan 1983/1988, p. 130). Ma<strong>in</strong>streameconomists <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1950s, though wrong on much, were <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> ideas,Buchanan says, <strong>and</strong> were not frauds or conscious parasites. S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>neconomics has become


252 Part I: Economicsa science without ultimate purpose or mean<strong>in</strong>g. It has allowed itself tobecome captive <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> technical tools that it employs without keep<strong>in</strong>gtrack <strong>of</strong> just what it is that <strong>the</strong> tools are to be used for. In a very realsense <strong>the</strong> economists <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1980s are illiterate <strong>in</strong> basic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>irown discipl<strong>in</strong>e.... eir <strong>in</strong>terest lies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> purely <strong>in</strong>tellectual properties<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> models with which <strong>the</strong>y work, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y seem to get <strong>the</strong>ir kicksfrom <strong>the</strong> discovery <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> propositions relevant only to <strong>the</strong>ir ownfantasy l<strong>and</strong>s. (1983/1988, pp. 126–127)Maurice Allais, a ma<strong>the</strong>matical economist who won <strong>the</strong> Nobel Prizetwo years after Buchanan did, shares his skepticism. For almost forty-fiveyears, Allais said <strong>in</strong> 1989, economic literature has featured “completelyartificial ma<strong>the</strong>matical models detached from reality.” Allais recommendsma<strong>the</strong>matics to economists not for its own sake “but as a means <strong>of</strong> explor<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> analyz<strong>in</strong>g concrete reality.” When nei<strong>the</strong>r a <strong>the</strong>ory nor its implications“can be confronted with <strong>the</strong> real world, that <strong>the</strong>ory is devoid <strong>of</strong>any scientific <strong>in</strong>terest.”In a broader context, Garrett Hard<strong>in</strong> (1986, pp. 175–176) observes an<strong>in</strong>formation glut. “A substantial <strong>and</strong> grow<strong>in</strong>g proportion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> scientificliterature is pure jam [<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> traffic jam], <strong>the</strong> consequence<strong>of</strong> egotistic scientists putt<strong>in</strong>g out multiple, repetitive publications <strong>in</strong> aneffort to be noticed.... Progress is impeded. Society suffers.” Referr<strong>in</strong>g to<strong>the</strong> exam<strong>in</strong>ation system for <strong>the</strong> M<strong>and</strong>ar<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> imperial Ch<strong>in</strong>a, MichaelWalzer (1983, p. 141) notes that “exam<strong>in</strong>ers <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly stressed memorization,philology, <strong>and</strong> calligraphy, <strong>and</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idates paid more attentionto old exam<strong>in</strong>ation questions than to <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> old books. Whatwas tested, <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly, was <strong>the</strong> ability to take a test.” In today’s academicworld, similarly, what gets rewarded seems to be <strong>the</strong> ability to getrewarded.Without charg<strong>in</strong>g specific <strong>in</strong>dividuals with misconduct or reprehensiblemotives, we may rem<strong>in</strong>d ourselves about gamesmanship. Occasionally<strong>the</strong> writer <strong>of</strong> an article will try to butter up prospective refereesor o<strong>the</strong>rwise engage <strong>in</strong> politick<strong>in</strong>g to get it published. What is more Bart Kosko may be exaggerat<strong>in</strong>g but not practic<strong>in</strong>g sheer <strong>in</strong>vention:Career science, like career politics, depends as much on career maneuver<strong>in</strong>g, postur<strong>in</strong>g,<strong>and</strong> politics as it depends on research <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> truth. Few know thatwhen <strong>the</strong>y start <strong>the</strong> game <strong>of</strong> science. But <strong>the</strong>y learn it soon enough. (1993, p. 40)Politics lies beh<strong>in</strong>d literature citations <strong>and</strong> omissions, academic promotions, governmentappo<strong>in</strong>tments, contract <strong>and</strong> grant awards, conference addresses <strong>and</strong> conferencecommittee-member choices, editorial-board selection for journals <strong>and</strong> book


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 253relevant to our topic, writers sometimes put on a display <strong>of</strong> erudition,us<strong>in</strong>g techniques more advanced than are helpful, o<strong>the</strong>rwise parad<strong>in</strong>gsupposed rigor, mak<strong>in</strong>g forays <strong>in</strong>to o<strong>the</strong>r academic discipl<strong>in</strong>es, or cit<strong>in</strong>gscarcely relevant but impressively obscure sources. Some <strong>of</strong> this gamesmanshipis no doubt tolerable: even serious researchers are entitled to alittle fun. It does little damage when it is evident for what it is. It is less tolerable,however, when it warps <strong>the</strong> writer’s approach to <strong>the</strong> subject matter<strong>and</strong> his or his readers’ underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g.is situation traces partly to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>centive structure <strong>in</strong> academe. Weobserve someth<strong>in</strong>g rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> “success <strong>in</strong>dicators” <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>Soviet comm<strong>and</strong> economy. Meet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> target, satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> criteria,becomes <strong>the</strong> objective, crowd<strong>in</strong>g out attention to <strong>the</strong> wants <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> customersor—<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> present context—<strong>the</strong> advancement <strong>of</strong> knowledge, <strong>the</strong>pleasure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> quest, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> enlightenment <strong>of</strong> readers <strong>and</strong> students. eblame falls partly on adm<strong>in</strong>istrators desir<strong>in</strong>g easy-to-adm<strong>in</strong>ister criteriafor tenure <strong>and</strong> promotion. As I have observed on committees <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwise,some evaluators focus not on <strong>the</strong> actual merits <strong>of</strong> scholarly work buton <strong>the</strong> supposed prestige <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> journals where it appeared, a considerationrelated <strong>in</strong> turn to attunement to fads <strong>and</strong> fashions. e “second-h<strong>and</strong>ism”duly condemned by Ayn R<strong>and</strong> rides high (see <strong>the</strong> passages from her worksrepr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> B<strong>in</strong>swanger 1986, pp. 438–441).series, reviewer selection for technical papers <strong>and</strong> contract proposals <strong>and</strong> universityaccreditation status, <strong>and</strong> most <strong>of</strong> all, where <strong>the</strong> political currents funnel <strong>in</strong>to a laserlikebeam, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> peer-review process <strong>of</strong> technical journal articles. (p. 42)Bartley’s 1990 book is a susta<strong>in</strong>ed expression <strong>of</strong> doubt about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives at work <strong>in</strong>academe. It explores <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sically unfathomable character <strong>of</strong> knowledge, shows to whata limited extent it can be owned <strong>and</strong> controlled, <strong>and</strong> argues that universities are not organizedso as readily to advance knowledge (Bartley f<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong>m <strong>of</strong>ten work<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st itsgrowth). Chapters on “e Curious Case <strong>of</strong> Karl Popper” <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> supposed threatthat Popper’s philosophy poses to <strong>in</strong>tellectual fashions provide a case study <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book’scontentions.Hausman 1992, p. 262, also mentions perverse <strong>in</strong>centives at work <strong>in</strong> academic economics. Not referr<strong>in</strong>g to academic economics <strong>in</strong> particular, Mark C. Henrie (1987, p. 333)notes that an “ability to argue any side <strong>of</strong> any question demonstrates <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong>technique; but technique alone does not provide <strong>the</strong> student any <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to which view istrue. Quite <strong>the</strong> opposite, it encourages virtuosity <strong>of</strong> argumentation for what is false, s<strong>in</strong>ceto argue falsehood persuasively more fully demonstrates comm<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> technique than toargue for what is true.”I also suspect some <strong>in</strong>choate notion that if falsifiability is a good characteristic <strong>of</strong> a<strong>the</strong>ory, downright falsity is even better.


254 Part I: EconomicsSometh<strong>in</strong>g may well be said for “schools,” which can encourage aresearcher with <strong>the</strong> prospect <strong>of</strong> a sympa<strong>the</strong>tic audience. But a school <strong>in</strong>fluentialenough to dom<strong>in</strong>ate what are considered to be success <strong>in</strong>dicators canhave a baneful <strong>in</strong>fluence, <strong>in</strong>hibit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dependent thought. Sometimes second-h<strong>and</strong>ers try to justify <strong>the</strong>ir stance by <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> freemarket <strong>in</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> services. Once, when <strong>the</strong> board <strong>of</strong> directors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Economic Association was discuss<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r to nom<strong>in</strong>ate aparticular economist for some position or o<strong>the</strong>r, a member whom I’ll identifyonly as “TS” said <strong>in</strong> effect: “It doesn’t matter what we here th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> hiswork; let <strong>the</strong> market decide.” TS went on to name <strong>the</strong> journals that hadpr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>the</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idate’s work. At least two th<strong>in</strong>gs were wrong with thisappeal to “<strong>the</strong> market.” First, <strong>the</strong> ultimate consumer, <strong>the</strong> reader <strong>of</strong> academicjournals—or, more exactly, <strong>the</strong> subscriber—has an <strong>in</strong>fluence moreattenuated <strong>and</strong> more subject to manipulation by o<strong>the</strong>rs than <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> consumer <strong>of</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary consumer goods <strong>and</strong> services. Editors <strong>and</strong>referees have reason <strong>and</strong> scope for heed<strong>in</strong>g fads <strong>and</strong> cliquish <strong>and</strong> personalconsiderations. ey are not risk<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir own money. Subscribers face tie<strong>in</strong>sales (which <strong>in</strong>clude association memberships <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed prestige<strong>of</strong> subscrib<strong>in</strong>g) <strong>and</strong> have reason, anyway, to learn about fads, whe<strong>the</strong>r<strong>the</strong>y like <strong>the</strong>m or not. It is harder <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed academic market than<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> real market for customers to know whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y got what <strong>the</strong>ypaid for.Second, s<strong>in</strong>ce when was <strong>the</strong> market, even <strong>the</strong> actual bus<strong>in</strong>ess market,supposed to be <strong>the</strong> arbiter <strong>of</strong> excellence <strong>in</strong> literature, art, music, science,or scholarship? S<strong>in</strong>ce when does it decide truth <strong>and</strong> beauty? e case for<strong>the</strong> free market is someth<strong>in</strong>g quite o<strong>the</strong>r than that it constitutes <strong>the</strong> verycriterion <strong>of</strong> what should be admired, <strong>and</strong> it ill serves <strong>the</strong> cause <strong>of</strong> a freesociety to misrepresent <strong>the</strong> case for <strong>the</strong> market.F<strong>in</strong>ally, TS’s position is <strong>the</strong> very prototype <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> second-h<strong>and</strong>ism diagnosedby Ayn R<strong>and</strong>. Misbehavior <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> “marketplace” for ideas is worsethan <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> marketplace <strong>of</strong> goods, suggests W.W. Bartley III, because fewpenalties aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>of</strong>fenders are readily enforceable, while “whistle-blowers”are severely punished (1990, chaps. 6 <strong>and</strong> 7; <strong>the</strong> analogy between <strong>the</strong> academic<strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess markets is fur<strong>the</strong>r dissected <strong>in</strong> Mirowsky 1992, pp. 239,247, <strong>and</strong> Mayer 1993, pp. 10ff., 84).


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 255 Overcom<strong>in</strong>g tacit methodological preachments requires, for one th<strong>in</strong>g,cultivat<strong>in</strong>g clarity. An article by Max Eastman (1929/1940) is worth cit<strong>in</strong>gif only for its <strong>in</strong>sightful title, “e Cult <strong>of</strong> Un<strong>in</strong>telligibility.” at labelfits not only Eastman’s specific target, “modernist” poetry, but much academicactivity. Yet contempt for convey<strong>in</strong>g a clear message violates <strong>the</strong>spirit <strong>of</strong> science, which “is noth<strong>in</strong>g but a persistent <strong>and</strong> organized effort totalk sense” (Eastman 1929/1940, p. 366). Bartley found <strong>the</strong> obscurantism<strong>of</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> entrenched ideologies occurr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> two ma<strong>in</strong> forms, <strong>in</strong>appropriatema<strong>the</strong>matical formalism <strong>and</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> clarity <strong>in</strong> speech <strong>and</strong> presentation(1990, pp. 132ff.). As Karl Popper taught, pretentiousness is immoral (Bartley1990, p. 159). Popper would “always try to dislodge his conversationalpartners from any habits or tricks that preserve <strong>the</strong>ir ability to impress <strong>and</strong>dom<strong>in</strong>ate, <strong>and</strong> to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pretence <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>the</strong>y do not possess”(Bartley 1990, p. 265).Authors <strong>of</strong> books on grammar <strong>and</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g style do not hesitate towarn <strong>the</strong>ir readers about specific errors <strong>and</strong> stylistic <strong>in</strong>felicities. In that connection,we do well to remember McCloskey’s top level <strong>of</strong> methodology,<strong>the</strong> ethics <strong>of</strong> scholarly discourse. Scientists are supposed to be engaged<strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>terpersonal endeavor, which <strong>in</strong>cludes, as McCloskey says, “conversation.”Well, <strong>the</strong>n, communicate. Do not pervert communication <strong>in</strong>to parad<strong>in</strong>ghow much you know <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics or <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> science orwhatever. Instead <strong>of</strong> striv<strong>in</strong>g to impress your reader, be polite to him. Edit;rewrite. Recognize that <strong>the</strong> form <strong>in</strong> which your ideas orig<strong>in</strong>ally occurredto you may not be <strong>the</strong> most effective way to put <strong>the</strong>m across. Do not supposethat employ<strong>in</strong>g symbols automatically confers a papal dispensationfrom obligations <strong>in</strong>cumbent on any writer.e <strong>of</strong>fenses I have <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong>clude writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> code, with symbolsreplac<strong>in</strong>g words, us<strong>in</strong>g symbols def<strong>in</strong>ed only haphazardly, omitt<strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>gfullabels from diagrams, <strong>and</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g cryptic expressions with variablemean<strong>in</strong>gs (such as “real exchange rate” or “appreciation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> exchangerate”). Perhaps your reader can break your code; perhaps he should be ableto figure out your argument even <strong>in</strong> its orig<strong>in</strong>al, unedited form. But whyshould he have to bo<strong>the</strong>r? He feels more comfortable with occasional reassurancesthat you <strong>and</strong> he are on <strong>the</strong> same wavelength. After all, you mightbe mak<strong>in</strong>g a mistake. I recall places where <strong>the</strong> writer used a slightly differentsymbol <strong>in</strong> a diagram than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> text, such as a lower-case <strong>in</strong>stead


256 Part I: Economics<strong>of</strong> upper-case letter or a curved letter l <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> a straight one. Did<strong>the</strong> writer <strong>in</strong>tend a dist<strong>in</strong>ction, <strong>and</strong> if so, what was it, or was he simplybe<strong>in</strong>g careless? Such time-consum<strong>in</strong>g puzzles could be avoided if <strong>the</strong>writer deigned to write clearly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place, perhaps even label<strong>in</strong>g hisdiagrams <strong>in</strong> English.e central fact <strong>of</strong> economics is scarcity. Your readers’ time is scarce,as well as <strong>the</strong>ir capacity for attention <strong>and</strong> effort. Besides figur<strong>in</strong>g yourmessage out, <strong>the</strong>y have o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs to do. Many topics with<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> outside<strong>of</strong> economics besides your current message are worth <strong>the</strong>ir attention, <strong>and</strong>your own. (As Wilhelm Röpke used to say, economics is a subject <strong>in</strong> whichunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g a part presupposes underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> whole, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>deedmore. An economist who is only an economist cannot even be a goodeconomist.)Remember that <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> dim<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g marg<strong>in</strong>al returns applieswidely, even to time <strong>and</strong> effort spent on a particular activity or topic. Evenfor readers who can follow an analysis, unnecessary formalist decorations<strong>of</strong>ten consume time that might have had o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> better uses (Mayer1993, p. 78). e pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> portfolio diversification applies not only to<strong>in</strong>vestment assets but also to knowledge <strong>of</strong> topics with<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> outside <strong>of</strong>economics.Encourag<strong>in</strong>gly, <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matician Paul Halmos similarly exhorts hiscolleagues. ey should write correct <strong>and</strong> clear English, keep<strong>in</strong>g Fowler,Roget, <strong>and</strong> Webster at h<strong>and</strong>. A writer who works eight hours to save fivem<strong>in</strong>utes for each <strong>of</strong> 1000 readers saves over eighty man-hours. Halmoswarns that <strong>the</strong> symbolism <strong>of</strong> formal logic, though sometimes <strong>in</strong>dispensable,is a cumbersome way <strong>of</strong> transmitt<strong>in</strong>g ideas. Nobody th<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> symbols.Cod<strong>in</strong>g by <strong>the</strong> author <strong>and</strong> decod<strong>in</strong>g by <strong>the</strong> reader waste <strong>the</strong> time <strong>of</strong>both <strong>and</strong> obstruct underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g. “e best notation is no notation,” Halmosadvises. Try to write a ma<strong>the</strong>matical exposition as you would speakit. “Pretend that you are expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> subject to a friend on a long walk<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> woods, with no paper available; fall back on symbolism only whenit is really necessary” (Halmos 1973/1981, p. 40). Avoid distract<strong>in</strong>g yourreader with irrelevant labels (for example, referr<strong>in</strong>g to “<strong>the</strong> function f ”when you will not be us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> label f aga<strong>in</strong>). When conveniently possible,avoid co<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g new technical terms. Take care about <strong>the</strong> appearance<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ted page. Solid prose will have a forbidd<strong>in</strong>g, sermony aspect; “apage full <strong>of</strong> symbols ... will have a frighten<strong>in</strong>g, complicated aspect” (p. 44).It may be that clarity does not pay. (It costs time, but editors <strong>and</strong> refereeshave an opportunity to impose discipl<strong>in</strong>e on authors <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>of</strong>


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 257<strong>the</strong> wider scholarly community.) Putt<strong>in</strong>g heavy dem<strong>and</strong>s on your readermay advertise your own learn<strong>in</strong>g. It may <strong>in</strong>timidate him <strong>in</strong>to not question<strong>in</strong>gyour argument. (Mayer 1993, p. 78, suggests that formalist trapp<strong>in</strong>gsmay help protect a paper from criticism by mak<strong>in</strong>g critical comment onit costly <strong>in</strong> time <strong>and</strong> effort.) You may make your message appear fresher<strong>and</strong> more important than it really is by practic<strong>in</strong>g product differentiation,as opposed to tak<strong>in</strong>g care to relate your message to <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g literature,exploit<strong>in</strong>g similarities, parallels, analogies, <strong>and</strong> contrasts. Perhaps reconditeness<strong>and</strong> obscurity really do bamboozle editors <strong>and</strong> readers; <strong>and</strong> perhapsun<strong>in</strong>telligibility masquerad<strong>in</strong>g as pr<strong>of</strong>undity may sometimes ward<strong>of</strong>f identification <strong>of</strong> what is no more than poor style. If so, a moral aspectenters <strong>in</strong>to writ<strong>in</strong>g. (Cf. McCloskey 1986, writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a slightly differentcontext.) If so, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, questions aga<strong>in</strong> arise about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>centive structureprevail<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> academia.At <strong>the</strong> very least, get your grammar, word usage, spell<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> punctuationright. (Nobody is <strong>in</strong>fallible, certa<strong>in</strong>ly not I, but at least one shouldwork at <strong>the</strong>se th<strong>in</strong>gs.) Why do economists tolerate so much slovenl<strong>in</strong>ess<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se respects? ey do not tolerate its counterpart <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>maticalstr<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> economics—not, that is, when <strong>the</strong>y notice it (<strong>and</strong> I have somestories to tell about this qualification). If rigor is prized, why shouldn’t itbe prized <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> cut-<strong>and</strong>-dried aspects <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g?If for some reason you cannot get your grammar <strong>and</strong> so forth right,<strong>the</strong>n hire someone to repair your writ<strong>in</strong>g before you ship it <strong>of</strong>f to a journal<strong>and</strong> perhaps even before you <strong>in</strong>flict it on colleagues. Beyond gett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mechanics right, strive for a readable style. When you ship your manuscript<strong>of</strong>f to a publisher, have it <strong>in</strong> a form <strong>in</strong> which you would be glad tosee it <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>t. Don’t count on someone else to improve it.ese exhortations bear on what to do about a national crisis (permitme to exaggerate as Andy Rooney does on <strong>the</strong> tube). Not even WalterBlock, who wrote a whole book (1976) try<strong>in</strong>g to portray <strong>the</strong> pimp,<strong>the</strong> drug pusher, <strong>the</strong> litterbug, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r unsavory types as heroes—noteven he attempted any defense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> itchy-f<strong>in</strong>gered copyeditor. atwould have been just too preposterous. I wonder whe<strong>the</strong>r obscurities, jargon,<strong>and</strong> symbols may not sometimes help protect authors from tamper<strong>in</strong>g:copyeditors may shy away from try<strong>in</strong>g to improve on manuscriptsthat <strong>the</strong>y cannot even underst<strong>and</strong>. Mere palpable slopp<strong>in</strong>ess, on <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, flags <strong>the</strong> copyeditors on. One <strong>of</strong> my bitterest compla<strong>in</strong>tsaga<strong>in</strong>st writers who th<strong>in</strong>k it beneath <strong>the</strong>m to bo<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong>ir grammar,spell<strong>in</strong>g, punctuation, <strong>and</strong> style is that <strong>the</strong>y create externalities: <strong>the</strong>y


258 Part I: Economics<strong>in</strong>flict <strong>the</strong> curse <strong>of</strong> copyedit<strong>in</strong>g even onto writers more careful than <strong>the</strong>mselves.Ideally, <strong>the</strong> author himself should be known to bear responsibilityfor what appears <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>t. If <strong>the</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g is excessively bad, <strong>the</strong> publishershould simply reject it. As th<strong>in</strong>gs now st<strong>and</strong>, however, sloppy writersprovide an excuse <strong>of</strong> sorts for not straightforwardly solv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> copyeditorproblem.I hope we are giv<strong>in</strong>g each o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> perhaps our students <strong>and</strong> readers,some moral support, some backbone, so that we can carry on our work <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> ways that we ourselves th<strong>in</strong>k best suited for learn<strong>in</strong>g how <strong>the</strong> worldactually operates. I hope we can carry on despite fads, fashions, perversesuccess <strong>in</strong>dicators, <strong>and</strong> preachments about “rigor.” I hope we will have<strong>the</strong> courage to unmask <strong>and</strong>, when appropriate, to defy methodologicalpreachments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> worst k<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>the</strong> tacit ones.Allais, Maurice. Remarks at McGill University, Montreal. Reported <strong>in</strong> IMF Survey(12 June 1989): 185.Bartley, William Warren, III. e Retreat to Commitment. 2ⁿ ed. La Salle, Ill.,<strong>and</strong> London: Open Court, 1984.. Unfathomed Knowledge, Unmeasured Wealth: On Universities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>Wealth <strong>of</strong> Nations. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1990.Bauer, Peter T. “International Economic Development.” Economic Journal 69(March 1959): 105–123.Bénassy, Jean-Pascal. “Nonclear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>Market</strong>s: Microeconomic Concepts <strong>and</strong>Macroeconomic Applications.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic Literature 31 ( June 1993):732–761.B<strong>in</strong>swanger, Harry, ed. e Ayn R<strong>and</strong> Lexicon. New York: New American Library,1986.Block, Walter. Defend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Undefendable. New York: Fleet, 1976.Brennan, Ge<strong>of</strong>frey, <strong>and</strong> Loren Lomasky. Democracy <strong>and</strong> Decision. Cambridge,U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1993.


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 259Bridgman, P.W. Reflections <strong>of</strong> a Physicist. New York: Philosophical Library, 1955.Brunner, Karl. “e Disarray <strong>in</strong> Macroeconomics.” In Monetary Economics <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> 1980s, edited by Forrest Capie <strong>and</strong> Ge<strong>of</strong>frey E. Wood, 197–233. London:Macmillan, 1989.Buchanan, James M. “Ceteris Paribus: Some Notes on Methodology.” Sou<strong>the</strong>rnEconomic Journal 24 ( January 1958): 259–270.. What Should Economists Do? Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1979.. “<strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>: 1957–1982.” 1983. In Ideas, eir Orig<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> eirConsequences, by omas Jefferson Center Foundation, 119–130. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton,D.C.: American Enterprise Institute, 1988.Cagan, Philip. “Money-Income Causality—A Critical Review <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> LiteratureS<strong>in</strong>ce A Monetary History.” In Money, History, <strong>and</strong> International F<strong>in</strong>ance:<strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> Honor <strong>of</strong> Anna J. Schwartz, edited by Michael D. Bordo, 117–151.Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1989.Caldwell, Bruce J., ed. Appraisal <strong>and</strong> Criticism <strong>in</strong> Economics: A Book <strong>of</strong> Read<strong>in</strong>gs.Boston: Allen & Unw<strong>in</strong>, 1984.Chamberl<strong>in</strong>, omas C. “e Method <strong>of</strong> Multiple Work<strong>in</strong>g Hypo<strong>the</strong>ses.” Journal<strong>of</strong> Geology 5, (November/December 1897): 837–848. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted as <strong>the</strong> pamphletMultiple Hypo<strong>the</strong>ses. Menlo Park: Institute for Humane Studies, n.d.Clower, Robert. Money <strong>and</strong> <strong>Market</strong>s. Edited by Donald A. Walker. New York:Cambridge University Press, 1984.Davis, Philip J., <strong>and</strong> Reuben Hersh. Descartes’ Dream. New York: Harcourt BraceJovanovich, 1986.Duhem, Pierre. e Aim <strong>and</strong> Structure <strong>of</strong> Physical eory. Translated by Philip P.Wiener. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press, 1954.Eastman, Max. “e Cult <strong>of</strong> Un<strong>in</strong>telligibility.” 1929. In America rough <strong>the</strong> Essay,edited by A.T. Johnson <strong>and</strong> Allen Tate, 362–378. New York: Oxford UniversityPress, 1940.Ekel<strong>and</strong>, Ivar. Ma<strong>the</strong>matics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Unexpected. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1988.Eucken, Walter. “On e eory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Centrally Adm<strong>in</strong>istered <strong>Economy</strong>: AnAnalysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German Experiment.” Translated by T.W. Hutchison. Economica15, no. 57 (February 1948): 79–100; <strong>and</strong> no. 59 (August 1948): 173–193.


260 Part I: EconomicsFrank, Robert H. “If Homo Economicus Could Choose His Own Utility Function,Would He Want One with a Conscience?” American Economic Review 77(September 1987): 593–604.Giere, Ronald N. Expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Science: A Cognitive Approach. Chicago: University<strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1988.Grossman, Herschel I. Review <strong>of</strong> Disequilibrium Economics, by Katsuhito Iwai.Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> 91 (April 1983): 343–344.Halmos, Paul R. “How to Write Ma<strong>the</strong>matics.” 1973. In How to Write Ma<strong>the</strong>matics,by N.E. Steenrod, P.R. Halmos, M.M. Schiffer, <strong>and</strong> J.A. Dieudonné,19–48. Providence: American Ma<strong>the</strong>matical Society, 1981.Hansen, Gary D., <strong>and</strong> Edward C. Prescott. “Did Technology Shocks Cause <strong>the</strong>1990–1991 Recession?” American Economic Review 83 (May 1993): 280–286.Hard<strong>in</strong>, Garrett. Filters aga<strong>in</strong>st Folly: How to Survive Despite Economists, Ecologists,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Merely Eloquent. New York: Pengu<strong>in</strong> Books, 1986.Hausman, Daniel M. e Inexact <strong>and</strong> Separate Science <strong>of</strong> Economics. Cambridge,U.K., <strong>and</strong> New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992.Henrie, Mark C. “Reason, Unreason, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Conservative.” Modern Age 31 (Summer/Fall1987): 332–342.Higgs, Robert. Crisis <strong>and</strong> Leviathan. New York: Oxford University Press, 1987.Hobbes, omas. Leviathan. 1651. Baltimore: Pengu<strong>in</strong> Books, 1968.Irel<strong>and</strong>, Peter N. “Money <strong>and</strong> Growth: An Alternative Approach.” American EconomicReview 84 (March 1994): 47–65.Jones, Robert, <strong>and</strong> Ge<strong>of</strong>frey Newman. “Economic Growth as a Coord<strong>in</strong>ationProblem.” Paper presented at <strong>the</strong> 1992 Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Economic Association meet<strong>in</strong>gs.K<strong>in</strong>g, Robert G. “e Interaction <strong>of</strong> Monetary Policy <strong>and</strong> Public Deficits.” InMonetary Policy for a Chang<strong>in</strong>g F<strong>in</strong>ancial Environment, edited by William S.Haraf <strong>and</strong> Philip Cagan, 160–165. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.: American EnterpriseInstitute Press, 1990.. “Will <strong>the</strong> New Keynesian Macroeconomics Resurrect <strong>the</strong> IS-LMModel?” Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic Perspectives 7 (W<strong>in</strong>ter 1993): 67–82.Klamer, Arjo. Conversations with Economists. Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Allanheld,1983.


Chapter : Tacit Preachments are <strong>the</strong> Worst K<strong>in</strong>d 261Klappholz, K., <strong>and</strong> J. Agassi. “Methodological Prescriptions <strong>in</strong> Economics.” Economica26 (February 1959): 60–74.Kosko, Bart. Fuzzy <strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g: e New Science <strong>of</strong> Fuzzy Logic. New York: Hyperion,1993.Krugman, Paul. What Do We Need to Know about <strong>the</strong> International Monetary System?<strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> International F<strong>in</strong>ance, no. 190. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: Pr<strong>in</strong>cetonUniversity International F<strong>in</strong>ance Section, July 1993.. Peddl<strong>in</strong>g Prosperity: Economic Sense <strong>and</strong> Nonsense <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Age <strong>of</strong> Dim<strong>in</strong>ishedExpectations. New York: Norton, 1994.Laidler, David. Tak<strong>in</strong>g Money Seriously <strong>and</strong> O<strong>the</strong>r <strong>Essays</strong>. Cambridge, Mass.:MIT Press, 1990.Lakatos, Imre. Pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Refutations: e Logic <strong>of</strong> Ma<strong>the</strong>matical Discovery. Editedby John Worrall <strong>and</strong> Elie Zahar. New York: Cambridge University Press,1976.LeRoy, Stephen F., <strong>and</strong> Larry D. S<strong>in</strong>gell, Jr. “Knight on Risk <strong>and</strong> Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty.”Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> 95 (April 1987): 394–406.Lucas, Robert E., Jr. “Some International Evidence on Output-Inflation Trade<strong>of</strong>fs.”American Economic Review 63 ( June 1973): 326–334.. “Methods <strong>and</strong> Problems <strong>in</strong> Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Cycle eory.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Money,Credit, <strong>and</strong> Bank<strong>in</strong>g 12, Pt. 2 (November 1980): 696–715.Lucas, Robert E., Jr., <strong>and</strong> omas J. Sargent. “After Keynesian Macroeconomics.”In After <strong>the</strong> Phillips Curve: Persistence <strong>of</strong> High Inflation <strong>and</strong> HighUnemployment, 49–72. Boston: Federal Reserve Bank <strong>of</strong> Boston, 1978.Machlup, Fritz. “e Inferiority Complex <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Social Sciences.” 1956. In Methodology<strong>of</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> O<strong>the</strong>r Social Sciences, chap. 13. New York: AcademicPress, 1978.Margolis, Howard. Selfishness, Altruism, <strong>and</strong> Rationality. New York: CambridgeUniversity Press, 1982.Mayer, omas. <strong>Truth</strong> versus Precision <strong>in</strong> Economics. Aldershot, U.K., <strong>and</strong> Brookfield,Vt.: Elgar, 1993.McCloskey, Donald N. e Rhetoric <strong>of</strong> Economics. Madison: University <strong>of</strong> Wiscons<strong>in</strong>Press, 1985.. “Why Economic Historians Should Stop Rely<strong>in</strong>g on Statistical <strong>Test</strong>s <strong>of</strong>Significance, <strong>and</strong> Lead Economists <strong>and</strong> Historians Into <strong>the</strong> Promised L<strong>and</strong>.”Cliometrics Society Newsletter 2 (December 1986): 5–7.


262 Part I: Economics. “Commentary” on Philip Mirowski’s paper. In Post-Popperian Methodology<strong>of</strong> Economics, edited by Neil de Marchi, 261–271. Boston: Kluwer, 1992.Mirowski, Philip. “ree Vignettes on <strong>the</strong> State <strong>of</strong> Economic Rhetoric.” InPost-Popperian Methodology <strong>of</strong> Economics, edited by Neil de Marchi, 235–259.Boston: Kluwer, 1992.Musgrave, Alan. “‘Unreal Assumptions’ <strong>in</strong> Economic eory: e F-Twist Untwisted.”Kyklos 34, no. 3 (1981): 377–387.Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Don. Money, Interest, <strong>and</strong> Prices. 2ⁿ ed. New York: Harper & Row,1965.Platt, John R. “Strong Inference.” Science 146 (October 1964): 347–353.Poole, William. “Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Monetary Aggregates Today.” Shadow Open<strong>Market</strong> Committee, Policy Statement <strong>and</strong> Position Papers (March 1994): 59-65.Schumpeter, Joseph A. History <strong>of</strong> Economic Analysis. New York: Oxford UniversityPress, 1954.Solow, Robert. “Economic History <strong>and</strong> Economics.” American Economic Review75 (May 1985): 328–331.Summers, Lawrence. “e Scientific Illusion <strong>in</strong> Empirical Macroeconomics.”Sc<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>avian Journal <strong>of</strong> Economics 93, no. 2 (1991): 129–148.Tob<strong>in</strong>, James. “Discussion.” In Models <strong>of</strong> Monetary Economies, edited by John H.Kareken <strong>and</strong> Neil Wallace, 83–90. M<strong>in</strong>neapolis: Federal Reserve Bank <strong>of</strong>M<strong>in</strong>neapolis, 1980.Walzer, Michael. Spheres <strong>of</strong> Justice. New York: Basic Books, 1983.Willes, Mark H. “‘Rational Expectations’ as a Counterrevolution.” e PublicInterest, Special <strong>Is</strong>sue (1980): 81–96.Williamson, Steve, <strong>and</strong> R<strong>and</strong>all Wright. “Barter <strong>and</strong> Monetary Exchange UnderPrivate Information.” American Economic Review 84 (March 1994): 104–123.W<strong>in</strong>ks, Rob<strong>in</strong> W. e Historian as Detective: <strong>Essays</strong> on Evidence. New York: Harper& Row, 1969.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “e Significance <strong>of</strong> Monetary Disequilibrium.” Cato Journal6 (Fall 1986): 369–399.. “Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences.” Eastern EconomicJournal 20 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g 1994): 157–169. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted here as chapter .


Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences * Quibbles over Walras’s Law trace, <strong>in</strong> my experience, to failure to recognizethat <strong>the</strong> Law is tautologically true. To forestall misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> this <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r pieces <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory, it is worth recogniz<strong>in</strong>g thatuseful tautologies are fairly numerous.is paper issues no methodological exhortations or taboos. It doesnot urge armchair <strong>the</strong>ory over empirical research. Instead, it looks at afeature shared by several specific examples <strong>of</strong> successful <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g. Justas scientists try to expla<strong>in</strong> puzzl<strong>in</strong>g phenomena by reveal<strong>in</strong>g uniformitieshidden beneath superficial diversities, so we may better underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>nature <strong>and</strong> force <strong>of</strong> argument on a particular topic by recogniz<strong>in</strong>g how itresembles (when it does) arguments on even quite different topics. Elucidat<strong>in</strong>gone style or str<strong>and</strong> or component <strong>of</strong> argument is not <strong>the</strong> same as<strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g on it as <strong>the</strong> only proper method <strong>of</strong> research or exposition.Tautologies are analytic or logically necessary propositions. ey arevalid thanks to cover<strong>in</strong>g all possibilities (“e world is ei<strong>the</strong>r round ornot round”) or thanks to <strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>itions. A negation <strong>of</strong> a tautologyis self-contradictory. (Consider deny<strong>in</strong>g “If A implies B, <strong>the</strong>n not-Bimplies not-A.”) Most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> tautologies mentioned below h<strong>in</strong>ge on <strong>the</strong>formulation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> terms <strong>and</strong> concepts, whose mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>terrelations <strong>the</strong>y illum<strong>in</strong>ate.Analytic propositions can “give us new knowledge” (or aid us <strong>in</strong> its pursuit).“ey call attention to l<strong>in</strong>guistic usage, <strong>of</strong> which we might o<strong>the</strong>rwise*From Eastern Economic Journal 20 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g 1994): 157–169. I am particularly th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> trouble <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g readers underst<strong>and</strong> Alan Rab<strong>in</strong>’s <strong>and</strong>my paper on “Monetary Aspects <strong>of</strong> Walras’s Law <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Stock-Flow Problem,” subsequentlypublished <strong>in</strong> 1997.263


264 Part I: Economicsnot be conscious, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y reveal unsuspected implications <strong>in</strong> our assertions<strong>and</strong> beliefs” (Ayer 1946/1969, p. 35). Logic <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics, althoughapodictically certa<strong>in</strong>, can sometimes yield surpris<strong>in</strong>g results. Analyticpropositions help one check that <strong>the</strong> factual propositions be<strong>in</strong>g broughtto bear on some problem are mutually consistent (pp. 36, 40–41). Tautologiescan be useful <strong>in</strong> apply<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> “translation test” (illustrated later) <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong> expos<strong>in</strong>g error (for noth<strong>in</strong>g contradict<strong>in</strong>g a logically necessary propositioncan be correct). Tautologies can be useful <strong>in</strong> focus<strong>in</strong>g attention <strong>and</strong>organiz<strong>in</strong>g discussion.e examples reviewed below illustrate John Harsanyi’s po<strong>in</strong>t (1976,p. 64) that social scientists encounter not only formal or logical problems<strong>and</strong> empirical problems but also conceptual-philosophical problems.Larry Laudan (1977, chap. 2) calls it “an enormous mistake ... to imag<strong>in</strong>ethat scientific progress <strong>and</strong> rationality consist entirely <strong>in</strong> solv<strong>in</strong>g empiricalproblems.” Grappl<strong>in</strong>g with conceptual problems “has been at least as important<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> science as empirical problem solv<strong>in</strong>g” (p. 45).One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most important ways science progresses is “<strong>the</strong> explication <strong>of</strong>conceptions” (William Whewell, quoted <strong>in</strong> Laudan 1977, p. 50).A <strong>the</strong>ory runs <strong>in</strong>to conceptual problems when it is <strong>in</strong>ternally <strong>in</strong>consistentor vague or when it conflicts with ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ory or doctr<strong>in</strong>e believedto be well founded (Laudan 1977, esp. pp. 48–49). Ptolemy’s astronomymanaged to avoid most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> empirical anomalies <strong>of</strong> earlier Greek astronomy,but at <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> “generat<strong>in</strong>g enormous conceptual problems” with itsepicycles, eccentrics, <strong>and</strong> equants. Its hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that certa<strong>in</strong> planets movearound empty po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> space, that planets do not always move at constantspeed, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like were <strong>in</strong> flagrant contradiction with <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>n acceptedphysical <strong>and</strong> cosmological <strong>the</strong>ories (Laudan 1977, pp. 51–52). Methodologicalnorms, <strong>in</strong> Laudan’s view, “have been perhaps <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle major sourcefor most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> controversies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> science, <strong>and</strong> for <strong>the</strong> generation<strong>of</strong> many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most acute conceptual problems with which scientistshave had to cope” (p. 58; italics omitted). “[I]t is usually easier to expla<strong>in</strong>away an anomalous experimental result than to dismiss out <strong>of</strong> h<strong>and</strong> a conceptualproblem” (p. 64; italics omitted).Referr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> particular to discussions <strong>of</strong> absolute <strong>and</strong> relational <strong>the</strong>ories<strong>of</strong> space <strong>and</strong> time, general relativity, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fieldequations, W.H. Newton-Smith (1981, p. 89) states, “What is at stake <strong>in</strong>this debate is largely conceptual.” eories must be assessed “<strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>ir power to avoid conceptual difficulties <strong>and</strong> not just <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>irpower to predict novel facts <strong>and</strong> expla<strong>in</strong> known facts.”


Chapter : Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences 265Ernst Mayr (1982, p. 23) rejects see<strong>in</strong>g “science merely as an accumulation<strong>of</strong> facts.” In biology, “most major progress was made by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduction<strong>of</strong> new concepts, or <strong>the</strong> improvement <strong>of</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g concepts. Ourunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world is achieved more effectively by conceptualimprovements than by <strong>the</strong> discovery <strong>of</strong> new facts, even though <strong>the</strong> twoare not mutually exclusive.”A.A. Z<strong>in</strong>ov’ev emphasizes how suitably chosen def<strong>in</strong>itions, terms, <strong>and</strong>symbols render scientific discussion more <strong>in</strong>tuitively obvious, compact,<strong>and</strong> convenient. In <strong>the</strong>ir absence, “<strong>the</strong> record <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> operat<strong>in</strong>gwith it become practically impossible. e search for <strong>the</strong> most convenientforms <strong>of</strong> abbreviation represents one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most important tasks <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>construction <strong>of</strong> scientific language <strong>in</strong> general” (1983, pp. 14–15).What ultimately counts <strong>in</strong> an empirical science, says Daniel Hausman(1992, p. 298) is identify<strong>in</strong>g regularities <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. “But sciencedoes not proceed by spott<strong>in</strong>g correlations among well-known observableproperties <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs. e construction <strong>of</strong> new concepts, <strong>of</strong> new ways <strong>of</strong>classify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> describ<strong>in</strong>g phenomena is an equally crucial part <strong>of</strong> science.Such conceptual work has been prom<strong>in</strong>ent <strong>in</strong> economics.” : ’ Two notable tautologies <strong>in</strong> economics illustrate certa<strong>in</strong> relations betweendef<strong>in</strong>itional truths <strong>and</strong> empirical reality. Walras’s Law illum<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>in</strong>terrelationsamong supplies <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s for goods, services, securities, <strong>and</strong>money <strong>and</strong> among <strong>the</strong>ir supply/dem<strong>and</strong> imbalances. e Law emphasizesthat no one th<strong>in</strong>g or group <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs can be <strong>in</strong> excess supply or excessdem<strong>and</strong> by itself. It <strong>the</strong>reby helps focus attention on <strong>the</strong> role <strong>in</strong> macroeconomicdisorder <strong>of</strong> a dist<strong>in</strong>ctively function<strong>in</strong>g object <strong>of</strong> exchange—money.Similarly, it emphasizes that no change <strong>in</strong> tastes or technology can affect<strong>the</strong> supply or dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle th<strong>in</strong>g alone; at least two th<strong>in</strong>gs must be<strong>in</strong>volved.In one formulation, Walras’s Law states that if a general-equilibriumequation system specifies equality between quantities supplied <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>ed<strong>of</strong> all goods <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy but one, <strong>the</strong>n an equation for <strong>the</strong>one rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g good would be otiose. Instead <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g ma<strong>the</strong>matically<strong>in</strong>dependent, it would merely duplicate <strong>in</strong>formation already conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r equations. Supply-dem<strong>and</strong> equilibrium for all goods but onealready implies equilibrium for whatever <strong>the</strong> rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g good may be.


266 Part I: EconomicsA second formulation, which straightforwardly implies <strong>the</strong> first, holds<strong>in</strong> disequilibrium as well as <strong>in</strong> equilibrium: <strong>the</strong> total value <strong>of</strong> all goods suppliedequals <strong>the</strong> total value <strong>of</strong> all goods dem<strong>and</strong>ed. (e term “goods” is<strong>in</strong>clusive here, cover<strong>in</strong>g not only commodities but also labor <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r services,securities, <strong>and</strong> money.) Quantities are valued at <strong>the</strong> prices at whichexchanges are accomplished or attempted, as <strong>the</strong> case may be. With excesssupplies counted as negative excess dem<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> values <strong>of</strong> allexcess dem<strong>and</strong>s is identically zero. (“Excess dem<strong>and</strong>” <strong>and</strong> “excess supply”refer here to market disequilibrium <strong>and</strong> frustration <strong>of</strong> attempted transactions.Someone act<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>crease his hold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> some good is not said tohave an excess dem<strong>and</strong> for it—not if he meets no frustration on <strong>the</strong> market.)(Lange 1942; Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong> 1965, pp. 73, 229, 258–262, <strong>and</strong> passim; Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>1987; Baumol 1965, pp. 340–342.)Walras’s Law is “an identity, ... little more than an account<strong>in</strong>g relationship”(Baumol 1965, p. 341). Where it does not hold, “people must, by def<strong>in</strong>ition,be plann<strong>in</strong>g to exchange goods which are not equal <strong>in</strong> value—anodd assertion for any monetary economy” (Baumol 1960, p. 30). e Lawholds because budget constra<strong>in</strong>ts operate <strong>and</strong> market transactions are twosided.Anyone try<strong>in</strong>g to acquire someth<strong>in</strong>g is by that very token <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gsometh<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> exchange <strong>of</strong> equal value at <strong>the</strong> price contemplated. Anyonetry<strong>in</strong>g to sell someth<strong>in</strong>g is dem<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> equal value <strong>in</strong> return.An attempted but frustrated transaction, like a successful one, <strong>in</strong>volvestwo goods <strong>and</strong> not just one. Each frustrated transaction leaves two excessdem<strong>and</strong> values, equal <strong>in</strong> size but opposite <strong>in</strong> algebraic sign.Yet complications arise, <strong>and</strong> Walras’s Law has itself sometimes beencalled <strong>in</strong>to question. In address<strong>in</strong>g fr<strong>in</strong>ge doubts, it is necessary to clarifysome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> very concepts that enter <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> Law. In particular, one mustdist<strong>in</strong>guish between “notional” <strong>and</strong> “effective” supplies <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong>between stock <strong>and</strong> flow conceptions <strong>of</strong> quantities. is paper’s purposedoes not require rehears<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se technicalities (although comments about<strong>the</strong> balance <strong>of</strong> payments <strong>in</strong> a later section will be suggestive). Its purpose,<strong>in</strong>stead, is simply to cite Walras’s Law as one example <strong>of</strong> a useful tautology.Ano<strong>the</strong>r familiar example is <strong>the</strong> equation <strong>of</strong> exchange MV=PQ. Interpretedas a tautology, <strong>the</strong> equation is necessarily true because <strong>of</strong> how itsterms are def<strong>in</strong>ed. It provides two different but reconcilable ways <strong>of</strong> look<strong>in</strong>gat nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>come (gross domestic product or some such magnitude).Its left side <strong>in</strong>terprets <strong>in</strong>come as <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong> money<strong>and</strong> its <strong>in</strong>come velocity <strong>of</strong> circulation; its right side, as output <strong>in</strong> physicalunits valued at <strong>the</strong> average price <strong>of</strong> a unit. (All four terms must be


Chapter : Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences 267def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> more careful detail, <strong>of</strong> course, than would serve our purposehere.) e equation focuses attention on questions <strong>of</strong> how changes <strong>in</strong>nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>come are split between price <strong>and</strong> output changes <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong>confrontation between <strong>the</strong> actual quantity <strong>of</strong> money <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> forhold<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> money. e latter is what velocity relates to, <strong>and</strong> say<strong>in</strong>g sorem<strong>in</strong>ds us <strong>of</strong> how to make a transition from <strong>the</strong> tautological equation to<strong>the</strong> condition for equilibrium between money’s supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>.e equation <strong>of</strong> exchange enters <strong>in</strong>to examples <strong>of</strong> what I call <strong>the</strong> translationtest. How plausible does <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>flationary wage-pricespiral unfueled by monetary expansion look when its implications aboutQ <strong>and</strong> V are drawn out? How well does <strong>the</strong> Keynesian <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ants<strong>of</strong> aggregate spend<strong>in</strong>g, conceptualized with <strong>the</strong> aid <strong>of</strong> its tautologythat nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>come = consumption + <strong>in</strong>vestment + governmentspend<strong>in</strong>g + exports − imports, translate <strong>in</strong>to terms <strong>of</strong> MV=PQ? Conversely,how well does <strong>the</strong> monetarist formulation translate <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> Keynesianformulation? Try<strong>in</strong>g to translate a proposition from one conceptualframework <strong>in</strong>to ano<strong>the</strong>r can sometimes suggest new <strong>in</strong>sights or exposeconcealed error.Suppose someone ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that <strong>the</strong> equation <strong>of</strong> exchange is false—not just trivial, not just lack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> applications, but false. He <strong>the</strong>reby showsthat he does not underst<strong>and</strong> what <strong>the</strong> equation means <strong>and</strong> how its termsare def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g ways. His position would be like that <strong>of</strong> someoneclaim<strong>in</strong>g to have met an unusual person, a married bachelor, or amarried man who, although not married to any particular woman, is never<strong>the</strong>lessmarried.e equation <strong>of</strong> exchange also illustrates <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t that whe<strong>the</strong>r a particulartautology is useful <strong>in</strong> illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g reality h<strong>in</strong>ges on facts <strong>of</strong> reality.(Compare <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> Po<strong>in</strong>caré’s conventionalism below.) Validity<strong>and</strong> usefulness, falsity <strong>and</strong> uselessness, are not <strong>the</strong> same th<strong>in</strong>gs. A propositionlack<strong>in</strong>g empirical application is not false merely for that reason.We can readily imag<strong>in</strong>e a “chairs” version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> equation <strong>of</strong> exchange.In CV c =PQ, P <strong>and</strong> Q would be <strong>the</strong> same as before, C would be <strong>the</strong> number<strong>of</strong> chairs <strong>in</strong> existence <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> country on average dur<strong>in</strong>g a year, <strong>and</strong> V cwould be <strong>the</strong> “velocity” <strong>of</strong> chairs, mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ratio <strong>of</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>cometo <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> chairs. anks to <strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>itions, CV c =PQ isjust as formally valid as MV=PQ; but because <strong>of</strong> facts about how money omas Hobbes (1651/1968, chaps. 8 <strong>and</strong> 46) suggested that one might test whe<strong>the</strong>ra piece <strong>of</strong> abstract philosophiz<strong>in</strong>g means anyth<strong>in</strong>g by see<strong>in</strong>g how readily it could be translatedfrom <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al language <strong>in</strong>to ano<strong>the</strong>r.


268 Part I: Economicsfunctions that are not also true <strong>of</strong> chairs, <strong>the</strong> money version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> equationhas a usefulness that <strong>the</strong> chairs version lacks. (One might quibbleover exactly what counts as a chair, just as over what counts as money, butsuch quibbles would be relatively peripheral to <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>and</strong> usefulness <strong>of</strong>ei<strong>the</strong>r equation.)As this example illustrates, <strong>the</strong> tautological validity <strong>and</strong> empirical applicability<strong>of</strong> a proposition are not <strong>the</strong> same th<strong>in</strong>g. Be<strong>in</strong>g a tautology ord<strong>in</strong>arilybars a proposition from be<strong>in</strong>g an exact description <strong>of</strong> reality, althoughit may be a stylization. e tautologies mentioned so far are tools, guides,rem<strong>in</strong>ders, illum<strong>in</strong>ators, organiz<strong>in</strong>g devices that may prove useful <strong>in</strong> com<strong>in</strong>gto grips with reality. e ma<strong>the</strong>matician <strong>and</strong> physicist Henri Po<strong>in</strong>caré emphasized <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong>conventions <strong>in</strong> science (Copleston 1985, chap. IX, pp. 271–273; Dantzig1954, esp. pp. 52–53, 64–68; Po<strong>in</strong>caré 1952, 1958). He did not ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>, <strong>of</strong>course, that all scientific propositions are true by mere stipulation, agreement,habit, or custom. He warned <strong>of</strong> too sharp a dichotomy betweenconvention <strong>and</strong> empirical fact. He criticized his disciple Edouard Le Royfor ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g that science consists only <strong>of</strong> conventions <strong>and</strong> owes itsapparent certitude to this fact (Po<strong>in</strong>caré 1958, chap. X, esp. p. 112). To suggestthat <strong>the</strong> scientist actually creates scientific fact itself is go<strong>in</strong>g muchtoo far toward nom<strong>in</strong>alism. Scientific laws are not artificial creations. Wehave no reason to regard <strong>the</strong>m as accidental, though it is impossible toprove <strong>the</strong>y are not (p. 14).Po<strong>in</strong>caré’s position, ra<strong>the</strong>r, is that conventions fruitfully stylize reality(although I am not aware <strong>of</strong> his us<strong>in</strong>g that particular word). Often <strong>the</strong> scientistsharpens up rough or vague concepts, categories, <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. Hereaches propositions that are true by convention or def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>and</strong> so arenot open to falsification. But nei<strong>the</strong>r are <strong>the</strong>y arbitrary. ey have provedconvenient for deal<strong>in</strong>g with reality, just as a decimal co<strong>in</strong>age is more convenient(though not truer) than a nondecimal co<strong>in</strong>age. e properties <strong>of</strong>reality enter <strong>in</strong>to determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r a particular def<strong>in</strong>ition or conventionis useful <strong>in</strong> deal<strong>in</strong>g with it.In ma<strong>the</strong>matical physics, what was orig<strong>in</strong>ally an empirical generalizationmay be so <strong>in</strong>terpreted as to become a disguised def<strong>in</strong>ition, not opento falsification (Copleston 1985, chap. IX, p. 273). When an experimentallaw has received sufficient confirmation, Po<strong>in</strong>caré says, we may ei<strong>the</strong>r


Chapter : Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences 269() leave it open to <strong>in</strong>cessant revision, end<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> demonstration that it isonly approximate or () elevate it <strong>in</strong>to a pr<strong>in</strong>ciple by adopt<strong>in</strong>g conventionsthat make it certa<strong>in</strong>ly true. A crystallized pr<strong>in</strong>ciple “is no longer subjectto <strong>the</strong> test <strong>of</strong> experiment. It is not true or false, it is convenient” (1958,pp. 124–125). Proceed<strong>in</strong>g that way has <strong>of</strong>ten been advantageous, but “if all<strong>the</strong> laws had been transformed <strong>in</strong>to pr<strong>in</strong>ciples noth<strong>in</strong>g would be left <strong>of</strong>science” (p. 125).Actual bodies become slightly deformed when moved, exp<strong>and</strong> whenwarmed, <strong>and</strong> so forth. Yet it would be hopelessly complicated for everystatement about <strong>the</strong> motion <strong>of</strong> a body to allow for its bend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> dilation.(Compare try<strong>in</strong>g to formulate Walras’s Law <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> balance<strong>of</strong>-paymentsaccount<strong>in</strong>g to allow even for misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r a particularproperty transfer was a sale or a gift.) For convenience, we <strong>in</strong>ventrigid bodies <strong>and</strong> idealized types <strong>of</strong> motion (Po<strong>in</strong>caré 1958, pp. 125–126). epropositions <strong>of</strong> mechanics refer to <strong>the</strong>se idealizations, which are never<strong>the</strong>lessuseful because <strong>the</strong>y are somehow close enough to reality. ey are convenient,but convenience—not only for you or me but for all <strong>of</strong> us <strong>and</strong> ourdescendants—has an objective aspect (p. 140).Po<strong>in</strong>caré <strong>in</strong>structively compares science to a library. Experimental physicsbuys <strong>the</strong> books. Ma<strong>the</strong>matical physics—<strong>the</strong> tautological aspect—drawsup <strong>the</strong> catalogue, mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> library much more useful to readers. It alsoreveals gaps <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> collection <strong>and</strong> so helps <strong>the</strong> librarian use his limited fundsjudiciously (1952, pp. 144–145).e laws <strong>of</strong> science, <strong>the</strong>n, are far from mere conventions. ey relateto a reality exist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>of</strong> how human be<strong>in</strong>gs describe it. However,conventions do enter <strong>in</strong>to stat<strong>in</strong>g its laws. Some prove more convenientthan <strong>the</strong>ir alternatives, <strong>and</strong> this difference h<strong>in</strong>ges on <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong>reality. Aga<strong>in</strong>, compare <strong>the</strong> “chairs” version with <strong>the</strong> “money” version <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> equation <strong>of</strong> exchange.e world <strong>of</strong> classical mechanics is an imag<strong>in</strong>ary, sharpened worlddescribable by <strong>in</strong>fallibly true propositions that never<strong>the</strong>less aid <strong>in</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> real world. is imag<strong>in</strong>ary world is a model. Model-build<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>volves use <strong>of</strong> conventional or tautological propositions. For similar remarks about astronomical systems, space, time, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> measurement<strong>of</strong> time, see Po<strong>in</strong>caré 1958, pp. 27–28, 30, 36, 69, 140–141; 1952, pp. 90–91; <strong>and</strong> Dantzig 1954,pp. 52–53, 64–68. On <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>etic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> gases, see Po<strong>in</strong>caré 1958, p. 131; 1952, p. 147; <strong>and</strong>Campbell 1957, pp. 126–131. For a general dist<strong>in</strong>ction between “empirical” <strong>and</strong> “abstract”objects <strong>and</strong> processes, see Z<strong>in</strong>ov’ev 1983, pp. 57–59, 170–171, <strong>and</strong> passim). On relations between models, <strong>the</strong>ories, <strong>and</strong> reality <strong>in</strong> economics <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> “categorymistake” <strong>of</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to test models, see Hausman 1992, pp. 76–79, 245, 273, <strong>and</strong> passim.


270 Part I: Economics Ma<strong>the</strong>matics is probably <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard example <strong>of</strong> a body <strong>of</strong> useful tautologies. (Conant 1953, p. 105, calls ma<strong>the</strong>matics a vast tautology; for Ayer1946/1969, p. 331, “<strong>the</strong> truths <strong>of</strong> logic <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics are analytic propositionsor tautologies,” <strong>and</strong> J.S. Mill was wrong <strong>in</strong> suppos<strong>in</strong>g that a situationoverthrow<strong>in</strong>g any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m could arise.) Although—or because—<strong>the</strong>propositions <strong>of</strong> geometry <strong>and</strong> trigonometry are tautologically true, <strong>the</strong>yare <strong>in</strong>dispensable <strong>in</strong> survey<strong>in</strong>g. e concept <strong>of</strong> zero radically simplifiesarithmetic <strong>and</strong> account<strong>in</strong>g.In <strong>the</strong> natural sciences, classical (Newtonian) mechanics perhaps comesclosest to shar<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> tautological character <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics. e formula“force = mass × acceleration” perta<strong>in</strong>s to reality, to be sure, but it alsorepresents <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> def<strong>in</strong>itions. “[T]he formula which connectsstatic force <strong>and</strong> acceleration ... is a tautology” (Dantzig 1954, p. 103). “Ifone wishes, one may say mass is def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> this manner, provided onealready knows what force is. One might prefer to assume that mass is<strong>the</strong> known quantity <strong>and</strong> def<strong>in</strong>e force by this equation. What is seen here... is <strong>the</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> relations between various concepts <strong>in</strong> order todef<strong>in</strong>e terms. Which comes first <strong>and</strong> which comes later is <strong>of</strong>ten a matter<strong>of</strong> choice” (Teller 1980, p. 39). e same formula f =ma illustrates <strong>the</strong> tautological element <strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gunits <strong>of</strong> measurement, whose importance <strong>in</strong> science is undeniable. In<strong>the</strong> meter-kilogram-second system, force is measured <strong>in</strong> newtons, onenewton be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> force required to give a mass <strong>of</strong> one kilogram an acceleration<strong>of</strong> one meter per second per second. (e unit <strong>of</strong> work or energy,<strong>the</strong> joule, is a force <strong>of</strong> one newton operat<strong>in</strong>g over a distance <strong>of</strong> one meter;e usefulness <strong>of</strong> model-build<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> some cases <strong>and</strong> for some purposes hardly justifies<strong>in</strong>sistence on it as <strong>the</strong> only acceptable method; it hardly justifies badger<strong>in</strong>g researcherswith rout<strong>in</strong>e cries <strong>of</strong> “What is your model?” <strong>and</strong> “How can your model be tested?” Sometimes tautologies look deceptively like brute facts <strong>of</strong> reality. It seems a brute factthat might quite conceivably have turned out o<strong>the</strong>rwise that exactly 143 prime numbersoccur <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> range <strong>of</strong> 100 to 1000. Yet this specific count follows rigorously from <strong>the</strong> veryconcepts <strong>of</strong> number <strong>and</strong> prime number. Although experience played an <strong>in</strong>dispensable role <strong>in</strong> its genesis, geometry is not anexperimental science. “[E]xperience does not tell us which geometry is true, it tells uswhich is <strong>the</strong> most convenient” (Po<strong>in</strong>caré, Space <strong>and</strong> Geometry, quoted without page number<strong>in</strong> Dantzig 1954, p. 52). Po<strong>in</strong>caré 1952, chap. VI, esp. pp. 97–106, makes similar but more detailed remarkson <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrelations <strong>of</strong> force, mass, <strong>and</strong> acceleration. Compare Meyerson1921/1991, esp. pp. 439–440, on <strong>the</strong> deductive nature <strong>of</strong> “rational mechanics.”


Chapter : Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences 271<strong>and</strong> 1055 joules = one British <strong>the</strong>rmal unit, a unit <strong>of</strong> some notoriety <strong>in</strong> U.S.tax-policy discussions <strong>of</strong> early 1993.)Electrical identities are broadly similar <strong>in</strong> character to <strong>the</strong> mechanicalidentities. e def<strong>in</strong>itional <strong>in</strong>terrelations among such units as joule, watt,volt, ampere, coulomb, <strong>and</strong> newton aga<strong>in</strong> illustrate tautologies at work.Gustav Robert Kirchh<strong>of</strong>f ’s laws for direct-current circuits are rem<strong>in</strong>iscent<strong>of</strong> Walras’s Law. ey guide <strong>the</strong> formulation <strong>of</strong> equations to besolved for <strong>the</strong> currents <strong>and</strong> voltages <strong>in</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> complicated circuits (Nau1958, pp. 39–43, 52, 72–73, 213, 305). e current law states that <strong>the</strong> sum<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> currents directed toward a node equals <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> currents directedaway from <strong>the</strong> node; with algebraic sign given proper attention, <strong>the</strong> sum<strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> currents directed toward a node is zero. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> voltagelaw, “<strong>the</strong> potential difference between two po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> a circuit is <strong>the</strong> algebraicsum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> potential differences (scalar quantities) across each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>elements traced between <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ts”; <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> voltages aroundany closed loop is thus zero (Nau 1958, pp. 39–40). Nau remarks (pp. 39,41) that <strong>the</strong> voltage law holds “[b]y def<strong>in</strong>ition” <strong>and</strong> that “[b]ookkeep<strong>in</strong>gwill be facilitated” by certa<strong>in</strong> conventions <strong>of</strong> notation.Biology tells us that organisms possess<strong>in</strong>g traits conducive to survival <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ir environments tend to survive <strong>and</strong> reproduce; o<strong>the</strong>rs do not. is pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<strong>of</strong> natural selection, though practically a tautology, yields <strong>in</strong>sights.Classify<strong>in</strong>g organisms <strong>in</strong>to species, genera, <strong>and</strong> higher orders servesga<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> assess<strong>in</strong>g evidence bear<strong>in</strong>g on heredity <strong>and</strong> evolution. Idealconceptualizations (never fully achieved) would make it tautologically true<strong>of</strong> a particular organism that, on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> its characteristics, it falls<strong>in</strong>to predef<strong>in</strong>ed classes. Ever s<strong>in</strong>ce Darw<strong>in</strong>, taxonomists have recognizedthat more than mere resemblance—ra<strong>the</strong>r, prop<strong>in</strong>quity <strong>of</strong> descent—is<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> classification. Darw<strong>in</strong> warned aga<strong>in</strong>st confus<strong>in</strong>g similaritiesdue to common descent with spurious similarities due to convergent evolutionunder environmental circumstances (Mayr 1982, pp. 210–212). Controversieshave arisen among taxonomists <strong>of</strong> various phenetic schools, whichrefra<strong>in</strong> from tak<strong>in</strong>g evidence from descent <strong>in</strong>to consideration, <strong>and</strong> adherents<strong>of</strong> cladistics, which does try to consider descent, <strong>and</strong> by a virtuallyautomatic method that would force careful analysis <strong>and</strong> proper weight<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> all characters. Both groups <strong>of</strong> taxonomists strive to elim<strong>in</strong>ate subjectivity<strong>and</strong> arbitrar<strong>in</strong>ess from classifications (Mayr 1982, pp. 209–233). e I am <strong>in</strong>debted to Roger Garrison for call<strong>in</strong>g my attention to Kirchh<strong>of</strong>f ’s laws <strong>and</strong> forthis reference.


272 Part I: Economicsrelevant po<strong>in</strong>t is that biologists have found it worthwhile to <strong>in</strong>vestigate<strong>and</strong> argue over <strong>the</strong> most expedient method <strong>of</strong> fram<strong>in</strong>g classifications, concepts,<strong>and</strong> tautologies.Suitable classifications are important <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistics also. Examples <strong>in</strong>clude<strong>the</strong> structural classification <strong>of</strong> languages as agglut<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g, isolat<strong>in</strong>g,<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>flect<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir classification by families or descent, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classification<strong>of</strong> consonants as aspirated or unaspirated, voiced or unvoiced.It is tautologically true that <strong>in</strong> English <strong>the</strong> sound <strong>of</strong> g is <strong>the</strong> voiced <strong>and</strong>unaspirated counterpart <strong>of</strong> k, which is unvoiced <strong>and</strong> aspirated. e verymean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “phoneme” implies that <strong>in</strong> any particular language, two (similar)sounds ei<strong>the</strong>r do or do not constitute <strong>the</strong> same phoneme; <strong>the</strong>re canbe no <strong>in</strong>-between degree <strong>of</strong> resemblance <strong>in</strong> this respect.Many more examples <strong>of</strong> tautology <strong>and</strong> truth by convention appearavailable <strong>in</strong> natural science. e several conservation laws, <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong>least action, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> time-m<strong>in</strong>imiz<strong>in</strong>g path <strong>of</strong> light (Gleick 1992, pp. 361,366) are worth attention. So is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>verse-square feature common to Newtoniangravitation, Coulomb’s law <strong>of</strong> electrostatic attraction <strong>and</strong> repulsion,<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensity <strong>of</strong> sound (subject to <strong>in</strong>terferences), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensity <strong>of</strong> light<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r electromagnetic radiation. is property accords with empiricalobservation, but one wonders whe<strong>the</strong>r it may not have a ma<strong>the</strong>maticalaspect mak<strong>in</strong>g it more than a brute fact. e area <strong>of</strong> a sphere is 4π times<strong>the</strong> square <strong>of</strong> its radius, suggest<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensity <strong>of</strong> anyth<strong>in</strong>g emanat<strong>in</strong>gfrom a central po<strong>in</strong>t is diluted over a larger area <strong>the</strong> greater <strong>the</strong> distancefrom that po<strong>in</strong>t, <strong>and</strong> diluted <strong>in</strong> such a way that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensity is <strong>in</strong>verselyproportional to that squared distance. Teller 1980, pp. 39–42, speaks <strong>in</strong>this connection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> gravitational force.) eformula for <strong>the</strong> area <strong>of</strong> a sphere “implies that <strong>the</strong> total energy cross<strong>in</strong>gany sphere surround<strong>in</strong>g a po<strong>in</strong>t source is <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> radius. us,<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>verse-square law for <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensity <strong>of</strong> radiation at a distance r from apo<strong>in</strong>t source is <strong>in</strong> accord with <strong>the</strong> law <strong>of</strong> conservation <strong>of</strong> energy—<strong>the</strong> totalenergy <strong>of</strong> a wave rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> same even though <strong>the</strong> wave is spread over agreater area” (Ditchburn 1981, p. 933). Ma<strong>the</strong>matical tautologies are familiar <strong>in</strong> microeconomics. Maximizations<strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it, utility, <strong>and</strong> welfare entail equalization <strong>of</strong> various marg<strong>in</strong>al Compare Richard Feynman’s view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conservation laws as sketched <strong>in</strong> Gleick1992, p. 361.


Chapter : Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences 273magnitudes. Descriptions <strong>of</strong> long-run equilibrium under perfect competitionare tautological yet illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g. In macroeconomics, work<strong>in</strong>g out<strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>of</strong> various quantifiable national <strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong> productconcepts has been deemed worthy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nobel prize.e money-multiplier formula <strong>of</strong> money-<strong>and</strong>-bank<strong>in</strong>g textbooks,which <strong>in</strong>volves various reserve <strong>and</strong> currency/deposit ratios, is tautologicallytrue when <strong>the</strong> ratios <strong>in</strong> it are <strong>in</strong>terpreted as actual ratios. When itsratios are re<strong>in</strong>terpreted as desired ones <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> formula itself re<strong>in</strong>terpretedas an equilibrium condition, <strong>the</strong> discussion center<strong>in</strong>g around it becomes a<strong>the</strong>ory ra<strong>the</strong>r than a tautology. (Compare <strong>the</strong> transition, mentioned earlier,between <strong>the</strong> tautological equation <strong>of</strong> exchange <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> condition <strong>of</strong>monetary equilibrium.)e government budget constra<strong>in</strong>t po<strong>in</strong>ts out <strong>the</strong> logical, not merelyempirical, necessity that government spend<strong>in</strong>g be covered by <strong>the</strong> aggregate<strong>of</strong> tax <strong>and</strong> similar revenues, borrow<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> money issue. Any propositionor proposal contradict<strong>in</strong>g this tautology is immediately discredited.Sheer arithmetic, if heeded, should br<strong>in</strong>g some discipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>to political discussion.If a politician proposes to <strong>in</strong>crease government spend<strong>in</strong>g, reducetaxes, <strong>and</strong> reduce <strong>the</strong> budget deficit, he is com<strong>in</strong>g awfully close to imply<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> money, to be counted as a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> revenue, unless hecan give a plausible Lafferesque explanation <strong>of</strong> how reduced tax rates willnever<strong>the</strong>less <strong>in</strong>crease tax revenues. President Bush’s 1992 campaign proposalfor lett<strong>in</strong>g taxpayers designate 10 percent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir payments to g<strong>of</strong>or reduc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> national debt—debt, not deficit—came awfully close, <strong>in</strong>its context, to imply<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> new money.Paul Samuelson reports that <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matician Stanislaw Ulamused to tease me by say<strong>in</strong>g, “Name me one proposition <strong>in</strong> all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> socialsciences which is both true <strong>and</strong> non-trivial.” is was a test that I alwaysfailed. But now, some thirty years later, on <strong>the</strong> staircase so to speak, anappropriate answer occurs to me: e Ricardian <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> comparativeadvantage; <strong>the</strong> demonstration that trade is mutually pr<strong>of</strong>itable even whenone country is absolutely more—or less—productive <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> everycommodity. at it is logically true need not be argued before a ma<strong>the</strong>matician;that it is not trivial is attested by <strong>the</strong> thous<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> important<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligent men who have never been able to grasp <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e for<strong>the</strong>mselves or to believe it after it was expla<strong>in</strong>ed to <strong>the</strong>m. (1969/1972,p. 683)Significantly, Samuelson calls <strong>the</strong> proposition “logically true,” <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwords, a tautology. e pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> comparative advantage is best seen,


274 Part I: Economics<strong>in</strong> my concurr<strong>in</strong>g view, not as a substantive empirical proposition but asa piece <strong>of</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g useful <strong>in</strong> expos<strong>in</strong>g a common fallacy. at fallacyrejects <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> mutually beneficial trade between two countriesone <strong>of</strong> which is more efficient or enjoys greater productivity or lower realcost than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r across <strong>the</strong> entire range <strong>of</strong> potentially tradable goods.Instead <strong>of</strong> quibbl<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g or possibility <strong>of</strong> such comparisons,<strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> comparative advantage concocts, for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> argument,an extreme case <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> postulated difference is unequivocal. It goeson to show that even <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case supposedly most embarrass<strong>in</strong>g forfree trade, ga<strong>in</strong>s from trade are available to both parties. It provides an“even-if/even-<strong>the</strong>n” argument.-- Fur<strong>the</strong>r examples <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational economics are <strong>in</strong>structive enough tomerit a separate section. e concepts <strong>of</strong> balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments account<strong>in</strong>g,as <strong>of</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary account<strong>in</strong>g, are tautologies. Just as <strong>the</strong> two sides <strong>of</strong> afirm’s balance sheet have identical totals, thanks to carefully formulated<strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g concepts, <strong>the</strong> same is true <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> credit or plus <strong>and</strong> debit orm<strong>in</strong>us sides <strong>of</strong> a country’s balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments statement for a def<strong>in</strong>itetime period. is equality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two totals presupposes complete <strong>and</strong>accurate <strong>in</strong>formation on all aspects <strong>of</strong> all relevant transactions. In practice,<strong>in</strong>adequacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation plagues presentation <strong>of</strong> an actual statement.Conceptual difficulties (concern<strong>in</strong>g, for example, <strong>the</strong> uncerta<strong>in</strong> classification<strong>of</strong> transactors as residents or nonresidents, <strong>the</strong> ambiguous dat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>some transactions, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>l<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> smuggled goods) require adopt<strong>in</strong>gsomewhat arbitrary conventions.Quibbles can thus arise. e balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments concept, like o<strong>the</strong>raccount<strong>in</strong>g conventions, <strong>the</strong> equation <strong>of</strong> exchange, <strong>and</strong> Walras’s Law, maybe defended aga<strong>in</strong>st quibbles by expound<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> rationale <strong>of</strong>analytical tautologies. An analogy comes to m<strong>in</strong>d with what StephanKörner calls “more or less near-empirical, but still non-empirical ma<strong>the</strong>matics”(1966, chap. VII, esp. pp. 98, 106–107). In reality, boundariesbetween various classes may be fuzzy, <strong>and</strong> a proposition about a particularentity be<strong>in</strong>g a member or nonmember <strong>of</strong> a particular class may be While one might sensibly do empirical research related to comparative advantage<strong>in</strong> some way or ano<strong>the</strong>r, it would be a category mistake to embark on test<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<strong>of</strong> comparative advantage, just as on test<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Heckscher-Ohl<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>orem or <strong>the</strong>Rybczynski <strong>the</strong>orem or <strong>the</strong> equation <strong>of</strong> exchange.


Chapter : Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences 275“neutral” ra<strong>the</strong>r than “true” or “false.” Still, we may treat <strong>in</strong>exact predicates<strong>and</strong> classes as if <strong>the</strong>y were exact, so replac<strong>in</strong>g neutral propositions bynonneutral ones. We can exhibit arithmetical concepts that are naturally<strong>and</strong> frequently identified—though never identical—with empirical ones.Discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se “complexes” is not empirical; it amounts at best to a“near-empirical” arithmetic. In balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments account<strong>in</strong>g, we idealize<strong>and</strong> sharpen <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>in</strong>volved, arriv<strong>in</strong>g at propositions that arelogical ra<strong>the</strong>r than brute empirical truths.No one, to my knowledge, denies that <strong>the</strong>se “near-empirical” categories<strong>and</strong> propositions are useful <strong>in</strong> analyz<strong>in</strong>g empirical reality. In particular,if transactions are classified <strong>in</strong>to separate “accounts” <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> balance <strong>of</strong>payments (say current account, private capital account, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial settlementsaccount), <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> “pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> compensat<strong>in</strong>g balances” comes <strong>in</strong>toplay: imbalance <strong>in</strong> one direction <strong>in</strong> one or more <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> accounts must bematched by opposite imbalance <strong>in</strong> one or more <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g accounts.(Compare Walras’s Law: excess dem<strong>and</strong> or supply <strong>of</strong> one th<strong>in</strong>g must bematched by opposite imbalance <strong>of</strong> one or more o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs.) If a countryis runn<strong>in</strong>g a deficit on current account, <strong>the</strong> balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments tautologyunderscores <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> how that deficit is be<strong>in</strong>g “f<strong>in</strong>anced.” Anenlighten<strong>in</strong>g truism is sometimes forgotten: no deficit can arise or persistunless it gets f<strong>in</strong>anced somehow or o<strong>the</strong>r. It is similarly enlighten<strong>in</strong>g torecognize a country’s balance <strong>of</strong> payments as <strong>the</strong> aggregate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualbalances <strong>of</strong> payments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> persons, firms, government agencies, <strong>and</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r organizations compos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> national economy.e central formula <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> three lead<strong>in</strong>g approaches to balance-<strong>of</strong>-paymentsanalysis—<strong>the</strong> elasticities, absorption, <strong>and</strong> monetaryapproaches—is valid because <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> terms itconta<strong>in</strong>s. e question <strong>of</strong> how <strong>the</strong>se three approaches <strong>in</strong>terrelate po<strong>in</strong>tsto <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> Niels Bohr’s “pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> complementarity” (Teller1980, pp. 93, 105–106, 138–140) beyond its orig<strong>in</strong>al range, as Bohr himselfhad foreseen. He recommended treat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> wave <strong>and</strong> particle <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong>light as complementary: physicists could legitimately employ each <strong>the</strong>orywhere it seemed to work, even if <strong>the</strong>y did not (yet) know how to reconcilethose seem<strong>in</strong>gly contradictory <strong>the</strong>ories. In balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments analysis,similarly, economists may legitimately draw whatever <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>the</strong>y can Körner ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that “[d]eductive abstraction, <strong>the</strong> cutt<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> irrelevancies, ...<strong>the</strong> elim<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>exactness, <strong>the</strong> draw<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> sharp demarcation-l<strong>in</strong>es through <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>iteconceptual borders” (1966, p. 167) are applied, for example, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> various systems <strong>of</strong> geometry(p. 112) <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> classical mechanics (p. 159).


276 Part I: Economicsfrom each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> three approaches, if necessary leav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir possible reconciliationuntil later.e absorption approach relates a country’s <strong>in</strong>ternational surplus (ordeficit) on current account to its excess (or shortfall) <strong>of</strong> national production<strong>in</strong> relation to national absorption, <strong>the</strong> latter be<strong>in</strong>g output absorbed<strong>in</strong> consumption, <strong>in</strong>vestment, <strong>and</strong> government activity. Equivalently, itrelates <strong>the</strong> country’s current-account surplus (or deficit) to <strong>the</strong> excess (orshortfall) <strong>of</strong> national sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> relation to national <strong>in</strong>vestment, a governmentsurplus or deficit count<strong>in</strong>g as part <strong>of</strong> or as a deduction from nationalsav<strong>in</strong>g.e monetary approach relates a country’s overall <strong>in</strong>ternational surplusor deficit (roughly, its balance on <strong>the</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial-settlements concept) tochanges <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> aggregate balance sheet <strong>of</strong> its monetary <strong>in</strong>stitutions. Itscentral formula, like <strong>the</strong> absorption-approach formula, h<strong>in</strong>ges on <strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>gdef<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>of</strong> its terms. Whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> approach is useful <strong>in</strong> practicedepends largely on whe<strong>the</strong>r monetary <strong>and</strong> nonmonetary accounts can bedist<strong>in</strong>guished clearly enough. One must avoid read<strong>in</strong>g causal significance<strong>in</strong>to mere tautological truths. It is a mistake, <strong>in</strong> particular, to supposethat growth <strong>of</strong> a country’s money supply necessarily represents <strong>in</strong>tentionalbuildups <strong>of</strong> cash balances.e elasticities approach centers around an algebraic expression whosesign supposedly <strong>in</strong>dicates whe<strong>the</strong>r currency devaluation “improves” or“worsens” <strong>the</strong> country’s balance <strong>of</strong> payments. is “stability” formula featuresterms for dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> supply elasticities <strong>of</strong> imports <strong>and</strong> exports. ema<strong>the</strong>matics <strong>of</strong> its derivation makes <strong>the</strong> formula tautologically valid, presuppos<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> it special though <strong>of</strong>ten tacit def<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> elasticities(<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> what respects <strong>the</strong>y are mutatis mut<strong>and</strong>is ra<strong>the</strong>r than ceterisparibus elasticities). Whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> approach is useful for analysis <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> real world depends largely on whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> conceptions <strong>of</strong> elasticitynecessary to make <strong>the</strong> formula correct are near enough to or too far fromord<strong>in</strong>ary conceptions <strong>of</strong> price elasticity.Sidney S. Alex<strong>and</strong>er (1952; 1959) criticized <strong>the</strong> elasticities analysis <strong>of</strong>exchange-rate adjustment as mere implicit <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g. e formula for“normal” response <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> balance <strong>of</strong> payments derives purely from manipulation<strong>of</strong> def<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>and</strong> has no operational content, he said, unless <strong>the</strong>import <strong>and</strong> export dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> supply functions whose elasticities enter<strong>in</strong>to it are <strong>in</strong>dependently specified. ose functions can hardly be specifiedso that <strong>the</strong>ir elasticities are “partial” elasticities, <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g how sensitively<strong>the</strong> quantities respond to <strong>the</strong>ir own prices when <strong>in</strong>comes <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r


Chapter : Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences 277prices rema<strong>in</strong> unchanged; for exchange-rate adjustment simply cannotleave <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs unchanged. Alternatively, <strong>the</strong> elasticities might be<strong>in</strong>terpreted as “total,” <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g how <strong>the</strong> quantities respond when not only<strong>the</strong>ir own prices but also everyth<strong>in</strong>g else change as <strong>in</strong> fact <strong>the</strong>y will change<strong>in</strong> direct or <strong>in</strong>direct response to <strong>the</strong> exchange-rate adjustment. e stabilityformula <strong>the</strong>n becomes tautologically correct but empty. No one couldknow <strong>the</strong> sizes <strong>of</strong> its “total” elasticities without already hav<strong>in</strong>g a completeanalysis <strong>of</strong> how domestic <strong>and</strong> foreign economies respond to <strong>the</strong> exchangerate. Carried to its ultimate degree, <strong>the</strong> total-elasticities approach wouldassert—emptily—that what happens depends on <strong>the</strong> elasticity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> country’sbalance <strong>of</strong> payments with respect to <strong>the</strong> exchange rate (Pearce 1970,passim).But <strong>the</strong> futility <strong>of</strong> an approach carried to its ultimate does not implyfutility carried judiciously part way. e analyst seeks some compromisebetween mean<strong>in</strong>gful but unmanageable realism <strong>and</strong> detail at one extreme<strong>and</strong> apparent simplicity but empt<strong>in</strong>ess at <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r extreme. In balance-<strong>of</strong>paymentsanalysis, such a compromise may well <strong>in</strong>volve ignor<strong>in</strong>g or stripp<strong>in</strong>gaway complications concern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> exact specification <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> elasticities.An admittedly tautological formula does never<strong>the</strong>less prove useful <strong>in</strong>contemplat<strong>in</strong>g what conditions would contribute <strong>and</strong> what ones wouldimpair “normal” response <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> balance <strong>of</strong> payments to <strong>the</strong> exchangerate. e examples presented here help one recognize a particular style or <strong>in</strong>gredient<strong>of</strong> argument <strong>and</strong> better underst<strong>and</strong> its application <strong>in</strong> particular contextsfrom its perhaps more familiar use <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. is recognition shouldhelp a writer forestall or answer illegitimate objections, such as empiricalquibbles raised aga<strong>in</strong>st tautologically true propositions like Walras’s Law<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> equation <strong>of</strong> exchange. Concepts may legitimately be formulatedso that certa<strong>in</strong> propositions about relations among <strong>the</strong>m are not merelytrue but necessarily true. Many propositions <strong>of</strong> science are true as a matter<strong>of</strong> convention, yet conventions are not arbitrary. Whe<strong>the</strong>r a convention isuseful <strong>and</strong> convenient h<strong>in</strong>ges on whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> how it makes contact withreality. Still o<strong>the</strong>r examples <strong>of</strong> tautology <strong>in</strong> economics may be found. James R. Wible(1982–1983) gives an <strong>in</strong>sightful if unenthusiastic review <strong>of</strong> tautological str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>macroeconomic literature <strong>of</strong> rational expectations.


278 Part I: EconomicsAlex<strong>and</strong>er, Sidney S. “Effects <strong>of</strong> a Devaluation on a Trade Balance.” IMF StaffPapers, (April 1952): 263–278.. “Effects <strong>of</strong> a Devaluation: A Simplified Syn<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>of</strong> Elasticities <strong>and</strong>Absorption Approaches.” American Economic Review (March 1959): 22–42.Ayer, Alfred J. “e A Priori.” 1946. In Necessary <strong>Truth</strong>, edited by L.W. Sumner<strong>and</strong> J. Woods, 27–43. New York: R<strong>and</strong>om House, 1969.Baumol, William J. “Monetary <strong>and</strong> Value eory: Comment.” Review <strong>of</strong> EconomicStudies (October 1960): 29–31.. Economic eory <strong>and</strong> Operations Analysis. 2ⁿ ed. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:Prentice Hall, 1965.Campbell, Norman R. Foundations <strong>of</strong> Science. 1919. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted New York: Dover,1957.Conant, James B. Modern Science <strong>and</strong> Modern Man. Garden City: DoubledayAnchor Books, 1953.Copleston, Frederick. A History <strong>of</strong> Philosophy. Vols. 7 to 9. New York: Doubleday,Image Book, 1985.Dantzig, Tobias. Henri Po<strong>in</strong>caré. New York: Scribner’s, 1954.Ditchburn, R.W. “Light.” In Encyclopedia Britannica, vol. 10: 928–949. Chicago:Encyclopaedia Britannica, 1981.Gleick, James. Genius: e Life <strong>and</strong> Science <strong>of</strong> Richard Feynman. New York: Pan<strong>the</strong>on,1992.Harsanyi, John C. <strong>Essays</strong> on Ethics, Social Behavior, <strong>and</strong> Scientific Explanation.Dordrecht <strong>and</strong> Boston: Reidel, 1976.Hausman, Daniel M. e Inexact <strong>and</strong> Separate Science <strong>of</strong> Economics. Cambridge,U.K., <strong>and</strong> New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992.Hobbes, omas. Leviathan. 1651. Harmondsworth <strong>and</strong> Baltimore: Pengu<strong>in</strong>,1968.Körner, Stephan. Experience <strong>and</strong> eory. New York: Humanities Press, 1966.Lange, Oskar. “Say’s Law: A Restatement <strong>and</strong> Criticism.” In Studies <strong>in</strong> Ma<strong>the</strong>maticalEconomics <strong>and</strong> Econometrics, edited by O. Lange et al., 49–68. Chicago:University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1942.


Chapter : Tautologies <strong>in</strong> Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences 279Laudan, Larry. Progress <strong>and</strong> Its Problems. Berkeley <strong>and</strong> Los Angeles: University<strong>of</strong> California Press, 1977.Mayr, Ernst. e Growth <strong>of</strong> Biological ought. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press<strong>of</strong> Harvard University Press, 1982.Meyerson, Émile. Explanation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Sciences. 1921. Translated by Mary-AliceSipfle <strong>and</strong> David A. Sipfle. Dordrecht <strong>and</strong> Boston: Kluwer, 1991.Nau, Robert H. Basic Electrical Eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g. New York: Ronald Press, 1958.Newton-Smith, W.H. e Rationality <strong>of</strong> Science. Boston <strong>and</strong> London: Routledge& Kegan Paul, 1981.Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Don. Money, Interest, <strong>and</strong> Prices. 2ⁿ ed. New York: Harper & Row,1965.. “Walras’s Law.” In e New Palgrave, vol. 4: 863–868. New York: StocktonPress, 1987.Pearce, I.F. International Trade. New York: Norton, 1970.Po<strong>in</strong>caré, Henri. Science <strong>and</strong> Hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Translated by “W.J.G.” New York: Dover,1952.. e Value <strong>of</strong> Science. Translated by G.B. Halsted. New York: Dover, 1958.Samuelson, Paul A. “e Way <strong>of</strong> an Economist.” 1969. Presidential Address <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> International Economic Association. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> e Collected ScientificPapers <strong>of</strong> Paul A. Samuelson, vol. 3: 675–685. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press,1972.Teller, Edward. e Pursuit <strong>of</strong> Simplicity. Malibu: Pepperd<strong>in</strong>e University Press,1980.Wible, James R. “e Rational Expectations Tautologies.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Post KeynesianEconomics (W<strong>in</strong>ter 1982/1983): 199–207.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B., <strong>and</strong> Alan Rab<strong>in</strong>. “Monetary Aspects <strong>of</strong> Walras’s Law <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>Stock-Flow Problem.” Atlantic Economic Journal 25 (March 1997): 18–36.Z<strong>in</strong>ov’ev, A.A. Logical Physics. Translated by O.A. Germogenova. Edited byR.S. Cohen. Dordrecht <strong>and</strong> Boston: D. Reidel Publish<strong>in</strong>g Company, 1983.


Politics <strong>and</strong>Philosophy


Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics * e very topic <strong>of</strong> ethics requires dipp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to metaphysics. Although Icannot settle an old issue, I must recognize it. Are <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ actions<strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong>ir decisions, desires, <strong>and</strong> characters fully determ<strong>in</strong>ed by circumstancesultimately outside <strong>the</strong>ir own control? If that were true—ifpeople lack free will <strong>and</strong> true choice—<strong>the</strong>n personal responsibility wouldlack mean<strong>in</strong>g. Praise <strong>and</strong> blame, reward <strong>and</strong> punishment, would have noapplication; <strong>and</strong> ethics as a field <strong>of</strong> study would lack any genu<strong>in</strong>e subjectmatter.is position, right or wrong, seems to have been <strong>the</strong> position <strong>of</strong>Immanuel Kant. roughout his Groundwork (1785/1964), Kant acknowledgesan ant<strong>in</strong>omy between freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> will <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> prevalence <strong>of</strong>causal laws <strong>of</strong> nature. He ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s, however, that freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> willis a necessary presupposition <strong>of</strong> morality. He suggests that <strong>the</strong> ant<strong>in</strong>omymight somehow be resolved through his dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligible<strong>and</strong> sensible worlds (noumenal <strong>and</strong> phenomenal worlds, <strong>in</strong> his technicalterm<strong>in</strong>ology). Experience, filtered through <strong>the</strong> Kantian “categories”<strong>of</strong> perception <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, imposes <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> tight causality; butunknowable characteristics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> noumenal world <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselvesmight make freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human will genu<strong>in</strong>e. Confessedly, all this isquite mysterious to me.e terms “free will” (or “free choice”) <strong>and</strong> “determ<strong>in</strong>ism” have noagreed precise mean<strong>in</strong>gs, so I cannot beg<strong>in</strong> by def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m. Explor<strong>in</strong>gwhat <strong>the</strong>se terms <strong>and</strong> concepts might mean <strong>and</strong> how <strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong>terrelate is ama<strong>in</strong> task <strong>of</strong> this appendix.We must, however, avoid “essentialism.” As criticized by Karl Popper(e.g., 1985, pp. 88–94), essentialism means focus<strong>in</strong>g on one or more pieces*Appendix to Chapter 2, pp. 40–58 <strong>and</strong> endnotes, <strong>in</strong> my Ethics as Social Science (Cheltenham,U.K., <strong>and</strong> Northampton, Mass.: Elgar, 2001).283


284 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>of</strong> term<strong>in</strong>ology, suppos<strong>in</strong>g that each one labels a def<strong>in</strong>ite aspect <strong>of</strong> reality,brood<strong>in</strong>g over <strong>the</strong>se aspects or concepts to grasp <strong>the</strong> “essence” <strong>of</strong> each, <strong>and</strong>perhaps brood<strong>in</strong>g fur<strong>the</strong>r over whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> realities correspond<strong>in</strong>g to twoor more concepts could exist toge<strong>the</strong>r. Try<strong>in</strong>g to ga<strong>in</strong> knowledge <strong>in</strong> thisway proceeds backward. Perceiv<strong>in</strong>g uniformities <strong>and</strong> diversities <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> realworld belongs ahead <strong>of</strong> brood<strong>in</strong>g over words to label <strong>the</strong>m. Conceivably,traditional formulations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole supposed issue <strong>of</strong> free will versusdeterm<strong>in</strong>ism will prove misconceived. My admiration for two ethicists <strong>in</strong> particular, Moritz Schlick <strong>and</strong> HenryHazlitt, predisposed me toward <strong>the</strong>ir solutions; yet <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> end I f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>m<strong>in</strong>complete or o<strong>the</strong>rwise unsatisfy<strong>in</strong>g. Schlick regarded <strong>the</strong> supposed issueas a mere pseudo-problem: determ<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> free will reconcile (1930/1961,chap. VII). Causality can operate while leav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividuals some freedomnot only over what acts <strong>the</strong>y perform but also over what choices <strong>the</strong>y make.e opposite <strong>of</strong> freedom is compulsion, <strong>and</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ation does not meancompulsion. In <strong>the</strong> words <strong>of</strong> R.E. Hobart, whose views are discussedbelow, compulsion implies causation but causation does not necessarilyimply compulsion. Schlick identifies a confusion between descriptive <strong>and</strong> prescriptivelaws. Scientific laws describe how <strong>the</strong> world works; <strong>the</strong>y do not prescribeevents; <strong>the</strong>y do not resemble totally enforced legislation mak<strong>in</strong>g eventsunfold as <strong>the</strong>y do. Kepler’s Laws describe how <strong>the</strong> planets revolve around<strong>the</strong> sun; <strong>the</strong>y are not prescriptions compell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m to revolve as <strong>the</strong>y do.e law <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> describes how buyers respond to alternative levels <strong>of</strong>an item’s price (apart from o<strong>the</strong>r overrid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluences); it does not compelbuyers to behave <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> way it describes. Walter Eucken (1950, pp. 50–51, 329–330) effectively blasts such essentialism or conceptualrealism <strong>in</strong> economics. Just what is compulsion? How may we dist<strong>in</strong>guish acts done under compulsion fromfree acts for which a person is responsible? In a sense, as Gerald Dwork<strong>in</strong> (1970/1984)notes, a person does his every act because he prefers it to any alternative open to himunder <strong>the</strong> circumstances—even submitt<strong>in</strong>g to a highwayman. Dwork<strong>in</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>guishes,<strong>the</strong>n, between two sorts <strong>of</strong> desires or reasons for action. A free act is one motivated by areason that <strong>the</strong> agent f<strong>in</strong>ds acceptable. A person acts under compulsion when respond<strong>in</strong>gto a reason that he does not want to have.Although Dwork<strong>in</strong> may be on <strong>the</strong> right track, his dist<strong>in</strong>ction is <strong>in</strong>exact. One mayundergo an operation, free from compulsion, while wish<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> reason for <strong>the</strong> operationdid not exist.


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 285ese dist<strong>in</strong>ctions help expla<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong>n, how a person could conceivablybe choos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g free from compulsion even when his choices <strong>and</strong>actions are causally determ<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple predictable. e opposite,presumably, would be choices made <strong>and</strong> actions taken by sheer chance orbaseless caprice. Choices <strong>and</strong> actions need not be stochastic or capriciousto be properly called free.If <strong>the</strong>ir choices <strong>and</strong> actions were totally unfree, people could not properlybe held answerable for <strong>the</strong>m. We do not blame a person for fir<strong>in</strong>ga shot if someone stronger forced <strong>the</strong> gun <strong>in</strong>to his h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> pulled hisf<strong>in</strong>ger aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> trigger. We do not hold someone guilty <strong>of</strong> a crime if hewas genu<strong>in</strong>ely <strong>in</strong>sane <strong>and</strong> lacked any control over his decision <strong>and</strong> action.It would be po<strong>in</strong>tless to hold <strong>the</strong> man whose h<strong>and</strong> was forcibly manipulatedor <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sane person accountable for an action not truly his own.Nei<strong>the</strong>r is responsible because nei<strong>the</strong>r enjoyed freedom <strong>of</strong> choice <strong>and</strong> willover his act. (Clear-cut examples like <strong>the</strong>se should not, however, <strong>in</strong>vitemultiply<strong>in</strong>g excuses to relieve persons <strong>of</strong> responsibility for <strong>the</strong>ir actions.)Responsibility presupposes a po<strong>in</strong>t for apply<strong>in</strong>g a motive, such asdesire to avoid blame or punishment or to w<strong>in</strong> praise or reward. Frequentlyit makes em<strong>in</strong>ent sense to apply motives to people <strong>and</strong> hold <strong>the</strong>m responsiblefor <strong>the</strong>ir choices <strong>and</strong> actions. is could not be true if no groundsexisted for attribut<strong>in</strong>g freedom to people. Hence <strong>the</strong>re are grounds forbelief <strong>in</strong> freedom <strong>in</strong> some sense associated with responsibility.More exactly, perhaps, <strong>the</strong> whole free-will/determ<strong>in</strong>ism controversyis a chimerical basis for question<strong>in</strong>g ord<strong>in</strong>ary ethical concepts. Schlick’sargument comes across to me as I have summarized it.C.A. Campbell (1951/1966) f<strong>in</strong>ds Schlick’s dist<strong>in</strong>ction between descriptive<strong>and</strong> prescriptive laws irrelevant. e usual reason for th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g thatmoral freedom presupposes some breach <strong>in</strong> causal cont<strong>in</strong>uity is not a beliefthat causal laws compel <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> way legislation compels but <strong>in</strong>stead is <strong>the</strong>belief that an unbroken causal cha<strong>in</strong> leaves no one able to choose <strong>and</strong> acto<strong>the</strong>r than as he does.Moral responsibility is not <strong>the</strong> same, says Campbell, as scope for sensiblyapply<strong>in</strong>g motives. Dogs can be tra<strong>in</strong>ed with punishments <strong>and</strong> rewards;yet we do not hold dogs morally responsible for what <strong>the</strong>y do. We canjudge dead men morally responsible for particular actions without be<strong>in</strong>gable to affect those past actions. Perhaps we might re<strong>in</strong>terpret Schlick asmean<strong>in</strong>g that a person is morally responsible when his motive could <strong>in</strong>pr<strong>in</strong>ciple be affected by reward or punishment, whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> judgesor observers are <strong>in</strong> a position to apply it. But this modification would


286 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophychange Schlick’s <strong>the</strong>ory, which l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>the</strong> whole mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> importance<strong>of</strong> moral responsibility “to our potential control <strong>of</strong> future conduct <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>terests <strong>of</strong> society” (Campbell 1951/1966, p. 115).Schlick identifies “Who is morally blameworthy?” with “Who is tobe punished?”—paradoxically, given his view <strong>of</strong> punishment as a purelyeducative measure, without retributive content. We <strong>of</strong>ten th<strong>in</strong>k it properto “punish” a person, <strong>in</strong> Schlick’s educative sense, even without hold<strong>in</strong>ghim morally blameworthy (Campbell 1951/1966, p. 116). We punish<strong>the</strong> dog. We punish demonstrators who may be obstruct<strong>in</strong>g traffic frommotives that even we, <strong>the</strong> judges, may th<strong>in</strong>k noble.I’ll try to rephrase or <strong>in</strong>terpret Campbell’s objection. Schlick sees <strong>in</strong>strumental,educative, value <strong>in</strong> apply<strong>in</strong>g rewards <strong>and</strong> punishments, whichhe identifies with hold<strong>in</strong>g people morally responsible. We could hardlydo so unless we attributed some freedom to people. But is this a validl<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> ideas? Perhaps rewards <strong>and</strong> punishments <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir generallygood consequences are just particular events <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> unbroken causal cha<strong>in</strong>.Metaphysical freedom cannot be established by po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> apparentor genu<strong>in</strong>e good consequences <strong>of</strong> reward <strong>and</strong> punishment.Campbell suspects that Schlick <strong>and</strong> many o<strong>the</strong>r philosophers cannotrecognize contracausal freedom as prerequisite to moral responsibility because,while deny<strong>in</strong>g that freedom, <strong>the</strong>y do accept <strong>the</strong> commonsense belief<strong>in</strong> moral responsibility (Campbell 1951/1966, p. 117).His own purpose, Campbell concludes (p. 135), has been not actuallyto defend free will but ra<strong>the</strong>r to show “that <strong>the</strong> problem as traditionallyposed is a real, <strong>and</strong> not a pseudo, problem.”’ Henry Hazlitt (1964/1972, chap. 27) tries to reconcile free will <strong>and</strong> responsibilitywith determ<strong>in</strong>ism, <strong>in</strong>terpreted as omnipresent cause <strong>and</strong> effect. Heagrees “that everyth<strong>in</strong>g that happens is a necessary outcome <strong>of</strong> a preced<strong>in</strong>gstate <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs” (p. 269). Like Schlick, however, he stresses that causationis not compulsion. Absence, not presence, <strong>of</strong> causation is what wouldexempt people from moral responsibility. “It is precisely because we do notdecide or act without cause that ethical judgments serve a purpose.... eknowledge that we will be held ‘responsible’ for our acts by o<strong>the</strong>rs, or eventhat we will be responsible <strong>in</strong> our own eyes for <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> ouracts, must <strong>in</strong>fluence those acts, <strong>and</strong> must tend to <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>direction <strong>of</strong> moral op<strong>in</strong>ion” (p. 275).


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 287Hazlitt warns aga<strong>in</strong>st confus<strong>in</strong>g determ<strong>in</strong>ism with materialism, <strong>in</strong>terpretedas <strong>the</strong> dogma that all causation, even <strong>in</strong> human affairs, operatesultimately through physical <strong>and</strong> chemical processes alone. He especiallywarns aga<strong>in</strong>st confus<strong>in</strong>g determ<strong>in</strong>ism with fatalism, which he <strong>in</strong>terpretsas <strong>the</strong> dogma that events will unfold as <strong>the</strong>y are bound to do, regardless<strong>of</strong> how people try to promote or prevent <strong>the</strong>m. Fatalism <strong>in</strong> this peculiarsense is obviously false. Human decisions, choices, wishes, reflection, <strong>and</strong>will clearly do <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> events. If, contrary to fact, <strong>the</strong>y didnot do so, or if <strong>the</strong>y operated only stochastically, outside <strong>of</strong> causal cha<strong>in</strong>s,<strong>the</strong>n notions <strong>of</strong> responsibility <strong>and</strong> ethics would have no application.Hazlitt accepts universal causation, <strong>the</strong>n, but dist<strong>in</strong>guishes sharplybetween its supposed operation solely <strong>in</strong> material ways <strong>and</strong> its operation<strong>in</strong> ways leav<strong>in</strong>g scope for human decision <strong>and</strong> will. But can this dist<strong>in</strong>ctioncarry all <strong>the</strong> weight Hazlitt places on it? Michael Slote (1990) expla<strong>in</strong>s how mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> implement<strong>in</strong>g ethicaljudgments could be sensible even if determ<strong>in</strong>ism prevailed, a questionhe does not tackle. Here I <strong>in</strong>terpret Slote’s argument toge<strong>the</strong>r with a commentaryby Peter van Inwagen (1990) <strong>and</strong> forgo try<strong>in</strong>g to paraphrase eachseparately.We may label a person or a dog <strong>and</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> actions as “vicious” <strong>and</strong>guard aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>and</strong> “punish” <strong>the</strong>m. Yet we may recognize that <strong>the</strong> person’sor dog’s disposition <strong>and</strong> actions trace to unfortunate genes or mental illnessor previous maltreatment, which attenuates or dispels moral culpability.We are not necessarily <strong>in</strong>consistent <strong>in</strong> both recogniz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> dispositions<strong>and</strong> actions as determ<strong>in</strong>ed yet judg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> punish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m as vicious.Our judg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> punish<strong>in</strong>g can <strong>the</strong>mselves be l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>isticcausation <strong>and</strong> may make <strong>the</strong> dispositions <strong>and</strong> actions less viciousthan <strong>the</strong>y would o<strong>the</strong>rwise be.Similarly, we tend to judge actual murder “more wrong” than a failedattempt; we revile <strong>and</strong> punish an actual murderer more severely than anattempted murderer. Both culprits may have had <strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong>tentions, <strong>and</strong>only sheer luck may have frustrated one attempt. Still it may make sense tocondemn <strong>and</strong> punish <strong>the</strong> successful murderer more severely. How a personis judged <strong>and</strong> punished may thus reasonably depend on more than what hefreely willed. Several considerations may warrant dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g betweenactual <strong>and</strong> attempted murder. Evil <strong>in</strong>tentions may be harder to prove <strong>in</strong>


288 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophya failed attempt. e gradation <strong>in</strong> punishments may help emphasize <strong>the</strong>public’s solemn condemnation <strong>of</strong> murder, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> subtle psychological waysit may cause more murder attempts to fail than o<strong>the</strong>rwise would.An analogy <strong>of</strong> sorts holds between <strong>the</strong>se considerations <strong>and</strong> F.A. Hayek’sargument (1960, chap. 6) about merit versus value <strong>in</strong> determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g aperson’s <strong>in</strong>come. Even though <strong>the</strong> market value <strong>of</strong> a person’s efforts probablydoes not correspond closely to his moral merit, powerful reasons arguefor allow<strong>in</strong>g market supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> to establish his <strong>in</strong>come anyway.Such remuneration may usefully guide <strong>in</strong>dividuals on how to use <strong>the</strong>irspecial talents <strong>and</strong> knowledge, <strong>and</strong> it may motivate appropriate k<strong>in</strong>ds<strong>and</strong> degrees <strong>of</strong> risk-bear<strong>in</strong>g. Above all, perhaps, alternative <strong>in</strong>stitutions<strong>in</strong>tended to attune remunerations to moral merit appear very unattractiveupon close analysis. Aga<strong>in</strong>, a person’s free will <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentions should notbe <strong>the</strong> only factors govern<strong>in</strong>g how o<strong>the</strong>r people treat him.Admittedly, full-fledged determ<strong>in</strong>ism still poses embarrassment forconsequentialist considerations like <strong>the</strong>se. If we recognize that our mak<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> implement<strong>in</strong>g ethical judgments <strong>and</strong> adopt<strong>in</strong>g this or that set<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions are <strong>the</strong>mselves fully caused <strong>and</strong> are mere l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> a tightcausal cha<strong>in</strong>, we run <strong>in</strong>to awkward paradoxes. ese perta<strong>in</strong> to <strong>the</strong> wholefree-will/determ<strong>in</strong>ism issue itself, however, ra<strong>the</strong>r than to ethical issues<strong>in</strong> particular. Determ<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>in</strong> its most extreme version (commonly attributed to Pierre-Simon de Laplace) is fatalism even more comprehensive than <strong>the</strong> varietyrejected by Hazlitt. It recognizes human will <strong>and</strong> decision as elements <strong>in</strong>one gr<strong>and</strong> cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> universal causation. Everyth<strong>in</strong>g that is happen<strong>in</strong>g orhas happened or will happen has been fated from <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> timeto happen exactly as it does or did or will. Causation operates tightly <strong>in</strong>every detail. Even all <strong>of</strong> a person’s thoughts as he deliberates whe<strong>the</strong>r toaccept a new job or break <strong>of</strong>f a love affair, <strong>and</strong> even all o<strong>the</strong>r persons’ reactionsto his decision, were fated to be exactly as <strong>the</strong>y turn out. Even allphilosophical controversies over <strong>the</strong> free-will issue itself take an exactlypredeterm<strong>in</strong>ed course. Far from deny<strong>in</strong>g that ideas <strong>and</strong> choices have consequences,extreme determ<strong>in</strong>ism ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that even <strong>the</strong>se are l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>great causal cha<strong>in</strong>.Laplace regards <strong>the</strong> present state <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> universe as <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> itsanterior state <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> cause <strong>of</strong> its next state. Ineluctable necessity rules.


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 289Noth<strong>in</strong>g would be uncerta<strong>in</strong> for a sufficiently vast <strong>in</strong>telligence; <strong>the</strong> future<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> past alike would be present to its eyes. A true act <strong>of</strong> free will isimpossible. Without a determ<strong>in</strong>ative motive, not even <strong>the</strong> nearest th<strong>in</strong>gto a free will could orig<strong>in</strong>ate even actions considered <strong>in</strong>different. e contraryop<strong>in</strong>ion is an illusion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d (Meyerson 1921/1991, pp. 563–564,cit<strong>in</strong>g Laplace’s éorie analytique des probabilités). (Boyle et al. 1976, pp. 57,86, give apt quotations from Laplace; fur<strong>the</strong>r discussion <strong>of</strong> Laplace<strong>and</strong>eterm<strong>in</strong>ism occurs <strong>in</strong> Popper 1982, pp. xx–xxi, 123–124, <strong>and</strong> passim; <strong>and</strong>Georgescu-Roegen 1971, p. 170 <strong>and</strong> passim.)Clarence Darrow used to defend his clients with such an argument.e accused crim<strong>in</strong>al is a mere l<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> cha<strong>in</strong>. Even his character <strong>and</strong> hisability or <strong>in</strong>ability to reshape it trace ultimately to causes outside himself,<strong>and</strong> he is <strong>the</strong>refore not responsible <strong>and</strong> not properly punishable for hiscrimes (Hospers 1961/1966, p. 41).Can anyone really believe <strong>in</strong> such tight universal causation? If onlyQueen Victoria had been a man, <strong>the</strong> Salic Law would not have separated<strong>the</strong> hi<strong>the</strong>rto l<strong>in</strong>ked crowns <strong>of</strong> Great Brita<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Hanover uponher—his—accession <strong>in</strong> 1837; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> subsequent history <strong>of</strong> Germany,Europe, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> world would probably have unfolded much differentlyfrom how it actually did. (Reflection on <strong>the</strong> events <strong>of</strong> 1866, 1870–1871, 1914,<strong>and</strong> 1917 helps expla<strong>in</strong> why.) Much depended, <strong>the</strong>n, on which particularsperm happened to fertilize her mo<strong>the</strong>r’s ovum at Victoria’s conception <strong>in</strong>1818. Yet this micro event <strong>and</strong> all its momentous consequences were boundto occur exactly as <strong>the</strong>y did. us must strict determ<strong>in</strong>ism ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>.No one, to my knowledge, espouses this position consistently. It is justtoo preposterous—though I may be mistaken <strong>in</strong> say<strong>in</strong>g so. One reason for call<strong>in</strong>g full determ<strong>in</strong>ism preposterous is that <strong>the</strong> worldseems to be gett<strong>in</strong>g more complicated over time. It is hard to imag<strong>in</strong>ehow <strong>the</strong> less complicated past might conta<strong>in</strong> all <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation necessary is particular example is my own, to <strong>the</strong> best <strong>of</strong> my recollection; yet it is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>spirit <strong>of</strong> essays collected <strong>in</strong> Squire 1931. ere, for example, W<strong>in</strong>ston Churchill speculateson what would have happened if Lee had not [sic] won <strong>the</strong> battle <strong>of</strong> Gettysburg, HilaireBelloc on what would have happened if <strong>the</strong> cart that <strong>in</strong> fact blocked Louis XVI’s escape atVarennes <strong>in</strong> June 1791 had gotten stuck before reach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> crucial place, <strong>and</strong> Emil Ludwigon what would have happened if German Emperor Frederick III had lived to reign until1914 <strong>and</strong> not just for his actual 99 days <strong>in</strong> 1888.Such examples mesh nicely with currently popular <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> “chaos” or “complexity.”


290 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyto specify <strong>the</strong> more complicated present <strong>and</strong> future <strong>in</strong> complete detail.Such complete specification would constitute at least an equal degree <strong>of</strong>complexity already prevail<strong>in</strong>g.e world is gett<strong>in</strong>g “more complicated” by any ord<strong>in</strong>ary st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong>judgment. More people are liv<strong>in</strong>g than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> past, with all <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>dividualcharacteristics <strong>and</strong> thoughts <strong>and</strong> actions. e number <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tricacy <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> works <strong>of</strong> man are <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> texts <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> books <strong>and</strong>articles ever written. e state <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world at any <strong>in</strong>stant <strong>in</strong>cludes all <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong> mispr<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> all <strong>the</strong>se documents, <strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong>slightest details <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> flyspecks <strong>and</strong> c<strong>of</strong>fee sta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual copies.Affairs on earth <strong>in</strong>teract with affairs throughout <strong>the</strong> universe. Men orman-made <strong>in</strong>struments have disturbed <strong>the</strong> surfaces <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moon <strong>and</strong> Mars,<strong>and</strong> rockets have escaped our solar system. Eclipses, comets, planetarymovements, <strong>and</strong> supernovas have affected human activities directly <strong>and</strong>through popular, religious, <strong>and</strong> scientific beliefs.If a later state is fully determ<strong>in</strong>ed by an earlier state, <strong>the</strong>n that earlierstate must conta<strong>in</strong> aspects or properties or patterns or whatever—whosetotality I am call<strong>in</strong>g “<strong>in</strong>formation”—specify<strong>in</strong>g that later state <strong>in</strong> completedetail. And if <strong>the</strong> world is generally gett<strong>in</strong>g more complicated over time,<strong>the</strong>n more <strong>in</strong>formation is required to specify a later state than an earlierstate. It is hard to imag<strong>in</strong>e how all <strong>the</strong> detailed <strong>in</strong>formation necessary tospecify <strong>the</strong> more complicated later state already existed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> simpler earlierstate. It is hard to believe that even <strong>the</strong> t<strong>in</strong>iest fraction <strong>of</strong> a second after<strong>the</strong> Big Bang, <strong>the</strong> universe already conta<strong>in</strong>ed detailed coded <strong>in</strong>formationabout everyth<strong>in</strong>g that would ever happen <strong>the</strong>reafter, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> exactconfiguration <strong>of</strong> every wisp <strong>of</strong> cloud I observed dur<strong>in</strong>g my last airplane trip<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> exact times at which <strong>and</strong> pressures with which I wouldstrike each key dur<strong>in</strong>g my current session at my computer keyboard. Fulldeterm<strong>in</strong>ism seems still more <strong>in</strong>credible because it <strong>in</strong>volves each state’sspecify<strong>in</strong>g not only one subsequent state but also all <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely many<strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g states (“<strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely many” if time is cont<strong>in</strong>uous).ese po<strong>in</strong>ts tell aga<strong>in</strong>st complete causal determ<strong>in</strong>ation. Its be<strong>in</strong>g hardto conceive <strong>of</strong> does not, however, constitute dispro<strong>of</strong>. Perhaps <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g Considerations resembl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se appear <strong>in</strong> Peirce 1958, selection 9, an article I hadread <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n forgotten many years before first draft<strong>in</strong>g this appendix.My appeal to <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g complexity <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation content may admittedly appear torun afoul <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> second law <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>rmodynamics, <strong>the</strong> entropy law, <strong>and</strong> I may be quite wrong.On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, that law <strong>in</strong> its central context perta<strong>in</strong>s to energy <strong>and</strong> its degradation;<strong>and</strong> its rationale is perhaps most clearly set forth with reference to <strong>the</strong> statistical properties<strong>of</strong> crowds <strong>of</strong> nonliv<strong>in</strong>g molecules. e law may not fully carry over to <strong>the</strong> present context.


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 291overall complexity is a mere illusion. Perhaps greater complexity <strong>in</strong> somedimensions—<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> products <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> details <strong>of</strong>flyspecks on published pages—is <strong>of</strong>fset somehow by reduced complexity<strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r dimensions. If so, what might <strong>the</strong>y be? Perhaps greater complexityon our earth, which, like our whole solar system, is an open system,is <strong>of</strong>fset somehow by reduced complexity elsewhere <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> universe. Evenso, wouldn’t <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t still hold that <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g complexity on our earthimplies <strong>in</strong>complete predictability <strong>of</strong> human affairs? By what mechanism,if any, could any <strong>of</strong>fsett<strong>in</strong>g reduced complexity elsewhere save <strong>the</strong> completepredictability <strong>of</strong> human affairs, if only <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple? But perhaps Iam wrong about my notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation required for complete causalspecification.Speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> total causal determ<strong>in</strong>ation, we may well pause to ask justwhat “cause” <strong>and</strong> “causality” mean. Try<strong>in</strong>g to frame objection-free def<strong>in</strong>itionsis a sober<strong>in</strong>g challenge. is very difficulty throws some slight extraembarrassment onto doctr<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> a great unbroken causal cha<strong>in</strong>.In argu<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acy or openness <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> universe, KarlPopper dist<strong>in</strong>guishes among “three worlds.” World 1 conta<strong>in</strong>s physicalobjects—rocks, trees, structures, liv<strong>in</strong>g creatures, <strong>and</strong> physical fields <strong>of</strong>force. World 2 is <strong>the</strong> psychological world <strong>of</strong> fears <strong>and</strong> hopes, <strong>of</strong> dispositionsto act, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> subjective experiences <strong>of</strong> all k<strong>in</strong>ds. World 3 conta<strong>in</strong>sproducts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human m<strong>in</strong>d—art works, ethical values, social <strong>in</strong>stitutions,<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual contents <strong>of</strong> books (books as physical objects belong toWorld 1), scientific problems, <strong>the</strong>ories, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g mistaken <strong>the</strong>ories, <strong>and</strong>solved <strong>and</strong> unsolved puzzles. Especially characteristic <strong>of</strong> World 3 is humanknowledge put <strong>in</strong>to words.Autonomous objects exist even <strong>in</strong> World 3. Human be<strong>in</strong>gs orig<strong>in</strong>allyconceived <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prime numbers <strong>and</strong> conjectured about <strong>the</strong>ir properties,but <strong>the</strong> primes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir properties have taken on an objective existence.It is a bare fact, but a logical truth ra<strong>the</strong>r than a cont<strong>in</strong>gent empirical fact,One difference from <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate processes is that <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation,as <strong>in</strong> biological evolution, selection may accomplish a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner directedness.It may be that on our earth <strong>and</strong> perhaps even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> universe as a whole, nei<strong>the</strong>r k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong>evolution violates <strong>the</strong> second law. See, for example, Popper 1985, selections 4 <strong>and</strong> 21; 1982, section 38; <strong>and</strong> his 1972 lecture,repr<strong>in</strong>ted 1982. Earlier (1908, repr<strong>in</strong>ted 1958, pp. 358–379; <strong>and</strong> 1908, repr<strong>in</strong>ted 1958,pp. 404–405), Charles S. Peirce had dist<strong>in</strong>guished among “three Universes <strong>of</strong> Experience.”Popper’s World 3 <strong>and</strong> Peirce’s first universe correspond fairly well, as do Popper’s World1 <strong>and</strong> Peirce’s second universe, but <strong>the</strong> rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g world <strong>and</strong> universe correspond looselyat best.


292 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophythat 143 prime numbers, no more <strong>and</strong> no fewer, exist <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> range <strong>of</strong> 100 to1000. Euclid already proved <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itude <strong>of</strong> prime numbers: no largestone exists. But is <strong>the</strong>re a largest pair <strong>of</strong> tw<strong>in</strong> primes (like 17 <strong>and</strong> 19, 521<strong>and</strong> 523, 1451 <strong>and</strong> 1453)? No one, <strong>the</strong> last I heard, has actually proved ei<strong>the</strong>ra “yes” or a “no” answer. e problem objectively exists as a challenge tohuman <strong>in</strong>telligence.e autonomous objects <strong>of</strong> World 3 <strong>in</strong>teract with World 1 through<strong>the</strong> human perceptions, feel<strong>in</strong>gs, dispositions, <strong>and</strong> decisions <strong>of</strong> World 2.e challenges <strong>of</strong> pure ma<strong>the</strong>matics lead to results that f<strong>in</strong>d applications<strong>in</strong> computer hardware <strong>and</strong> s<strong>of</strong>tware, which <strong>in</strong> turn function <strong>in</strong> chang<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> physical world. Some challenges <strong>of</strong> her field lead a ma<strong>the</strong>maticianto results that enhance her reputation <strong>and</strong> w<strong>in</strong> her an appo<strong>in</strong>tment at aprestigious university, where she has a house—a physical object—built <strong>in</strong>accordance with her tastes <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>creased <strong>in</strong>come.World 3 is <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sically open or emergent, says Popper (1972/1982,p. 5); any <strong>the</strong>ory hold<strong>in</strong>g scientific <strong>and</strong> artistic creation ultimately expla<strong>in</strong>ableby physics <strong>and</strong> chemistry seems absurd to him. Moreover, <strong>in</strong>terrelationsamong <strong>the</strong> three Worlds render <strong>the</strong> whole universe partly open <strong>and</strong>emergent.I am not sure that Popper would agree, but his concept <strong>of</strong> World 3 <strong>in</strong>particular, <strong>the</strong> world <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs like scientific <strong>the</strong>ories, does help underl<strong>in</strong>ehow preposterous it is to suppose that each later state <strong>of</strong> affairs is totallyspecified by earlier states. Scientific progress does occur. New knowledge,by its very mean<strong>in</strong>g, was not available <strong>in</strong> advance; <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>gbe<strong>in</strong>g known before it is known is self-contradictory. <strong>Is</strong> it plausible,<strong>the</strong>n, to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that all <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical <strong>and</strong> physical knowledge notyet achieved but that will be achieved <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> next hundred years somehowalready exists <strong>in</strong> latent form, already somehow coded <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> current state<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> universe, along with <strong>the</strong> date <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r details <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discovery <strong>of</strong>each bit <strong>of</strong> that future knowledge? (Many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> associated challengesalready exist as problems belong<strong>in</strong>g to Popper’s World 3, but this is not<strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> preexistence <strong>of</strong> solutions both to unsolved problems <strong>and</strong>to problems not yet even formulated.)Gerd Gigerenzer <strong>and</strong> coauthors (1989/1993, esp. pp. 59–68, 276–285) reviewapparent <strong>and</strong> supposed implications <strong>of</strong> probability <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> statisticsfor free will versus determ<strong>in</strong>ism. ese discipl<strong>in</strong>es have been successfully


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 293applied on <strong>the</strong> assumption that some sheer r<strong>and</strong>om processes do operate<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world, which is some evidence, if weak, that determ<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>in</strong> natureis <strong>in</strong>complete. Scientists <strong>and</strong> philosophers such as James Clerk Maxwell<strong>and</strong> Charles Peirce have believed that airtight causality does not operate<strong>in</strong> every little detail <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> universe, that some element <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>omnessrema<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> that free will might occupy this gap somehow. And such gapsmight not be conf<strong>in</strong>ed to <strong>the</strong> subatomic level that quantum <strong>the</strong>ory dealswith. (Here I <strong>in</strong>sert <strong>the</strong> obligatory allusion to Heisenberg’s <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acypr<strong>in</strong>ciple concern<strong>in</strong>g subatomic r<strong>and</strong>omness.) Maxwell <strong>and</strong> Peirce (1877,repr<strong>in</strong>ted 1958, p. 95; articles <strong>of</strong> 1891, repr<strong>in</strong>ted 1955, pp. 9, 319) po<strong>in</strong>ted to<strong>the</strong> statistical or probabilistic aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>etic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> gases, whichenvisages <strong>the</strong> constituent molecules mov<strong>in</strong>g at different r<strong>and</strong>omly determ<strong>in</strong>edvelocities <strong>and</strong> chang<strong>in</strong>g velocities as <strong>the</strong>y collide with one ano<strong>the</strong>r<strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> sides <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conta<strong>in</strong>er. Peirce also noted <strong>the</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om nature<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> biological mutations on which natural selection operates.Karl Popper also argued for <strong>the</strong> genu<strong>in</strong>eness <strong>of</strong> chance events evenabove <strong>the</strong> subatomic level or even <strong>the</strong> molecular level. What expla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong>statistical stability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> heads <strong>and</strong> tails produced by a penny-toss<strong>in</strong>gmach<strong>in</strong>e? Or consider Alfred L<strong>and</strong>é’s conception <strong>of</strong> dropp<strong>in</strong>g ivory ballsonto <strong>the</strong> center <strong>of</strong> a suitably positioned steel blade, very nearly half <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> balls fall<strong>in</strong>g on each side. For a determ<strong>in</strong>ist, barred by his doctr<strong>in</strong>efrom appeal<strong>in</strong>g to r<strong>and</strong>omness <strong>and</strong> reduced to imag<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> mutual cancellation<strong>of</strong> many small causes, <strong>the</strong> lawlike statistical process must rema<strong>in</strong>ultimately irreducible <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>explicable (Popper 1982, pp. 96–104).Quantum-level <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r small-scale <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acies ga<strong>in</strong> relevancefrom <strong>the</strong> fact that micro differences can have macro consequences. Erw<strong>in</strong>Schröd<strong>in</strong>ger gave <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical example <strong>of</strong> a cat whose survival ordeath <strong>in</strong> an experiment depends on an apparatus detect<strong>in</strong>g particles emittedr<strong>and</strong>omly <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>frequently <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> decay <strong>of</strong> a radioactive element. efar-reach<strong>in</strong>g consequences <strong>of</strong> Queen Victoria’s sex, already mentioned,provide ano<strong>the</strong>r example. is micro-to-macro pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is fur<strong>the</strong>r illum<strong>in</strong>atedby <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics <strong>of</strong> chaos, even though <strong>the</strong> (hypo<strong>the</strong>tical) systemsused <strong>in</strong> expound<strong>in</strong>g chaos <strong>the</strong>ory are fully determ<strong>in</strong>istic.An element <strong>of</strong> sheer chance <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> universe appears to operate, <strong>the</strong>n,along with <strong>the</strong> causality that is also evident. Admittedly, <strong>the</strong> pervasiveappearance <strong>of</strong> chance or r<strong>and</strong>omness does not rigorously rule out completeLaplacean causality. (Laplace himself made contributions to probability<strong>the</strong>ory.) My statistics pr<strong>of</strong>essor at Columbia University around 1948,Frederick C. Mills, avoided speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “chance,” period; he always used


294 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophysome such expression as “<strong>the</strong> complex <strong>of</strong> unknown causes called chance.”Perhaps he had good reason for speak<strong>in</strong>g so carefully. (In his 1938 book,p. 436, he lists three assumptions underly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> derivation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> normalcurve <strong>of</strong> error: “() e causal forces affect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividual events are numerous,<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> approximately equal weight. () e causal forces affect<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>dividual events are <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>of</strong> one ano<strong>the</strong>r. () e operation <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> causal forces is such that deviations above <strong>the</strong> mean <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>edresults are balanced as to magnitude <strong>and</strong> number by deviations below<strong>the</strong> mean.”)Ano<strong>the</strong>r reservation about sheer chance or r<strong>and</strong>omness requires mention.Chance poses no less difficulty for commonsense notions <strong>of</strong> humanfreedom <strong>and</strong> responsibility than tight causality would. To <strong>the</strong> extent thata person’s actions, decisions, deliberations, <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ations, feel<strong>in</strong>gs, experiences,capabilities, <strong>and</strong> character traits occur by sheer chance, <strong>the</strong>y are nomore mean<strong>in</strong>gfully his own, <strong>and</strong> he is no more truly responsible for <strong>the</strong>m,than would be true if <strong>the</strong>y all traced fully to external causes. Actions <strong>and</strong>thoughts governed by sheer chance are no more compatible with hum<strong>and</strong>ignity <strong>and</strong> responsibility, as ord<strong>in</strong>arily conceived, than <strong>the</strong>ir be<strong>in</strong>g dom<strong>in</strong>atedby external causes. Dignity <strong>and</strong> responsibility, if genu<strong>in</strong>e, presupposesometh<strong>in</strong>g beyond chance l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g events; <strong>the</strong>y presuppose a causall<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual plays some <strong>in</strong>dependent part.While elements <strong>of</strong> sheer chance <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world do not imply freedom <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> will, “<strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om phenomena at <strong>the</strong> quantum level doestake <strong>the</strong> st<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> argument that man cannot will freely because <strong>the</strong>material world is governed by determ<strong>in</strong>ism. Clearly, a completely determ<strong>in</strong>isticworld <strong>and</strong> a man with an absolutely free will are <strong>in</strong>compatibleconditions” (Georgescu-Roegen 1971, p. 177, <strong>in</strong> part cit<strong>in</strong>g H. Margenau,Hermann Weyl, <strong>and</strong> A.S. Edd<strong>in</strong>gton). (I’ll add that not merely an “absolutely”but even a partially free will is <strong>in</strong>compatible with complete determ<strong>in</strong>ism.)e po<strong>in</strong>t so far is not that <strong>in</strong>dications <strong>of</strong> sheer chance <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>world establish <strong>the</strong> case for free will but only that <strong>the</strong>y defuse one particulark<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> argument aga<strong>in</strong>st it.Causality as opposed to chance is required for any predictability <strong>in</strong>human behavior. Yet predictability does not rob human be<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> dignityusually associated with free will <strong>and</strong> responsibility. If anyth<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>contrary is true. Suppose that a friend <strong>of</strong> yours had an opportunity to steal10,000 while escap<strong>in</strong>g suspicion. In fact <strong>the</strong> money rema<strong>in</strong>s unstolen.Which would your friend ra<strong>the</strong>r hear from you: “I was sure that you wouldnot steal <strong>the</strong> money” or “I didn’t have a clue whe<strong>the</strong>r or not you would steal


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 295it”? Would your friend be <strong>in</strong>sulted by your th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that his behavior ispredictable? (Compare Hobart 1934/1984, p. 81).Far from be<strong>in</strong>g vitiated by elements <strong>of</strong> stable relations—<strong>of</strong> causality—among events <strong>and</strong> circumstances, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g character traits <strong>and</strong> actions,<strong>the</strong> very concepts <strong>of</strong> free choice <strong>and</strong> responsibility presuppose such elements.Often <strong>the</strong>se elements make confident predictions possible, all withoutundercutt<strong>in</strong>g notions <strong>of</strong> free choice <strong>and</strong> responsibility.Sheer chance, <strong>in</strong> short, not only does not establish <strong>the</strong> case for humanfreedom <strong>and</strong> responsibility but even poses difficulties <strong>of</strong> its own. Its role <strong>in</strong>my argument is different <strong>and</strong> slighter: it underm<strong>in</strong>es one particular argumentaga<strong>in</strong>st freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> will.Once chance has shaken <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> total causal determ<strong>in</strong>ation, <strong>the</strong>path rema<strong>in</strong>s open for consider<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r someth<strong>in</strong>g besides chancemight also contribute to <strong>the</strong> evident openness or <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>universe. Everyday evidence, considered next, testifies to some sort <strong>of</strong> freewill. at evidence can be questioned, but <strong>the</strong> questions rely precisely on<strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ist doctr<strong>in</strong>e that is itself open to question. Everyone’s experience suggests that people’s decisions, talk, writ<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>and</strong>thoughts do <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> events. e thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g determ<strong>in</strong>istor fatalist would not deny this personal experience, but he would questionits significance. Our decisions <strong>and</strong> thoughts, <strong>in</strong>fluential though <strong>the</strong>yare, are mere l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> unbroken causal cha<strong>in</strong>s. Each decision, utterance,<strong>and</strong> thought is caused by o<strong>the</strong>r events <strong>and</strong> circumstances, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g physicalconditions, <strong>the</strong> previous thoughts <strong>and</strong> utterances <strong>of</strong> oneself <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rpeople, <strong>and</strong> one’s own <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people’s character traits, genetic makeups,<strong>and</strong> current <strong>and</strong> past environments—accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ist. Each<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se causal l<strong>in</strong>ks traces to contemporaneous <strong>and</strong> earlier l<strong>in</strong>ks—<strong>and</strong> soon, presumably, back to <strong>the</strong> Big Bang.A hardened habitual crim<strong>in</strong>al could have avoided committ<strong>in</strong>g each <strong>of</strong>his crimes if he had willed not to commit it. But could he have so willed?Well, yes, if his character had been different. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, it would havebeen different if his earlier actions <strong>and</strong> decisions <strong>and</strong> circumstances hadbeen different. But could <strong>the</strong>y have been different? ese earlier character<strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>gevents <strong>and</strong> circumstances, perhaps especially <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g hischildhood environment <strong>and</strong> his genetic makeup, were <strong>the</strong>mselves l<strong>in</strong>ks<strong>in</strong> an unbroken causal cha<strong>in</strong>.


296 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophye complete determ<strong>in</strong>ist is unimpressed, <strong>the</strong>n, by <strong>the</strong> observationthat <strong>the</strong> crim<strong>in</strong>al could cont<strong>in</strong>gently have avoided committ<strong>in</strong>g his crimes.Far from prov<strong>in</strong>g his responsibility for <strong>the</strong>m, that observation is an un<strong>in</strong>formativetruism. It merely says that if <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> a causal cha<strong>in</strong> had beendifferent from what <strong>the</strong>y actually were <strong>and</strong> had been fated to be, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>outcome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cha<strong>in</strong> would have been different from what it <strong>in</strong> fact was.Despite <strong>the</strong>se assertions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> (imag<strong>in</strong>ary) fatalist, we all have personalexperience with mak<strong>in</strong>g decisions ourselves. We decide, true enough,largely <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> light <strong>of</strong> external circumstances. Often <strong>the</strong>se <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>the</strong>expected reactions <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people. But it is we ourselves who weigh <strong>the</strong>considerations pull<strong>in</strong>g one way <strong>and</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r. We know from our own experiencewith decisions, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>and</strong> from what observation suggestsabout <strong>the</strong> decisions <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people, that people do respond to prospects<strong>of</strong> reward <strong>and</strong> punishment, approval <strong>and</strong> disapproval. (Surely economistsunderst<strong>and</strong> about <strong>in</strong>centives.) Hold<strong>in</strong>g people responsible does affect <strong>the</strong>irbehavior.A fatalist could accept this conclusion without ab<strong>and</strong>on<strong>in</strong>g his doctr<strong>in</strong>e.He could agree that if juries, judges, <strong>and</strong> legislatures generally accepted <strong>the</strong>Clarence Darrow defense, crime would be more rampant than it is <strong>in</strong> fact,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> world a more miserable place. Society is fortunate, he could agree,that juries, judges, <strong>and</strong> legislatures, usually ignor<strong>in</strong>g Clarence Darrow, as<strong>the</strong>y are fated to ignore him, do hold crim<strong>in</strong>als responsible <strong>and</strong> do punish<strong>the</strong>m. We are fortunate, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words, that his determ<strong>in</strong>ist <strong>the</strong>ory is notgenerally accepted <strong>and</strong> implemented. Yet <strong>the</strong> fatalist could ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> thathis <strong>the</strong>ory is correct, that he is fated to propound it exactly as he does, <strong>and</strong>that—probably fortunately—you <strong>and</strong> I <strong>and</strong> most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> us are never<strong>the</strong>lessfated to reject it.How would <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> strict determ<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>in</strong>terpret academic disputesover that <strong>the</strong>ory itself? Taken literally, it would regard each move<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> dispute—each conversation, lecture, journal article, criticism <strong>of</strong> anarticle, reply to <strong>the</strong> criticism, <strong>and</strong> every slight detail <strong>in</strong> each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se—assimply a particular l<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> great causal cha<strong>in</strong>. e determ<strong>in</strong>ist philosopherwould agree that his latest paper on <strong>the</strong> topic was fated <strong>in</strong> every slightestdetail to say what it does say, fated not only by what he had heard <strong>and</strong>read on <strong>the</strong> topic but by his genes <strong>and</strong> childhood experiences <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>numerableo<strong>the</strong>r circumstances. All reactions to his paper are similarly fated.Yet this consideration does not necessarily lead him to ab<strong>and</strong>on <strong>the</strong> wholeissue <strong>and</strong> turn to some o<strong>the</strong>r branch <strong>of</strong> philosophy or some o<strong>the</strong>r l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong>work. He could stick to <strong>the</strong> issue, recogniz<strong>in</strong>g that he is fated to do so <strong>and</strong>


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 297that his work on it, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs’ reactions to it, are fated to turn out exactlyas <strong>the</strong>y do.is determ<strong>in</strong>ist position, <strong>the</strong>n, may not be downright <strong>in</strong>consistentwith itself, not downright self-refut<strong>in</strong>g. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is practically <strong>in</strong>credible. - Joseph M. Boyle, Jr., Germa<strong>in</strong> Grisez, <strong>and</strong> Olaf Tollefsen (1976) expose<strong>the</strong> self-contradictory position <strong>of</strong> one who “rationally affirms” full determ<strong>in</strong>ismor, as <strong>the</strong>y say, denies that anyone has any “free choice.” (To “rationallyaffirm” a proposition goes beyond merely mention<strong>in</strong>g it or consider<strong>in</strong>git possible; it means hold<strong>in</strong>g that it is true or at least more reasonablyacceptable than its contradictory.) A philosopher who argues that persons<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> issue ought rationally to accept <strong>the</strong> no-free-choice positionmust believe that although <strong>the</strong>y are not compelled to accept it, <strong>the</strong>ycan rationally accept it (“ought implies can”); <strong>the</strong>y have some freedom <strong>of</strong>choice <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> matter. Yet <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ist proposition be<strong>in</strong>g urged deniesthat <strong>the</strong> persons addressed have any freedom. Ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ist isthus contradict<strong>in</strong>g himself or else is po<strong>in</strong>tlessly urg<strong>in</strong>g people to do whatby his own doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong>y cannot do—make <strong>the</strong> free choice <strong>of</strong> rationallyaccept<strong>in</strong>g that doctr<strong>in</strong>e.Boyle <strong>and</strong> his coauthors do <strong>in</strong> effect recognize <strong>the</strong> possibility, mentioned<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g section, that determ<strong>in</strong>ism is true <strong>and</strong> that participants<strong>in</strong> controversy over it versus free choice are behav<strong>in</strong>g like fully programmedrobots whose every slightest verbal move <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> game is a fullydeterm<strong>in</strong>ed ra<strong>the</strong>r than rationally chosen action. “To affirm [<strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ist]position <strong>in</strong> this way, however, is to withdraw from <strong>the</strong> philosophicalcontroversy” (p. 169). Besides be<strong>in</strong>g practically <strong>in</strong>credible <strong>and</strong> besides putt<strong>in</strong>g its proponents<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> position <strong>of</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r contradict<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mselves or avow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mselvesto be mere robots ra<strong>the</strong>r than rational controversialists, determ<strong>in</strong>ism isirrefutable or unfalsifiable—<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bad sense. It has a built-<strong>in</strong> immunityto any adverse evidence; its claim to say anyth<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>ite about how e argument <strong>of</strong> Boyle et al. is extremely complex, detailed, <strong>and</strong> repetitious, conta<strong>in</strong>smany cross-references <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r obstacles to comprehension, <strong>and</strong> does, after all, occupy anentire book; so I cannot guarantee that my summary is entirely faithful to <strong>the</strong>ir argument.


298 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>the</strong> world actually works is a sham. No perceptions <strong>of</strong> persons that <strong>the</strong>yare more than mere cogs <strong>in</strong> tightly work<strong>in</strong>g mach<strong>in</strong>ery, that <strong>the</strong>y havesome scope for mak<strong>in</strong>g decisions not totally predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong>ir geneticmakeups <strong>and</strong> past experiences, count for anyth<strong>in</strong>g; for <strong>the</strong>se very perceptionshave <strong>the</strong>mselves been predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed. Similarly, no number <strong>of</strong>episodes <strong>in</strong> which unexpected, astonish<strong>in</strong>g, or unpredictable decisions <strong>of</strong>particular persons brought major consequences count for anyth<strong>in</strong>g. Apparentexamples <strong>of</strong> formidable exertions <strong>of</strong> will count for noth<strong>in</strong>g. e <strong>the</strong>oryitself rules such episodes out as evidence on <strong>the</strong> grounds that <strong>the</strong> citeddecisions <strong>and</strong> exertions, as well as <strong>the</strong>ir be<strong>in</strong>g unexpected, astonish<strong>in</strong>g, orapparently unpredictable, are <strong>the</strong>mselves mere l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> universal causalcha<strong>in</strong>. Examples <strong>in</strong> which a person seems to have changed his very characterby effort <strong>of</strong> will would not faze <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ist. He would ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>that <strong>the</strong> person’s exertion <strong>of</strong> will, <strong>and</strong> with what degree <strong>of</strong> success, were<strong>the</strong>mselves predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed. Determ<strong>in</strong>ism does not deny that praise <strong>and</strong>blame, reward <strong>and</strong> punishment, can be efficacious <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>g behavior;it simply ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that <strong>the</strong>se <strong>in</strong> turn are predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed.What adverse evidence <strong>of</strong> any sort is even conceivable, <strong>the</strong>n, fromwhich <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory does not protect itself <strong>in</strong> advance? A <strong>the</strong>ory that canaccommodate absolutely any evidence does not specify any genu<strong>in</strong>e restrictionson how <strong>the</strong> real world actually works; its ostensible empirical characteris a sham.Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory does not carry any actual implications forhow to live one’s own life or for public policy. Should <strong>in</strong>dividuals cultivatea sense <strong>of</strong> control over <strong>the</strong>ir own decisions <strong>and</strong> actions or, at <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rextreme, cultivate a fatalistic outlook? Some psychologists may <strong>of</strong>fer <strong>the</strong>one l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> advice <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>the</strong> opposite l<strong>in</strong>e; but <strong>in</strong> any case, each ismerely <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> advice he is fated to <strong>of</strong>fer. A determ<strong>in</strong>ist philosopheris not necessarily bound to advise <strong>the</strong> fatalistic outlook; for he may recognize<strong>the</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> feel<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> autonomy <strong>and</strong> responsibility <strong>and</strong> himselffeel, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, that he is fated not to undercut such feel<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>benefits flow<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong>m. Each ord<strong>in</strong>ary <strong>in</strong>dividual, similarly, is receiv<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> advice he is fated to receive <strong>and</strong> will respond to it, along with o<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>fluences, as he is fated to respond.Should crim<strong>in</strong>als be held more responsible for <strong>the</strong>ir actions <strong>and</strong> moreliable to punishment than <strong>the</strong>y currently are or, on o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, should <strong>the</strong>Clarence Darrow defense be given greater heed? e first policy shift mayreduce crime <strong>and</strong> make for a healthier society on that account, althoughit would be unfair to crim<strong>in</strong>als who are, on <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ist <strong>the</strong>ory, mere


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 299unfortunate l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> a causal cha<strong>in</strong>. (Incidentally, doesn’t determ<strong>in</strong>ismunderm<strong>in</strong>e even <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> unfairness?) In ei<strong>the</strong>r case, policymakerswill hear <strong>the</strong> arguments <strong>the</strong>y are fated to hear <strong>and</strong> respond as <strong>the</strong>y arefated to do.In short, <strong>the</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ist <strong>the</strong>ory not only has built-<strong>in</strong> immunity toadverse evidence but also lacks implications about how to apply it <strong>in</strong> practice.It is empty. Individuals, by <strong>and</strong> large, cannot br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mselves toregard it as mean<strong>in</strong>gful <strong>and</strong> to conduct <strong>the</strong>ir own lives <strong>and</strong> public policy<strong>in</strong> accordance with it.I am say<strong>in</strong>g not that full determ<strong>in</strong>ism is wrong but that it is an empty,mean<strong>in</strong>gless doctr<strong>in</strong>e. is conclusion is not, I believe, one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> airydismissals <strong>of</strong> philosophical issues that used to characterize a crude logicalpositivism. I have tried to show that total fatalistic determ<strong>in</strong>ism is empty, perhapseven absurd. We might now try to focus on <strong>the</strong> opposite extreme position,except that complete free will <strong>and</strong> absolute <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ism are downright<strong>in</strong>conceivable. No conceivable self is free <strong>of</strong> a biological nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>fluences imposed by an external world. Still, let us see how far we canget <strong>in</strong> imag<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a self whose will is essentially free.A self whose character had been determ<strong>in</strong>ed not by heredity <strong>and</strong> environmentbut only <strong>in</strong>ternally would be <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> a core self, a m<strong>in</strong>iatureself with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> self, as R.E. Hobart says (1934/1984). But how couldthat core self be free from external <strong>in</strong>fluences? Only by its character hav<strong>in</strong>gbeen determ<strong>in</strong>ed by a fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>ternal m<strong>in</strong>iature self, <strong>and</strong> so on <strong>in</strong> preposterous<strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite regress. “To cause his orig<strong>in</strong>al self a man must have existedbefore his orig<strong>in</strong>al self. <strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong>re someth<strong>in</strong>g humiliat<strong>in</strong>g to him <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> factthat he is not a contradiction <strong>in</strong> terms?” (Hobart 1934/1984, p. 505).In some respects, <strong>of</strong> course, a person’s earlier self does partially shapehis later self: his earlier decisions <strong>and</strong> actions affect his capacity for <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ations toward later experiences, decisions, <strong>and</strong> actions. But if a persondoes improve his qualities, what could merit praise but <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>gredient<strong>of</strong> aspiration <strong>and</strong> resolution <strong>in</strong> him that made his effort possible (Hobart1934/1984, p. 505)? What could merit praise except features <strong>of</strong> an alreadyexist<strong>in</strong>g character that could not have been fully its own creation? Onepraiseworthy character trait is <strong>the</strong> capacity to respond suitably to praise,blame, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> responsibility.


300 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyAny consistently conceivable self must to at least some extent, <strong>the</strong>n—<strong>and</strong> experience suggests a large extent—be <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> external forces.What implications follow concern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> freedom, autonomy, dignity,<strong>and</strong> responsibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual? Hobart faces <strong>the</strong> question: How cananyone be praised or blamed if heredity <strong>and</strong> circumstance have ultimatelygiven him his qualities? Does <strong>the</strong> fact that a person did not create himselfbar recogniz<strong>in</strong>g his character for what it is? If—<strong>in</strong>conceivably—someonehad somehow made his own “orig<strong>in</strong>al character,” <strong>and</strong> a f<strong>in</strong>e one, <strong>and</strong> ifwe praised him for it, we would be ascrib<strong>in</strong>g a still earlier character tohim. Praise or blame for decisions or actions refers to what k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> persontook <strong>the</strong>m; <strong>the</strong>re is noth<strong>in</strong>g else for praise or blame to refer to (Hobart1934/1984, p. 505).A person’s character at a particular time is what it is. It <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>es him to<strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentions <strong>and</strong> decisions <strong>and</strong> actions that it does <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>e himtoward; so it mean<strong>in</strong>gfully exposes him to admiration or reprehension,praise or blame. is is true regardless <strong>of</strong> just how his character came tobe what it is. A reprehensible character rema<strong>in</strong>s reprehensible even thoughit can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed, or expla<strong>in</strong>ed away, as <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> adverse heredity<strong>and</strong> environment. e notion <strong>of</strong> character be<strong>in</strong>g admirable or reprehensibleonly to <strong>the</strong> extent that it is <strong>in</strong>ternally determ<strong>in</strong>ed, free <strong>of</strong> external<strong>in</strong>fluences, is a self-contradictory notion.An analogy <strong>of</strong> sorts holds with a person’s wants <strong>and</strong> tastes. J.K. Galbraith(1958, esp. chap. XI) made much <strong>of</strong> what he called <strong>the</strong> “dependenceeffect”: many <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>dividual’s wants <strong>in</strong> modern society are notwants that he would experience spontaneously if left to himself. Instead,his wants are created by <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m. e consumptionpatterns <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r members <strong>of</strong> society, <strong>and</strong> notoriously advertis<strong>in</strong>g,create wants. Wants that are artificial <strong>in</strong> this sense cannot be urgent orimportant, so <strong>the</strong> implication runs (<strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> Galbraith’s view, <strong>in</strong>comesthat might never<strong>the</strong>less be spent on meet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m may properly betaxed heavily to f<strong>in</strong>ance really important services <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds supplied bygovernment).F.A. Hayek (1961/1967) calls this argument a non sequitur. Supposethat people would <strong>in</strong>deed feel no need for someth<strong>in</strong>g if it were not produced.If that fact did prove <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> small value, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> highestproducts <strong>of</strong> human endeavor, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> arts, literature, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> marvels<strong>of</strong> high technology, would be <strong>of</strong> small value. St<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>of</strong> hygiene <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for products with which to meet <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> aris<strong>in</strong>g spontaneouslywith<strong>in</strong> each separate <strong>in</strong>dividual, are likewise social products.


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 301More generally, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual himself is <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> social forces,operat<strong>in</strong>g largely through language, which conditions his thoughts, values,<strong>and</strong> activities. Recogniz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual as a social product <strong>in</strong> noway denies that happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> misery, success <strong>and</strong> frustration, are experiencedby <strong>in</strong>dividuals; <strong>the</strong>re is no such th<strong>in</strong>g as collective happ<strong>in</strong>ess dist<strong>in</strong>ctfrom <strong>and</strong> transcend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals. Recogniz<strong>in</strong>ghow society shapes its members <strong>in</strong> no way imposes collectivist or communitarianra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>in</strong>dividualist th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> policies.e analogy, <strong>in</strong> brief, amounts to this: A person’s tastes are what <strong>the</strong>yare <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir gratification or frustration causes him pleasure or unhapp<strong>in</strong>ess,even though his tastes are <strong>the</strong>mselves largely <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> external<strong>in</strong>fluences. Similarly, a person’s character is what it is <strong>and</strong> does exposehim to admiration <strong>and</strong> praise or reprobation <strong>and</strong> blame, even thoughhis character, like his tastes, is itself largely <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> external <strong>in</strong>fluences.Praise <strong>and</strong> reward, blame <strong>and</strong> punishment, are appropriate to <strong>the</strong> extentthat <strong>the</strong>y are capable <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>g actions, decisions,<strong>and</strong> character traits, <strong>in</strong>appropriate o<strong>the</strong>rwise—so Moritz Schlick persuasivelyargues. Hav<strong>in</strong>g grown up <strong>in</strong> ghetto poverty is no valid excuse forrobbery, mayhem, or murder; on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, it is po<strong>in</strong>tless to blamea person for actions imposed by congenital deformity or actual <strong>in</strong>sanity.Reward <strong>and</strong> punishment, praise <strong>and</strong> blame, all implicitly acknowledge apartial determ<strong>in</strong>ism operat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> human affairs. (Sometimes, however, adist<strong>in</strong>ction holds between punishment <strong>and</strong> blame, as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>unruly dog. Individual or collective self-defense aga<strong>in</strong>st crim<strong>in</strong>ally <strong>in</strong>sanepersons, as aga<strong>in</strong>st mad dogs, is not <strong>the</strong> same as assign<strong>in</strong>g moral culpability.“Punishment” <strong>in</strong> such a case, like quarant<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> a disease-carrier, isnot punishment <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> fullest sense.)Praise or blame, reward or punishment, is appropriate for an act committedfreely, even <strong>and</strong> especially for one committed <strong>in</strong> accordance with<strong>the</strong> agent’s moral character. Its appropriateness does not h<strong>in</strong>ge on <strong>the</strong>agent’s character be<strong>in</strong>g totally uncaused, whatever that might mean. Praiseor blame would be <strong>in</strong>appropriate if it would have no effect on acts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>type <strong>in</strong> question <strong>and</strong> no effect on propensities to commit <strong>the</strong>m.Partial determ<strong>in</strong>ism, which responsibility presupposes, is fundamentallydifferent both from full determ<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> from complete (perhapsstochastic) <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ism. It recognizes that causality does operate <strong>in</strong>human affairs, as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> universe. It recognizes that how an<strong>in</strong>dividual will decide when fac<strong>in</strong>g a particular choice may be heavily or


302 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophydecisively <strong>in</strong>fluenced by his genetic makeup <strong>and</strong> by his past experiences.ese <strong>in</strong>fluences <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>the</strong> arguments he has heard <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> thoughtsthat have been aroused <strong>in</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> responsibility<strong>and</strong> prospects <strong>of</strong> praise <strong>and</strong> blame. Partial determ<strong>in</strong>ism does not ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>,however, that absolutely everyth<strong>in</strong>g is fully predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>utestdetail. It allows some scope for chance <strong>and</strong> possibly, also, some scope for<strong>the</strong> autonomy (or whatever it might be called) that doctr<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> free willallude to.Unlike full determ<strong>in</strong>ism, <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> only partial determ<strong>in</strong>ism, recogniz<strong>in</strong>gscope for some sort <strong>of</strong> free will, does not enjoy built-<strong>in</strong> immunityto adverse evidence <strong>and</strong> is not devoid <strong>of</strong> practical implications. Ifpeople never experienced feel<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> autonomy <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g decisions—if<strong>the</strong>y never experienced situations <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y felt that <strong>the</strong>y personallywere weigh<strong>in</strong>g conflict<strong>in</strong>g considerations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves mak<strong>in</strong>g decisions,free <strong>of</strong> total outside compulsion <strong>and</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>t, <strong>and</strong> if, on <strong>the</strong> contrary,<strong>the</strong>y always perceived <strong>the</strong>mselves under identifiable tight compulsions<strong>and</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>ts—<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> free will would falter. Orif people sometimes did experience feel<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> autonomy but could beshown <strong>in</strong> each case that <strong>the</strong> feel<strong>in</strong>gs were illusory <strong>and</strong> shown <strong>in</strong> detail justhow <strong>the</strong>ir supposed free choices were <strong>in</strong> fact externally predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>full, aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> free-will doctr<strong>in</strong>e would be underm<strong>in</strong>ed. Most obviously,<strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e would be discredited if people were always keenly aware <strong>of</strong>be<strong>in</strong>g mere l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> a causal cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> if <strong>the</strong>y recognized <strong>in</strong> detail justwhat causes were operat<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g recogniz<strong>in</strong>g just how variousfacts <strong>and</strong> arguments came to <strong>the</strong>ir attention <strong>and</strong> what weight each <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>se comm<strong>and</strong>ed.Discredit<strong>in</strong>g evidence <strong>of</strong> this sort is conceivable, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> free-will doctr<strong>in</strong>eitself does not rule out its significance. at very fact shows that <strong>the</strong>doctr<strong>in</strong>e is not empty. e absence <strong>of</strong> such discredit<strong>in</strong>g evidence suggests,fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, that <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e may be correct. But it does not, <strong>of</strong> course,prove that it is right; no doctr<strong>in</strong>e about empirical reality can ever be provedabsolutely.Discuss<strong>in</strong>g free will versus determ<strong>in</strong>ism was necessary because many philosophersconsider <strong>the</strong> issue genu<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> important, <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>question <strong>of</strong> moral responsibility <strong>and</strong> so with ethics <strong>in</strong> general. e fatalistdoctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> an unbroken cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> tight causal determ<strong>in</strong>ation operat<strong>in</strong>g


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 303from <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> time, <strong>of</strong> apparently ever more complex states <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> world hav<strong>in</strong>g been fully specified <strong>in</strong> advance by <strong>the</strong> apparently lesscomplex earlier states—that doctr<strong>in</strong>e is practically <strong>in</strong>credible. e idea <strong>of</strong>some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> sheer chance almost imposes itself. Chance enters ethical discussionnot because it itself provides scope for responsible human choicebut because it underm<strong>in</strong>es <strong>the</strong> claims <strong>of</strong> full, fatalistic determ<strong>in</strong>ism. Oncedeterm<strong>in</strong>ism is shaken, <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> some sort <strong>of</strong> free will, operat<strong>in</strong>g alongside <strong>of</strong> both causation <strong>and</strong> chance, ga<strong>in</strong>s a possible foothold. Everydaypersonal experience supports some such idea.One question, however, rema<strong>in</strong>s dangl<strong>in</strong>g: Can a person’s will be shaped<strong>in</strong> any manner o<strong>the</strong>r than by chance <strong>and</strong> by external <strong>in</strong>fluences such asheredity, environment, <strong>and</strong> experiences (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g exposure to ideas concern<strong>in</strong>gresponsibility, praise, <strong>and</strong> blame)? <strong>Is</strong> reflection <strong>in</strong> one’s own m<strong>in</strong>dsuch an “o<strong>the</strong>r” manner? No, or not unequivocally; for although ampleexperience testifies to its reality, that reflection is itself conditioned byexternal <strong>in</strong>fluences, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> actions <strong>and</strong> ideas <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people. Yetsome such “o<strong>the</strong>r” manner <strong>of</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ation seems to be what <strong>the</strong> cheerleadersfor free will are postulat<strong>in</strong>g.One approach to a solution—to reconcil<strong>in</strong>g free will with <strong>the</strong> sort<strong>of</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ism that science deals <strong>in</strong>—appeals to <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> emergentproperties. “Specific comb<strong>in</strong>ations, arrangements or <strong>in</strong>teractions <strong>of</strong> componentscan give rise to totally new attributes. e whole is more than <strong>the</strong>sum <strong>of</strong> its parts.” Diamond <strong>and</strong> charcoal possess properties quite differentfrom those <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir component carbon atoms. A drum made from flatplanks can roll. An essay has mean<strong>in</strong>g not conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>kdots on <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ted page. Laws <strong>of</strong> grammar are quite different from butnot <strong>in</strong>compatible with laws <strong>of</strong> physics. Similarly, somehow, <strong>the</strong> humanm<strong>in</strong>d is able “to make choices not determ<strong>in</strong>ed solely by external or geneticallyfixed factors; <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d is self-programm<strong>in</strong>g—it modifies its ownprocesses” (Voss 1995/1996).I admittedly cannot form a satisfactorily def<strong>in</strong>ite conception <strong>of</strong> whatsuggestions like that may be gett<strong>in</strong>g at. I claim, <strong>the</strong>n, not to have settled<strong>the</strong> free-will issue but to have kept alive <strong>the</strong> possibility that if it is notmerely a pseudo-problem after all, it anyway is not a problem subversive<strong>of</strong> ethics. e determ<strong>in</strong>ist <strong>the</strong>sis appears mean<strong>in</strong>gless <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> carry<strong>in</strong>gbuilt-<strong>in</strong> immunity to any conceivable adverse evidence. S<strong>in</strong>ce noobservations about <strong>the</strong> world could conceivably clash with it, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sisdoes not really say anyth<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> world <strong>and</strong> about whe<strong>the</strong>r any freewill operates <strong>in</strong> it.


304 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyWhile <strong>the</strong> free-will/determ<strong>in</strong>ism issue thus dangles unsettled, we allf<strong>in</strong>d ourselves seized with <strong>in</strong>eradicable impressions (or illusions) that weenjoy some freedom <strong>of</strong> action <strong>and</strong> choice <strong>and</strong> even <strong>of</strong> will. When we writeas scholars, we simply cannot believe that our every word is precisely predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed<strong>and</strong> will draw precisely predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed reactions from our fellowscholars.Sometimes we f<strong>in</strong>d two or more str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory applicable to certa<strong>in</strong>phenomena without our be<strong>in</strong>g able—yet, anyway—to reconcile thosestr<strong>and</strong>s, which may even appear <strong>in</strong>consistent. An example concerns <strong>the</strong>apparent dual nature (wave <strong>and</strong> particle natures) <strong>of</strong> light <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> electrons.e pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> complementarity, <strong>in</strong>troduced to physics by Niels Bohr,condones apply<strong>in</strong>g each str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory where it does good service whilestill hop<strong>in</strong>g to reconcile <strong>the</strong> different str<strong>and</strong>s, perhaps by modify<strong>in</strong>g oneor all (Teller 1980, pp. 93, 105–106, 138–140). Economists formerly didnot know, <strong>and</strong> some would say still do not know, how fully to reconcilethree str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments analysis, <strong>the</strong> elasticities, absorption,<strong>and</strong> monetary approaches. It makes sense anyway to apply each approachwhere it does good service while still seek<strong>in</strong>g a fuller reconciliation among<strong>the</strong>m.Similarly, <strong>in</strong> analyz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> worlds <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> human affairs, wef<strong>in</strong>d it reasonable to believe <strong>in</strong> tight causality or <strong>in</strong> causality loosened byan element <strong>of</strong> sheer chance. We also f<strong>in</strong>d reason—or at least <strong>the</strong> pressure<strong>of</strong> compell<strong>in</strong>g personal experience—to believe <strong>in</strong> a loosen<strong>in</strong>g by some element<strong>of</strong> free will. e correspond<strong>in</strong>g str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory are complementary.S<strong>in</strong>ce we cannot really believe that ethics is a field deprived <strong>of</strong> subject matter,let us cont<strong>in</strong>ue <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g it. Let us condemn, though, <strong>the</strong> tactic <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g mere cheerlead<strong>in</strong>g forfree will <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> guise <strong>of</strong> argument. (Free will is good, those who doubt itare scoundrels, <strong>and</strong> we are on <strong>the</strong> side <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good.) As David Hume said,“this question should be decided by fair arguments before philosophers,[ra<strong>the</strong>r] than by declamations before <strong>the</strong> people” (1739–1740/1961, Bk. II,Pt. III, last paragraph <strong>of</strong> Sec. II). Edward N. Lorenz (1993, pp. 159–160) rem<strong>in</strong>ds us that we should believe even <strong>in</strong>an uncomfortable truth ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>in</strong> an appeal<strong>in</strong>g falsehood. at premise recommendsbeliev<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> free will. If it is a reality, our choice is correct. If it is not, we still shall nothave made an <strong>in</strong>correct choice, s<strong>in</strong>ce, lack<strong>in</strong>g free will, we shall not have made any choiceat all.


Chapter : Free Will <strong>and</strong> Ethics 305Boyle, Joseph M., Jr., Germa<strong>in</strong> Grisez, <strong>and</strong> Olaf Tollefsen. Free Choice: A Self-Referential Argument. Notre Dame, Ind.: University <strong>of</strong> Notre Dame Press,1976.Campbell, C.A. “<strong>Is</strong> ‘Freewill’ a Pseudo-Problem?” 1951. In Free Will <strong>and</strong> Determ<strong>in</strong>ism,edited by Bernard Ber<strong>of</strong>sky, 112–135. New York: Harper & Row, 1966.Dwork<strong>in</strong>, Gerald. “Act<strong>in</strong>g Freely.” 1970. In Reason at Work: Introductory Read<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>in</strong> Philosophy, edited by Steven M. Cahn, Patricia Kitcher, <strong>and</strong> George Sher,509–522. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1984.Eucken, Walter. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Economics. Translated by T.W. Hutchison.London: Hodge, 1950.Galbraith, John Kenneth. e Affluent Society. Boston: Houghton Miffl<strong>in</strong>, 1958.Georgescu-Roegen, Nicholas. e Entropy Law <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Economic Process. Cambridge,Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971.Gigerenzer, Gerd, Zeno Swijt<strong>in</strong>k, eodore Porter, Lorra<strong>in</strong>e Daston, JohnBeatty, <strong>and</strong> Lorenz Krüger. e Empire <strong>of</strong> Chance. 1989. Cambridge <strong>and</strong> NewYork: Cambridge University Press, 1993.Hayek, F.A. “e Non Sequitur <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘Dependence Effect’.” 1961. In Studies<strong>in</strong> Philosophy, Politics <strong>and</strong> Economics. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press,1967.. e Constitution <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1960.Hazlitt, Henry. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Morality. 1964. Los Angeles: Nash, 1972.Hobart, R.E. “Free Will as Involv<strong>in</strong>g Determ<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong> Inconceivable WithoutIt.” 1934. In Reason at Work: Introductory Read<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> Philosophy, edited bySteven M. Cahn, Patricia Kitcher, <strong>and</strong> George Sher, 494–508. New York:Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1984.Hospers, John. “What Means this Freedom?” 1961. In Free Will <strong>and</strong> Determ<strong>in</strong>ism,edited by Bernard Ber<strong>of</strong>ski, 26–45. New York: Harper & Row, 1966.Hume, David. A Treatise <strong>of</strong> Human Nature. 1739–1740. Garden City: DoubledayDolph<strong>in</strong>, 1961.Kant, Immanuel. Groundwork <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Metaphysic <strong>of</strong> Morals. 1785. Translated byH.J. Paton. New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1964.


306 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyLorenz, Edward N. e Essence <strong>of</strong> Chaos. Seattle: University <strong>of</strong> Wash<strong>in</strong>gton Press,1993.Meyerson, Émile. Explanation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Sciences. 1921. Translated by Mary-AliceSipfle <strong>and</strong> David A. Sipfle. Dordrecht <strong>and</strong> Boston: Kluwer, 1991.Mills, Frederick C. Statistical Methods Applied to Economics <strong>and</strong> Bus<strong>in</strong>ess. Rev. ed.New York: Holt, 1938.Peirce, Charles S. Values <strong>in</strong> a Universe <strong>of</strong> Chance. 1877. Edited by Philip P. Wiener.Garden City: Doubleday Anchor Books, 1958.. “e Scientific Attitude <strong>and</strong> Fallibilism.” 1891. In Philosophical Writ<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>of</strong> Peirce, edited by Justus Buchler, 42–59. New York: Dover, 1955.Popper, Karl. “Indeterm<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>Is</strong> Not Enough.” Lecture at <strong>the</strong> Mont Péler<strong>in</strong> Societymeet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Munich, September 1972. Pr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> e Open Universe, 30–36.Totowa, N.J.: Rowan <strong>and</strong> Littlefield, 1982.. Unended Quest. Rev. ed. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1982.. Popper Selections. Edited by David Miller. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: Pr<strong>in</strong>cetonUniversity Press, 1985.Schlick, Moritz. Problems <strong>of</strong> Ethics. 1930. Translated by David Ryn<strong>in</strong>, 1939. NewYork: Dover, 1961.Slote, Michael. “Ethics without Free Will.” Social eory <strong>and</strong> Practice 16 (Fall1990): 369–383.Squire, John Coll<strong>in</strong>gs, ed. If, or History Rewritten. New York: Vik<strong>in</strong>g, 1931.Teller, Edward. e Pursuit <strong>of</strong> Simplicity. Malibu: Pepperd<strong>in</strong>e University Press,1980.van Inwagen, Peter. “Response to Slote.” Social eory <strong>and</strong> Practice 16 (Fall 1990):385–395.Voss, Peter. “Freewill <strong>and</strong> Determ<strong>in</strong>ism.” 1995. Revised 1996. http://mol.redbarn.org/objectivism/writ<strong>in</strong>g/PeterVoss/FreeWillAndDeterm<strong>in</strong>ism.html.


Elementos del EconomiaPolitic *Le economia politic jace al <strong>in</strong>tersection del sciencia economic, <strong>the</strong>oriapolitic, e philosophia. Io conduceva un sem<strong>in</strong>ario <strong>in</strong> iste campo durantemulte annos al Universitate de Virg<strong>in</strong>ia e postea al Universitate Auburn.Le studentes e io revideva le conception libertari del governamento e conceptionesplus collectivista. Ma non preoccupa vos: mi proposito hodienon es recrutar vos a mi proprie puncto de vista politic. Como altere parlatorese como io ipse a previe reuniones del UMI, io vole illustrar le <strong>in</strong>terl<strong>in</strong>guaparlate e un vocabulario anque technic <strong>in</strong> discuter un large varietatede <strong>the</strong>mas. Mi studentes e io comenciava per explorar le rolo de judicios de valor<strong>in</strong> recommendar e decider politicas public (como regulationes economice impostos). On debe dist<strong>in</strong>guer <strong>in</strong>ter judicios de valor, anque appellatepropositiones normative, e propositiones positive, que es observationes defactos o <strong>in</strong>ferentias de logica. Exemplos de propositiones de factos e logicaes illos del stricte <strong>the</strong>oria economic. Le philosopho e economista DavidHume (Scotia, 1711–1776) <strong>in</strong>sisteva super iste dist<strong>in</strong>ction, postea appellatele «Furca de Hume»: on non pote derivar un conclusion super que es bon orecommendabile, o le contrario, solo per le factos e le logica. Brevemente,on non pote derivar un debe de un es. Per exemplo, solo ab le facto medicalque il es periculose pro le sanitate del <strong>in</strong>fante si un fem<strong>in</strong>a gravide bibealcohol, on non pote arrivar at judicio que un fem<strong>in</strong>a gravide debe abst<strong>in</strong>erse del alcohol. Pro un tal conclusion, on besonia non solo le factos medical*is <strong>in</strong>troduction to political economy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Public Choice school was a talk at<strong>the</strong> Interl<strong>in</strong>gua conference, Prague, 7 August 1995, published as a pamphlet by UnionMundial pro Interl<strong>in</strong>gua, Bilthoven, Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s, 1995.307


308 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyma anque le judicio normative que le sanitate de <strong>in</strong>fantes es desirabile, emesmo plus desirabile que le placeres momentari de lor matres <strong>in</strong> biberalcohol. Un altere exemplo: solo del proposition factual e de logica queun certe politica economic conducerea al miseria de personas <strong>in</strong> generale que un politica alternative conducerea al felicitate general, on non potejudicar le prime politica mal e le secunde bon; on besonia anque un judicionormative contra le miseria e pro le felicitate.Como iste exemplos suggere, on pote discuter judicios relativementespecific—como pro e contra politicas specific—per <strong>in</strong>vocar e factos e logicae altere e plus pr<strong>of</strong>unde judicios de valor. On pote condemnar le mentir,le defraudar, e le furar per demonstrar que tal conductos tende a subverterle felicitate general, juncte con un judicio <strong>in</strong> favor del felicitate. Le judicio<strong>in</strong> favor del felicitate es pro le plus de personas, probablemente, un judiciode valor fundamental, como on dice. Per le def<strong>in</strong>ition de un judicio fundamental,on non pote arguer <strong>in</strong> su favor; on es al f<strong>in</strong> de argumentation;on debe appellar al observation o <strong>in</strong>tuition directe. Ma como iste exemploanque suggere, disputas super judicios fundamental de valor es rar. Quas<strong>in</strong>emo dubitarea que le miseria es mal e le felicitate es bon, ma quasi nemopensarea a demonstrar lo; un tal demonstration exigerea un appello a unjudicio ancora plus fundamental, le qual on pote a pena imag<strong>in</strong>ar.Nos non ha le tempore hic pro appr<strong>of</strong>undar nos <strong>in</strong> iste dist<strong>in</strong>ctiones<strong>in</strong>ter factos, logica, e valores e <strong>in</strong>ter valores relativemente specific e valoresfundamental. Io pote solo subl<strong>in</strong>ear que iste <strong>the</strong>mas philosophic esimportante <strong>in</strong> identificar le fontes exacte de disaccordo <strong>in</strong> disputas superpoliticas governamental como <strong>in</strong> le vita personal. Judicios de bon e mal es materias de ethica, e le ethica es a base del conceptosde philosophia politic e le derectos del hom<strong>in</strong>e. In plus, le fundamentode ethica pote a pena esser altere que utilitari. Le criterio quasi-ultimatede actiones, regulas, tractos de character, etc. es le cooperation social, ocomo alicunos dice, le societate civil. Illo es un societate ben functionante<strong>in</strong> le qual le <strong>in</strong>dividuos pote viver <strong>in</strong>simul <strong>in</strong> pace, beneficiante mutualmentede lor <strong>in</strong>teractiones e lor commercio. Le analyse del cooperationsocial es le gr<strong>and</strong>e campo commun <strong>in</strong>ter le ethica e le scientia social. Actiones,regulas, e tractos de character se judica bon o mal secundo que illostende a appoiar o subverter le cooperation social. Io appella isto le criterioquasi-ultimate proque illo es solmente un medio, ben que le medio


Chapter : Elementos del Economia Politic 309<strong>in</strong>dispensabile, al desideratum f<strong>in</strong>al, que es le felicitate human (<strong>in</strong> un sensoconvenibilemente extendite del parola «felicitate»). In mi sem<strong>in</strong>arios nos discuteva le perspicacias de David Hume, F.A. Hayek,Robert Alexrod, David Gauthier, Loren Lomasky, e alteres super lepossibile evolution «spontanee» del cooperation <strong>in</strong>ter hom<strong>in</strong>es. Axelrodempleava torneos e simulationes per computator pro explorar le joco repetitedel «dilemma del prisioneros». (On lo appella assi ab un certe exemplost<strong>and</strong>ard del joco.) In un s<strong>in</strong>gule session o reprisa del joco, s<strong>in</strong> reguardoa eventual repetitiones, le action plus avantagiose e strictemente rationalpro cata un del duo jocatores es cercar exploitar le altere (non cooperar),s<strong>in</strong> reguardo a su action. Infortunatemente, qu<strong>and</strong>o ambes age assi, rationalmente<strong>in</strong> le sense stricte, le resultato es mal pro ambes. Qu<strong>and</strong>o, alcontrario, cata un age cooperativemente, le resultato es assatis bon proambes Ma, como jam stipulate, qu<strong>and</strong>o cata uno decide su strategia separatemente,su action strictemente rational es cercar exploitar le altere; alteremente,on se trova le victima. Alora, le problema es: que <strong>in</strong>centivo hacata jocator prender un perspectiva plus large e non persequer su propriestricte avantage immediate?Le solution appare <strong>in</strong> un joco repetite <strong>in</strong> multe reprisas. Cata jocatorapprende que su actiones transmitte signales al altere. In le experimentosde Axelrod, le strategia plus successose es render le par (anglese: «tit-fortat»).<strong>Is</strong>to vole dicer: on comencia jocar cooperativemente; ma si le opponenteage exploitevemente, on retalia <strong>in</strong> le reprisa sequente. Si le opponenterecomencia jocar cooperativemente, on lo face anque. Le pr<strong>in</strong>cipiosuccessose es cooperar, ma non lassar se dupar: jocar reciprocamente.<strong>Is</strong>te strategia se dist<strong>in</strong>gue del pr<strong>in</strong>cipio christian de verter le altere gena.Ille conducta christian pote semblar confortabile <strong>in</strong> le s<strong>in</strong>gule caso, e onpote illuder se que illo es mesmo nobile e philanthropic. Al contrario,tal vertimento del altere gena facilita le via pro le predatores; illo tende atraher le predation non solo a se ipse ma anque a altere personas <strong>in</strong>nocente.Dunque, illo es anti-social. On debe non premiar ma punir e discoragiarle aspirante predatores. Le strategia vermente social pro le longe term<strong>in</strong>oes le reciprocitate: responder al cooperation e benevolentia con le mesmo,ma punir le predation.Obviemente, le joco del dilemma del prisioneros e le experimentosde Axelrod es un metaphora pro le sociatate. Mesmo si cata <strong>in</strong>dividuo


310 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyproseque solo su proprie <strong>in</strong>teresse, un reguardo pro le longe term<strong>in</strong>o e prole reactiones de altere personas pote <strong>in</strong>ducer le a ager reciprocamente. Lecooperation pote evolver «spontaneamente».Le metaphora de Axelrod e altere recercatores <strong>in</strong> su tradition es un merpr<strong>of</strong>ilation de certe aspectos del societate, e on debe evitar mis<strong>in</strong>terpretationdel concepto «reciprocitate». Reciprocar non vole dicer <strong>in</strong>sister superun stricte excambio de beneficios recipite e beneficios fornate, toto mesurate<strong>in</strong> moneta. Le reciprocitate <strong>in</strong> societate es le bon voluntate a tractaraltere personas con un certe benevolentia generalisate e expectar un similetractamento ab le alteres, ma non le voluntate a tolerar le maltractamento,que <strong>in</strong>vitarea le predation non solo contra se ipse ma anque contra alterepersonas. Reciprocitate es le excambio—non necessarimente strictementecalculate—de attitudes e actiones appropriate. (De modo similar, le parola«mercato» non se restr<strong>in</strong>ge sempre a transactiones strictemente economic.In un senso extendite, le «mercato» es un metaphora pro omne relationesvoluntari <strong>in</strong>ter hom<strong>in</strong>es, <strong>in</strong> contrasto con relationes imponite per fortia <strong>of</strong>raude o costumes rigide e oppressive.)Multo economicamente productive, pro recoltar le ganios del specialisatione commercio, es le gr<strong>and</strong>e processo national e mundial de excambiosmultilateral de benes e servicios <strong>in</strong>ter milliones e billiones de personasqui non se cognosce le un le altere. In iste processo de cooperation impersonal,evaluationes monetari es <strong>in</strong>dispensabile. Ma non omne relationes<strong>in</strong>ter hom<strong>in</strong>es es relationes del mercato commercial e del moneta. Comodice F.A. Hayek, laureato Nobel e celebre campion del economia del mercato,un ethica de solidaritate es debite <strong>in</strong> parve gruppos special contenite<strong>in</strong> le gr<strong>and</strong>e societate de <strong>in</strong>tercambios economic mundial—gruppos comole familia, bon amicos, e forsan enthusiastas devote a un causa commun.In un certe grado, on poterea adder, le mesmo pote applicar se anque<strong>in</strong>ter collegas pr<strong>of</strong>essional e <strong>in</strong>ter empleatos e empleatores associate desdelonge tempore. In un gr<strong>and</strong>e societate o «ord<strong>in</strong>e extendite» (como lo appellaHayek), le <strong>in</strong>dividua appert<strong>in</strong>e a ord<strong>in</strong>es de plure typos. Le <strong>in</strong>timitateatt<strong>in</strong>gite <strong>in</strong>tra parve gruppos special ha un gr<strong>and</strong>e valor psychologic.Persequer su <strong>in</strong>teresse personal stricte e immediate, <strong>in</strong>sister super calculosmonetari de costos e beneficios, e <strong>in</strong>sister super reciprocitate strictementeconcipite anque <strong>in</strong>ter membros de tal gruppos—tote isto destruereagr<strong>and</strong>e valores. «Si nos sempre applicava le regulas del ord<strong>in</strong>e extenditea nostre gruppamentos plus <strong>in</strong>time, nos los applattarea. Dunque nos debeapprender viver <strong>in</strong> duo species de mundo simul». (“If we were always toapply <strong>the</strong> rules <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> extended order to our more <strong>in</strong>timate group<strong>in</strong>gs, we


Chapter : Elementos del Economia Politic 311would crush <strong>the</strong>m. So we must learn to live <strong>in</strong> two sorts <strong>of</strong> world at once.”Hayek, e Fatal Conceit, 1989, p. 18.) Le mercato e le moneta es onstitutiones<strong>in</strong>dispensabile al superviventia e conforto human. Ma non omneaspectos del vita debe o pote esser transationes monetari. Infortunatemente, non omne personas observa le regulas de cooperationsocial; alicunos es predatores, crim<strong>in</strong>ales. Il se besonia un agentia del societatepro restr<strong>in</strong>ger les e punir les. Assi argumenta omas Hobbes <strong>in</strong> sulibro Leviathan de 1651. Pro le disveloppamento economic e assi pro un vitaconfortabile—pro un modo commode de viver, como dice Hobbes—il sebesonia le pace e securitate, comprendente le securitate de proprietate privateprotegite per un governamento adequate. S<strong>in</strong> illo, le vita del hom<strong>in</strong>ees—e hic seque, <strong>in</strong> le libro de Hobbes, un description citate tanto frequentemente<strong>in</strong> anglese que illo deveni toto enoiose. Ma io vole traducerle parolas <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terl<strong>in</strong>gua. Alora, s<strong>in</strong> le protection del pace e securitate,dice Hobbes, le vita del hom<strong>in</strong>e es «solitari, povre, nauseabunde, brutal,e breve». De facto, nos observa tal conditiones hodie <strong>in</strong> plure paises delTertie Mundo, e pro le rationes explicate per Hobbes.David Hume enuncia tres regulas necessari pro un societate prospere:le securitate de possessiones, lor transferentia ab un proprietario ad unaltere solo per consentimento (e non per fortia o fraude), e le fidelitate apromissas. S<strong>in</strong> le observation general de iste regulas, le gente ha <strong>in</strong>centivosrelativemente debile pro facer planos pro le futuro, pro <strong>in</strong>terprenderprojectos cooperative complicate e extendite <strong>in</strong> tempore, pro sparniar, epro <strong>in</strong>vestir.Inter le attitudes philosophic circa le quales se ragia disputas superpoliticas plus specific, uno notabile es le equalitarismo. <strong>Is</strong>te attitude <strong>in</strong>cargareale governamento a facer le conditiones economic del <strong>in</strong>dividuos edel stratas del societate m<strong>in</strong>us differente que illos alteremente esserea.Pauco controverse es le idea de un rete social de securitate, que voledicer le <strong>in</strong>stitutiones pro adjutar le plus povre e <strong>in</strong>fortunate membros delsocietate. Plus controverse es le idea que le equalitarismo debe extenderse al supposite problema del troppo gr<strong>and</strong>e ricchessas e que le governamentodebe anque dim<strong>in</strong>uer le fortunas del familias plus ric. In discuterle equalitarismo, on debe considerar le relationes <strong>in</strong>ter le equalitatee le libertate personal. Esque il es possibile persequer politicas de redistribution,e specialmente politicas pro punir le plus ric personas, s<strong>in</strong> ulle


312 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophycosto <strong>in</strong> le libertate personal e s<strong>in</strong> ulle periculo de un governamento troppopotente? : Discussiones de libertate es confundite per varie <strong>in</strong>terpretationes. Perexemplo, un lector (Angus Sibley) scribe al magaz<strong>in</strong>e e Economist(numero del 21 de januario de 1995):Conflicto <strong>in</strong>ter libertate e communitate es <strong>in</strong>evitabile ubi le libertate essimplemente prendite signiflcar «... le derecto del <strong>in</strong>dividuo de non suffrerimposition per alteres». Compara le op<strong>in</strong>ion de un em<strong>in</strong>ente moderne<strong>the</strong>ologo, Patre Bernard Har<strong>in</strong>g: «In essentia, le libertate es le poter defacer le bon». Hic es un plus large e plus ric concepto de libertate quecohere melio con le necessitate basic de communitate.Alora, ille lector e le Patre Har<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terpreta le libertate como le poterde facer lo que se considera bon e conforme al necessitates de communitate.Per iste <strong>in</strong>terpretation, qu<strong>and</strong>o le stato preveni un <strong>in</strong>dividuo de ager <strong>in</strong>un modo considerate mal, on non <strong>in</strong>fr<strong>in</strong>ge su libertate (o su ver libertate).Como equivoc! Ma tal equivocationes es assatis commun <strong>in</strong> discussionesde philosophia politic, como demonstra Sir <strong>Is</strong>aiah Berl<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> un famoseconferentia.Un <strong>in</strong>terpretation del libertate plus franc e plus conforme al l<strong>in</strong>guageord<strong>in</strong>ari es suggerite per plure philosophos politic: Le libertate de un personaes le absentia de restrictiones e compulsiones super su activitatesimponite per altere personas (<strong>in</strong>cludente agentes del stato). <strong>Is</strong>te def<strong>in</strong>itionadmitte considerar varie typos e grados de restriction del libertate; onpote <strong>in</strong>vestigar eventual <strong>in</strong>compatibilitates <strong>in</strong>ter varie libertates specific dedifferente personas; on pote <strong>in</strong>vestigar relationes <strong>in</strong>ter libertate personal emesuras pro promover le equalitate.On debe dist<strong>in</strong>guer <strong>in</strong>ter le libertate de un pais ab un governamentoestranie e le libertate personal de su habitantes, i.e., le absentia de plure<strong>in</strong>trusiones, typicamente governamental, <strong>in</strong> le vita del <strong>in</strong>dividuo. Le citatanosde plure paises <strong>in</strong> le Tertie Mundo, specialmente <strong>in</strong> Africa, ha experimentatele ganio de libertate national (per le decolonisation) ma le perditade gr<strong>and</strong>e partes de lor libertates personal.Un altere parola multo abusate per confusiones sentimental es «democratia».Frequentemente on <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>in</strong> su signification non solo un forma


Chapter : Elementos del Economia Politic 313o modo particular de governamento ma anque varie species de bon conditionescomo «libertate, equalitate, fraternitate», varie conceptiones dejustitia social, varie derectos del <strong>in</strong>dividuo e del societate, e mesmo le stilode vita american. Assi on confunde dist<strong>in</strong>cte conceptiones sub un s<strong>in</strong>guleetiquetta e impedi considerar <strong>in</strong> que grado le varie bon conditiones escompatibile le un con le altere. Per exemplo, que tensiones existe <strong>in</strong>terle dom<strong>in</strong>antia del majoritate e le libertate personal? On glissa ab pensarque le democratia es bon a pensar que plus de democratia es melior e que,dunque, il es bon facer plus e plus decisiones democraticamente, que voledicer lassar los facer per le governamento democratic, que vole dicer quele governamento los face.Un adjuta al clar pensamento es le def<strong>in</strong>ition de democratia suggeriteper Joseph Schumpeter (<strong>in</strong>ter alteres). Le democratia es un methodoparticular pro seliger, <strong>in</strong>fluer, e reimplaciar le governatores politic; illo esle methodo de libere competition pro le scrut<strong>in</strong>ios de un large electorato<strong>in</strong> electiones periodic. Como mer methodo pro seliger le governatores, ledemocratia non pote esser un scopo f<strong>in</strong>al, un desideratum <strong>in</strong> su propriederecto. In particular, le governamento del majoritate non es bon <strong>in</strong> se.Plus vic<strong>in</strong> a un tal scopo es le cooperation social con pace, securitate, elibertate personal. Con le conception stricte del democratia como un specificmethodo politic, on pote considerar le tensiones e compatibilitates<strong>in</strong>ter iste methodo e altere conditiones desirate como «libertate, equalitate,fraternitate» e le bon functionamento del economia. On recognosceque le democratia non es le mesmo que libertate personal e que anquegovernamentos democratic pote <strong>in</strong>fr<strong>in</strong>ger le libertate personal e le derectosdel hom<strong>in</strong>e. On pote comparar le democratia con altere methodospolitic; e si on trova que illo es m<strong>in</strong>us mal que le alteres, iste conclusionnon justifica le cont<strong>in</strong>ue extension del poteres e activitates de un governamentodemocratic. Il se besonia limitationes anque al activitates de un talgovernamento.Como dice Schumpeter, le democratia es un mer methodo pro att<strong>in</strong>gerf<strong>in</strong>es ulterior. Totevia, le Consilio de Registratores de Votantes delContato Lee (ubi io vive) ha annunciate <strong>in</strong> le jornal local (Lee CountyEagle de 14 e 21 augusto 1994): «Il non ha un plus gr<strong>and</strong>e derecto <strong>in</strong> unsocietate libere que le derecto, honor, e deber de votar». William Bradfordha diagnosticate iste specie de confusion <strong>in</strong> un essayo super «Le Nove ReligionCivic». E on pensa al fatuitates que circulava un anno retro super le«restauration del democratia» a Haiti, pais ubi il nunca ha habite le democratia.


314 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy Le democratia es preferibile a altere formas de governamento, ma isto nonvole dicer que facer le cosas democraticamente, illo es, per governamentodemocratic, es preferibile a altere methodos a ager, como per transactionesvoluntari <strong>in</strong> le mercato. Non plus vole illo dicer que limitationes super ledemocratia es necessarimente mal (<strong>in</strong> despecto del epi<strong>the</strong>to «antidemocratic»).Considera, per exemplo, le objectiones commun ma mal concipitecontra le limitationes a term<strong>in</strong>os legislative <strong>in</strong> le Statos Unite o a un amendamentoconstitutional pro le budget equilibrate. Io critica le superstitionesre le democratia <strong>in</strong> arguer pro limitar le sphera e le poteres del governamentoe non pro le autoritarismo o alicun altere forma de governamento.In comparation con altere formas, le democratia ha importante avantages(cf. e Economist del 27 augusto 1994). (Totevia, il ha argumentos rationabilepro un rege o reg<strong>in</strong>a constitutional <strong>in</strong>tra un regime pr<strong>in</strong>cipalmentedemocratic.) Le <strong>the</strong>mas que io revide hodie forma parte—lontan del toto—del materiasde recerca del economistas del Schola de Selection Public (“public choiceschool”). Io non ha le tempore pro describer le extension e subtilitate delor recercas; io pote solo mentionar alicun aspectos o <strong>the</strong>mas. Lor recercasapplica le conceptos e methodos del analyse economic al <strong>in</strong>vestigar lefunctionamento de <strong>in</strong>stitutiones s<strong>in</strong> scopo lucrative, super toto le governamentoe su varie partes, nivellos, e <strong>in</strong>stitutiones. On preme le analyseusque al actor <strong>in</strong>dividual. Le idea central, banal ma decisive, es que le <strong>in</strong>dividuoses fundamentalmente le mesme <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutiones governamental que<strong>in</strong> le vita private. Solo per devenir politico o empleato public, le <strong>in</strong>dividuonon acquire plus de spirito social o plus de distachamento que le persona<strong>in</strong>tegral qui ille jam es. Cata <strong>in</strong>dividuo ha su preferentias e scopos personal(que non debe esser strictemente egoista); e <strong>in</strong> persequer su scopos, catauno responde a opportunitates e <strong>in</strong>centivos (<strong>in</strong>cludente resultatos e costosexpectate).Le prime gr<strong>and</strong>e obra de iste schola (ultra, forsan, un libro de AnthonyDowns de 1957) es Le Calculo del Consentimento (e Calculus <strong>of</strong> Consent),publicate <strong>in</strong> 1962 per James M. Buchanan e Gordon Tullock. Le Pr<strong>of</strong>essorBuchanan, qui ganiava le Premio Nobel <strong>in</strong> le Scientia Economic <strong>in</strong> 1986,es le prime Associato Dist<strong>in</strong>guite del Union Mundial pro Interl<strong>in</strong>gua.


Chapter : Elementos del Economia Politic 315 In considerar le actores <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong> le processo politic, on non debe oblidarle votante ord<strong>in</strong>ari (le elector, e anque le non-votanter proque nonomne citatanos exerce lor derecto a votar). On recognosce su «ignorantiarational»: al <strong>in</strong>dividuo, ord<strong>in</strong>arimente, il non vale le pena expender temporee energia <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>formar se ben del questiones politic proque su actionpersonal <strong>in</strong> acquirer <strong>in</strong>formation non cambiara le resultato del election.On pote dem<strong>and</strong>ar: viste que le s<strong>in</strong>gule voto del <strong>in</strong>dividuo non determ<strong>in</strong>ale resultato, proque mesmo votar? On suggere varie explicationes.Alicun votantes pensa a lor supposite responsibilitate <strong>in</strong> prender parte <strong>in</strong>un ceremonia civic e assi exprimer solidaritate con ideales democratic. Alicunostrova le acto de votar un modo personalmente <strong>in</strong>costose de exprimeremotiones de benevolentia—o de malitia. Precisemente proque su <strong>in</strong>fluentiaes tanto diluite, quasi nulle, le votante <strong>in</strong>dividual pote ager s<strong>in</strong> sensode responsabilitate personal.On remarca le basse qualitate de discussiones del politica public, specialmentepoliticas economic. On concentra le attention at troppo breveterm<strong>in</strong>o; on non pensa al consequentias al longe term<strong>in</strong>o de politicas quesuperficialmente pote semblar attractive. On tende a creditar o blasmar lepresidente o partito <strong>in</strong> poter pro le bon o mal stato currente del cyclo conjunctural;on non comprende que iste mesme cyclo resulta ab <strong>in</strong>stitutionesque persiste trans le varie adm<strong>in</strong>istrationes. On comprende mal le moneta.Per exemplo, le notion prevale que le taxas de <strong>in</strong>teresse es mer parametrosfixate per le banca central, fixate a basse nivello qu<strong>and</strong>o le banca se sentibenevolente e a alte nivello qu<strong>and</strong>o illo se senti malevolente. Le subtilitatesdel relationes <strong>in</strong>ter le <strong>in</strong>flation de precios e le crescimento del productiontotal se perde <strong>in</strong> le discussion public. Le publico non comprende le statoprecari del dollar, que remane s<strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ition.<strong>Is</strong>te basse nivello de discussion seque del ignorantia rational del votante<strong>in</strong>dividual e del realismo del politicos <strong>in</strong> tractar le votantes como illes vermentees e vermente pensa. Lor ignorantia lassa gr<strong>and</strong>e campo pro ledemogogia. Ord<strong>in</strong>arimente il non servi le <strong>in</strong>teresse del politicos predicarbon senso economic.omas Sowell ha dicite; «Le prime lection del scientia economic esle raritate: il nunquam ha assatis de alique pro satisfacer a omnes quilo vole. Le prime lection del politica es disdignar le prime lection delscientia economic». (“e first lesson <strong>of</strong> economics is scarcity: ere isnever enough <strong>of</strong> anyth<strong>in</strong>g to satisfy all those who want it. e first lesson


316 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>of</strong> politics is to disregard <strong>the</strong> first lesson <strong>of</strong> economics.” Citate <strong>in</strong> CEIUpDate, julio de 1994).Ultra le votante rationalmente ignorante, nos considera le membrose representantes de <strong>in</strong>teresses economic special, qui ha rationes pro <strong>in</strong>formarse ben e exercer pression super le politicos. Simile <strong>in</strong> iste respecto esilles que on pote denom<strong>in</strong>ar «hobbyistas», qui, per exemplo, cerca regulationesplus rigorose contra supposite periculos <strong>in</strong> activitates de sport o <strong>in</strong>le dieta del hom<strong>in</strong>e medie o qui vole plus gr<strong>and</strong>e fundos governamentalpro recercas contra le syndrorna de immunodeficientia acquirite (SIDA)o altere maladias particular o qui conduce un cruciada contra le aborto opro le derecto del fem<strong>in</strong>a a seliger. On comprende proque tal <strong>in</strong>teressesspecial e tal hobbyistas ha multo plus de <strong>in</strong>fluentia politic que le citatanoord<strong>in</strong>ari, cuje <strong>in</strong>teresses es relativemente negligite.Un altere classe de participantes <strong>in</strong> le processo politic es, obviemente, lepoliticos mesme. Duo seculos retro <strong>in</strong> le Statos Unite, le <strong>of</strong>ficiales publice le legislatores esseva, al m<strong>in</strong>us idealmente, citatanos de spirito civic quioccupava lor <strong>of</strong>ficios temporarimente o solo un parte del tempore e postearetornava a lor fermas o altere occupationes normal. (On pensa al ancianromano C<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>natus e a George Wash<strong>in</strong>gton.) Hodie le politica ha deveniteun pr<strong>of</strong>ession de horario complete e un carriera del vita. Le politicosipse ha devenite un <strong>in</strong>teresse special, con su particular desiros e puncto devista. <strong>Is</strong>to es un del rationes pro le proposition de poner limites a quanteannos on pote servir <strong>in</strong> un <strong>of</strong>ficio determ<strong>in</strong>ate. (<strong>Is</strong>te reforma certo nonsanarea omne defectos del systema politic, ma il ha un certe senso.) Il haconflictos <strong>in</strong>ter le <strong>in</strong>teresse personal del politico e le <strong>in</strong>teresse general delpais.Le politicos ha breve horizontes de tempore e vision restr<strong>in</strong>gite como<strong>in</strong> un tunnel. Como mentionate, illes exploita le ignorantia del votanteord<strong>in</strong>ari. Pro le publicitate e probabilemente anque pro un senso de amorproprie e de importantia, illes tende a <strong>in</strong>ventar ideas brillante e cercarimpler los per le fortia del lege. On perveni a pensar del governamentocomo Fee Benefic. On glissa a pensar que si alique es bon o desirabile, legovernamento debe provider o promover o subsidiar lo. Si alique es mal,le governamento debe supprimer o discoragiar lo. On glissa a attribueriste responsibilitates specialmente al governamento national, oblidanteque sub le Constitution american su poteres es strictemente limitate e


Chapter : Elementos del Economia Politic 317que le plus gr<strong>and</strong>e parte del poteres e responsabilitates es restr<strong>in</strong>gite alc<strong>in</strong>quanta Statos e su subdivisiones politic e al populo mesme. On tendea pensar que opposition a un proponite action del governamento nationales opposition al ben ipse e consentimento al mal ipse.Exemplos de benes e males que le governamento debe promover orernediar, secundo le caso, listate <strong>in</strong> nulle ord<strong>in</strong>e special, es: education,repastos pro <strong>in</strong>fantes, systemas de pension, drogas, pornographia, discim<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>in</strong>ter le racias e altere manifestationes del pensamento pauconobile, consideration special pro personas con h<strong>and</strong>icaps corporal o mental,le congedo ab le empleo <strong>in</strong> caso de problemas familial, le securitatephysic <strong>in</strong> le empleo e <strong>in</strong> le sport, preservation de terras humide, e le suppositealte cultura <strong>in</strong> le artes, television, e radio. In martio de 1995, perle posta, le assi denom<strong>in</strong>ate Gente pro le Via American (People for <strong>the</strong>American Way) me ha <strong>in</strong>vitate a «<strong>in</strong>rolar me <strong>in</strong> le battalia contra le censura»(“jo<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> battle aga<strong>in</strong>st censorship”)—per contribuer moneta, ilva s<strong>in</strong> dicer. Le «censura» <strong>in</strong> ille appello se refere al propositiones pro discont<strong>in</strong>uarle subsidios del governamento national al television.On se rememora rarmente del Lege de Consequentias Non Intendite.On non da debite attention a effectos lateral non desirate e a alternativasal action governamental.<strong>Is</strong>te generalisationes re breve horizontes, legislation de ideas suppositebrillante, e vision de tunnel es documentate <strong>in</strong> libros de James L. Payne,Robert Higgs, e Richard Epste<strong>in</strong> e <strong>in</strong> studios caso per caso del systemapolitic <strong>in</strong> le Statos Unite, e specialmente del Congresso, studios scribiteper jornalistas, empleatos <strong>in</strong> le <strong>of</strong>ficios al Coll<strong>in</strong>a del Capitolio <strong>in</strong> Wash<strong>in</strong>gton,e altere proxime observatores. Io recommenda Alan Ehrenhalt, eUnited States <strong>of</strong> Ambition, John Jackley, Hill Rat, e Eric Felten, e Rul<strong>in</strong>gClass. Le <strong>the</strong>oria del selection public explora le positiones e <strong>in</strong>centivos specialanque del bureaucrates. Mesmo si su motivation es purmente le ben delpublico, un bureaucrate sape plus del nobile mission de su proprie bureauque de altere usos, public e private, del moneta e ressources necessari. Illevole <strong>in</strong>crementar le gr<strong>and</strong>or e le budget de su bureau. Un bureau tende aformar alliantias <strong>in</strong>ter se, le sector private affectate, e le committees parlamentaricargate con su supervision. Tote isto contribue al crescimento delgovernamento.


318 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyOn debe considerar le situationes special anque de advocatos, litigantes,judices, e juratos. Le processos de lege pro traher judicamentos f<strong>in</strong>anciariab «tascas pr<strong>of</strong>unde» deveni ancora un maniera de abusar le governamentoad <strong>in</strong> un organo de redistribution de ricchessas, mesmo dumimpedir lor creation. Mesmo si il es desirabile implementar le preferentias del populo, onconstata que le mechanismo democratic los registra pauc accuratemente.On parla frequentemente del fallimentos del processo del mercato economic.A causa de tal appellate «externalitates», le personas qui decide lenatura e extension de varie activitates non debe prender <strong>in</strong> considerationtote le costos e beneficios. On mira al governamento pro remediar talsituationes.Alora, le fallimentos del processo democratic es ancora plus grave.Decisiones facite s<strong>in</strong> adequate comparation de costos e beneficios esancora pejor. <strong>Is</strong>to se explica non solo per le considerationes jam <strong>in</strong>dicatesuper le positiones de <strong>in</strong>dividuos ma anque per certe technicalitates. Plure«paradoxos de votation» es ben cognoscite. On construe exemplos con listasmonstrante le ord<strong>in</strong>es <strong>in</strong> le quales le votantes o gruppos de votantesprefere le politicos o c<strong>and</strong>idatos alternative. Secundo le detalios del processo,on demonstra como un politica o c<strong>and</strong>idato con m<strong>in</strong>us appoio queun alternativa pote nonobstante prevaler. (Per exemplo, suppone que plusde membros del electorato o del legislatura prefere le option A al option Be anque un majoritate prefere option B al option C. Logicamente, per le«transitivitate de preferentias», on pensarea que le option C perde, ma iles ben possibile que illo gania.)Io non ha le tempore pro presentar tal exemplos <strong>in</strong> detalio. Io mentionarasolo alicun phenomenos simile. Uno es le phenomeno de «m<strong>in</strong>oritatesgoverna» (assi appellate per Robert Dahl): ni «le majoritate» ni «lem<strong>in</strong>oritate», ma «m<strong>in</strong>oritates», plural, governa. Typicamente, le majoritate<strong>in</strong> favor de un particular c<strong>and</strong>idato o partito es un coalition de diversem<strong>in</strong>oritates, cata un con su desiros particular. Il pote facilemente evenirque un particular projecto de lege es adoptate contra le desiros de un majoritatedel populo o del legislatores proque su preferentias super iste particularprojecto es relativemente debile e illo forma parte de un pacchettoassemblate per implicite or explicite commercio <strong>in</strong> votos. Post toto, le politicoses <strong>in</strong>terprenditores <strong>in</strong> questa de votos; e illes functiona per assemblar


Chapter : Elementos del Economia Politic 319coalitiones pro servir un multiplicitate de <strong>in</strong>teresses special cuje desiros,anque contra illos del population <strong>in</strong> general, es relativemente <strong>in</strong>tense.<strong>Is</strong>te paradoxo de «m<strong>in</strong>oritates governa» es un aspecto del confusionde questiones o <strong>the</strong>mas <strong>in</strong> le processo politic. Rarmente selige le votantes<strong>in</strong>ter dist<strong>in</strong>cte e clar accostamentos a cata s<strong>in</strong>gule question. Plus tostoilles debe seliger <strong>in</strong>ter pacchettos de positiones mal def<strong>in</strong>ite re un varietatede questiones. In plus, le c<strong>and</strong>idatos e partitos politic evita formular supositiones e pacchettos de positiones <strong>in</strong>necessarimente clarmente proqueilles es anxiose de non alienar le electores qui poterea esser perdite perclar positiones re s<strong>in</strong>gule questiones. Brevemente, le c<strong>and</strong>idatos e partitosha rationes pro confunder le questiones. Il ha un tendentia verso unmal def<strong>in</strong>ite centro del camm<strong>in</strong>o, un position centristic. E proque on evitaclar formulationes <strong>in</strong> le processo politic, le location de iste centro flotta alderiva trans le annos. Illo que se considera realista—politicamente possibileflotta al deriva, e le populo ha pauc opportunitate a determ<strong>in</strong>ar leresultato a longe term<strong>in</strong>o. Partialmente a causa de iste manco de precision, le participantes <strong>in</strong> leprocesso politic non ha <strong>in</strong>centivos pro cercar comparationes accurate delbeneficios e costos de programmas governamental. Le deficits chronic delbudgets governamental <strong>in</strong> le Statos Unite e a ver dicer <strong>in</strong> le plus gr<strong>and</strong>eparte del paises es un gr<strong>and</strong>e exemplo e consequentia de iste manco de<strong>in</strong>centivos appropriate e le fragmentation de responsabilitate.De plus <strong>in</strong> plus on considera le governamento como mechanismo delredistribution, e non solo per un rete de securitate social contra le gr<strong>and</strong>ee nonprevisibile <strong>in</strong>fortunitates del vita. Le litigation—le avide recurso alprocesos al lege—es un note exemplo. Le notion de responsabilitate f<strong>in</strong>anciaripro productos allegate esser defectuose se ha exp<strong>and</strong>ite quasi <strong>in</strong> lenotion que nemo debe suffrer un mal fortuna s<strong>in</strong> que alicun altere pagale expensas, recompensation, e frequentemente anque penalitate. On daattention <strong>in</strong>adequate al effectos super le disposition de facer <strong>in</strong>novationese currer riscos <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terprisas <strong>in</strong>dustrial e commercial.On non considera que le activitate governamental <strong>in</strong> iste varie campospote obstruer alternativas melior. Si le governamento non se habeva<strong>in</strong>miscite, qui sape lo que <strong>in</strong>terprenditores private haberea <strong>in</strong>ventate <strong>in</strong> suloco? On debe rememorar se de lo que Frédéric Bastiat (1801–1850) scribevasuper lo que on vide e lo que on non vide. Si le governamento cessava


320 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophybloccar le via, alternativas melior poterea disveloppar se (ben que, confessemente,con difficultates transitional, que se derivarea del <strong>in</strong>volvimento<strong>in</strong>itial del governamento).Il es ironic que nos nos ha habituate a expectar tanto del governamento,viste le triste historia de su excessive ambitiones. Le chronic deficit governamentalduce a expectar un quasi-repudiation del debito governamentalo quasi-bancarupta del governamento. Io dice «quasi» proque isto eveniranon aperternente ma per le collapso <strong>in</strong>flationari del dollar. Io non dice queisto evenira jam <strong>in</strong>tra pauc annos, ma f<strong>in</strong>almente. E il es <strong>the</strong>oricamentepossibile que le governamento cambia curso a bon tempore.Mi conclusion es: Nos non debe lassar nos dupar per irreflexive laudes deldemocratia. Nos debe guardar le governamento, mesmo governamentodemocratic, con un oculo realistic. Nos debe prestar attention re quanteaspectos del vita <strong>in</strong>cargar al governamento. Re le futuro, il ha mesmo alicunrationes pro sperantia. Un es le comprension del governamento e deleconomia politic que cresce <strong>in</strong> le mundo academic, gratias specialmente allabores del Schola de Selection Public, e que poterea f<strong>in</strong>almente prevaler<strong>in</strong> le gr<strong>and</strong>e publico. Mesmo le pubtico ord<strong>in</strong>ari comencia devenir sageal trucos del governamento, que, como dice Harry Brown, c<strong>and</strong>idato prole nom<strong>in</strong>ation presidential del Partito Libertari <strong>in</strong> le Statos Unite, perdespatio pro manovrar.


<strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias TowardOverregulation? * “ ” Often it is appropriate to consider <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> government regulation<strong>in</strong>dustry by <strong>in</strong>dustry or problem by problem, focus<strong>in</strong>g on specific facts.Heaven knows <strong>the</strong>re has been enough <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> opposite: adopt<strong>in</strong>g regulationsligh<strong>the</strong>artedly, as if good <strong>in</strong>tentions were justification enough. On<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, sometimes it is appropriate to step back from a narrowlyfactual focus <strong>and</strong> consider a broader question. Preoccupation with <strong>the</strong>immediate <strong>and</strong> specific is part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem with government action. A broader view suggests that our political system harbors a bias towardoveractivity. Regulation is just one <strong>of</strong> several th<strong>in</strong>gs that government doesprobably too much <strong>of</strong>. Such a bias, if it does exist, argues for seek<strong>in</strong>g—orrestor<strong>in</strong>g—constitutional restra<strong>in</strong>ts on regulatory activity <strong>and</strong> for not lett<strong>in</strong>geach particular issue be decided on its own narrow apparent merits.Despite <strong>the</strong> scorn <strong>of</strong> hard-nosed positivists, human rights belong <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>discussion.Strictly speak<strong>in</strong>g, perhaps, what argues for restra<strong>in</strong>t is not an <strong>in</strong>contestablebias toward too much regulation but a structure <strong>of</strong> government*From Rights <strong>and</strong> Regulation, eds. Tibor R. Machan <strong>and</strong> M. Bruce Johnson (San Francisco<strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass.: Pacific Institute for Public Policy Research <strong>and</strong> Ball<strong>in</strong>ger,1983), 99–126. As F.A. Hayek notes, “we are not fully free to pick <strong>and</strong> choose whatever comb<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>of</strong> features we wish our society to possess, or to ... build a desirable social order likea mosaic by select<strong>in</strong>g whatever particular parts we like best.” Yet this idea “seems to be<strong>in</strong>tolerable to modern man.” e suggestion draws scorn that unwanted developments maynecessarily stem from earlier decisions. “I am myself now old enough,” Hayek cont<strong>in</strong>ued,“to have been told more than once by my elders that certa<strong>in</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir policywhich I foresaw would never occur, <strong>and</strong> later, when <strong>the</strong>y did appear, to have been told byyounger men that <strong>the</strong>se had been <strong>in</strong>evitable <strong>and</strong> quite <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>of</strong> what <strong>in</strong> fact wasdone” (1973, pp. 59–60).321


322 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophydecisionmak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> which prospective costs <strong>and</strong> benefits escape accurateconfrontation. e result may be too much regulation <strong>in</strong> some directions<strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> some sense, too little <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. Errors <strong>of</strong> omission do not cancelout errors <strong>of</strong> hyperactivity, though, <strong>and</strong> a case for restra<strong>in</strong>t rema<strong>in</strong>s.What might <strong>the</strong> ideal amount <strong>of</strong> government mean? Even withoutbe<strong>in</strong>g able to say (<strong>and</strong> without fac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> anarchists’ challenge to any governmentat all), one can still recognize aspects <strong>of</strong> decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g processesthat tilt <strong>the</strong> outcome toward too much government. Some utterly familiarfacts suggest this conclusion. Admittedly, I may have overlooked somepowerful <strong>and</strong> even overrid<strong>in</strong>g biases work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> opposite direction. Asa contribution to discussion, though, I report <strong>the</strong> biases I see <strong>and</strong> challenge<strong>the</strong> reader to expla<strong>in</strong> any opposite ones that might override <strong>the</strong>m. Almost everyone who plays a part <strong>in</strong> governmental decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g, from<strong>the</strong> average citizen on up, has a fragmentary view. No one has, or has reasonto seek, a full view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prospective costs <strong>and</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> a contemplatedactivity. ( Just one k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> relatively specific <strong>and</strong> obvious exampleconcerns federal shar<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> many state <strong>and</strong> local projects, with<strong>the</strong> result that <strong>the</strong> local authorities are decid<strong>in</strong>g on expenditure <strong>of</strong> what,from <strong>the</strong>ir po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> view, are “ten-cent dollars” or “fifty-cent dollars.”)Noth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> government corresponds to <strong>the</strong> market process <strong>of</strong> spontaneouscoord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> decentralized decisions; noth<strong>in</strong>g corresponds to its way <strong>of</strong>br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g even remote considerations to <strong>the</strong> attention <strong>of</strong> each decentralizeddecisionmaker <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> prices. Knowledge, authority, <strong>in</strong>centives,<strong>and</strong> responsibility are largely fragmented <strong>and</strong> uncoord<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> political<strong>and</strong> governmental process. Far-reach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> long-run consequences<strong>of</strong> decisions receive skimpy attention.One aspect <strong>of</strong> this fragmentation, noted by Samuel Brittan, is that“<strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> a political decision is borne by people o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> voter. Acustomer buy<strong>in</strong>g a suit or a wash<strong>in</strong>g mach<strong>in</strong>e has to bear <strong>the</strong> cost himself.”Someone vot<strong>in</strong>g for a c<strong>and</strong>idate who makes some attractive promise, however,usually—<strong>and</strong> realistically—assumes “that o<strong>the</strong>rs will bear <strong>the</strong> cost”(Brittan 1978, pp. 165–166). Obviously, I have <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d Hayek 1945.Of course, externalities, transactions costs, <strong>and</strong> all that keep <strong>the</strong> price system from operat<strong>in</strong>gwith all imag<strong>in</strong>able perfection. But what is a fr<strong>in</strong>ge “imperfection” <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> marketeconomy is a central characteristic <strong>of</strong> governmental decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 323Any number <strong>of</strong> government activities might each seem desirable byitself <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs, but it does not necessarily followthat <strong>the</strong> whole agglomeration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m is also desirable. To supposeso would be to commit <strong>the</strong> fallacy <strong>of</strong> composition, <strong>of</strong> suppos<strong>in</strong>g that anyth<strong>in</strong>gtrue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> part or <strong>in</strong>dividual must also be true <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole or group.Add<strong>in</strong>g any particular government function to all <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs complicates<strong>the</strong> tasks <strong>of</strong> choos<strong>in</strong>g, operat<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> supervis<strong>in</strong>g those o<strong>the</strong>rs. e morefunctions <strong>the</strong> government takes on <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> more complicated <strong>the</strong>y are,<strong>the</strong> more <strong>the</strong>y must be left to <strong>the</strong> “experts”; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> people’s elected representatives,let alone <strong>the</strong> people <strong>the</strong>mselves, are less able to exercise close<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formed control. e elected representatives, who supposedly shouldmonitor <strong>the</strong> experts, must largely depend on <strong>the</strong>m for <strong>in</strong>formation; <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> experts have <strong>the</strong>ir own special views about <strong>the</strong>ir work.Particular government programs, <strong>and</strong> especially agglomerations <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>m, have remote, unforeseen consequences. e current <strong>in</strong>flation is oneexample. Burgeon<strong>in</strong>g programs—<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g, ironically, ones <strong>in</strong>tended tohelp make <strong>the</strong> citizens economically secure—have led to federal deficits,government borrow<strong>in</strong>g, upward pressures on <strong>in</strong>terest rates, FederalReserve actions to restra<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir rise, consequent excessive expansion <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> monetary base <strong>and</strong> money supply, price <strong>in</strong>flation, fur<strong>the</strong>r allowancefor <strong>in</strong>flation <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rates, fur<strong>the</strong>r short-run efforts to restra<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>irrise by monetary expansion, establishment <strong>of</strong> a momentum <strong>in</strong> prices <strong>and</strong>wages such that an anti<strong>in</strong>flationary turn <strong>in</strong> monetary policy would notbr<strong>in</strong>g quick success but would br<strong>in</strong>g a recession, monetary accommodation<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ris<strong>in</strong>g wages <strong>and</strong> prices, <strong>and</strong> so on. e result is all <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>securitythat <strong>in</strong>flation br<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong> disruption <strong>of</strong> economic calculation. A stillmore pervasive example—so one might argue—is that <strong>the</strong> accumulation<strong>of</strong> government activities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir repercussions br<strong>in</strong>gs a drift <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> wholecharacter <strong>of</strong> our social, political, <strong>and</strong> economic system; yet that drift wasnever squarely faced <strong>and</strong> decided on as a political issue. “” Overregulation stems from a “basic flaw” <strong>in</strong> our political system closelyrelated to <strong>the</strong> flaw noted <strong>in</strong> current arguments for a constitutional limitto government tax<strong>in</strong>g or spend<strong>in</strong>g. Because <strong>of</strong> its close relation to <strong>the</strong> See, <strong>in</strong> part, Friedman 1962, p. 32. In <strong>the</strong> technical jargon, government activities haveexternal diseconomies. One presentation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> diagnosis appears <strong>in</strong> Rickenbacker <strong>and</strong> Uhler 1977, chap. 1.


324 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophypresent topic, <strong>the</strong> central argument is worth review<strong>in</strong>g. e alternativeto such a limit—lett<strong>in</strong>g total spend<strong>in</strong>g emerge as <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuallyenacted appropriations—is biased upward. Some people are especially<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> government spend<strong>in</strong>g on rivers <strong>and</strong> harbors <strong>and</strong> military<strong>in</strong>stallations, o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>in</strong> spend<strong>in</strong>g for schools <strong>and</strong> teachers, o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>in</strong> hous<strong>in</strong>gsubsidies, <strong>and</strong> still o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>in</strong> energy-research contracts. Because <strong>of</strong> itsspecial <strong>in</strong>terest, each group is well <strong>in</strong>formed about <strong>the</strong> government actionit wants <strong>and</strong> has arguments for it readily at h<strong>and</strong>. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>benefits <strong>of</strong> its favorite program will be relatively concentrated on itselfra<strong>the</strong>r than diluted over <strong>the</strong> entire population, its members have <strong>in</strong>centivesto <strong>in</strong>cur <strong>the</strong> trouble <strong>and</strong> expense <strong>of</strong> press<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> group’s views on <strong>the</strong>legislators. A c<strong>and</strong>idate or legislator, for his part, knows that each special<strong>in</strong>terest cares <strong>in</strong>tensely about what concerns it <strong>and</strong> fears that los<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>support <strong>of</strong> only a few such <strong>in</strong>terests could cost him election or reelection;so he tends to be responsive. e l<strong>in</strong>ks between particular government expenditures <strong>and</strong> particulartax collections are loose. No one really knows who will ultimately pay for agovernment program. e voter can drift <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that someone else,perhaps “<strong>the</strong> rich” or <strong>the</strong> big corporations, will pay or ought to pay. (Noteven economists know who ultimately pays <strong>the</strong> corporate <strong>in</strong>come tax.) It iseasy to drift <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> government gets resources out <strong>of</strong> somesort <strong>of</strong> fourth dimension. Politicians will not hasten to disabuse voters <strong>of</strong>this “fiscal illusion.” Nowadays, with taxes <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>flation be<strong>in</strong>g what <strong>the</strong>yare, this illusion is evaporat<strong>in</strong>g; but <strong>the</strong> very fact that <strong>the</strong> present state <strong>of</strong>affairs could develop suggests that some such illusion has been at workuntil recently.An art-lov<strong>in</strong>g journalist has unwitt<strong>in</strong>gly illustrated <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> attitudethat exp<strong>and</strong>s government activity—<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby also illustrated <strong>the</strong> logic<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> limit he was compla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st (Sansweet 1978, p. 11). State<strong>and</strong> local government actions taken after passage <strong>of</strong> Proposition 13 <strong>in</strong> Californiareveal, he compla<strong>in</strong>ed, that many <strong>of</strong>ficials see <strong>the</strong> arts as an expendableelitist pursuit. e recent tremendous growth <strong>in</strong> public fund<strong>in</strong>g for<strong>the</strong> arts had suddenly been thrown <strong>in</strong>to reverse. A 60 percent slash <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>budget <strong>of</strong> a state agency mak<strong>in</strong>g grants to art programs <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualartists had lowered California to 44th place among all states <strong>in</strong> per capitafund<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> arts. Yet, he cont<strong>in</strong>ued, <strong>the</strong> arts pay <strong>the</strong> wages <strong>of</strong> hundreds See “S<strong>in</strong>gle-<strong>Is</strong>sue Politics,” <strong>in</strong> Newsweek 1978, pp. 48–60, <strong>and</strong>, on congressmen’s feel<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>security, see Mann 1978.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 325<strong>of</strong> thous<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> people, directly <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>directly. How many restaurantsnear <strong>the</strong> Music Center <strong>in</strong> downtown Los Angeles would rema<strong>in</strong> openwithout <strong>the</strong> audiences that <strong>the</strong> Center draws? e arts <strong>of</strong>fer pleasure <strong>and</strong>enterta<strong>in</strong>ment <strong>and</strong> stimulation. State <strong>and</strong> local governments have madetoo much <strong>of</strong> a commitment to <strong>the</strong>m to back out now without seriouslyretard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir progress. “A society that considers it a frill to nourish itssoul is <strong>in</strong> deep trouble.” In reply, a reader asked: “What k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> troublecan be expected by a society that depends on government to nourishits soul?” (Beaver 1978, p. 12). e journalist tacitly accepts <strong>the</strong> notionthat not to f<strong>in</strong>ance particular activities by taxes—by compulsion—is tobe neglectful <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. Also noteworthy is his misuse, regard<strong>in</strong>g downtownLos Angeles, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> overworked <strong>the</strong>oretical argument about externalities—here,spillover benefits.Much <strong>the</strong> same po<strong>in</strong>ts that apply to spend<strong>in</strong>g apply also to regulation.Some economic <strong>in</strong>terest groups benefit from regulation (perhaps it protects<strong>the</strong>m aga<strong>in</strong>st competition) <strong>and</strong> automatically have <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives to press c<strong>and</strong>idates <strong>and</strong> legislators for what <strong>the</strong>y want. elatter, for <strong>the</strong>ir part, are rationally more responsive to special-<strong>in</strong>terest pressuresthan to <strong>the</strong> general <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> average voters, who are rationallyignorant <strong>and</strong> apa<strong>the</strong>tic about <strong>the</strong> details <strong>of</strong> public policy. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,citizens who identify <strong>the</strong>mselves with some cause—protect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> environment,crack<strong>in</strong>g down on health <strong>and</strong> safety hazards, develop<strong>in</strong>g exoticenergy sources, foster<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> arts, remedy<strong>in</strong>g supposedly unjust <strong>in</strong>equalities,suppress<strong>in</strong>g (or facilitat<strong>in</strong>g) abortion, improv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g habits<strong>of</strong> school children, or whatever—take on <strong>the</strong> political characters <strong>of</strong> special<strong>in</strong>terests <strong>and</strong>, like <strong>the</strong>m, tend to have disproportionate <strong>in</strong>fluence withpoliticians or <strong>the</strong> relevant bureaucrats. e much discussed “new class”<strong>of</strong> activist <strong>in</strong>tellectuals <strong>and</strong> publicists belongs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> story. Legislators,bureaucrats, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> government <strong>the</strong>mselves have personalstakes <strong>in</strong> government activism, though many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m are no doubts<strong>in</strong>cerely motivated to do good as <strong>the</strong>y conceive <strong>of</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g good <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>irown special niches <strong>in</strong> life. None <strong>of</strong> this amounts to cast<strong>in</strong>g aspersions on <strong>the</strong> moral characters <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> people who take part <strong>in</strong> decid<strong>in</strong>g on government activities. I am simplydraw<strong>in</strong>g implications from <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>se people decide <strong>and</strong> act


326 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophywith<strong>in</strong> particular frameworks <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation, <strong>in</strong>centives, tests <strong>of</strong> performance,<strong>and</strong> rewards. Economists, long successful with methodological<strong>in</strong>dividualism <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own field, are now apply<strong>in</strong>g that approach to underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>ghow people behave <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> governmental framework. We, <strong>the</strong> analysts,project ourselves <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>essman, consumer, bureaucrat,legislator, political c<strong>and</strong>idate, or whoever it is whose decisions <strong>and</strong> actionswe are try<strong>in</strong>g to underst<strong>and</strong>. We consider his motivations <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives,perhaps even <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> circumstances affect<strong>in</strong>g his self-esteem, as wellas <strong>the</strong> opportunities <strong>and</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>ts he faces. We can draw relevant <strong>in</strong>formationfrom our own personal thoughts, actions, <strong>and</strong> experiences. Suchan approach does not depend on <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>undities <strong>of</strong> psychology. It draws<strong>in</strong>ferences from familiar facts about human nature <strong>and</strong> about decisionmak<strong>in</strong>gsituations. e “average voter” is <strong>the</strong> voter considered at r<strong>and</strong>om, o<strong>the</strong>rwise than asa member <strong>of</strong> any special <strong>in</strong>terest group. (To take account <strong>of</strong> nonvot<strong>in</strong>g,perhaps <strong>the</strong> term should be “average citizen.”) He does not automaticallypossess <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation needed to weigh <strong>the</strong> pros <strong>and</strong> cons <strong>of</strong> more or lessspend<strong>in</strong>g on each special group’s favorite project. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gsuch <strong>in</strong>formation would cost him money, time, <strong>and</strong> trouble better devotedto o<strong>the</strong>r purposes. He pr<strong>of</strong>its more from a day spent learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> strong<strong>and</strong> weak po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> different makes <strong>of</strong> car or refrigerator, when he wantsto buy a new one, than from a day spent try<strong>in</strong>g to learn <strong>the</strong> advantages<strong>and</strong> disadvantages <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>creased government spend<strong>in</strong>g on aircraft carriersor urban renewal.Acquir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong>formation about public issues has a lowpay<strong>of</strong>f because it is a “public good.” e st<strong>and</strong>ard rationale for hav<strong>in</strong>g anygovernment at all is that it is necessary to provide public goods, such asnational defense, police protection, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> legal system. eir benefitscannot be conf<strong>in</strong>ed to people who voluntarily contribute money or effortfor <strong>the</strong>m. Each person might as well sit back <strong>and</strong> enjoy a free ride on Kenneth N. Waltz makes an analogous po<strong>in</strong>t, which illum<strong>in</strong>ates this one, <strong>in</strong> hiseory <strong>of</strong> International Politics (1979). Almost regardless <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal character <strong>of</strong> itsregime, we can say much about how a country behaves <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> arena <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational politics<strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> situation confront<strong>in</strong>g it—<strong>in</strong> particular, accord<strong>in</strong>g to whe<strong>the</strong>r or not it is adom<strong>in</strong>ant power <strong>and</strong>, if it is, whe<strong>the</strong>r it is one <strong>of</strong> several or one <strong>of</strong> only two dom<strong>in</strong>antpowers.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 327<strong>the</strong> expenditures or efforts <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. So government sells public goodscompulsorily, for taxes. But no such solution, imperfect as it may be, hasbeen found for <strong>the</strong> public good <strong>of</strong> monitor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> government itself. Ifan average voter should go to <strong>the</strong> trouble <strong>of</strong> keep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formed <strong>and</strong> politicallyactive, most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> benefits, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> sounder policy, wouldaccrue to o<strong>the</strong>rs. While reap<strong>in</strong>g only a very m<strong>in</strong>or share <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se benefits,he would have to bear all <strong>of</strong> his own costs. He has about as little reasonto <strong>in</strong>cur <strong>the</strong>m as he would have to stop driv<strong>in</strong>g his car to hold downair pollution. He has little <strong>in</strong>centive to work for what is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> general<strong>in</strong>terest. Exhort<strong>in</strong>g citizens to study <strong>the</strong> issues <strong>and</strong> take an active role <strong>in</strong> politicslargely ignores <strong>the</strong>se facts. It tacitly regards concern with governmentalaffairs as a noble activity hold<strong>in</strong>g a special claim on each citizen’s attention.Actually, badger<strong>in</strong>g him to divert his money, time, <strong>and</strong> energy from workor recreation to political studies that perplex or bore him will contributelittle to wise policymak<strong>in</strong>g. It is an imposition, too, if hold<strong>in</strong>g down <strong>the</strong>range <strong>of</strong> government decisions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place could have held down<strong>the</strong>se dem<strong>and</strong>s on his attention.Even if, implausibly, <strong>the</strong> voter should become well <strong>in</strong>formed <strong>and</strong> voteaccord<strong>in</strong>gly, he cannot express himself on each program separately. If he isvot<strong>in</strong>g on issues at all when choos<strong>in</strong>g between c<strong>and</strong>idates, he is vot<strong>in</strong>g onpolicy positions all jumbled toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> vaguely specified packages, alongwith <strong>the</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idates’ actual or advertised personalities. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, hisown monitor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> government through <strong>in</strong>formed vot<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>and</strong> lobby<strong>in</strong>g)would do little good unless o<strong>the</strong>r voters jo<strong>in</strong>ed him. He is onlyone out <strong>of</strong> many, <strong>and</strong> his own <strong>in</strong>formed vote would hardly be decisivefor <strong>the</strong> outcome <strong>of</strong> an election or for <strong>the</strong> decision on some program. Itis rational for him to content himself with superficial notions about electionissues, vot<strong>in</strong>g for a party label out <strong>of</strong> habit or for a well-packaged e concept <strong>of</strong> monitor<strong>in</strong>g as a public good is due, I believe, to Rol<strong>and</strong> McKean. e weakness <strong>of</strong> personal <strong>in</strong>centives to seek collective ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>in</strong>dividual benefitsis a lead<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>me <strong>of</strong> Mancur Olson, Jr., e Logic <strong>of</strong> Collective Action (1965). e freeridemotivation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> average voter also characterizes <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual member <strong>of</strong> a special<strong>in</strong>terest group. It operates, though, to a lesser degree. e group member belongsto a smaller group with a more <strong>in</strong>tense <strong>and</strong> concentrated <strong>in</strong>terest than <strong>the</strong> averagevoter does; his own <strong>in</strong>terest is less diluted by be<strong>in</strong>g shared with o<strong>the</strong>rs. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, asOlson notes, an organized <strong>in</strong>terest group may be able to comm<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> support <strong>of</strong> itsmembers by supply<strong>in</strong>g services <strong>of</strong> value to <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>dividually, such as bus<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>in</strong>formation<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r trade-association services, <strong>in</strong> addition to its collectively desired lobby<strong>in</strong>gfunction.


328 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophypersonality out <strong>of</strong> whim. His position is different from that <strong>of</strong> peoplewho would reap concentrated benefits from particular programs <strong>and</strong> havegood prospects <strong>of</strong> promot<strong>in</strong>g government activism <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir favor. Average<strong>and</strong> special-<strong>in</strong>terest voters alike, though, enjoy an apparent freedom frompersonal responsibility <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> vot<strong>in</strong>g booth; each is act<strong>in</strong>g anonymouslyalong with many o<strong>the</strong>rs.It is doubtful that bus<strong>in</strong>essmen, as such, have any strong <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong>work<strong>in</strong>g to limit government <strong>in</strong>tervention. Just because <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> keyactors <strong>in</strong> a free-market economy, it does not follow that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualbus<strong>in</strong>essman f<strong>in</strong>ds it <strong>in</strong> his self-<strong>in</strong>terest to work to preserve such an economy.Bus<strong>in</strong>essmen can cope with regulation. Its burdens may not be muchworse than those <strong>of</strong> competition, which, anyway, some k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> regulationrestra<strong>in</strong>. e prospects for bus<strong>in</strong>essmen <strong>of</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary ability relativeto <strong>the</strong> prospects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most dynamic entrepreneurs may even be better<strong>in</strong> a highly regulated economy than under substantial laissez faire; enjoy<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> quiet life may be easier. Hence <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>tlessness <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>essmenexhort<strong>in</strong>g each o<strong>the</strong>r to do a better job <strong>of</strong> communicat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir case to <strong>the</strong>public. Bus<strong>in</strong>essmen as such, ra<strong>the</strong>r than simply as human be<strong>in</strong>gs, are not<strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> beneficiaries <strong>of</strong> a free economy.With little personal <strong>in</strong>centive really to underst<strong>and</strong> public affairs, <strong>the</strong>average voter tends to work with ideas that are <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> air. e attitude doesseem to prevail widely <strong>the</strong>se days that if anyth<strong>in</strong>g is bad—pornography, orsmall children’s eat<strong>in</strong>g medic<strong>in</strong>e that <strong>the</strong>y shouldn’t have, or junk food <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> schools—<strong>the</strong>n it is <strong>the</strong> government’s job to suppress it. Similarly, ifanyth<strong>in</strong>g is good—hous<strong>in</strong>g, arts, effective drugs, good nutrition—<strong>the</strong>ngovernment ought to promote or subsidize it. is attitude parallels <strong>the</strong>doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> altruism, which receives wide lip service, <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e that oneought to be primarily concerned with <strong>the</strong> (supposed) <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rpeople. It is wickedly selfish, <strong>the</strong>n, to oppose a program for do<strong>in</strong>g good,even if it does cost tax money. (Government programs <strong>in</strong> one’s own special<strong>in</strong>terest can readily be rationalized <strong>in</strong> altruistic terms, as good for o<strong>the</strong>rpeople also. It is a rout<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong>oretical exercise for economists to concoct“externality” arguments for government <strong>in</strong>terventions.) e altruist doctr<strong>in</strong>emeshes well with <strong>the</strong> idea that it is slightly <strong>in</strong>decent to be a rightist<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> presumption that <strong>the</strong> decent <strong>and</strong> humane position on any issue isat least a little left <strong>of</strong> center (Ellul 1968, pp. 215–219). “Rational ignorance” is a lead<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>me <strong>of</strong> Anthony Downs, An Economic eory <strong>of</strong>Democracy (1957).


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 329e psychological roots <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terventionism <strong>in</strong>clude people’s tendencyto believe what <strong>the</strong>y want to believe <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> read<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> politicians toexploit this tendency. In political argumentation, plausibility counts. Mereslogans <strong>and</strong> name-call<strong>in</strong>g sometimes work. e acceptance <strong>of</strong> merely plausiblearguments is aided by a trait <strong>of</strong> contemporary thought roughly equivalentto what F.A. Hayek has called “scientism.” Just as Chanticleerthought his crow<strong>in</strong>g made <strong>the</strong> sun rise, so voters <strong>and</strong> politicians seem toth<strong>in</strong>k that <strong>the</strong>ir laws are what make good th<strong>in</strong>gs happen. People are unaccustomedto conceiv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> how good results will occur unless <strong>the</strong>y areexplicitly sought; <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>visible h<strong>and</strong> is not universally appreciated. Whena problem has become politically fashionable, to suggest leav<strong>in</strong>g its solutionto private <strong>in</strong>itiative seems callous. Action is considered “positive”<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore good, while opposition is “negative” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore bad.Support for activism <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>es with <strong>the</strong> idea that democracy is agood th<strong>in</strong>g. at idea slides <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> belief that do<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs democratically,that is, through democratic government, that is, through government,is a good th<strong>in</strong>g.Ano<strong>the</strong>r reason for <strong>the</strong> widespread appeal <strong>of</strong> government <strong>in</strong>terventionis disregard <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>completeness <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation,transactions, <strong>and</strong> decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> public sector while emphasiz<strong>in</strong>gsuch “imperfections” <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> private sector. Tacitly, <strong>the</strong> governmentis regarded as a philosopher-k<strong>in</strong>g, totally benevolent, omniscient, efficient,<strong>and</strong> effective. H<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g over a problem to such an entity seems like solv<strong>in</strong>git. So far we have been consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> average voter, his circumstances <strong>and</strong>attitudes, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> appeals directed toward him. Next we turn to special<strong>in</strong>terests <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n to “hobbyists.” Politicians are tempted to appease each Here I am fall<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to temptation—<strong>in</strong>to amateur psychologiz<strong>in</strong>g—<strong>and</strong> what followsshould perhaps be discounted. His articles on “Scientism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Study <strong>of</strong> Society” are repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> e Counter-Revolution <strong>of</strong> Science (Hayek 1952, Pt. 1). See below <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> section on “crowd<strong>in</strong>g out.” George Stigler quotes a pair <strong>of</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r typical passages on <strong>the</strong> defects <strong>of</strong> a privatemarket economy that could readily be overcome by “a socialist economy” (Oskar Lange)or by “<strong>the</strong> State” (A.C. Pigou). en he substitutes “Almighty Jehovah” <strong>and</strong> “his SereneOmnipotence” for <strong>the</strong> words here <strong>in</strong> quotation marks—with amus<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> tell<strong>in</strong>g effect.See Stigler 1975, pp. 112–113. e assumption illustrated is now be<strong>in</strong>g underm<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong>application <strong>of</strong> methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism to <strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> government.


330 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyclamor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terest by help<strong>in</strong>g it get what it wants <strong>and</strong> to compensate <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>rs by do<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> same for <strong>the</strong>m. Under <strong>the</strong>se circumstances, logroll<strong>in</strong>g(explicit <strong>in</strong> legislatures <strong>and</strong> implicit <strong>in</strong> political platforms) assembles majoritiesout <strong>of</strong> essentially unrelated m<strong>in</strong>orities. “M<strong>in</strong>orities rule” (Dahl 1963,pp. 125–130)—not <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ority, but an implicit coalition <strong>of</strong> several m<strong>in</strong>orities.Suppose that for each <strong>of</strong> three programs, 25 percent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> votersfavor it so <strong>in</strong>tensely that <strong>the</strong>y would vote for whichever c<strong>and</strong>idate supportsit, regardless <strong>of</strong> his position on o<strong>the</strong>r issues. Seventy-five percent <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> voters oppose each program, but only mildly. Suppose, fur<strong>the</strong>r, that<strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ority favor<strong>in</strong>g each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> three programs is a dist<strong>in</strong>ct group. (Torecognize that two or three <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> groups have some members <strong>in</strong> commonwould complicate <strong>the</strong> example without affect<strong>in</strong>g its po<strong>in</strong>t.) A c<strong>and</strong>idatesupport<strong>in</strong>g all three programs would be elected overwhelm<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>and</strong> beput <strong>in</strong> a position to work for <strong>the</strong>ir enactment, even though 75 percent <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> electorate opposed each program. e same sort <strong>of</strong> implicit logroll<strong>in</strong>goperates, though less clearly than <strong>in</strong> this example, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> governmentbudgets. As <strong>the</strong> example suggests, by <strong>the</strong> way, <strong>the</strong> political processaffords scope for political entrepreneurship <strong>and</strong> not just for passiveresponse to exist<strong>in</strong>g dem<strong>and</strong>s.Particularly as <strong>the</strong> vote-trad<strong>in</strong>g process spreads out over time <strong>and</strong> overnumerous separate ballots, spurious consensus becomes possible. Policycomb<strong>in</strong>ations get adopted that could not have comm<strong>and</strong>ed a majority ifconsidered as a whole. e procedure <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g decisions year by yearleads to commitments to <strong>the</strong> future growth <strong>of</strong> spend<strong>in</strong>g that are not seenor not appreciated when made, yet are hard to reverse later. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,<strong>the</strong> automatic growth <strong>of</strong> revenue as <strong>the</strong> economy grows <strong>and</strong> as <strong>in</strong>flationproceeds, push<strong>in</strong>g taxpayers <strong>in</strong>to higher brackets, allows <strong>the</strong> governmentto avoid an explicit decision to raise taxes to cover <strong>in</strong>creased spend<strong>in</strong>g(Ste<strong>in</strong> 1978, p. 20).e politics <strong>of</strong> abortion illustrates <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensely concernedm<strong>in</strong>orities. e California <strong>and</strong> Massachusetts legislatures were so embroiled<strong>in</strong> controversy over public fund<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> abortions <strong>in</strong> July 1978 that<strong>the</strong>y failed to f<strong>in</strong>ish <strong>the</strong>ir budget work <strong>in</strong> time for <strong>the</strong> new fiscal year. As<strong>in</strong>gle issue fought over <strong>in</strong>tensely by small but well-organized groups c<strong>and</strong>istract politicians’ attention from matters <strong>of</strong> broad but unfocused publicconcern. Similarly, a vast majority may grumble about high taxes, butits concern is so diffuse (or has been, until recently) that it can seldom “M<strong>in</strong>orities Rule” is <strong>the</strong> title <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> repr<strong>in</strong>ted version <strong>of</strong> Dahl 1963, pp. 124–134, <strong>in</strong>Fe<strong>in</strong> 1964, pp. 125–130.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 331counterbalance powerful m<strong>in</strong>ority pressures work<strong>in</strong>g for specific spend<strong>in</strong>gprograms (Wall Street Journal 1978, p. 20).Activists on all sides <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> abortion issue are examples <strong>of</strong> what I call“hobbyists,” who engage <strong>in</strong> political study <strong>and</strong> activity not so much forobvious material ga<strong>in</strong> as because <strong>the</strong>y have identified <strong>the</strong>mselves withsome mission or are seek<strong>in</strong>g an outlet for <strong>the</strong>ir energies or a sense <strong>of</strong> participation<strong>in</strong> admirable causes. Hobbyists <strong>in</strong>clude people who want a federalcrash program to cure a disease that killed a relative, or who have lost achild <strong>in</strong> a boat<strong>in</strong>g accident <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore seek federal regulation, or wantsubsidies for art or music, or want preservation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unspoiled wilderness.People act<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> dis<strong>in</strong>terested public spirit count among <strong>the</strong> hobbyists;<strong>the</strong> term is not meant disparag<strong>in</strong>gly. Stretched a bit, <strong>the</strong> term also covers“consumer advocates,” who, for <strong>the</strong> publicity <strong>the</strong>y thrive on, require “a constantsupply <strong>of</strong> new charges aga<strong>in</strong>st new villa<strong>in</strong>s ... suitably pr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>hot <strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> outrage” (Stigler 1975, p. 188).By <strong>the</strong> very nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir “hobbies,” just as by <strong>the</strong> very nature <strong>of</strong> specialeconomic <strong>in</strong>terests, most hobbyists are press<strong>in</strong>g for more governmentactivity. A belief <strong>in</strong> laissez faire or limited government is itself a hobby forsome people, to be sure; but it is just one among a great many hobbies, most<strong>of</strong> which do tend toward <strong>in</strong>terventionism. It is no real embarrassment forthis argument that some <strong>in</strong>tellectuals do take an anti<strong>in</strong>terventionist st<strong>and</strong>.Of course some are libertarians, but psychological factors <strong>and</strong> aspects <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> democratic process make it difficult for <strong>the</strong>ir view to prevail <strong>in</strong> practice.Hobbyists are charmed at hav<strong>in</strong>g one central focus, Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, for<strong>the</strong>ir persuasive efforts <strong>and</strong> charmed by <strong>the</strong> prospect <strong>of</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> force<strong>of</strong> government to impose what <strong>the</strong>y want. Success seems easier along thatroute than along <strong>the</strong> route <strong>of</strong> persuad<strong>in</strong>g myriads <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals voluntarilyto observe, for example, stricter st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>of</strong> boat<strong>in</strong>g safety. Hobbyistsseek<strong>in</strong>g enterta<strong>in</strong>ment or a sense <strong>of</strong> participation are <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to want tobe <strong>in</strong> fashion. If altruist <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terventionist doctr<strong>in</strong>es prevail, <strong>the</strong>y will goalong. e politician, to thrive <strong>in</strong> his career, must recognize <strong>the</strong> voters as <strong>the</strong>yare—<strong>the</strong> average voters with <strong>the</strong>ir susceptibilities, <strong>the</strong> special <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>and</strong>


332 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyhobbyists with <strong>the</strong>ir particular concerns. Like most people, he wants toth<strong>in</strong>k well <strong>of</strong> himself; he wants to th<strong>in</strong>k he is accomplish<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g.His particular mission <strong>in</strong> life is to perceive problems <strong>and</strong> get governmentprograms enacted to solve <strong>the</strong>m. Even when out <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>fice, <strong>the</strong> politici<strong>and</strong>oes not typically strive to limit <strong>the</strong> scope for do<strong>in</strong>g good <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficehe hopes to w<strong>in</strong> at <strong>the</strong> next election. In <strong>of</strong>fice, he wants to carry forthhis uncompleted programs <strong>and</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>ue serv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> public better than hisopponents could do.Publicity is helpful <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> quest for votes. (So is hav<strong>in</strong>g patronage withwhich to reward supporters, <strong>and</strong> to which government expansion contributes.)One way to ga<strong>in</strong> favorable publicity is to become identified withone or more problems <strong>and</strong> with proposals for <strong>the</strong>ir solution—pollution,unemployment, <strong>the</strong> urban crisis, <strong>the</strong> energy crisis, <strong>the</strong> expenses <strong>of</strong> medicalcare, poverty, <strong>in</strong>equality, or whatever. It may even count as a solutionthat <strong>the</strong> proposed legislation merely creates a new agency assigned to dealwith <strong>the</strong> problem. One reason for delegat<strong>in</strong>g work to regulatory agenciesis that <strong>the</strong> legislature has too much to do to consider problems <strong>and</strong> solutions<strong>in</strong> detail; legislat<strong>in</strong>g, along with <strong>the</strong> barga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g necessary for it, isa high-cost activity with steeply ris<strong>in</strong>g marg<strong>in</strong>al costs (Posner 1974). Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,<strong>the</strong> vagueness <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> h<strong>and</strong>l<strong>in</strong>g a problem by turn<strong>in</strong>g it overto a new agency can itself be helpful <strong>in</strong> lull<strong>in</strong>g possible opposition, just asvagueness <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> word<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a proposed <strong>in</strong>ternational agreement may behelpful <strong>in</strong> gett<strong>in</strong>g all parties to accept it.e <strong>in</strong>dividual advocate <strong>of</strong> one particular bit <strong>of</strong> government expansionhas little personal <strong>in</strong>centive to consider <strong>the</strong> external diseconomies thatmay result <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> enhanced role <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>adequately supervisedexperts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> worsened difficulties <strong>of</strong> monitor<strong>in</strong>g government. Nei<strong>the</strong>rhe nor <strong>the</strong> voters will recognize any responsibility <strong>of</strong> his for such longrunconsequences. Later on, after such pseudosolutions have enhanced<strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> adm<strong>in</strong>istrators, reduced <strong>the</strong> relative power <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> people <strong>and</strong> “[T]he people’s representatives seem to be enchanted with <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong>y arenot do<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir job unless <strong>the</strong>y are manufactur<strong>in</strong>g laws” (McClellan 1974, p. 66). See Benjam<strong>in</strong> Constant, Cours de Politique Constitutionnelle (1818–1820), as quoted <strong>in</strong>Bertr<strong>and</strong> de Jouvenel 1949, p. 384; <strong>and</strong> also de Jouvenel himself, p. 10. Relevant here is Amitai Etzioni 1972, pp. 88–92, 142–143. Headed “Got a problem ... ?... call or write e Gr<strong>and</strong> Shaman,” <strong>the</strong> article notes people’s propensity to look to <strong>the</strong>federal government for solutions to all sorts <strong>of</strong> problems. Its ma<strong>in</strong> concern, however, is <strong>the</strong>empty, symbolic character <strong>of</strong> many ostensible solutions. Speeches are made, conferencesheld, commissions appo<strong>in</strong>ted, bills passed, agencies established, funds appropriated, <strong>and</strong>programs launched, <strong>of</strong>ten do<strong>in</strong>g little <strong>of</strong> substance to treat <strong>the</strong> problems <strong>in</strong>volved.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 333<strong>the</strong>ir elected representatives, <strong>in</strong>creased <strong>the</strong> difficulties <strong>of</strong> monitor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>government, <strong>and</strong> exp<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> scope for court cases, <strong>the</strong>se un<strong>in</strong>tendedresults will hardly be traced to <strong>and</strong> blamed on <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al sponsors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>legislation. Meanwhile, <strong>the</strong>y get credit for be<strong>in</strong>g concerned with problems.Politicians <strong>and</strong> government <strong>of</strong>ficials tend to have short time horizons.Unlike corporation executives, who may hold stock or stock options <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>ir companies <strong>and</strong> whose performance tends to be assessed <strong>and</strong> reportedon <strong>the</strong> stock market anyway, government <strong>of</strong>ficials hold no shares <strong>of</strong> stockwhose current prices might reflect assessments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> long-run consequences<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir actions; hence, short-run electoral concerns tend to prevail.How much <strong>in</strong>centive, for example, do mayors have to mount strongresistance to <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> unionized city employees? Mayor John L<strong>in</strong>dsay<strong>of</strong> New York “took <strong>the</strong> attitude that he would not be around <strong>in</strong> tenyears. He thought he would be ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> White House or do<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>gelse, so he decided to pay people <strong>of</strong>f with promises <strong>of</strong> pensions thatwould come due when he was no longer mayor” (Bork 1978, p. 13).e personal qualities useful <strong>in</strong> ga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g favorable publicity <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> politicalwheel<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> deal<strong>in</strong>g are not likely to co<strong>in</strong>cide with <strong>the</strong> personalqualities <strong>of</strong> a competent, far-sighted, <strong>and</strong> courageous statesman. Nei<strong>the</strong>rare <strong>the</strong> qualities <strong>of</strong> a successful campaigner, which <strong>in</strong>clude adroitness <strong>in</strong>project<strong>in</strong>g an appeal<strong>in</strong>g personality <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> cleverly stat<strong>in</strong>g or obscur<strong>in</strong>gissues. Similarly, a competent <strong>and</strong> devoted public servant would havera<strong>the</strong>r different qualities than a personally successful bureaucrat, whoseabilities might run more toward cultivat<strong>in</strong>g superiors by promot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irpersonal ambitions.Exceptions do occur. Why can’t a politician see it as his mission <strong>in</strong> lifeto do good by resist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> revers<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> trend toward ever more government?If that resistance really is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> average citizen, why See Ellul 1967, pp. 150–151: “e politician is generally not competent with regard to<strong>the</strong> problems that are his to solve, particularly if, as it is now <strong>in</strong>evitable, he has becomea specialist <strong>in</strong> political affairs.... e political leader must be a politician by trade, whichmeans to be a clever technician <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> capture <strong>and</strong> defense <strong>of</strong> positions.... desire for powerclearly has priority ... because he cannot undertake just <strong>and</strong> desirable reforms or guard <strong>the</strong>common good unless he first obta<strong>in</strong>s power <strong>and</strong> keeps it.... e two forms <strong>of</strong> politics ...dem<strong>and</strong> radically different personal qualities <strong>and</strong> contrary preoccupations. To be a clevermaneuverer <strong>in</strong> arriv<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> summit is no qualification for perceiv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> common good,mak<strong>in</strong>g decisions, be<strong>in</strong>g politically enlightened, or master<strong>in</strong>g economic problems. Conversely,to have <strong>the</strong> moral qualities <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual competence to be capable <strong>of</strong> genu<strong>in</strong>ethought <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> eventually putt<strong>in</strong>g a genu<strong>in</strong>e political program <strong>in</strong>to operation <strong>in</strong> no wayensures hav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> equipment to reach <strong>the</strong> top.”


334 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophycan’t <strong>the</strong> politician both serve his self-esteem <strong>and</strong> w<strong>in</strong> votes by campaign<strong>in</strong>gon such a platform?Conceivably he might. But <strong>the</strong>se questions, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> refut<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>argument about activist biases, merely note a possible <strong>of</strong>fset. For severalreasons, this <strong>of</strong>fset is unlikely to be strong. (e exceptional politicianto whom <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g remarks do not apply st<strong>and</strong>s at a disadvantage <strong>in</strong>w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g elections <strong>and</strong> wield<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence.) First, a political career wouldgenerally have been less appeal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place to a skeptic aboutgovernment than to a man who saw great opportunities <strong>in</strong> it for do<strong>in</strong>ggood. Opportunities for also ga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g personal success <strong>in</strong> that endeavorare greater for a politician, as for a bureaucrat, if government is big <strong>and</strong>grow<strong>in</strong>g than if it is kept small. Secondly, w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g elections on a platform<strong>of</strong> restrict<strong>in</strong>g government activities depends on a greater degree <strong>of</strong> sophisticatedunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g among voters than <strong>the</strong>y are likely to have (althoughhope on this score is now emerg<strong>in</strong>g). Even if a politician is concernedwith enlighten<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> citizens over <strong>the</strong> long run, he must realize that hischances <strong>of</strong> provid<strong>in</strong>g enlightenment are poor if <strong>the</strong> voters remove himfrom political life. He directs his campaign<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> citizens as <strong>the</strong>y are<strong>and</strong> as <strong>the</strong>y th<strong>in</strong>k, not to <strong>the</strong> economists <strong>and</strong> political philosophers that<strong>the</strong>y are not.A third l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> rebuttal denies <strong>the</strong> common idea that politicians try tosell <strong>the</strong>ir programs to voters for votes quite as bus<strong>in</strong>essmen try to sell <strong>the</strong>irwares to consumers for dollars. e analogy is defective <strong>in</strong> many respects.For example, c<strong>and</strong>idates go beyond direct appeals to <strong>the</strong> electorate. eyalso seek votes <strong>in</strong>directly by appeal<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>fluential op<strong>in</strong>ionmakers <strong>and</strong> too<strong>the</strong>r politicians. Alliances are essential for gett<strong>in</strong>g nom<strong>in</strong>ations, gett<strong>in</strong>gallocations <strong>of</strong> party funds <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r help <strong>in</strong> campaigns, <strong>and</strong> logroll<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>enactment <strong>of</strong> one’s favorite projects (<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby ga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> personal status).e <strong>in</strong>dividual politician has to tailor his appeal partly to o<strong>the</strong>r politicians,most <strong>of</strong> whom <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>e toward an activist government for <strong>the</strong> reasonsunder discussion. Even <strong>the</strong> exceptional politician is restra<strong>in</strong>ed, <strong>the</strong>n, fromadvocat<strong>in</strong>g as much limitation <strong>of</strong> government power as he might o<strong>the</strong>rwisepersonally favor.Our amateur psychologiz<strong>in</strong>g about politicians should pay some attentionto <strong>the</strong> members <strong>of</strong> legislators’ staffs. With government expansion <strong>and</strong>legislative burdens mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g dem<strong>and</strong>s on <strong>the</strong>ir employers’ time<strong>and</strong> ability to absorb <strong>in</strong>formation, staff members have grow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence.ey fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ir own careers by help<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir employers ga<strong>in</strong> prom<strong>in</strong>ence.Bright ideas help. Although a few ideas may focus on repeal<strong>in</strong>g


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 335laws <strong>and</strong> abolish<strong>in</strong>g agencies, activism generally <strong>of</strong>fers more scope forbrightness, as well as for ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g political alliances, especially <strong>in</strong> an<strong>in</strong>tellectual atmosphere predisposed to activism. e bureaucrat, like <strong>the</strong> politician, may well see his mission <strong>in</strong> life as do<strong>in</strong>ggood through <strong>the</strong> agency <strong>of</strong> government. He is likely, though, except at<strong>the</strong> highest levels, to be a specialist. (At <strong>the</strong> highest levels, he is likelyto be mobile between government positions <strong>and</strong> to be judged more byhis reputed abilities <strong>and</strong> performance <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> short run than by <strong>the</strong> longrunconsequences <strong>of</strong> how he runs any particular agency.) e specialistidentifies with <strong>the</strong> mission <strong>of</strong> his bureau, appreciates <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> its services,but appreciates less clearly <strong>the</strong> alternative results obta<strong>in</strong>able fromdevot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> necessary money <strong>and</strong> resources to o<strong>the</strong>r purposes, public orprivate. Like most people, he wants to th<strong>in</strong>k that his job is important <strong>and</strong>dem<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> that he is do<strong>in</strong>g it well. With a bigger budget <strong>and</strong> a largerstaff, he could serve <strong>the</strong> public still better. Fortunately for his ambitions,<strong>the</strong> legislators must depend largely on what he <strong>and</strong> his fellow experts tell<strong>the</strong>m about <strong>the</strong> benefits <strong>and</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> his agency’s activities. Because hisjob is specialized <strong>and</strong> complicated <strong>and</strong> because <strong>the</strong>y have o<strong>the</strong>r tasks also,<strong>the</strong> legislators cannot monitor him closely. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, alliances tend t<strong>of</strong>orm among <strong>the</strong> agency, <strong>the</strong> members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> legislative committee monitor<strong>in</strong>git, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> constituency <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> private sector that benefits from <strong>the</strong>agency’s services or regulations. Judges, like o<strong>the</strong>r government decisionmakers, are <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>in</strong> a position totake a narrow view, do<strong>in</strong>g what seems good or benevolent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> particularcase at h<strong>and</strong> without hav<strong>in</strong>g to weigh costs aga<strong>in</strong>st benefits carefully<strong>and</strong> without hav<strong>in</strong>g to exercise adequate foresight about <strong>the</strong> long-run William A. Niskanen (1971) argues that bureaucrats strive to maximize <strong>the</strong>ir budgets.Years earlier, Ludwig von Mises had stressed <strong>the</strong> contrast between a pr<strong>of</strong>it-seek<strong>in</strong>gfirm <strong>and</strong> a bureau. In a firm, <strong>the</strong> higher executives can monitor <strong>the</strong> performance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>irsubord<strong>in</strong>ates by f<strong>in</strong>ancial account<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> test <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>and</strong> loss. Monitor<strong>in</strong>g is morecomplicated <strong>in</strong> a nonpr<strong>of</strong>it organization. Especially <strong>in</strong> one that gets its funds from budgetappropriations ra<strong>the</strong>r than by sell<strong>in</strong>g goods or services to will<strong>in</strong>g customers, <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancialtests are necessarily weakened, <strong>and</strong> detailed “bureaucratic” rules <strong>and</strong> regulations must take<strong>the</strong>ir place as best <strong>the</strong>y can (Mises 1945).


336 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyrepercussions <strong>of</strong> a particular decision. Of course, judges are under an obligationto decide accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> law, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g precedent; but when legislation,adm<strong>in</strong>istrative decrees, lawsuits, <strong>and</strong> court decisions have vastlyproliferated, <strong>the</strong> judge—cued by <strong>the</strong> litigants’ attorneys—has all <strong>the</strong> moredecisions to hunt among for <strong>the</strong> precedent that will rationalize <strong>the</strong> decisionhe wants to make.Nathan Glazer (1975) describes several factors contribut<strong>in</strong>g to a tide<strong>of</strong> judicial activism. Powerful new <strong>in</strong>terests are at work, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g publicadvocacylaw centers supported by government or foundations. “Law—for<strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> correction <strong>of</strong> presumed evils, for chang<strong>in</strong>g governmentpractices, for overrul<strong>in</strong>g legislatures, executives, <strong>and</strong> adm<strong>in</strong>istrators, for<strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>of</strong> replac<strong>in</strong>g democratic procedures with <strong>the</strong> authoritari<strong>and</strong>ecisions <strong>of</strong> judges—became enormously popular” (p. 123). Second,<strong>the</strong> courts must work out <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> positions once taken <strong>and</strong> cannoteasily withdraw from <strong>the</strong>ir implications. New decisions create precedentswhose applications <strong>and</strong> extensions cannot be fully foreseen; case lawevolves with a momentum <strong>of</strong> its own. Examples concern <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>of</strong>“st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g” to sue, <strong>of</strong> due process, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> equal protection. ird, expansion<strong>of</strong> government activity provides all <strong>the</strong> more subject matter for court cases.e “facts” relevant to court decisions become all <strong>the</strong> more numerous <strong>and</strong>complex. Social science becomes relevant; <strong>and</strong> as it changes, so may <strong>the</strong>law. e judges acquire all <strong>the</strong> more opportunities for second-guess<strong>in</strong>gnot only ord<strong>in</strong>ary citizens but also <strong>the</strong> legislative <strong>and</strong> executive branches<strong>of</strong> government. In short, <strong>the</strong> courts well illustrate <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>me <strong>of</strong>this paper: <strong>the</strong> fragmentation, on <strong>the</strong> governmental scene, <strong>of</strong> cost-benefitcalculation, decisions, <strong>and</strong> responsibility. Consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> circumstances <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives <strong>of</strong> voters, politicians, bureaucrats,<strong>and</strong> judges does seem to reveal a bias toward hyperactive government.Yet Anthony Downs (1960), who had lucidly expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> rationality<strong>of</strong> voter ignorance, went on to <strong>of</strong>fer a supposed explanation <strong>of</strong> “why <strong>the</strong>government budget is too small <strong>in</strong> a democracy.” e core <strong>of</strong> his argumentis that <strong>the</strong> rationally ignorant voter does not appreciate all <strong>the</strong> remote <strong>and</strong>problematical benefits that government programs would provide. As societybecomes wealthier <strong>and</strong> more complex, <strong>the</strong> potential scope for remote Glazer cites numerous specific examples <strong>of</strong> judicial activism. I have rearranged <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>terpreted Glazer’s po<strong>in</strong>ts.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 337<strong>and</strong> poorly understood but genu<strong>in</strong>e government benefits exp<strong>and</strong>s. Publicgoods do not enjoy <strong>the</strong> advertis<strong>in</strong>g that private goods do. e average voteris highly aware, however, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> government programs as reflected<strong>in</strong> his taxes. Cater<strong>in</strong>g to such voters, politicians hold tax<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> spend<strong>in</strong>gdown to levels at which <strong>the</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> additional spend<strong>in</strong>g would stillexceed <strong>the</strong> costs.Several th<strong>in</strong>gs are wrong with this argument. First, taxes are not allthat evident to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual voter. Excise taxes are concealed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> prices<strong>of</strong> products, <strong>and</strong> just which persons ultimately bear <strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> corporation<strong>in</strong>come tax is even more obscure. Even personal <strong>in</strong>come taxes canbe made less conspicuous by withhold<strong>in</strong>g. Downs does not take adequateaccount <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se tax concealments. He does not adequately recognize <strong>the</strong>several dist<strong>in</strong>ct ways <strong>in</strong> which <strong>in</strong>flation can br<strong>in</strong>g what amounts to hiddentax <strong>in</strong>creases. He does not recognize how easy it is for governmentto spend <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>cremental tax revenues generated by economic growth. Hedoes not take “fiscal illusion” seriously enough. Second, politicians havediscovered <strong>the</strong> beauties <strong>of</strong> deficit spend<strong>in</strong>g; <strong>and</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>the</strong>y do withshort time horizons, <strong>the</strong>y do not agonize over an ultimate day <strong>of</strong> reckon<strong>in</strong>g.ird, Downs gives only unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g examples <strong>of</strong> governmentactivities that have th<strong>in</strong> but widespread benefits, or benefits that are great<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> long run but unnoticed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> short run. In fact, his chief exampleseems to be foreign aid. Although he notes <strong>the</strong> coercive nature <strong>of</strong> deal<strong>in</strong>gswith government, he seems not to recognize that private activitiescarried out with resources not taxed away might <strong>the</strong>mselves have remotebenefits <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> coercive nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> expansion <strong>of</strong> government activitymakes that expansion less likely to leave a net excess <strong>of</strong> benefit over costthan <strong>the</strong> alternative <strong>of</strong> voluntary expansion <strong>of</strong> private activity. He does notrecognize <strong>the</strong> differential <strong>in</strong>centives that special private <strong>in</strong>terests have topress exaggerated claims about <strong>the</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> government programsthat <strong>the</strong>y are seek<strong>in</strong>g.Fourth, while Downs applies <strong>the</strong> approach <strong>of</strong> methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualismto <strong>the</strong> voter, he does not apply it consistently to bureaucrats,politicians, judges, <strong>and</strong> litigants. In some passages, he refers to “<strong>the</strong> govern<strong>in</strong>gparty” or even “<strong>the</strong> government” as if it were a monolithic entitymak<strong>in</strong>g coord<strong>in</strong>ated choices ra<strong>the</strong>r than an assemblage <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual personseach work<strong>in</strong>g with his own drives, motives, opportunities, <strong>in</strong>centives,constra<strong>in</strong>ts, <strong>and</strong> special po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view. He does not take heed <strong>of</strong> how<strong>in</strong>dividual legislators or c<strong>and</strong>idates can call for particular spend<strong>in</strong>g programswithout call<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> taxes to pay for <strong>the</strong>m. He supposes that each


338 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophybureau would submit its budget requests to, <strong>in</strong> effect, “<strong>the</strong> directors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>govern<strong>in</strong>g party,” who, anxious for votes, would develop suitable checkson <strong>the</strong> bureau’s expansionism. He does not recognize, as William Niskanen(1971) later expla<strong>in</strong>ed, that self-aggr<strong>and</strong>iz<strong>in</strong>g bureaus are <strong>in</strong> fact notsupervised by a sufficiently authoritative central budget<strong>in</strong>g agency. On<strong>the</strong> contrary, <strong>the</strong>y are likely to develop cozy relations with <strong>the</strong> congressionalcommittees that are supposed to monitor <strong>the</strong>m. In short, Downsfails to grasp <strong>the</strong> full implications <strong>of</strong> fragmented government decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g. e fragmentation <strong>of</strong> decisions over time contributes to an un<strong>in</strong>tendeddrift <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole economic <strong>and</strong> political system. Especiallyunder a two-party system, platform-builders <strong>and</strong> campaigners <strong>of</strong>tenavoid draw<strong>in</strong>g issues <strong>in</strong> a clear-cut way. A c<strong>and</strong>idate opposed to protectivetariffs would not call for complete free trade for fear <strong>of</strong> los<strong>in</strong>g someprotectionist voters who would support him on o<strong>the</strong>r issues. He realizesthat many a voter will choose <strong>the</strong> lesser evil ra<strong>the</strong>r than “waste his vote”on a third party even if one happened to mirror his own set <strong>of</strong> views moreaccurately. <strong>Political</strong> straddl<strong>in</strong>g, toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> jumbl<strong>in</strong>g toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong>unrelated issues (<strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idates’ personalities) <strong>in</strong> every election,water down <strong>the</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terventionism versus <strong>the</strong> free market <strong>in</strong>to anun<strong>in</strong>spir<strong>in</strong>g choice between parties lean<strong>in</strong>g just a little more one way ora little more <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. Incentives <strong>and</strong> prejudices favor<strong>in</strong>g a middle-<strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>-roadposition leave <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> cumulative policy drift to whoeverare most active <strong>in</strong> locat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> two sides <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> road, or even justone side. e k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> choices that voters <strong>and</strong> politicians consider feasible(<strong>and</strong>, similarly, <strong>the</strong> positions <strong>the</strong>y consider unrealistically extreme) areconditioned by how policy has been drift<strong>in</strong>g. Resistance to drift weakenswhen not only politicians but even scholars make a fetish <strong>of</strong> recommend<strong>in</strong>gonly policies <strong>the</strong>y consider politically “realistic.” Under such circumstances,discussion does not adequately consider long-run repercussions<strong>and</strong> long-run compatibilities <strong>and</strong> clashes among various goals <strong>and</strong> measures.Major choices, such as ones affect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> general character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> An early explanation was provided by Harold Hotell<strong>in</strong>g (1929) <strong>in</strong> an article basicallydeal<strong>in</strong>g with economic matters. On <strong>the</strong> harmfulness <strong>and</strong> even immorality <strong>of</strong> such “realism,” see Clarence E. Philbrook1953.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 339economic <strong>and</strong> social system, may get made by default as <strong>the</strong> cumulativeresult <strong>of</strong> piecemeal decisions whose comb<strong>in</strong>ed tendencies were not realizedwhen <strong>the</strong>y were made. Closely related to dispersion <strong>of</strong> decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g among persons <strong>and</strong> overtime is dispersion <strong>of</strong> responsibility. <strong>in</strong>gs that would be considered morallyreprehensible if done by a s<strong>in</strong>gle decisionmaker escape moral condemnationwhen done by government, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is not apparent where <strong>the</strong>responsibility lies. Examples are our <strong>in</strong>flation mess, <strong>the</strong> quasi-repudiation<strong>of</strong> government debt, <strong>the</strong> taxation <strong>of</strong> phantom earn<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> phantom capitalga<strong>in</strong>s, even when <strong>the</strong> taxpayer has suffered a real loss <strong>and</strong> even whenhe has suffered it on bonds <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> government itself, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> government’scont<strong>in</strong>ued push<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its sav<strong>in</strong>gs bonds.Fragmentation <strong>of</strong> decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g is not to be condemned tout court.In many cases, keep<strong>in</strong>g decisions close to <strong>the</strong> affected level will improve<strong>the</strong> cost-benefit confrontation. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, it helps preserve freedom.In fact, this is one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> chief arguments for <strong>the</strong> market as opposed togovernment control. Ano<strong>the</strong>r disadvantage <strong>of</strong> rout<strong>in</strong>e reliance on government to suppress allbad <strong>and</strong> promote all good is that it tends to freeze out alternative solutionsto <strong>the</strong> problems tackled. It can hamper diverse <strong>in</strong>itiatives <strong>and</strong> experimentation.It can crowd out private activity by tax<strong>in</strong>g away funds that “e system <strong>of</strong> direct regulation cannot allow flexibility <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> application to <strong>in</strong>dividualcases because favoritism cannot be dist<strong>in</strong>guished from flexibility <strong>and</strong> diversity <strong>of</strong>conditions cannot be dist<strong>in</strong>guished from caprice. e price system, however, possessesthis remarkable power: if we make an activity expensive <strong>in</strong> order to reduce its practice,those who are most attached to <strong>the</strong> practice may still cont<strong>in</strong>ue it. It is <strong>the</strong> system whichexcludes from an <strong>in</strong>dustry not those who arrived last but those who prize least <strong>the</strong> right towork <strong>in</strong> that <strong>in</strong>dustry. It is <strong>the</strong> system which builds roads by hir<strong>in</strong>g men with an aptitudefor road-build<strong>in</strong>g, not by <strong>the</strong> corvée <strong>of</strong> compulsory labor” (Stigler 1975, p. 36).e recent gasol<strong>in</strong>e shortage <strong>and</strong> proposals to deal with it by ration<strong>in</strong>g or by mak<strong>in</strong>geverybody forgo driv<strong>in</strong>g one day a week, or <strong>the</strong> nonsystem <strong>of</strong> ration<strong>in</strong>g by <strong>in</strong>convenience,all illustrate Stigler’s po<strong>in</strong>ts about regulation versus <strong>the</strong> market. Regulation cannot take<strong>in</strong>to account <strong>the</strong> detailed personal knowledge that people have about <strong>the</strong>ir own needs <strong>and</strong>wants <strong>and</strong> circumstances.


340 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophypeople would o<strong>the</strong>rwise spend <strong>the</strong>mselves on satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir wants, bytransferr<strong>in</strong>g real resources from <strong>the</strong> private to <strong>the</strong> public sector, by creat<strong>in</strong>gor threaten<strong>in</strong>g subsidized competition with private approaches, <strong>and</strong> bystifl<strong>in</strong>g imag<strong>in</strong>ation with <strong>the</strong> thought that <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>in</strong> question isalready be<strong>in</strong>g taken care <strong>of</strong>. It is <strong>in</strong>structive to ponder what <strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong>affairs <strong>in</strong> education, health <strong>and</strong> retirement programs, hous<strong>in</strong>g, transportation,<strong>the</strong> mails, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r fields would be today if government had notgotten so heavily <strong>in</strong>volved as it has <strong>in</strong> fact. One frequent advantage <strong>of</strong>private over government f<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>g is that it can take better account <strong>of</strong>how strongly people desire an activity on <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> its various possibleforms. Far from <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> an activity argu<strong>in</strong>g for its be<strong>in</strong>gtaken over by <strong>the</strong> government, one should th<strong>in</strong>k that its importance arguesaga<strong>in</strong>st its be<strong>in</strong>g dom<strong>in</strong>ated by one big supplier. It is all <strong>the</strong> more regrettablewhen various monopolized activities are monopolized by <strong>the</strong> samemonopolist <strong>and</strong> when economic <strong>and</strong> political power are comb<strong>in</strong>ed, withall that implies about potentialities for coercion.What crowd<strong>in</strong>g out means is illustrated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> field <strong>of</strong> energy. Proposalsabound for government action <strong>and</strong> subsidies to develop non-conventionalsources. Taxpayers would <strong>in</strong> effect have to pay <strong>the</strong> differencebetween <strong>the</strong> high cost <strong>and</strong> lower price <strong>of</strong> subsidized fuels; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y couldnot, act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividually, escape this burden by energy conservation. Productionfrom conventional sources <strong>and</strong> potential production from unsubsidizednew sources will suffer as producers f<strong>in</strong>d it easier <strong>and</strong> less risky totake government h<strong>and</strong>outs. Not only money but also talent <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>genuitywill be diverted from o<strong>the</strong>r types <strong>of</strong> production, exploration, <strong>and</strong> research<strong>in</strong>to those favored by <strong>the</strong> government. Bus<strong>in</strong>ess firms <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors willshy away from risky, expensive, long-term-oriented projects not only forfear <strong>of</strong> future government-subsidized competition but also for fear <strong>of</strong>future <strong>in</strong>fr<strong>in</strong>gements on property rights. e history <strong>of</strong> energy policy,toge<strong>the</strong>r with current demogogy, provides ample grounds for <strong>the</strong> latterfear: firms <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors must recognize <strong>the</strong> prospect that even after risk<strong>in</strong>gheavy losses, <strong>the</strong>y will not be allowed to collect exceptionally largepr<strong>of</strong>its from successful hunches <strong>and</strong> good luck. Government reassurances,even if made, would nowadays not be credible. is example bearson a broader po<strong>in</strong>t about remote repercussions—remote <strong>in</strong> time <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> sectoraffected. A violation <strong>of</strong> property rights—perhaps restrictions on use <strong>of</strong> Paul L. Joskow <strong>and</strong> Robert S. P<strong>in</strong>dyck develop po<strong>in</strong>ts like <strong>the</strong>se <strong>in</strong> “ose SubsidizedEnergy Schemes” (1979, p. 12).


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 341property ra<strong>the</strong>r than outright public purchase—may seem <strong>the</strong> economical<strong>and</strong> expedient th<strong>in</strong>g to do <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual case. Yet <strong>in</strong> contribut<strong>in</strong>gto an atmosphere <strong>of</strong> uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, it can have grave repercussions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>long run.An advocate <strong>of</strong> limited government cannot specify just what non-governmentalsolution to a problem might have been found if it had not beencrowded out. An economist sympa<strong>the</strong>tic to <strong>the</strong> market can expla<strong>in</strong> howentrepreneurs have <strong>in</strong>centives to seek unfilled wants <strong>and</strong> ways <strong>of</strong> fill<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>m, but he cannot predict what unfilled wants are go<strong>in</strong>g to be filled,<strong>and</strong> how <strong>and</strong> when. Hence his position seems complacent; it reeks <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> ivory tower. In contrast, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terventionist position looks concrete,active, practical, <strong>and</strong> down-to-earth.Here I am <strong>in</strong> danger <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g misunderstood. While I deplore regulat<strong>in</strong>gvoluntary transactions that are not immoral <strong>and</strong> that adults areundertak<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>ir eyes open, <strong>the</strong> case is different with hidden safetyor health hazards or with <strong>the</strong> imposition <strong>of</strong> costs onto <strong>in</strong>nocent third parties.I have qualms about cold-turkey deregulation <strong>in</strong> such cases. Yet over<strong>the</strong> long run, phas<strong>in</strong>g out government regulation could open <strong>the</strong> way forentrepreneurial discovery <strong>of</strong> alternatives that we can hardly imag<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>advance. Such alternatives might, for example, <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>in</strong>spection <strong>and</strong> certificationby specialist firms, as well as regulations imposed by <strong>in</strong>surancecompanies as a condition <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>surance. My emphasis, however, is not onpredict<strong>in</strong>g alternative approaches but on <strong>the</strong>ir unpredictability <strong>and</strong> on howcentral control can forestall <strong>the</strong>ir discovery. See Hayek 1973, especially <strong>the</strong> section headed “Freedom can be preserved only byfollow<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>and</strong> is destroyed by follow<strong>in</strong>g expediency,” pp. 56–59. Hayek rem<strong>in</strong>dsus that <strong>the</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> civilization rest on us<strong>in</strong>g more knowledge than can be deployed<strong>in</strong> any deliberately concerted effort. “S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> freedom rests on opportunitiesit provides for unforeseen <strong>and</strong> unpredictable actions, we will rarely know what we losethrough a particular restriction <strong>of</strong> freedom.” Any restriction will aim at some foreseeableparticular benefit, while what it forecloses will usually rema<strong>in</strong> unknown <strong>and</strong> disregarded.Decid<strong>in</strong>g each issue on its own apparent merits means overestimat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> advantages <strong>of</strong>central direction. <strong>Is</strong>rael M. Kirzner expla<strong>in</strong>s how regulation can impede <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> discovery. Hisconcern, however, is not so much with alternative solutions to problems taken under <strong>the</strong>government’s w<strong>in</strong>g as, ra<strong>the</strong>r, with discovery <strong>of</strong> new <strong>and</strong> better goods <strong>and</strong> services <strong>and</strong> productionmethods. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, regulation diverts entrepreneurs’ energies from seek<strong>in</strong>gdiscoveries <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se constructive k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>in</strong>to cop<strong>in</strong>g with or circumvent<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> regulations<strong>the</strong>mselves. See Kirzner 1979, esp. chap. 4.


342 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy Costs (<strong>and</strong> conceivably benefits) <strong>of</strong> regulatory measures <strong>in</strong>clude effectson <strong>the</strong> whole social, political, <strong>and</strong> economic climate <strong>and</strong> on people’sattitudes. One example <strong>of</strong> what I have <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d concerns how even <strong>the</strong>vaguest h<strong>in</strong>ts about discrim<strong>in</strong>atory enforcement <strong>of</strong> myriad regulations canbe used to encourage “voluntary” compliance with <strong>the</strong> wage <strong>and</strong> price controlsdecreed by <strong>the</strong> president, without legal authority, <strong>in</strong> October 1978. Ano<strong>the</strong>r hard-to-fathom cost is <strong>the</strong> danger (already alluded to <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sectionon “e Courts”) <strong>of</strong> underm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> rule <strong>of</strong> law <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> law’s objectivity,predictability, <strong>and</strong> worth<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> respect.My worries do not h<strong>in</strong>ge on any particular one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> several <strong>the</strong>ories<strong>of</strong> regulation that are <strong>in</strong> circulation. I am not, for example, adopt<strong>in</strong>gas <strong>the</strong> central story <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory that regulated <strong>in</strong>dustries “capture” <strong>the</strong>irregulatory authorities. No doubt some aspects even <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> public-<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> regulation enter <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> explanation <strong>of</strong> why we have so much<strong>of</strong> it. Numerous pressures, motivations, <strong>and</strong> governmental decisionmakers<strong>in</strong>teract. e issue <strong>of</strong> regulation falls under <strong>the</strong> broader question <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r policyshould serve pr<strong>in</strong>ciple or expediency, <strong>the</strong> latter mean<strong>in</strong>g to act on <strong>the</strong>supposed merits <strong>of</strong> each <strong>in</strong>dividual case, narrowly considered. Elements<strong>of</strong> an answer to that question argue for fram<strong>in</strong>g policy with prime attention,<strong>in</strong>stead, to <strong>the</strong> general framework <strong>of</strong> rules with<strong>in</strong> which persons <strong>and</strong>companies can pursue <strong>the</strong>ir own goals. (In philosophical term<strong>in</strong>ology, <strong>the</strong>argument favors rules-utilitarianism over act-utilitarianism.)Some types <strong>of</strong> regulation are even open to objection on ethical grounds.Notions <strong>of</strong> human rights properly belong <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussion, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>grights <strong>of</strong> people to make open-<strong>and</strong>-above-board voluntary transactions Referr<strong>in</strong>g to this program, one Federal Reserve economist has written as follows:“Violators are explicitly threatened with bad publicity <strong>and</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> government contracts.Implicitly, possible violators must be aware <strong>of</strong> potential retaliation by regulatory agenciesnot formally <strong>in</strong>corporated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> wage-price control program.... Due to <strong>the</strong> magnitude<strong>of</strong> discretionary authority possessed by <strong>the</strong> Internal Revenue Service, Environmental ProtectionAgency, Federal Trade Commission, Occupational Safety <strong>and</strong> Health Adm<strong>in</strong>istration,etc., a large potential for retaliation confronts any bus<strong>in</strong>ess” (Webb 1979, p. 14 n.). See Stigler 1975; Richard A. Posner 1974; <strong>and</strong> Sam Peltzman 1976. “More generally, different types <strong>of</strong> constitutionally empowered agents on <strong>the</strong> politicalscene—bureaucrats, judges, legislators, <strong>and</strong> elected executives—each br<strong>in</strong>g dist<strong>in</strong>ctmotivations, authorities, <strong>and</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> political exchange that leadsto <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al regulatory outcome” (Hirshleifer 1976, p. 242).


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 343with each o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> to use <strong>and</strong> deal <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own property. It is a questionableview to accord equal respect to people’s use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own property<strong>and</strong> forcible <strong>in</strong>terference with that use. at view sets aside <strong>the</strong> question<strong>of</strong> who has a right to do what <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> which expectedpattern <strong>of</strong> property use <strong>and</strong> resource allocation appeals more to politicians<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r outside observers. What implications follow from my argument, if it is broadly correct? Mostgenerally, it recommends alertness to activist bias, <strong>and</strong> an appropriate constitutionalattitude. Proposals have been made for a regulatory budget:<strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> annual limit to each regulatory agency’s expenses wouldbe not only its own cash outlays but also <strong>the</strong> estimated costs that compliancewith its regulations would impose on <strong>the</strong> private sector. Admittedly,implement<strong>in</strong>g such a proposal would run <strong>in</strong>to practical difficulties, but itis ma<strong>in</strong>ly its spirit that concerns us here.It is <strong>in</strong>structive to review <strong>the</strong> rationale for <strong>the</strong> analogous proposal <strong>of</strong>plac<strong>in</strong>g a constitutional limit on federal government tax<strong>in</strong>g or spend<strong>in</strong>g.e opportunity to enact such a limit would give <strong>the</strong> public at large <strong>the</strong>hi<strong>the</strong>rto lack<strong>in</strong>g means to vote on <strong>the</strong> total <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> government budget. Byvot<strong>in</strong>g for a limit, a majority could override <strong>the</strong> spend<strong>in</strong>g bias that arisesfrom <strong>the</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong> smaller special-<strong>in</strong>terest decisions. e peopleassign a budget to <strong>the</strong> legislature <strong>and</strong> require it spend <strong>the</strong> limited amount<strong>of</strong> money <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> most effective way. (Supporters <strong>of</strong> a limit ask: if familieshave to operate with<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>come ceil<strong>in</strong>gs, why shouldn’t <strong>the</strong> governmentalso?) Overall limitation would force choices among <strong>the</strong> many spend<strong>in</strong>gprograms that might be separately desirable. To argue persuasively <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>face <strong>of</strong> a given budget total, a group want<strong>in</strong>g a particular program wouldhave to po<strong>in</strong>t out o<strong>the</strong>r budget items that could <strong>and</strong> should be cut. Special<strong>in</strong>terests would <strong>the</strong>n be forced to work for <strong>the</strong> general <strong>in</strong>terest ra<strong>the</strong>r thanaga<strong>in</strong>st it.Regulatory activity is not as quantifiable as tax<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> spend<strong>in</strong>g. But itwould be premature to give up on <strong>in</strong>genuity. Perhaps a quantitative specificationwill prove impossible <strong>and</strong> procedural restra<strong>in</strong>ts will have to serve asa substitute. A constitutional amendment might require that enactment <strong>of</strong> See Tibor R. Machan 1979. See Wall Street Journal 1978 <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> particular, Milton Friedman 1978, pp. 7–14.


344 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophynew regulatory measures be coupled with repeal <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>of</strong> comparablescope (perhaps as judged by numbers <strong>of</strong> regulators <strong>in</strong>volved, or number <strong>of</strong>persons or dollar volume <strong>of</strong> activities <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> private sector directly affected).Perhaps it would be necessary to settle for some vaguer <strong>and</strong> more nearlyonly hortatory restra<strong>in</strong>t. Anyway, good <strong>in</strong>tentions would not be enoughto justify a new regulation; <strong>the</strong> proposed measure would have to be shownto be not merely desirable but exceptionally so, desirable even aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong>background <strong>of</strong> an already overgrown government. e objective is a framework<strong>of</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>and</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>in</strong> which different government activitiesare seen to be <strong>in</strong> rivalry with one ano<strong>the</strong>r, each cost<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> sacrifice <strong>of</strong>o<strong>the</strong>rs. Ideally, advocates <strong>of</strong> each new regulatory measure would accept<strong>the</strong> obligation <strong>of</strong> show<strong>in</strong>g it to be so desirable as to be worth <strong>the</strong> sacrifice<strong>of</strong> specified exist<strong>in</strong>g regulations.Opponents sometimes charge that a budget limit would undemocraticallytie <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> democratic government, <strong>and</strong> a similar objectionwould no doubt be made to constitutional restrictions on regulation. Yet<strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r limit is not to undercut democracy but to make itmore effective by remedy<strong>in</strong>g a flaw that has so far kept <strong>the</strong> people fromcontroll<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> overall consequences <strong>of</strong> piecemeal decisions. A budgetlimit or a regulatory limit no more subverts democracy than <strong>the</strong> FirstAmendment does by sett<strong>in</strong>g limits to what Congress may do. Withoutthat amendment, popular majorities might have placed many particularrestrictions on freedom <strong>of</strong> speech, but our Found<strong>in</strong>g Fa<strong>the</strong>rs rolled all<strong>the</strong>se issues up toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> lett<strong>in</strong>g each one be decided by a separatemajority vote (Friedman 1978, pp. 8–10).Just as proponents <strong>of</strong> tax cuts or budget limits face <strong>the</strong> supposedlyembarrass<strong>in</strong>g dem<strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y draw up lists <strong>of</strong> specific expenditure cuts,so proponents <strong>of</strong> limits to regulation might encounter a similar dem<strong>and</strong>.is one might well be easier to comply with than <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> aboutspend<strong>in</strong>g cuts. Ei<strong>the</strong>r dem<strong>and</strong>, however, is unreasonable. It <strong>in</strong> effect <strong>in</strong>vites<strong>the</strong> limitationists to shut up unless <strong>the</strong>y exhibit detailed knowledge <strong>of</strong> government(<strong>and</strong> private) activities that <strong>the</strong>y cannot realistically be expectedto have. It tacitly denies that <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> specialization <strong>and</strong> division <strong>of</strong>labor applies <strong>in</strong> public policymak<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r areas <strong>of</strong> life. It tacitly supposesthat general knowledge—namely, knowledge <strong>of</strong> bias <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> currentsystem—is worthless unless accompanied by detailed fur<strong>the</strong>r knowledgeon <strong>the</strong> part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same persons. Yet <strong>the</strong> very purpose <strong>of</strong> an overall limitis to br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> detailed knowledge <strong>of</strong> its possessors to bear <strong>in</strong> cop<strong>in</strong>g withthat bias.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 345e private sector is rout<strong>in</strong>ely made <strong>the</strong> target <strong>of</strong> regulation because <strong>of</strong>externalities, mean<strong>in</strong>g cases <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> persons who decide on someactivity or its scale decide wrongly because <strong>the</strong>y do not <strong>the</strong>mselves bearor take full account <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> its costs <strong>and</strong> benefits. How ironic, <strong>the</strong>n,rout<strong>in</strong>ely to expect a solution from government! Government is <strong>the</strong> prototypicalsector <strong>in</strong> which decisionmakers do not take accurate account <strong>of</strong>all <strong>the</strong> costs as well as all <strong>the</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> each activity. e fragmentation<strong>of</strong> decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> responsibility goes part way toward expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gthis condition, along with <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> opportunities <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centivesthat bureaucrats, politicians, legislative staff members, judges, <strong>and</strong> citizenshave.It is difficult to compare even <strong>the</strong> relatively direct <strong>and</strong> obvious costs<strong>and</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>dividual government policy action. It is practicallyimpossible to assess <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>direct <strong>and</strong> long-run consequences <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualactions <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir aggregate, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir effects on <strong>the</strong> drift<strong>of</strong> policy <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic <strong>and</strong> social system. eaggregate <strong>of</strong> activities all appear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividually desirable may itself turnout quite undesirable. Hence <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> frankly allow<strong>in</strong>g considerations<strong>of</strong> political philosophy <strong>in</strong>to policy discussions. Broad pr<strong>in</strong>ciplesshould count, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> skepticism about government activity.Even when no strong <strong>and</strong> obvious disadvantages are apparent, <strong>the</strong>reis presumption (though a defeasible one) aga<strong>in</strong>st each new governmentfunction. e pragmatic, “realistic” approach <strong>of</strong> consider<strong>in</strong>g each <strong>in</strong>dividualfunction separately <strong>and</strong> narrowly, on its own supposed merits, is fatallyflawed.Our Found<strong>in</strong>g Fa<strong>the</strong>rs accepted <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> human rights that governmentshould not violate. at concept need not be based on mysticism.It follows from a version <strong>of</strong> rules-utilitarianism (as dist<strong>in</strong>guished from actutilitarianism).As John Stuart Mill argued (<strong>in</strong> Utilitarianism, chapter 5,writ<strong>in</strong>g when <strong>the</strong> word “justice” had not yet been stretched <strong>in</strong>to uselessnessfor all but emotive purposes), unswerv<strong>in</strong>gly to put respect for justiceahead <strong>of</strong> what might be called narrow expediency is a rule <strong>of</strong> topmost utility(or expediency <strong>in</strong> a broad <strong>and</strong> deep sense). I believe it can be shownthat respect for <strong>and</strong> bas<strong>in</strong>g policy on certa<strong>in</strong> rights <strong>and</strong> values, like justice, Externalities are due, anyway, not to <strong>the</strong> very logic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market system but todifficulties <strong>and</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> fully apply<strong>in</strong>g that system, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g property rights, to <strong>the</strong> cases<strong>in</strong> question.


346 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyaccords with human nature <strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> society <strong>in</strong> which peoplehave good chances for cooperat<strong>in</strong>g effectively as <strong>the</strong>y pursue happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ir own specific ways. Ludwig von Mises <strong>and</strong> Henry Hazlitt, follow<strong>in</strong>gDavid Hume, have persuasively argued that social cooperation is suchan <strong>in</strong>dispensable means to people’s pursuit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own diverse specificgoals that it deserves recognition practically as a goal <strong>in</strong> its own right. Considerations like <strong>the</strong>se merit respect aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> appraisals <strong>of</strong> governmentregulation.Beaver, Roy A. Letter to Wall Street Journal, 26 July 1978.Bork, Robert. Taxpayers’ Revolt: Are Constitutional Limits Desirable? AmericanEnterprise Institute Round Table, July 1978. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.: AmericanEnterprise Institute, 1978.Brittan, Samuel. e <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> <strong>of</strong> Inflation. Edited by Fred Hirsch <strong>and</strong>John H. Goldthorpe. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1978.Dahl, Robert A. A Preface to Democratic eory. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1963.de Jouvenel, Bertr<strong>and</strong>. On Power. New York: Vik<strong>in</strong>g, 1949.Downs, Anthony. An Economic eory <strong>of</strong> Democracy. New York: Harper, 1957.. “Why <strong>the</strong> Government Budget is Too Small <strong>in</strong> a Democracy.” WorldPolitics 3 ( July 1960): 541–563.Ellul, Jacques. e <strong>Political</strong> Illusion. Translated by Konrad Kellen. New York:Knopf, 1967.. A Critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> New Commonplaces. Translated by Helen Weaver. NewYork: Knopf, 1968.Etzioni, Amitai. “e Gr<strong>and</strong> Shaman.” Psychology Today 6 (November 1972):88–92, 142–143.Fe<strong>in</strong>, Leonard J., ed. American Democracy. New York: Holt, R<strong>in</strong>ehart <strong>and</strong> W<strong>in</strong>ston,1964. See Ludwig von Mises 1949 <strong>and</strong> 1957, esp. pp. 57–58; <strong>and</strong> Henry Hazlitt 1964. Anemphasis on social cooperation as a near-ultimate criterion, if not <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term,traces back at least as far as omas Hobbes.


Chapter : <strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? 347Friedman, Milton. Capitalism <strong>and</strong> Freedom. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1962.. “e Limitations <strong>of</strong> Tax Limitation.” Policy Review 5 (Summer 1978):7–14.Glazer, Nathan. “Towards an Imperial Judiciary?” e Public Interest 41 (Fall 1975):104–123.Hayek, F.A. “e Use <strong>of</strong> Knowledge <strong>in</strong> Society.” American Economic Review 35(September 1945): 519–530.. e Counter-Revolution <strong>of</strong> Science. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1952.. Rules <strong>and</strong> Order. Vol. 1 <strong>of</strong> Law, Legislation <strong>and</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University<strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1973.Hazlitt, Henry. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Morality. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>,1964.Hirshleifer, Jack. “Comment” on “Toward a More General eory <strong>of</strong> Regulation,”by Sam Peltzman. Journal <strong>of</strong> Law <strong>and</strong> Economics 19 (August 1976):242.Hotell<strong>in</strong>g, Harold. “Stability <strong>in</strong> Competition.” Economic Journal 39 (March 1929):41–57.Joskow, Paul L., <strong>and</strong> Robert S. P<strong>in</strong>dyck. “ose Subsidized Energy Schemes.”Wall Street Journal, 2 July 1979.Kirzner, <strong>Is</strong>rael M. e Perils <strong>of</strong> Regulation: A <strong>Market</strong>-Process Approach. Law <strong>and</strong>Economics Center Occasional Paper. Coral Gables, Fla.: Law <strong>and</strong> EconomicsCenter <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Miami, 1979.Machan, Tibor R. “Some Normative Considerations <strong>of</strong> Deregulation.” Journal<strong>of</strong> Social <strong>and</strong> <strong>Political</strong> Studies 3 (W<strong>in</strong>ter 1979): 363–377.Mann, omas E. Unsafe at Any Marg<strong>in</strong>. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.: American EnterpriseInstitute, 1978.McClellan, James. “e Tyranny <strong>of</strong> Legalism.” A review <strong>of</strong> Bruno Leoni, Freedom<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Law. University Bookman (Spr<strong>in</strong>g 1974): 66.Mises, Ludwig von. Bureaucracy. London: Hodge, 1945.. Human Action. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1949.. eory <strong>and</strong> History. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1957.


348 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyNiskanen, William A. Bureaucracy <strong>and</strong> Representative Government. Chicago: Ald<strong>in</strong>e-A<strong>the</strong>rton,1971.Olson, Mancur, Jr. e Logic <strong>of</strong> Collective Action. Cambridge, Mass.: HarvardUniversity Press, 1965.Peltzman, Sam. “Toward a More General eory <strong>of</strong> Regulation.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Law<strong>and</strong> Economics 19 (August 1976): 211–240.Philbrook, Clarence E. “‘Realism’ <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal.” American Economic Review43 (December 1953): 846–859.Posner, Richard A. “eories <strong>of</strong> Economic Regulation.” Bell Journal <strong>of</strong> Economics<strong>and</strong> Management Science 5 (Autumn 1974): 335–358.Rickenbacker, William F., <strong>and</strong> Lewis K. Uhler. A Taxpayer’s Guide to Survival:Constitutional Tax-Limitation. Briarcliff Manor, N.Y.: National Tax-Limitation Committee, 1977.Sansweet, Stephen J. “Proposition 13’s Impact on <strong>the</strong> Arts.” Wall Street Journal,14 July 1978.“S<strong>in</strong>gle-<strong>Is</strong>sue Politics.” Newsweek, 6 November 1978.Ste<strong>in</strong>, Herbert. “e Real Reasons for a Tax Cut.” Wall Street Journal, 18 July1978.Stigler, George J. e Citizen <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> State. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press,1975.Wall Street Journal. Editorial. 12 July 1978.Waltz, Kenneth N. eory <strong>of</strong> International Politics. Read<strong>in</strong>g, Mass., <strong>and</strong> MenloPark, Calif.: Addison-Wesley Publish<strong>in</strong>g Company, 1979.Webb, Roy H. “Wage-Price Restra<strong>in</strong>t <strong>and</strong> Macroeconomic Disequilibrium.”Federal Reserve Bank <strong>of</strong> Richmond Economic Review 65, no. 3 (May/June1979).


Economics <strong>and</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples *e title does not announce a talk about <strong>the</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> Economicscourse. Instead, I am go<strong>in</strong>g to deliver a sermon—<strong>and</strong> I use <strong>the</strong> word <strong>in</strong>a self-deprecatory sense. So far as my sermon champions pr<strong>in</strong>ciple overexpediency, it is directed more toward academics <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir roles as selfappo<strong>in</strong>tedpolicy advisers than toward practic<strong>in</strong>g politicians. Politicianscould not function without mak<strong>in</strong>g compromises. Senator Everett Dirksenused to say, quite aptly, “I am a man <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, <strong>and</strong> my chief pr<strong>in</strong>cipleis flexibility.”Now, a sermon is not required on an occasion like this one. Some <strong>of</strong> mypredecessors have talked about technicalities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir special fields. On <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>re is plenty <strong>of</strong> precedent for talk<strong>in</strong>g more about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrelations<strong>of</strong> topics than about <strong>the</strong> details <strong>of</strong> any, for mak<strong>in</strong>g broad observations<strong>and</strong> sweep<strong>in</strong>g conjectures, <strong>and</strong> for <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a personal element.My <strong>the</strong>me is <strong>the</strong> two-way relation that exists between economics <strong>and</strong>general pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> behavior. Economics helps us underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature<strong>and</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> such pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, <strong>the</strong>ir serviceability, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> conditions thattend to support or underm<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong>m. Economists can help expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> respect<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciples not only<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> economic policy but also <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>teractions amonghuman be<strong>in</strong>gs. Relevant str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory refer to: <strong>the</strong> concept,made familiar by Hayek (1967, chap. 6) <strong>of</strong> “results <strong>of</strong> human action butnot <strong>of</strong> human design” (ethical codes <strong>and</strong> languages, as well as money <strong>and</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions, be<strong>in</strong>g prime examples); <strong>the</strong> importance, for*Presidential address at meet<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Economic Association, pr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong>Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Economic Journal 42 (April 1976): 559–571. e section “Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>and</strong> Policy” <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al version <strong>of</strong> this article was removedfor brevity. Its major po<strong>in</strong>ts are addressed <strong>in</strong> chapter , “<strong>Is</strong> ere a Bias Toward Overregulation?”.349


350 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophya function<strong>in</strong>g society, <strong>of</strong> people’s hav<strong>in</strong>g some basis for predict<strong>in</strong>g eacho<strong>the</strong>r’s actions; <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>evitable imperfection, <strong>in</strong>completeness, dispersion,<strong>and</strong> costl<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> knowledge; <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g transactions <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> negotiat<strong>in</strong>g,monitor<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> enforc<strong>in</strong>g agreements, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequent usefulness<strong>of</strong> tacit agreements <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formally enforced rules; applications <strong>of</strong>methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> property-rights <strong>the</strong>ory to analysis<strong>of</strong> nonmarket <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> activities; concepts <strong>of</strong> externalities <strong>and</strong> collectivegoods <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed free-rider problem; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong>general <strong>in</strong>terdependence.Such concepts enter <strong>in</strong>to expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> usefulness <strong>of</strong> ethical rules <strong>and</strong>even <strong>of</strong> concern with people’s characters. Statutory law cannot preventall bad <strong>and</strong> enforce all good behavior. Laws attempt<strong>in</strong>g that would beprohibitively costly to frame <strong>and</strong> enforce, as would <strong>the</strong> mobilization <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> necessary <strong>in</strong>formation. ey would have to be sweep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> vague,would leave dangerous scope for adm<strong>in</strong>istrative discretion, <strong>and</strong> would violate<strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> nulla poena s<strong>in</strong>e lege. e law could not enforce ord<strong>in</strong>arydecency, let alone actual benevolence. (“Ord<strong>in</strong>ary decency” meanssuch th<strong>in</strong>gs as honesty, respect for o<strong>the</strong>r people’s rights, <strong>and</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g considerate,as <strong>in</strong> not throw<strong>in</strong>g bottles <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> street or mak<strong>in</strong>g too much noise.)e very attempt at legal enforcement <strong>of</strong> decency, though doomed to failure,would spell totalitarian control over people’s lives. is is not to denythat properly enforceable ethical st<strong>and</strong>ards exist—far from it, <strong>and</strong> I shallhave more to say about enforcement later on—, but <strong>the</strong> case is overwhelm<strong>in</strong>gfor keep<strong>in</strong>g those st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir enforcement outside <strong>the</strong> realm<strong>of</strong> government <strong>and</strong> for keep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>formal, flexible, <strong>and</strong> subject topiecemeal, gradual, decentralized reform (Hazlitt 1964, esp. pp. 184–185). A social scientist may take <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> how ethical pr<strong>in</strong>ciples relate to <strong>the</strong> function<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> a social <strong>and</strong> economic system without imag<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g himself to possess superior moralcharacter. It is no co<strong>in</strong>cidence that many em<strong>in</strong>ent economists have pursued such an <strong>in</strong>terest—DavidHume, Adam Smith, John Stuart Mill, Henry Sidgwick, J.M. Keynes, <strong>and</strong>James Buchanan, to mention a few. Without implicat<strong>in</strong>g him <strong>in</strong> any mistakes <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>Is</strong>hould particularly like to mention my colleague Rol<strong>and</strong> McKean, a former president <strong>of</strong>our Association, with whose ideas on <strong>the</strong> economics <strong>of</strong> morality m<strong>in</strong>e run largely <strong>in</strong> parallel.See, for example, his two papers <strong>of</strong> 1974. I should also like to acknowledge a significantparallelism (despite some differences) with <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r former president <strong>and</strong>a former colleague, James Buchanan, whose e Limits <strong>of</strong> Liberty (1975) I have read s<strong>in</strong>cedeliver<strong>in</strong>g this address. e most basic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> morality, I would argue, are relatively unchang<strong>in</strong>g, deriv<strong>in</strong>gas <strong>the</strong>y do from human nature, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g man’s nature as a social animal. But <strong>the</strong>specific rules that are appropriate do change as factual circumstances <strong>and</strong> knowledgechange. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, as Hazlitt suggests, <strong>the</strong>re may be such a th<strong>in</strong>g as progress <strong>in</strong> moral


Chapter : Economics <strong>and</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples 351(Vagueness <strong>and</strong> flexibility are undesirable, however, as characteristics <strong>of</strong>government law.)For <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> respective merits <strong>of</strong> voluntarism <strong>and</strong> law <strong>in</strong> variousaspects <strong>of</strong> life, let us consider <strong>the</strong> familiar k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> appeal for voluntaryrestra<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> pric<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> wage dem<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>in</strong> energy consumption, <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong> spend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vest<strong>in</strong>g abroad. Such an approach tends, I argue, tounderm<strong>in</strong>e ord<strong>in</strong>ary morality. By <strong>and</strong> large, it is <strong>in</strong> a person’s long-runself-<strong>in</strong>terest to behave with ord<strong>in</strong>ary decency <strong>and</strong> to cultivate <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong>character that leads him to do so. For this proposition to hold true, social<strong>in</strong>stitutions should be such as to hold down tension between self-<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>and</strong> social <strong>in</strong>terest (ostensible or actual), allow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>visible h<strong>and</strong> towork. While legal rules <strong>and</strong> penalties do have a role <strong>in</strong> such arrangements,it is tremendously important for social cooperation that people generallybe able to trust each o<strong>the</strong>r anyway. Voluntary decency is a scarce resourcenot to be wasted.“Wast<strong>in</strong>g” voluntary decency means putt<strong>in</strong>g an excessive stra<strong>in</strong> on<strong>the</strong> implicit contract exist<strong>in</strong>g among members <strong>of</strong> society to treat eacho<strong>the</strong>r decently. Such a stra<strong>in</strong> occurs when, as is likely to be true <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>context <strong>of</strong> appeals to “voluntary” economic self-denial, behavior <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>supposed social <strong>in</strong>terest does <strong>in</strong> fact clash with self-<strong>in</strong>terest. A counterargumentto my contention is <strong>of</strong>ten more implicit than explicit. It seesvalue <strong>in</strong> giv<strong>in</strong>g people exercise for <strong>the</strong>ir moral muscles—habit-form<strong>in</strong>gexercise <strong>in</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>g aside self-<strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> social <strong>in</strong>terest. I conjecture,though, that plenty <strong>of</strong> occasions for moral exercise arise anyway <strong>in</strong> everydaylife, when an excessively narrow <strong>and</strong> short-run conception <strong>of</strong> self<strong>in</strong>terestclashes with a fuller conception. I am warn<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d<strong>of</strong> exercise that stra<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> damages moral muscles because <strong>the</strong> clashbetween self-<strong>in</strong>terest <strong>and</strong> supposed social <strong>in</strong>terest is genu<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> notmerely apparent.underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, with a m<strong>in</strong>ority <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals lead<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> way. In morality as <strong>in</strong> law, cont<strong>in</strong>uity<strong>and</strong> modifiability both have value. Change is desirable <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> chang<strong>in</strong>g circumstances<strong>and</strong> knowledge, but not change so rapid that people cannot act <strong>and</strong> formexpectations on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> a known moral code. Or so argue writers whom I respect, such as Moritz Schlick (1930/1962), MortimerAdler (1970), <strong>and</strong> Ayn R<strong>and</strong> (1957 <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r novels). In effect <strong>the</strong>y argue that <strong>the</strong> bestprospects for a satisfy<strong>in</strong>g life h<strong>in</strong>ge on hav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> character that sometimes leadsone to subord<strong>in</strong>ate one’s immediate narrow <strong>in</strong>terest or whim to one’s more endur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terest.Yet exceptions do occur; <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> rare cases, decency will cost a man his life. Still, whilea decent character does not guarantee happ<strong>in</strong>ess—noth<strong>in</strong>g can—it tends to improve <strong>the</strong>probabilities. See Schlick 1930/1962, pp. 185–199, but esp. pp. 193–194.


352 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyExpect<strong>in</strong>g people to act aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong>ir own economic <strong>in</strong>terest tendsto undercut <strong>the</strong> signal<strong>in</strong>g function <strong>of</strong> prices <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>centive <strong>of</strong> lossavoidance<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it. How are people to know, <strong>the</strong>n, when it is legitimate<strong>and</strong> when illegitimate to pursue economic ga<strong>in</strong>? Why should <strong>the</strong>ysuppose that <strong>the</strong> President <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States knows best? Why should<strong>the</strong>y respect an attempt to obta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> possibly momentous legislationby bypass<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> constitutional process? To exhort people to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>of</strong> compliance as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>in</strong>terest when it pla<strong>in</strong>ly is not, or to appealto self-sacrifice as if it were <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> morality, is to undercut <strong>the</strong>rational basis <strong>of</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> even rationality itself. It obscures <strong>the</strong> compatibilitybetween social <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>and</strong> rational self-<strong>in</strong>terest that can generallyhold under appropriate social <strong>in</strong>stitutions. is educative effect isespecially perverse when <strong>the</strong> ostensible social <strong>in</strong>terest is not genu<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong>when <strong>the</strong> economic controls would be damag<strong>in</strong>g even if enforced by law.Appeals to voluntary sacrifice promote perverse selection by penaliz<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> people who do comply to <strong>the</strong> benefit <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. M<strong>in</strong>e is similar to GarrettHard<strong>in</strong>’s po<strong>in</strong>t (1968/1969) about <strong>the</strong> voluntary approach to populationcontrol <strong>in</strong> an overpopulated country: <strong>the</strong> people who comply <strong>the</strong>rebycontribute to <strong>the</strong> population relatively few persons exposed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir formativeyears to <strong>the</strong>ir own moral st<strong>and</strong>ards (<strong>and</strong> also hav<strong>in</strong>g whatever genesmay be relevant). e noncompliers will have relatively many children,who will grow up exposed to <strong>the</strong> lower moral st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir parents (aswell as hav<strong>in</strong>g any relevant “bad” genes). Over time, <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>rs will outbreed<strong>the</strong> decent people. In economic affairs, similarly, <strong>the</strong> compliant bus<strong>in</strong>essmanwho holds his sell<strong>in</strong>g price below <strong>the</strong> market-clear<strong>in</strong>g level will I am referr<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>of</strong> course, to <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> ga<strong>in</strong> as such, not to <strong>the</strong> methods used.Ly<strong>in</strong>g, cheat<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> steal<strong>in</strong>g do not become right by be<strong>in</strong>g used <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwisehonorable ends. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> voluntary approach tends to obscure responsibility for <strong>the</strong> unsatisfactoryconditions occasion<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> appeals to restra<strong>in</strong>t <strong>and</strong> sacrifice. Appeals to ord<strong>in</strong>arycitizens to “Stop Inflation” by restra<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> consumption or <strong>in</strong> pay<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>creased prices(appeals such as were frequent late <strong>in</strong> 1971) tend to draw attention away from <strong>the</strong> realsource <strong>of</strong> trouble. As Robert G. Olson says (1965, pp. 12, 126), “<strong>the</strong> probable effect <strong>of</strong> urg<strong>in</strong>g a man toact contrary to what he rationally regards as his own best <strong>in</strong>terests is ei<strong>the</strong>r to embitterhim or to <strong>in</strong>spire contempt for reason.” “If ... an economic system is such that honestyputs an <strong>in</strong>dividual at a serious competitive disadvantage, <strong>the</strong> system is at least as much atfault as <strong>the</strong> dishonest <strong>in</strong>dividual, for honesty ought to pay not only with prestige but withpr<strong>of</strong>its.” I cite Hard<strong>in</strong> only to clarify my po<strong>in</strong>t, not to echo his specific recommendation onan issue ra<strong>the</strong>r far afield from my present topic.


Chapter : Economics <strong>and</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples 353have to turn away some customers, who will <strong>the</strong>n buy from his noncomply<strong>in</strong>grivals. In earn<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>and</strong> w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g control over resources, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong>less public-spirited bus<strong>in</strong>essmen will prevail over <strong>the</strong> more public-spirited.By practic<strong>in</strong>g restra<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> driv<strong>in</strong>g, public-spirited car owners will leavemore gasol<strong>in</strong>e available, <strong>and</strong> at a lower price than o<strong>the</strong>rwise, to driversless public-spirited than <strong>the</strong>mselves. Eventually such effects become evident,fur<strong>the</strong>r support<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> perverse idea that morality is for suckers <strong>and</strong>dupes.In contrast with “voluntary” controls, legally enacted penalties aga<strong>in</strong>stspecifically def<strong>in</strong>ed violations do tend to make compliance serve <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual’sself-<strong>in</strong>terest. e contrast weakens, though, if supposedly compulsorycontrols, by <strong>the</strong>ir nature, are easy to evade, so that any compliancemust <strong>in</strong> effect be voluntary. e contrast also weakens if <strong>the</strong> lawmakes crimes out <strong>of</strong> actions not o<strong>the</strong>rwise morally wrong, or if <strong>the</strong> controlsbecome so extensive <strong>and</strong> complicated that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual can hardlyknow just what is expected <strong>of</strong> him.My criticism <strong>of</strong> voluntary economic controls does not imply oppositionto voluntarism <strong>in</strong> all aspects <strong>of</strong> life. Quite <strong>the</strong> contrary: preciselybecause voluntarism is <strong>in</strong>dispensable, we must beware <strong>of</strong> misus<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>subvert<strong>in</strong>g it. Far from deny<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong>re are valid dist<strong>in</strong>ctions betweenright <strong>and</strong> wrong, I am stress<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> alternatives to detailed governmentalcompulsion <strong>and</strong> prohibition. Many types <strong>of</strong> wrongdo<strong>in</strong>g can be discouraged,if at all, only <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>formal, de-centralized way. Discouragementconsists <strong>in</strong> part <strong>of</strong> an atmosphere <strong>in</strong> which wrongdoers bear certa<strong>in</strong> costs,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g, perhaps, that <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g regarded with appropriate revulsion.Although deal<strong>in</strong>g with relatively trivial cases, a memorable Newsweekcolumn by Stewart Alsop (1970, p. 100) conta<strong>in</strong>s valuable <strong>in</strong>sights. “[T]heman who makes a justified fuss,” said Alsop, “does a public service.” Alsopcited examples <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>difference <strong>of</strong> clerks at railroad ticket counters <strong>and</strong>hotel desks as long queues formed, <strong>the</strong> surl<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> waiters, <strong>the</strong> dishonor<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> confirmed air reservations. Pr<strong>of</strong>essor David Kle<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> MichiganState University practices render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> public service that Alsoppraised. When a Montreal hotel tried to dishonor his confirmed reservation,Kle<strong>in</strong> gave <strong>the</strong> desk clerk three m<strong>in</strong>utes to f<strong>in</strong>d him a room; o<strong>the</strong>rwise,he would change to his pajamas <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lobby <strong>and</strong> go to sleep on as<strong>of</strong>a. Kle<strong>in</strong> got his room. Kle<strong>in</strong> also makes it his practice to bill bus<strong>in</strong>ess Alsop deplored “<strong>the</strong> sheepish docility <strong>of</strong> most American customers.” “In <strong>the</strong> public<strong>in</strong>terest, <strong>the</strong> pricks should be kicked aga<strong>in</strong>st at every opportunity.”


354 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyfirms for time spent cop<strong>in</strong>g with errors on <strong>the</strong>ir part. A quiet, well-bredscene does not embarrass him. “[I]f more people did what I do,” he says,“bus<strong>in</strong>ess practices might improve.” If middle-class people used <strong>the</strong>ir clout“<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> right way, <strong>the</strong>y could make enormous changes <strong>in</strong> retail<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r practices” (Nemy 1974). Alsop <strong>and</strong> Kle<strong>in</strong> were suggest<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> exceptional victim who doesprotest deserves admiration for impos<strong>in</strong>g costs on abuses <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby discourag<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>ir repetition. Because this service is a public good, as Alsopnoted, <strong>the</strong> protester unfortunately reaps only a fraction at best <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> totalbenefit from his action.A fur<strong>the</strong>r reason why <strong>in</strong>centives to protest are <strong>in</strong>adequate emergesfrom Helmut Schoeck’s analysis <strong>of</strong> a case less trivial than those reportedby Alsop <strong>and</strong> Kle<strong>in</strong>. Schoeck’s case may even afford <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to why totalitarianregimes can <strong>of</strong>ten enjoy apparent mass support. Schoeck supposesthat a new center <strong>of</strong> power has come <strong>in</strong>to be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> some organization, perhapsby foul means. It seeks to br<strong>in</strong>g “under its dom<strong>in</strong>ation those groups<strong>and</strong> persons who have not yet submitted to it.” Some groups or personswill already have l<strong>in</strong>ed up beh<strong>in</strong>d it, “whe<strong>the</strong>r out <strong>of</strong> greed, cowardice,stupidity or genu<strong>in</strong>e enthusiasm. But <strong>the</strong>se men ... are not satisfied withconform<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>mselves, <strong>and</strong> almost <strong>in</strong>variably develop <strong>in</strong>tense feel<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong>hostility towards those who cont<strong>in</strong>ue to st<strong>and</strong> aside.... Tension, usuallyorig<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> conformists, <strong>the</strong>n arises between those who conform<strong>and</strong> those who do not.” A conformist “begrudges o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>the</strong>ir courage,<strong>the</strong> freedom <strong>the</strong>y still enjoy.” He “sees both himself <strong>and</strong> his chosen powergroup endangered by those who obviously prefer ... to keep <strong>the</strong>ir distance.ose at <strong>the</strong> periphery <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> power center ... now beg<strong>in</strong> to exert pressureon o<strong>the</strong>r people ... with <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> gett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m to conform as well”(Schoeck 1966/1970, pp. 89–90).Schoeck could have streng<strong>the</strong>ned his analysis by <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g Leon Fest<strong>in</strong>ger’s<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> cognitive dissonance (1957, p. 4, chap. 4 <strong>and</strong> passim).ose who resist evil not only fail to reap <strong>the</strong> full benefits <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir publicservice but even risk be<strong>in</strong>g reviled for perform<strong>in</strong>g it. O<strong>the</strong>rs will prefer to e Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Economic Association has been victimized by <strong>the</strong> double-book<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>hotel rooms for convention sessions. Vigorous protest <strong>in</strong> every such case would presumablyhold down this sort <strong>of</strong> abuse, thus conferr<strong>in</strong>g external benefits. On <strong>the</strong> external benefits<strong>of</strong> what Buchanan calls “strategic courage” <strong>in</strong> tough <strong>in</strong>dividual cases <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> externalcosts <strong>of</strong> what he calls “pragmatic compassion”—but “pragmatic compliance” might be abetter term—, see his 1972/1975. Strategic courage is related to act<strong>in</strong>g on pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, whilepragmatic compliance follows from treat<strong>in</strong>g each case on its own narrow merits.


Chapter : Economics <strong>and</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples 355be “realistic,” to “get along.” ose who conform out <strong>of</strong> cowardice or calculation(to use Schoeck’s words) shun fac<strong>in</strong>g that fact; such a cognitionwould be dissonant with <strong>the</strong>ir self-image as decent human be<strong>in</strong>gs. eyhave to adjust <strong>the</strong>ir cognitions. ey come to believe that conformity isproper <strong>and</strong> moral, that <strong>the</strong> usurp<strong>in</strong>g power is worthy <strong>and</strong> its tactics honorable.e nonconformists pose an obstacle to this adjustment <strong>of</strong> cognitions,so <strong>the</strong> adjustment proceeds until <strong>the</strong> collaborators can really believethat <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs are scoundrels. A fur<strong>the</strong>r str<strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> cognitivedissonance is ironic but underst<strong>and</strong>able: <strong>the</strong> more nearly just barely adequatewas <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ducement to collaborate, <strong>the</strong> stronger is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal pressureon <strong>the</strong> collaborator to adjust his cognitions until he believes, s<strong>in</strong>cerely,that he has lent his support to a worthy cause. No one likes to believe tha<strong>the</strong> has betrayed his pr<strong>in</strong>ciples for small stakes, although as Elliot Aronson(1972) says, if a man sells out for a large amount <strong>of</strong> money, <strong>the</strong>n he hasas many cognitions as dollars that are consonant with his hav<strong>in</strong>g taken ast<strong>and</strong> he does not really believe <strong>in</strong>.For reasons like <strong>the</strong>se, <strong>the</strong>n, prospective resisters may decide not tomake <strong>the</strong> necessary sacrifice <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place. Why not cultivate a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong>stoicism <strong>in</strong>stead? Why not sit back, possibly enjoy<strong>in</strong>g a free ride if o<strong>the</strong>rpeople do raise <strong>the</strong> “justified fuss”?Such passiveness is re<strong>in</strong>forced if people actually believe <strong>in</strong> “turn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r cheek” <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> not pass<strong>in</strong>g judgment on o<strong>the</strong>r people’s actions. Passivenesscan create external diseconomies by almost <strong>in</strong>vit<strong>in</strong>g repetition <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> wrongs tolerated. ere is such a th<strong>in</strong>g as culpable bl<strong>in</strong>dness to evil.Harold Macmillan had a po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> say<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong> British cab<strong>in</strong>et member<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1930s who rema<strong>in</strong>ed pacifistic <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nazi menacethat “he was a good man <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> worst sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word” (quoted <strong>in</strong> Davis1975, p. 338).Let me be clear. I am not call<strong>in</strong>g for promiscuous meddl<strong>in</strong>g. I am notcall<strong>in</strong>g on everyone to go around hunt<strong>in</strong>g for misbehavior to condemn.Instead, I am referr<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> people directly acqua<strong>in</strong>ted with abuses.Silent acquiescence on <strong>the</strong>ir part is no virtue. Still, I would not say that In effect, though not <strong>in</strong> so many words, this is <strong>the</strong> advice <strong>of</strong> such writers as AlbertEllis (1968, esp. chap. 13), <strong>and</strong>, with Robert Harper (Ellis <strong>and</strong> Harper 1961), <strong>and</strong> HarryBrowne (1974), <strong>the</strong> best-sell<strong>in</strong>g amateur economist <strong>and</strong> gold bug. e Honor System at <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia depends on <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness <strong>of</strong> studentswho know <strong>of</strong> violations to accuse <strong>the</strong> <strong>of</strong>fenders. Silence <strong>in</strong> such cases is considereddishonorable, subversive <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> system. e system applies only to students, not to facultymembers <strong>and</strong> adm<strong>in</strong>istrators.


356 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>the</strong>y have an actual obligation to speak out at great personal cost. I am urg<strong>in</strong>ga good deal less. Anyone who does render that public service deservesat least sympa<strong>the</strong>tic underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g.Worse than free rid<strong>in</strong>g on o<strong>the</strong>r people’s carry<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> protestaga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>in</strong>justices is <strong>the</strong> free-rid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> culprits <strong>the</strong>mselves. e moreprevalent <strong>and</strong> well based is <strong>the</strong> belief that people are generally decent<strong>and</strong> honest, <strong>the</strong> greater is <strong>the</strong> chance that culprits have to benefit from<strong>the</strong> presumption that <strong>the</strong>y too have <strong>the</strong>se virtues. ey will enjoy a freeride on, while pos<strong>in</strong>g unfair competition with, <strong>the</strong> warranted credibility <strong>of</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r people. I conjecture that a general atmosphere <strong>of</strong> decency <strong>and</strong> trust<strong>in</strong> society is unstable for at least two reasons. e more prevalent knaverybecomes, <strong>the</strong> stronger is <strong>the</strong> temptation on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual to behavelikewise, ra<strong>the</strong>r than lie down like a doormat (Hazlitt 1964, pp. 155–156).On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, as I have just been argu<strong>in</strong>g, when morality does generallyprevail, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual violator has a correspond<strong>in</strong>gly high chance<strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> presumption that he is decent <strong>and</strong> honest thoughhe is not. Just as X-<strong>in</strong>efficiency probably causes more economic loss than allocative<strong>in</strong>efficiency, so, I conjecture, does <strong>the</strong> impairment <strong>of</strong> social cooperationthrough erosion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> presumption <strong>of</strong> decency <strong>and</strong> honesty. atpresumption—<strong>and</strong> its basis <strong>in</strong> fact—is practically <strong>in</strong>dispensable for coord<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ diverse activities <strong>and</strong> so for an economically progressivesociety. What economists are capable <strong>of</strong> contribut<strong>in</strong>g to analysis<strong>of</strong> this connection may well have more significance for welfare than fur<strong>the</strong>rref<strong>in</strong>ements <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> deviations from Pareto-optimality. Already,some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> best writ<strong>in</strong>gs on economic backwardness <strong>and</strong> economic developmentdo lay stress on <strong>the</strong> ethos <strong>of</strong> society. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, as Buchanan (1965) has expla<strong>in</strong>ed, largeness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> society or groupconcerned probably <strong>in</strong>creases <strong>the</strong> temptation on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual to behave immorally. e st<strong>and</strong>ard reference to a burgeon<strong>in</strong>g literature on this topic is Leibenste<strong>in</strong> 1966. Banfield 1958 has shown <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> “amoral familism” (an excessively narrow <strong>and</strong>short-run concern for <strong>the</strong> material welfare <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nuclear family), toge<strong>the</strong>r with dishonesty,suspiciousness, <strong>and</strong> envy, <strong>in</strong> imped<strong>in</strong>g social cooperation <strong>and</strong> economic development<strong>in</strong> a town <strong>of</strong> sou<strong>the</strong>rn Italy around 1955. e importance <strong>of</strong> attitudes <strong>and</strong> culture for developmentor backwardness is <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>me <strong>of</strong> Z<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong> 1963. While Z<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong> does not particularlyemphasize trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> honesty, he does recognize <strong>the</strong>ir importance <strong>in</strong>several contexts. He also notes <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> bureaucrats’ abid<strong>in</strong>g by pr<strong>in</strong>ciple ra<strong>the</strong>rthan undercutt<strong>in</strong>g predictability by decid<strong>in</strong>g each case on its own merits. See also Wraith<strong>and</strong> Simpk<strong>in</strong>s 1964, particularly pp. 155, 157, 189, where <strong>the</strong> authors note <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess<strong>and</strong> account<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> deterr<strong>in</strong>g corruption.


Chapter : Economics <strong>and</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples 357In conclusion <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> summary, economic <strong>the</strong>ory helps clarify <strong>the</strong> usefulness<strong>and</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> leav<strong>in</strong>g much <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> good <strong>and</strong> evil to <strong>in</strong>formalpr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir decentralized, nongovernmental enforcement. Italso po<strong>in</strong>ts out dangers to such pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>and</strong> obstacles to such enforcement.It helps expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> broad pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> assess<strong>in</strong>g economicpolicies <strong>and</strong> helps expla<strong>in</strong> why <strong>the</strong> merits <strong>of</strong> each specific government<strong>in</strong>tervention, narrowly assessed, are not <strong>the</strong> only relevant considerations.We should appraise each proposed <strong>in</strong>tervention, as best we can, for itslikely legal, political, social, <strong>and</strong> ethical repercussions—for its repercussionson <strong>the</strong> system as a whole. If we avoid apprais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> compar<strong>in</strong>galternative economic systems as wholes, if we avoid form<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> act<strong>in</strong>gon a coherent conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good society, we shall make momentouschoices <strong>in</strong> ignorance <strong>and</strong> by default. e opposite approach, respect<strong>in</strong>gpr<strong>in</strong>ciples, would go far, I believe, toward re<strong>in</strong>stat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> wisdom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Found<strong>in</strong>g Fa<strong>the</strong>rs regard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>and</strong> power <strong>of</strong> government.Abelson, Philip H. “Federal Intervention <strong>in</strong> Universities.” Science 190 (17 October1975): editorial page.Adler, Mortimer J. e Time <strong>of</strong> Our Lives. New York: Holt, R<strong>in</strong>ehart <strong>and</strong> W<strong>in</strong>ston,1970.Alsop, Stewart. “Let’s Raise More Hell.” Newsweek, 9 March 1970.Aronson, Elliot. e Social Animal. San Francisco: Freeman, 1972.Banfield, Edward C., assisted by Laura C. Banfield. e Moral Basis <strong>of</strong> a BackwardSociety. New York: Free Press, 1958.Browne, Harry. How I Found Freedom <strong>in</strong> an Unfree World. New York: AvonBooks, 1974.Brown<strong>in</strong>g, Edgar K. “Why <strong>the</strong> Social Insurance Budget <strong>Is</strong> Too Large <strong>in</strong> aDemocracy.” Economic Inquiry 13 (September 1975): 373–388.Buchanan, James M. “Ethical Rules, Expected Values, <strong>and</strong> Large Numbers.”Ethics 76 (October 1965): 1–13.. “America’s ird Century <strong>in</strong> Perspective.” Atlantic Economic Journal 1(November 1973): 3–12.


358 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy. e Limits <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1975.. “e Samaritan’s Dilemma.” Manuscript, 1972. In Altruism, Morality,<strong>and</strong> Economic eory, edited by E.S. Phelps. New York: Russell Sage Foundation,1975.Dahl, Robert. “M<strong>in</strong>orities Rule.” 1963. In American Democracy, edited by LeonardJ. Fe<strong>in</strong>, 123–130. New York: Holt, R<strong>in</strong>ehart <strong>and</strong> W<strong>in</strong>ston, 1964.Davis, Joseph S. e World between <strong>the</strong> Wars, 1919–39: An Economist’s View. Baltimore:Johns Hopk<strong>in</strong>s University Press, 1975.Downs, Anthony. An Economic eory <strong>of</strong> Democracy. New York: Harper, 1957.. “Why <strong>the</strong> Government Budget is Too Small <strong>in</strong> a Democracy.” WorldPolitics 3 ( July 1960): 541–563.Ellis, Albert. <strong>Is</strong> Objectivism a Religion? New York: Lyle Stuart, 1968.Ellis, Albert, <strong>and</strong> Robert Harper. A Guide to Rational Liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> an IrrationalWorld. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1961.Etzioni, Amitai. “e Gr<strong>and</strong> Shaman.” Psychology Today 6 (November 1972):88–92, 142–143.Fest<strong>in</strong>ger, Leon. A eory <strong>of</strong> Cognitive Dissonance. Evanston, Ind. <strong>and</strong> WhitePla<strong>in</strong>s, N.Y.: Row, Peterson, 1957.Friedman, Milton. Capitalism <strong>and</strong> Freedom. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1962.Glazer, Nathan. “Towards an Imperial Judiciary?” e Public Interest, no. 41 (Fall1975): 104–123Greenfield, Meg. “Food for ought.” Newsweek, 10 November 1975.Hard<strong>in</strong>, Garrett. “e Tragedy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Commons.” 1968. In Population, Evolution,<strong>and</strong> Birth Control, 2ⁿ ed., edited by Hard<strong>in</strong>, 367–381. San Francisco: Freeman,1969.Hayek, F.A. Studies <strong>in</strong> Philosophy, Politics <strong>and</strong> Economics. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong>Chicago Press, 1967.. Rules <strong>and</strong> Order. Vol. 1 <strong>of</strong> Law, Legislation <strong>and</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University<strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1973.Hazlitt, Henry. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Morality. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>,1964.


Chapter : Economics <strong>and</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples 359Hotell<strong>in</strong>g, Harold. “Stability <strong>in</strong> Competition.” Economic Journal 39 (March 1929):41–57.Kahn, Robert L., Barbara A. Gutek, Eugenia Barton, <strong>and</strong> Daniel Katz. “AmericansLove <strong>the</strong>ir Bureaucrats.” Psychology Today 9 ( June 1975): 66–71.Leibenste<strong>in</strong>, Harvey. “Allocative Efficiency vs. ‘X-Efficiency’.” American EconomicReview 56 ( June 1966): 392–415.McKean, Rol<strong>and</strong> N. “Collective Choice.” In Social Responsibility <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Bus<strong>in</strong>essPredicament, edited by James W. McKie, 109–134. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.:Brook<strong>in</strong>gs Institution, 1974.. “Economics <strong>of</strong> Ethical <strong>and</strong> Behavioral Codes.” Manuscript, 1974.Mises, Ludwig von. Bureaucracy. London: Hodge, 1945.Nemy, Enid. “Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Rebels Aga<strong>in</strong>st System.” New York Times News Servicedispatch, Charlottesville Daily Progress, 15 December 1974.Niskanen, William A., Jr. Bureaucracy <strong>and</strong> Representative Government. Chicago:Ald<strong>in</strong>e, 1971.Olson, Mancur, Jr. e Logic <strong>of</strong> Collective Action. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard UniversityPress, 1965.Olson, Robert G. e Morality <strong>of</strong> Self-Interest. New York: Harcourt Brace &World, 1965.Ortega y Gasset, José. e Revolt <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Masses. 1930. New York: Norton, 1957.Philbrook, Clarence H. “‘Realism’ <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal.” American Economic Review43 (December 1953): 846–859.R<strong>and</strong>, Ayn. Atlas Shrugged. New York: New American Library, 1957.Rawls, John. A eory <strong>of</strong> Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,1971.Schlick, Moritz. Problems <strong>of</strong> Ethics. 1930. Translated by D. Ryn<strong>in</strong>. New York:Dover, 1962.Schoeck, Helmut. Envy: A eory <strong>of</strong> Social Behaviour. 1966. Translated by MichaelGlenny <strong>and</strong> Betty Ross. New York: Harcourt Brace & World, 1970.Smith, Adam. e eory <strong>of</strong> Moral Sentiments. 1759. In Adam Smith’s Moral <strong>and</strong><strong>Political</strong> Philosophy, edited by Herbert W. Schneider. New York: HarperTorchbook, 1970.


360 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyV<strong>in</strong>er, Jacob. “e Short View <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Long <strong>in</strong> Economic Policy.” 1940. In eLong View <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Short, 103–130. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1958.V<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, Rutledge. “On Two Foundation Concepts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> eory <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong><strong>Economy</strong>.” Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> 77 (March/April 1969): 199–218.. On Apprais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Performance <strong>of</strong> an Economic System. Cambridge, U.K.,<strong>and</strong> New York: Cambridge University Press, 1984.Wilson, James O. “e Rise <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Bureaucratic State.” e Public Interest, no. 41(Fall 1975): 77–103.Wraith, Ronald, <strong>and</strong> Edgar Simpk<strong>in</strong>s. Corruption <strong>in</strong> Develop<strong>in</strong>g Countries. NewYork: Norton, 1964.Z<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Maurice. Development for Free Asia. New ed. New York: Oxford UniversityPress, 1963.


American DemocracyDiagnosed *Alan Ehrenhalt earned a master’s degree <strong>in</strong> journalism, has worked as apolitical reporter, editor, <strong>and</strong> columnist, has been a Nieman Fellow atHarvard <strong>and</strong> a visit<strong>in</strong>g scholar <strong>in</strong> political science at Berkeley, <strong>and</strong> is nowexecutive editor <strong>of</strong> Govern<strong>in</strong>g magaz<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> Wash<strong>in</strong>gton. His new book,e United States <strong>of</strong> Ambition, shapes his keen observations <strong>in</strong>to an <strong>in</strong>telligiblepattern.e U.S. political system has changed vastly from what it was severaldecades ago. Old-style mach<strong>in</strong>es like <strong>the</strong> one bossed <strong>in</strong> Utica, NewYork, by Rufus Elefante (never elected to anyth<strong>in</strong>g) are gone. <strong>Political</strong> partieshave lost <strong>the</strong>ir organized character. Experienced politicians <strong>and</strong> partyleaders no longer have much chance to screen potential c<strong>and</strong>idates. Successno longer belongs to team players. e political process has becomemuch more open to leaderless <strong>in</strong>dividuals seek<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>fice on <strong>the</strong>ir own. “eskills that work <strong>in</strong> American politics at this po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> history are those <strong>of</strong>entrepreneurship. At all levels <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> political system ... it is unusual forparties to nom<strong>in</strong>ate people. People nom<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong>mselves” (p. 17).ose who ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> keep <strong>of</strong>fice tend to be people who like politics, seeit as a full-time career, <strong>and</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r enjoy campaign<strong>in</strong>g or dislike its rigorsless than most people would. ey bask <strong>in</strong> publicity <strong>and</strong> put a relativelylow value on privacy. As careerist pr<strong>of</strong>essionals, <strong>the</strong>y develop expertise<strong>in</strong> fundrais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> exploit<strong>in</strong>g technology <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> media. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,people who have <strong>the</strong>se tastes tend to be people who believe <strong>in</strong> activistgovernment. Even out <strong>of</strong> genu<strong>in</strong>e public spirit, <strong>the</strong>y work to exp<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>irscope for do<strong>in</strong>g good <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir favorite way, through exercis<strong>in</strong>g governmentalpower.*From Liberty 5 ( January 1992): 69–71. Review <strong>of</strong> Alan Ehrenhalt, e United States<strong>of</strong> Ambition: Politicians, Power, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Pursuit <strong>of</strong> Office (New York: Times Books, 1991).361


362 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyPeople with a negative image <strong>of</strong> government, see<strong>in</strong>g it as overly meddlesome,or whatever, tend to shun politics. Exceptions do exist, but <strong>the</strong>yare just that, exceptions; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y tend not to persevere <strong>in</strong> politics as tenaciouslyas career-oriented devotees <strong>of</strong> activist government. Under our currentsystem, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, a party’s success depends on steadily recruit<strong>in</strong>gfull-time talent. Government-bash<strong>in</strong>g does not build majorities. RonaldReagan’s antigovernment rhetoric re<strong>in</strong>forced a distaste for political careersamong young Republicans.When conservatives occasionally come to power, <strong>the</strong>y do not do muchto roll back activist programs already <strong>in</strong> place. “Government programsacquire an <strong>in</strong>ertia <strong>and</strong> a set <strong>of</strong> constituencies that make repeal look likeonerous <strong>and</strong> politically costly work, even for a newly <strong>in</strong>stalled conservativeregime that f<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong>m unattractive” (p. 64).[T]hrough <strong>the</strong> 1970s <strong>and</strong> 1980s, <strong>the</strong> Democratic party streng<strong>the</strong>ned itselfas <strong>the</strong> vehicle for people who grew up <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> government <strong>and</strong> politics<strong>and</strong> wanted to make a career <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. And <strong>the</strong> Republican partywas forced to compete as <strong>the</strong> vehicle <strong>of</strong> those who felt that governmentwas a dirty bus<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y were demean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mselves to takepart <strong>in</strong> it. (p. 222)Ehrenhalt illustrates his po<strong>in</strong>ts with case studies <strong>of</strong> local government(Concord, CA.; Utica, N.Y.; Greenville county, S.C.), state government(South Carol<strong>in</strong>a, Alabama, Connecticut, Colorado, Wiscons<strong>in</strong>), <strong>and</strong> members<strong>of</strong> Congress.In Wiscons<strong>in</strong>, for example, <strong>the</strong> peoplehave never chosen <strong>the</strong> Democratic party en bloc to be <strong>the</strong> legislativemajority. e question is not put to <strong>the</strong> electorate that way.... Wiscons<strong>in</strong>’svoters have elected <strong>in</strong>dividual Democrats who outperformed <strong>the</strong>iropposition at <strong>the</strong> tasks a modern political career requires. e electoratehas not sent <strong>the</strong>m to govern; it has merely ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> conditionsunder which <strong>the</strong>y could send <strong>the</strong>mselves. (p. 142)In Wiscons<strong>in</strong>, “<strong>the</strong> GOP has become <strong>the</strong> party <strong>of</strong> C<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>natus—<strong>the</strong>party <strong>of</strong> those who, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al analysis, would ra<strong>the</strong>r be do<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>gelse for a liv<strong>in</strong>g. e Democrats are <strong>the</strong> party <strong>of</strong> those who believe,with [Assemblyman] David Clarenbach, that ‘I can’t th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> anyth<strong>in</strong>g I’dra<strong>the</strong>r devote my life to’” (p. 126).As Ehrenhalt recognizes, his observations do not fully apply to <strong>the</strong>general election for President. For a brief period every four years, after


Chapter : American Democracy Diagnosed 363<strong>the</strong> self-nom<strong>in</strong>ation process is over, <strong>the</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ions <strong>and</strong> values <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> electorateare decisive. However little <strong>the</strong> voters know about <strong>the</strong> vast majority<strong>of</strong> political choices confront<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m, “<strong>the</strong>y do have endur<strong>in</strong>g images<strong>of</strong> what <strong>the</strong> two major parties are about <strong>in</strong> presidential politics” (p. 270).ey apply <strong>the</strong>se images <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y pay attention to <strong>the</strong> campaign as <strong>the</strong>ychoose between <strong>the</strong> two major c<strong>and</strong>idates—or many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> voters do, so<strong>the</strong> qualification should run. Ano<strong>the</strong>r qualification should be that <strong>the</strong> votersare choos<strong>in</strong>g only between two c<strong>and</strong>idates that <strong>the</strong>y have not <strong>the</strong>mselvesdeliberately nom<strong>in</strong>ated.Ehrenhalt identifies a “central contradiction” <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> U.S. political systemthat cries out for explanation: although voters have shown a clear preferencefor Republican presidential c<strong>and</strong>idates over <strong>the</strong> last twenty years,this has done noth<strong>in</strong>g to give <strong>the</strong> GOP a majority <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> country as awhole (p. 208). Yet his own method <strong>of</strong> analysis suggests how to expla<strong>in</strong>this “contradiction,” as well as <strong>the</strong> common observation (if it is correct)that voters tend to disda<strong>in</strong> Congress <strong>in</strong> general while admir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir ownparticular representative.Presidential elections deal with <strong>the</strong> big picture. Voters are <strong>in</strong>terested<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formed—relatively. ey have a chance to express conservatismmore effectively than <strong>in</strong> local <strong>and</strong> Congressional elections.Voters may dislike <strong>the</strong> performance <strong>of</strong> Congress as a whole. Tak<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> system as given, though, <strong>the</strong>y can sensibly elect a representative whoknows how to manipulate it <strong>in</strong> defense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>terests. Forbearance fromgrabb<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir own supposed share <strong>of</strong> federal largesse would not appreciablyturn <strong>the</strong> system around. Responsible government—governmentresponsible to <strong>the</strong> general public <strong>in</strong>terest ra<strong>the</strong>r than overresponsive, piecemeal,to numerous local <strong>and</strong> special <strong>in</strong>terests—is a public good; pursu<strong>in</strong>git has prisoners’-dilemma aspects. Why should one’s own representativebehave responsibly when few o<strong>the</strong>rs would follow <strong>the</strong> example <strong>and</strong> when<strong>the</strong> pay<strong>of</strong>f to himself <strong>and</strong> his or her constituents would be so slight <strong>and</strong>conjectural? Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore—as is one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book’s ma<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mes—<strong>the</strong>irrepresentative tends to be a specialist <strong>in</strong> provid<strong>in</strong>g services to constituents<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> project<strong>in</strong>g an attractive personal image.Ehrenhalt mentions <strong>the</strong> chronic U.S. government budget deficit as anexample <strong>of</strong> irresponsibility or dissipation <strong>of</strong> responsibility <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> political<strong>and</strong> legislative processes (although he does not phrase <strong>the</strong> matter just thatway; see pp. 245–250). More generally, <strong>the</strong> political system has developeda critical flaw: “It has allowed power <strong>and</strong> leadership, at many levels, simplyto evaporate” (p. 38).


364 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyWhat accounts for changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> political system over <strong>the</strong> past fewdecades? Ehrenhalt makes or h<strong>in</strong>ts at several suggestions. Skill <strong>in</strong> communicat<strong>in</strong>g—<strong>in</strong>town meet<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>in</strong> door-to-door canvass<strong>in</strong>g, on television, <strong>in</strong>direct-mail literature—has ga<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> importance (p. 19). “e more campaign<strong>in</strong>gbecomes a science unto itself, <strong>the</strong> more public <strong>of</strong>fices <strong>and</strong> rewardsflow to people who have mastered its details” (p. 206).Air condition<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> jet planes helped change <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> Congress.More so than before, serv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> it can <strong>and</strong> must be a year-round, fulltimeoccupation; yet members can keep <strong>in</strong> touch with <strong>the</strong>ir constituents.But long weekends back <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> district, toge<strong>the</strong>r with heavier work loads,have fur<strong>the</strong>r eroded camaraderie among <strong>the</strong> members (p. 234 <strong>in</strong> particular).On local as well as congressional levels, an explosion <strong>in</strong> staff<strong>in</strong>g haschanged <strong>the</strong> legislative process, mak<strong>in</strong>g legislatures both more competent<strong>and</strong> more active (p. 138).Redistrict<strong>in</strong>g under <strong>the</strong> 1962 Supreme Court decision <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> civilrightsmovement contributed to open<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>the</strong> political system. Changedconvention rules <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>creased importance <strong>of</strong> primaries have altered<strong>the</strong> presidential race. Vietnam <strong>and</strong> Watergate created opportunities forantiestablishment, antiorganization types (pp. 152, 209–210).Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se po<strong>in</strong>ts, obviously, are just as much features as explanations<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> new system <strong>and</strong> require explanation <strong>the</strong>mselves. Ehrenhaltdoes not, <strong>and</strong> does not claim to, provide anyth<strong>in</strong>g approach<strong>in</strong>g a full, wellarticulated,persuasive explanation.Still, he has made a praiseworthy contribution to political science. Itmeshes nicely with <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> public-choice economists. Perhaps moreacademically oriented researchers will build on his work, figur<strong>in</strong>g out, forexample, how to obta<strong>in</strong> statistics on <strong>the</strong> personal characteristics <strong>of</strong> politicians<strong>and</strong> how to test his <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>genious ways.e book’s two f<strong>in</strong>al paragraphs state a brief conclusion. Our politicalsystem is deficient <strong>in</strong> leadership, discipl<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness to seekaccommodation <strong>of</strong> divergent personal preferences. It generates a politics<strong>of</strong> postur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> stalemate. Yet it will not do simply to blame ambitiouspr<strong>of</strong>essional politicians for “this mess”:We underst<strong>and</strong> more than we might like to admit about city councilsthat can’t defer to leadership; about state legislatures where every <strong>in</strong>dividualis a faction unto himself; about a Congress that lacks any sort <strong>of</strong>mean<strong>in</strong>gful community among its members. We underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>se problems,or should, because <strong>the</strong>y are all around us <strong>in</strong> American life. For all


Chapter : American Democracy Diagnosed 365our ignorance as voters <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>attentiveness as citizens, we have a politicsthat is, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> end, appropriate to its time <strong>and</strong> place.is ra<strong>the</strong>r lame conclusion overlooks <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>of</strong> Anthony Downs<strong>in</strong> An Economic eory <strong>of</strong> Democracy (1957): It is perfectly rational for <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual citizen ord<strong>in</strong>arily to rema<strong>in</strong> ignorant <strong>of</strong> political issues <strong>and</strong> give<strong>the</strong>m only superficial attention. Any reform effort that hopes to succeedmust take this circumstance to heart.Ehrenhalt nei<strong>the</strong>r fully expla<strong>in</strong>s our political malady nor gives adviceon how to cure it. Yet even unaccompanied by an etiology <strong>and</strong> a prescription,his diagnosis is well worth hav<strong>in</strong>g. Although Ehrenhalt is not push<strong>in</strong>gany particular ideological l<strong>in</strong>e, his analysis tempts me to <strong>of</strong>fer somelibertarian embroidery.Sheer eloquence, I conjecture, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a knack for devis<strong>in</strong>g memorableslogans, succeeds better <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> political arena than competent concernfor <strong>the</strong> sizes or importance <strong>of</strong> various supposed problems <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>benefits <strong>and</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> remedies <strong>of</strong>fered. Know<strong>in</strong>g economics can hobble<strong>the</strong> honest politician, while <strong>the</strong> pangs <strong>of</strong> conscience spare <strong>the</strong> economicignoramus as he prevails with promises <strong>and</strong> eloquence. Concern for <strong>the</strong>long run is a similar h<strong>and</strong>icap, s<strong>in</strong>ce look<strong>in</strong>g good at election time is whatcounts.ese are among <strong>the</strong> reasons why <strong>the</strong> qualities <strong>and</strong> skills <strong>of</strong> a successfulpolitical campaigner do not co<strong>in</strong>cide with those <strong>of</strong> a good governmentexecutive or legislator (as Ehrenhalt noted <strong>in</strong> Concord, CA., p. 55). “eability to canvass for votes <strong>in</strong> Iowa or New Hampshire does not have muchto do with <strong>the</strong> qualities that make a successful president. But it has cometo be a virtual prerequisite for anyone who wants <strong>the</strong> job” (p. 206).Ehrenhalt fur<strong>the</strong>r helps us underst<strong>and</strong> why <strong>the</strong> outcome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> politicalprocess does not necessarily represent <strong>the</strong> will <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> people. It is afallacy to say (as George Will <strong>and</strong> Herbert Ste<strong>in</strong> did) that people mustbe pretty well satisfied with government as a whole; o<strong>the</strong>rwise <strong>the</strong>y wouldvote to change it. e voters do not have an opportunity to express <strong>the</strong>mselves,<strong>and</strong> express <strong>the</strong>mselves knowledgeably, on <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> government<strong>and</strong> its overall scale <strong>of</strong> activity. e political process operates witha bias toward bigness. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, voters are probably trapped <strong>in</strong> a k<strong>in</strong>d<strong>of</strong> prisoners’ dilemma (as suggested <strong>in</strong> remarks about Congress above).Ehrenhalt’s readers will see fur<strong>the</strong>r reasons for skepticism about democracyas a good <strong>in</strong> its own right. Democracy is a particular politicalmethod, a method <strong>of</strong> choos<strong>in</strong>g, replac<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>g our rulers.


366 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyIdeally it <strong>of</strong>fers us a way <strong>of</strong> avoid<strong>in</strong>g or dismiss<strong>in</strong>g rulers who woulddestroy our <strong>in</strong>dividual rights. It is a radically <strong>in</strong>accurate method <strong>of</strong> implement<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> desires <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> people, but <strong>the</strong> alternative political methodsare even worse. It is a gross fallacy to slide from <strong>the</strong> case for democracy as<strong>the</strong> least bad political method <strong>in</strong>to admir<strong>in</strong>g political methods as such <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>to a supposed case for throw<strong>in</strong>g more <strong>and</strong> more aspects <strong>of</strong> life <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>political—mean<strong>in</strong>g governmental—arena. Ehrenhalt’s observations bolster<strong>the</strong> case for strictly limit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>of</strong> government.Although reforms <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> democratic process will not dispel <strong>the</strong> dangers<strong>of</strong> big government, Ehrenhalt’s book should arouse <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> explor<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>m. e case for limit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> governmental <strong>of</strong>fice looksbetter. So does <strong>the</strong> case for choos<strong>in</strong>g legislators, or some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, by lotra<strong>the</strong>r than by election. So, perhaps, do <strong>the</strong> radical reforms suggested byF.A. Hayek <strong>in</strong> e <strong>Political</strong> Order <strong>of</strong> a Free People (1979).Prospects for reform<strong>in</strong>g politics <strong>and</strong> restra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g government may lookbleak just now. In <strong>the</strong> long run, though, experience, reason, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> growth<strong>of</strong> organized knowledge can change what is politically feasible. (e historical<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual demise <strong>of</strong> socialism is a case <strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t.) Ehrenhalthas made a solid contribution to this growth <strong>of</strong> knowledge. So do<strong>in</strong>g, heprovides grounds for optimism.


Civic Religion Reasserted *In recent decades <strong>the</strong> public-choice school has been apply<strong>in</strong>g economicanalysis to political <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> activities. People are fundamentally<strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong> government as <strong>in</strong> private life. In try<strong>in</strong>g to achieve <strong>the</strong>ir purposes(which need not be narrowly egoistic ones), <strong>in</strong>dividuals respond toopportunities <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives. e specifics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se are different <strong>in</strong> politicsthan <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> marketplace <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess.One implication is that <strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary voter seldom f<strong>in</strong>ds it worth whileto become well <strong>in</strong>formed on a wide range <strong>of</strong> political issues. Almost neverwould his trouble change an election result or <strong>the</strong> policies adopted. Hehas better uses for his time <strong>and</strong> energy. e private market gives him abetter chance than politics does to satisfy his own preferences, even quirkyones. Similarly, he has only slight opportunities <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives to monitor<strong>the</strong> performance <strong>of</strong> his supposed servants <strong>in</strong> government. Special <strong>in</strong>terestgroups have better opportunities to steer government policies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir ownfavorite directions.For <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r reasons—only some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m noticed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bookunder review—<strong>the</strong> democratic political process responds <strong>in</strong>accurately towhat <strong>the</strong> citizens would desire if <strong>the</strong>y were well <strong>in</strong>formed. Modern democraticgovernment has a bias toward counterproductive hyperactivity.An extensive literature mak<strong>in</strong>g such po<strong>in</strong>ts meets sweep<strong>in</strong>g rejectionby a Berkeley Ph.D. graduate, former assistant pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> political scienceat <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Chicago, <strong>and</strong> now pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> economics at <strong>the</strong>University <strong>of</strong> California at Santa Cruz. In an earlier article now exp<strong>and</strong>ed<strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> book, Donald Wittman claimed that “democratic markets workas well as economic markets” (1989, p. 1395). e book (1995, p. 1) weakensthis claim <strong>in</strong>to “both political <strong>and</strong> economic markets work well.” In article<strong>and</strong> book alike, Wittman claims that <strong>the</strong> democratic process is “efficient,”*From Liberty 10 ( January 1997): 57–60, <strong>the</strong>re titled “We Many, We Happy Many.”Review <strong>of</strong> Donald A. Wittman, e Myth <strong>of</strong> Democratic Failure: Why <strong>Political</strong> InstitutionsAre Efficient (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1995).367


368 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyscarcely bo<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>g to describe what his st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> comparison might be.He does <strong>in</strong>voke, but only ritualistically, <strong>the</strong> criteria <strong>of</strong> Pareto optimality<strong>and</strong> wealth maximization (pp. 3–6, 22 n., chap. 11). Relative to what isdemocracy “efficient”? Relative to o<strong>the</strong>r forms <strong>of</strong> government? Relative toleav<strong>in</strong>g wide aspects <strong>of</strong> life outside <strong>the</strong> political arena, as <strong>the</strong> AmericanFounders evidently <strong>in</strong>tended? Wittman does not say.Wittman argues his efficiency claim feebly. He scarcely goes beyondassert<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> positions he attacks are <strong>in</strong>correct or have been “exaggerated.”(“I have already argued that <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>of</strong> opportunism by politicianshas been greatly exaggerated,” p. 33.) Such claims are hard to confront<strong>and</strong> are correspond<strong>in</strong>gly limp, s<strong>in</strong>ce some exaggerations occur onalmost any side <strong>of</strong> any issue. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, Wittman relies heavily on <strong>the</strong>analogy—hardly more than that—between economic markets <strong>and</strong> democraticpolitics (“this book develops an <strong>in</strong>visible-h<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> efficientdemocratic markets,” p. 3). Gordon Tullock, Richard Posner, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rshad argued that spend<strong>in</strong>g to curry government favors will tend to dissipate<strong>the</strong> rents sought. Wittman replies that rules will develop to m<strong>in</strong>imize <strong>the</strong>social cost. Campaign contributions are not dead losses; <strong>the</strong>y help providevaluable <strong>in</strong>formation. Besides, rent-seek<strong>in</strong>g goes on <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess sectoralso. Pet stores push sales <strong>of</strong> bird feeders, which redistributes <strong>in</strong>comefrom humans to birds. If rent-seek<strong>in</strong>g is not viewed as a serious problem<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess sector, it probably should not be so viewed <strong>in</strong> politicalmarkets ei<strong>the</strong>r (p. 36).Wittman provides many more examples <strong>of</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g merely to talk awaypo<strong>in</strong>ts made by public-choice analysts. <strong>Political</strong> entrepreneurs, like bus<strong>in</strong>essentrepreneurs, can ga<strong>in</strong> from discover<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> exploit<strong>in</strong>g unknowndem<strong>and</strong>s, provid<strong>in</strong>g related <strong>in</strong>formation, <strong>and</strong> clear<strong>in</strong>g up confusion. Sodo<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>y help solve <strong>the</strong> supposed problems <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “rational ignorance”<strong>of</strong> voters <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> differential <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>of</strong> special <strong>in</strong>terests. As for pr<strong>in</strong>cipal-agentproblems (problems <strong>of</strong> monitor<strong>in</strong>g by voters <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir supposedpolitical servants), well, <strong>the</strong>y are mitigated by <strong>in</strong>stitutions such as governmentstructure, political parties, <strong>and</strong> c<strong>and</strong>idate reputation. Besides, if<strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>cipal cannot monitor his political agent, <strong>the</strong>n nei<strong>the</strong>r can <strong>the</strong> academicresearcher. Competition for <strong>of</strong>fice reduces politicians’ potential foropportunism <strong>and</strong> shirk<strong>in</strong>g. e party is <strong>the</strong> analogue <strong>in</strong> politics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>franchise <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess sector. Party labels, accumulated reputations,<strong>in</strong>terest-group endorsements, <strong>and</strong> comparative political advertis<strong>in</strong>g alsoprovide good substitutes for specific knowledge about particular c<strong>and</strong>idates.Voters discount <strong>in</strong>formation from sources known to be biased. As


Chapter : Civic Religion Reasserted 369for <strong>the</strong> allegation that “diffuse taxpayers” are <strong>in</strong>sensitive to spend<strong>in</strong>g forconcentrated <strong>in</strong>terests, well, un<strong>in</strong>formed people may even exaggerate <strong>the</strong>extent <strong>and</strong> harm <strong>of</strong> pork-barrel projects. Even if some voters do make<strong>in</strong>correct choices, <strong>the</strong> law <strong>of</strong> large numbers is likely to yield <strong>the</strong> correctmajority choice anyway. <strong>Political</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g legislatures muchsmaller than <strong>the</strong> constituencies represented, reduce transactions costs <strong>and</strong>facilitate efficient policy deals. Despite supposed problems <strong>of</strong> transitivity,externalities, localism, <strong>and</strong> pressure groups, efforts to ga<strong>in</strong> a majoritypush a government toward achiev<strong>in</strong>g efficient outcomes. Local zon<strong>in</strong>g,for example, is likely to be efficient.Here are three more examples <strong>of</strong> Wittman’s style <strong>of</strong> argument. () Dovoters shift some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> current government spend<strong>in</strong>g ont<strong>of</strong>uture generations through debt-f<strong>in</strong>anced deficits? ree short sentencesassum<strong>in</strong>g that taxes fall on l<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduce a sweep<strong>in</strong>g conclusion: “eburden <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> debt falls on <strong>the</strong> present generation, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y will <strong>the</strong>reforechoose <strong>the</strong> optimal discount rate, just as <strong>the</strong>y choose <strong>the</strong> optimalpolicy <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r areas” (p. 159). () “[E]fficient economic markets constra<strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> behavior <strong>of</strong> democratic markets. If vote-maximiz<strong>in</strong>g politicians tryto monkey with <strong>the</strong> economy, it backfires—<strong>the</strong> economy becomes lessefficient, <strong>and</strong> workers <strong>and</strong> capitalists vote <strong>the</strong>m out <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>fice. So politiciansare restra<strong>in</strong>ed from such maneuvers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place” (p. 176). () Inmak<strong>in</strong>g consumption-versus-<strong>in</strong>vestment decisions <strong>in</strong> a socialist economy,“Vote-maximiz<strong>in</strong>g politicians would aga<strong>in</strong> be constra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir choicesby requirements <strong>of</strong> an efficient economy. Mak<strong>in</strong>g different choices wouldultimately yield fewer votes” (p. 176). “Ultimately”—perhaps so, if freedom<strong>and</strong> democracy survive under socialism; but why should <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualpolitician care about “ultimately”?Wittman provides little susta<strong>in</strong>ed reason<strong>in</strong>g to support his positions,<strong>and</strong> scant evidence beyond airy references to <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> elections,parties, ideologies, rivalries, campaign<strong>in</strong>g, Congressional hear<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>and</strong> s<strong>of</strong>orth. He does cite many books <strong>and</strong> articles claimed to support his position,but he cites <strong>the</strong>m sweep<strong>in</strong>gly, without detailed discussion. He spendsmore space on <strong>the</strong> supposed methodological <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r flaws <strong>of</strong> studiesthat reach contrary conclusions. One whole chapter criticizes psychologicalstudies cast<strong>in</strong>g doubt on how dependably people behave “rationally”as economists underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> term.Wittman pays little or no attention to major str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> public-choiceliterature. While he does paw away at <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> voter ignorance,he seems not deeply to appreciate why superficiality is rational for <strong>the</strong>


370 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>in</strong>dividual voter (<strong>and</strong> nonvoter). O<strong>the</strong>r such phenomena <strong>in</strong>clude: <strong>the</strong> fuzz<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> issues <strong>in</strong> a two-party system (<strong>the</strong> Hotell<strong>in</strong>g effect), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> associateddrift over time <strong>in</strong> what positions are considered respectably ma<strong>in</strong>stream;<strong>the</strong> jumbl<strong>in</strong>g toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> diverse issues <strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>in</strong>coherent packages;<strong>the</strong> chasm between <strong>the</strong> personal qualities <strong>of</strong> an effective campaigner<strong>and</strong> those <strong>of</strong> a sound statesman; various ra<strong>the</strong>r mechanical <strong>in</strong>accuracies<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> political process (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g several paradoxes <strong>of</strong> vot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> whatRobert Dahl labeled “m<strong>in</strong>orities rule”); <strong>the</strong> fragmentation <strong>of</strong> decisionmak<strong>in</strong>gpower <strong>and</strong> responsibility among levels <strong>and</strong> branches <strong>of</strong> government<strong>and</strong> among <strong>in</strong>dividual politicians, bureaucrats, <strong>and</strong> judges; <strong>the</strong> analogous<strong>in</strong>tertemporal fragmentation <strong>of</strong> responsibility; <strong>the</strong> associated reasons whypoliticians <strong>and</strong> bureaucrats have short time horizons; <strong>the</strong> forestall<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>market solutions to problems by governmental preemption; <strong>the</strong> way thatgovernment activism, far from just remedy<strong>in</strong>g externalities <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> privatesector, creates major externalities <strong>in</strong> government decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g itself;<strong>the</strong> lesser scope for prices to function <strong>in</strong> government than <strong>in</strong> markets; <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> coercive aspect <strong>of</strong> government that is absent from private bus<strong>in</strong>ess.He does not draw <strong>the</strong> implications <strong>of</strong> politicians’ <strong>and</strong> bureaucrats’ constitut<strong>in</strong>gspecial <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own (he should have taken to heart suchcase studies as Alan Ehrenhalt, e United States <strong>of</strong> Ambition, 1991; JohnJackley, Hill Rat, 1992; <strong>and</strong> Eric Felten, e Rul<strong>in</strong>g Class, 1993).One wonders what world Wittman has been liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>. Hasn’t he noticedexamples <strong>of</strong> government irresponsibility <strong>and</strong> failure <strong>in</strong> policy oncrime, education, welfare, regulation, litigation, money, <strong>and</strong> budget<strong>in</strong>g?Can voters diagnose who is responsible for current poor economic performance,especially given lags <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> policies? Hasn’t Wittmannoticed voters’ tendency to blame or credit <strong>the</strong> adm<strong>in</strong>istration <strong>in</strong> powerfor <strong>the</strong> current stage <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle? Hasn’t he noticed <strong>the</strong> wretchedquality <strong>of</strong> arguments on economic policy issues presented by all majorsides <strong>and</strong> reported on television <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> popular press? Doesn’t he recognizethat <strong>the</strong> quality <strong>of</strong> political discussion is so low because politiciansappeal to voters as <strong>the</strong>y actually are, with <strong>the</strong>ir short attention spans <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ir actual circumstances?Although Wittman neglects most such counterevidence, his treatment<strong>of</strong> what he does notice suggests how he would deal with <strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> it. Itis all too easy, he says, to po<strong>in</strong>t to such st<strong>and</strong>ard examples <strong>of</strong> supposedgovernment <strong>in</strong>efficiency as rent control, tariffs, tobacco <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r farmsubsidies, <strong>and</strong> agricultural-market<strong>in</strong>g orders. But some observers compla<strong>in</strong>about too much foreign aid or too much support for right-w<strong>in</strong>g


Chapter : Civic Religion Reasserted 371dictators; o<strong>the</strong>rs compla<strong>in</strong> about too little. “So, while just about everyonehas her [sic] <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> government failure, at least half must be wrong.”“[M]any examples <strong>of</strong> political-market failure are mutually contradictory<strong>and</strong> methodologically unsound” (chap. 13, quotations from pp. 182 <strong>and</strong> 181).Wittman’s arguments are not only feeble but sometimes <strong>in</strong>consistent.“[O]pportunism by politicians is mitigated when <strong>the</strong>y are paid abovemarketsalaries <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n threatened with los<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>fice if <strong>the</strong>y shirk. efact that c<strong>and</strong>idates engage <strong>in</strong> very costly election campaigns is consistentwith <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that hold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>fice pays above-market salaries” (p. 27).What, <strong>the</strong>n, has become <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> much trumpeted competition? Don’t <strong>the</strong>costly campaigns dissipate wealth? And how does Wittman’s judgmentabout politicians’ salaries square with his equally bli<strong>the</strong> judgment (p. 106)that bureaucrats’ wages are kept at <strong>the</strong> competitive level?Ironically, Wittman’s book, like <strong>the</strong> precursor article, was published at<strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Chicago, a citadel <strong>of</strong> positivism <strong>in</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong><strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>sistence that <strong>the</strong>ories be falsifiable. (I <strong>in</strong>terpret this, perhaps charitably,as <strong>in</strong>sistence that <strong>the</strong>ories have actual content, as opposed to be<strong>in</strong>g formulatedwith built-<strong>in</strong> immunity to any adverse evidence.) Wittman himselfmakes self-congratulatory remarks about sound <strong>and</strong> unsound methodologies.His two conclud<strong>in</strong>g chapters, total<strong>in</strong>g only 13 pages, bear <strong>the</strong> titles“e <strong>Test</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> eory” <strong>and</strong> “Epilogue: e Burden <strong>of</strong> Pro<strong>of</strong>.” (Page 2 hadalready placed “<strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> ... on those who argue that democraticpolitical markets are <strong>in</strong>efficient.”) e reader expects Wittman at last tosay what he would recognize as weighty evidence or argument aga<strong>in</strong>st his<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>and</strong> say how it st<strong>and</strong>s up to <strong>the</strong> test.Yet he does not follow through. Even so, he ends his book claim<strong>in</strong>gto have “carried over to models <strong>of</strong> political-market failure” <strong>the</strong> suspicionabout underly<strong>in</strong>g assumptions that economists properly apply to assertions<strong>of</strong> failure <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess sector. “I have argued that voters make<strong>in</strong>formed judgments <strong>and</strong> that democratic markets are competitive” (p. 192).“Economists do not dwell on bus<strong>in</strong>ess error or pathological consumerbehavior.” Instead, <strong>the</strong>y “analyze <strong>the</strong> normal <strong>and</strong> look for efficiency explanationsfor abnormal market behavior. Similarly, political scientists shouldnot dwell on <strong>the</strong> mistakes made by political markets” (p. 193 n.). But hedoes not claim to have actually shown that democracy is efficient. efuzz<strong>in</strong>ess that rema<strong>in</strong>s renders his <strong>the</strong>sis even less testable than it mighthave been if more sharply formulated. Aga<strong>in</strong> he <strong>in</strong>s<strong>in</strong>uates that <strong>the</strong> burden<strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> lies on those who would deny <strong>the</strong> presumption <strong>of</strong> efficiency toeconomic markets <strong>and</strong> political markets alike.


372 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyat someth<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>in</strong>adequate <strong>and</strong> perverse as this book (<strong>and</strong> its predecessorarticle) has been written <strong>and</strong> published under prestigious academicauspices is a phenomenon cry<strong>in</strong>g out for explanation. Tackl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> puzzleis important, for <strong>the</strong> book’s mere existence <strong>and</strong> academic trapp<strong>in</strong>gs willcarry some weight. Along with like-m<strong>in</strong>ded academics, politicians <strong>and</strong>bureaucrats relish support from what “studies have shown.”Before explor<strong>in</strong>g possible explanations, I should confess to <strong>in</strong>dignationdat<strong>in</strong>g back to <strong>the</strong> 1989 article. Perhaps my judgment must be discounted.I used to criticize that article <strong>in</strong> my graduate sem<strong>in</strong>ars <strong>in</strong> politicaleconomy. What called my attention to <strong>the</strong> book was Donald Boudreaux’sexcellent, <strong>and</strong> properly adverse, review article on it <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first issue (Spr<strong>in</strong>g1996) <strong>of</strong> e Independent Review. (In hopes <strong>of</strong> avoid<strong>in</strong>g duplication, I setBoudreaux’s review aside while read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> book <strong>and</strong> draft<strong>in</strong>g my ownreview.)I must also confess to embarrassment. It is a commonplace remark thatone should not ask about people’s motives. Yet sometimes such <strong>in</strong>quiry isnecessary. A detective <strong>in</strong> a murder case must conjecture about motiveswhile formulat<strong>in</strong>g rival hypo<strong>the</strong>ses <strong>and</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to rule out all but one <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>m. e <strong>in</strong>tellectual puzzle <strong>of</strong> a curious book requires a roughly similarprocedure.My first hypo<strong>the</strong>sis must be that Wittman is driven by passion fortruth. Conceivably he is quite right: <strong>the</strong> now-familiar public-choice <strong>the</strong>ories<strong>of</strong> bureaucracy <strong>and</strong> democratic politics are radically deficient, <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ways he diagnoses. Democratic processes do <strong>in</strong>deed closely resemblecompetitive processes <strong>in</strong> markets for goods <strong>and</strong> services. It is I whoam wrong, bl<strong>in</strong>ded by m<strong>in</strong>dless <strong>in</strong>dignation to <strong>the</strong> merits <strong>of</strong> Wittman’sbrilliant revisionism.But o<strong>the</strong>r hypo<strong>the</strong>ses suggest <strong>the</strong>mselves. e thought did cross mym<strong>in</strong>d that Wittman’s book (<strong>and</strong> article) might be a susta<strong>in</strong>ed spo<strong>of</strong>, likephysicist Alan Sokal’s article on “postmodern gravity” <strong>in</strong> Social Text, or ifnot a spo<strong>of</strong>, at least a move <strong>in</strong> an academic game. Wittman does acknowledge(p. ix) that he has been play<strong>in</strong>g a “game,” that latecomers to an <strong>in</strong>tellectualcontroversy enjoy an advantage, <strong>and</strong> that he has “had a lot <strong>of</strong> fun.”Or perhaps Wittman was try<strong>in</strong>g, as an exercise, to make <strong>the</strong> best casefor democratic government he could devise. “Democratic decisions shouldbe treated as <strong>in</strong>nocent until proven guilty,” he says, “<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y deserve alawyer argu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir side <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> case” (p. 193). With ample talent alreadymak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> prosecution’s case, perhaps Wittman chose to write <strong>the</strong> legalbrief for <strong>the</strong> defense. Lett<strong>in</strong>g someone else recognize how weak even that


Chapter : Civic Religion Reasserted 373best case is—provok<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> reader toward a judgment <strong>of</strong> his own—mightbe an effective way to re<strong>in</strong>force public-choice-type skepticism about activistdemocratic government.One variant <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis about an <strong>in</strong>tellectual exercise is thatWittman saw an opportunity to fill a vacant niche <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> academic l<strong>and</strong>scape.From that hi<strong>the</strong>rto unoccupied “<strong>in</strong>tellectual foxhole” (as CharlesPeirce said), he might sally forth <strong>in</strong> battle with holders <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r positions.Evidently <strong>the</strong> marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas had left room for an academicallycredentialed rehabilitation <strong>of</strong> what R.W. Bradford (1993, pp. 159–165)has called “e New Civic Religion”—pop wisdom about <strong>the</strong> virtue <strong>and</strong>efficacy <strong>of</strong> vot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> about <strong>the</strong> m<strong>and</strong>ates conferred by elections. I do notknow about Wittman, but as a general proposition, hold<strong>in</strong>g a dist<strong>in</strong>ctive<strong>in</strong>tellectual position can draw <strong>in</strong>vitations to attend scholarly conferences<strong>and</strong> contribute chapters to collective works. Serv<strong>in</strong>g as a foil for o<strong>the</strong>r positionsis not necessarily disreputable: as John Stuart Mill said <strong>in</strong> On Liberty,truth may sometimes streng<strong>the</strong>n its appeal by struggle aga<strong>in</strong>st error, evencontrived error.e hypo<strong>the</strong>sis about niche-fill<strong>in</strong>g meshes with one about <strong>the</strong> state<strong>of</strong> academic economics (at least as diagnosed by several em<strong>in</strong>ent participants).Academics feel pressure to publish <strong>and</strong> be noticed. Latch<strong>in</strong>g ontoa fad is one way. Deliver<strong>in</strong>g shock value—be<strong>in</strong>g an iconoclast, challeng<strong>in</strong>gestablished beliefs—is ano<strong>the</strong>r way, which can even add to <strong>the</strong> “fun” <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>game. Occasionally <strong>the</strong> two approaches can even blend <strong>in</strong>to a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> rout<strong>in</strong>eorig<strong>in</strong>ality: extend a fad so as to challenge yet ano<strong>the</strong>r widely acceptedbelief. I have observed plenty <strong>of</strong> faddism, iconoclasm, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir comb<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>in</strong> my own field <strong>of</strong> macroeconomics. Certa<strong>in</strong> str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Chicago <strong>and</strong>UCLA economics cultivate <strong>the</strong> fad <strong>of</strong> argu<strong>in</strong>g that whatever <strong>in</strong>stitutionor practice has long endured <strong>the</strong>reby demonstrates a certa<strong>in</strong> efficiency,whe<strong>the</strong>r or not its rationale has hi<strong>the</strong>rto been spelled out. Such iconoclasticfaddism (or chic iconoclasm) purports to rationalize forms <strong>of</strong>protection <strong>and</strong> rent-shift<strong>in</strong>g long condemned by ma<strong>in</strong>stream economists.Wittman’s work could be ano<strong>the</strong>r example, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>tentionally or notI do not know.Follow<strong>in</strong>g academic practice <strong>in</strong> one or several <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se ways need not<strong>in</strong>dicate <strong>in</strong>s<strong>in</strong>cerity or o<strong>the</strong>r personal immorality. Besides, Leon Fest<strong>in</strong>ger’spr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> cognitive dissonance may be at work. If one feels uncomfortableas a gamesman say<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs one does not really believe, one canremove or forestall <strong>the</strong> dissonance by com<strong>in</strong>g quite s<strong>in</strong>cerely to believethose th<strong>in</strong>gs.


374 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyI do not know which <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>ses mentioned is correct; maybesome o<strong>the</strong>r one is. Pend<strong>in</strong>g fur<strong>the</strong>r evidence, we should perhaps opt for acharitable one. Meanwhile, Wittman’s judgments rema<strong>in</strong> puzzl<strong>in</strong>gly perverse.If <strong>the</strong>y should succeed <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g a great splash, that would reflectadversely on academic social science <strong>and</strong> on popular discourse <strong>in</strong>fectedby it.Bradford, R.W., ed. It Came from Arkansas. Port Townsend, Wash.: Liberty Publish<strong>in</strong>g,1993.Wittman, Donald A. “Why Democracies Produce Efficient Results.” Journal <strong>of</strong><strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> 97 (December 1989): 1395–1424.Wittman, Donald A. e Myth <strong>of</strong> Democratic Failure. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong>Chicago Press, 1995.


A Libertarian Case forMonarchy * Clear thought <strong>and</strong> discussion suffer when all sorts <strong>of</strong> good th<strong>in</strong>gs, like liberty,equality, fraternity, rights, majority rule, <strong>and</strong> general welfare—some<strong>in</strong> tension with o<strong>the</strong>rs—are marketed toge<strong>the</strong>r under <strong>the</strong> portmanteaulabel “democracy.” Democracy’s core mean<strong>in</strong>g is a particular method <strong>of</strong>choos<strong>in</strong>g, replac<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>g government <strong>of</strong>ficials (Schumpeter1950/1962). It is not a doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> what government should <strong>and</strong> should notdo. Nor is it <strong>the</strong> same th<strong>in</strong>g as personal freedom or a free society or an egalitariansocial ethos. True enough, some classical liberals, like omas Pa<strong>in</strong>e(1791–1792/1989) <strong>and</strong> Ludwig von Mises (1919/1983), did scorn hereditarymonarchy <strong>and</strong> did express touch<strong>in</strong>g faith that representative democracywould choose excellent leaders <strong>and</strong> adopt policies truly serv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> common<strong>in</strong>terest. Experience has taught us better, as <strong>the</strong> American Foundersalready knew when construct<strong>in</strong>g a government <strong>of</strong> separated <strong>and</strong> limitedpowers <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> only filtered democracy.As an exercise, <strong>and</strong> without claim<strong>in</strong>g that my arguments are decisive,I’ll contend that constitutional monarchy can better preserve people’s freedom<strong>and</strong> opportunities than democracy as it has turned out <strong>in</strong> practice. *From Liberty 18 ( January 2004): 37–42, where this article was titled “Monarchy:Friend <strong>of</strong> Liberty.” I do not know how to test my case econometrically. e control variables to be<strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> equations regress<strong>in</strong>g a measure <strong>of</strong> liberty or stability or prosperity or whateveron presence or absence <strong>of</strong> monarchy <strong>of</strong> some type or o<strong>the</strong>r are too <strong>in</strong>effable <strong>and</strong> too many.We would have to devise variables for such conditions as history <strong>and</strong> traditions, geography,climate, natural resources, type <strong>of</strong> economic system, past forms <strong>of</strong> government, ethnicity<strong>and</strong> ethnic homogeneity or diversity, education, religion, <strong>and</strong> so on. Plausible historicaldata po<strong>in</strong>ts are too few. Someone cleverer than I might devise some sort <strong>of</strong> econometrictest after all. Meanwhile, we must weigh <strong>the</strong> pros <strong>and</strong> cons <strong>of</strong> monarchy <strong>and</strong> democracyaga<strong>in</strong>st one ano<strong>the</strong>r qualitatively as best we can.375


376 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyMy case holds only for countries where ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g or restor<strong>in</strong>g (or conceivably<strong>in</strong>stall<strong>in</strong>g) monarchy is a live option. We Americans have sounderhope <strong>of</strong> reviv<strong>in</strong>g respect for <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> our Founders. Our traditionscould serve some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> functions <strong>of</strong> monarchy <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r countries.An unelected absolute ruler could conceivably be a thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>gclassical liberal. Although a wise, benevolent, <strong>and</strong> liberal-m<strong>in</strong>ded dictatorshipwould not be a contradiction <strong>in</strong> terms, no way is actually available toassure such a regime <strong>and</strong> its cont<strong>in</strong>uity, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g frictionless succession.Some element <strong>of</strong> democracy is <strong>the</strong>refore necessary; totally replac<strong>in</strong>git would be dangerous. Democracy allows people some <strong>in</strong>fluence on who<strong>the</strong>ir rulers are <strong>and</strong> what policies <strong>the</strong>y pursue. Elections, if not subverted,can oust bad rulers peacefully. Citizens who care about such th<strong>in</strong>gs canenjoy a sense <strong>of</strong> participation <strong>in</strong> public affairs.Anyone who believes <strong>in</strong> limit<strong>in</strong>g government power for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong>personal freedom should value also hav<strong>in</strong>g some nondemocratic element<strong>of</strong> government besides courts respectful <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own narrow authority.While some monarchists are reactionaries or mystics, o<strong>the</strong>rs (like Erikvon Kuehnelt-Leddihn <strong>and</strong> Sean Gabb, cited below) do come across asgenu<strong>in</strong>e classical liberals. Democracy has glar<strong>in</strong>g defects. As various paradoxes <strong>of</strong> vot<strong>in</strong>g illustrate,<strong>the</strong>re is no such th<strong>in</strong>g as any coherent “will <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> people.” Governmentitself is more likely to supply <strong>the</strong> content <strong>of</strong> any supposed general will(Constant 1814–1815/1988, p. 179). W<strong>in</strong>ston Churchill reputedly said: “ebest argument aga<strong>in</strong>st democracy is a five-m<strong>in</strong>ute conversation with <strong>the</strong>average voter” (Bra<strong>in</strong>yQuote <strong>and</strong> several similar sources on <strong>the</strong> Internet).e ord<strong>in</strong>ary voter knows that his vote will not be decisive <strong>and</strong> has littlereason to waste time <strong>and</strong> effort becom<strong>in</strong>g well <strong>in</strong>formed anyway.is “rational ignorance,” so called <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> public-choice literature,leaves correspond<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence to o<strong>the</strong>r-than-ord<strong>in</strong>ary voters (Campbell Monarchist organizations exist <strong>in</strong> surpris<strong>in</strong>gly many countries; a few <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir websites appear <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> References. Even Argent<strong>in</strong>a has a small monarchist movement,described <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> September 1994 issue <strong>of</strong> Monarchy at <strong>the</strong> site <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> International MonarchistLeague. Barry 2003 partially summarizes <strong>the</strong>m. Hayek 1979 describes <strong>the</strong> defects at length<strong>and</strong> proposes an elaborate reform <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> system <strong>of</strong> representation, not discuss<strong>in</strong>g monarchy.James Buchanan <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Public Choice school analyze democracy <strong>in</strong> many writ<strong>in</strong>gs.


Chapter : A Libertarian Case for Monarchy 3771999). Politics becomes a squabble among rival special <strong>in</strong>terests. Coalitionsform to ga<strong>in</strong> special privileges. Legislators engage <strong>in</strong> logroll<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>enact omnibus spend<strong>in</strong>g bills. Politics itself becomes <strong>the</strong> chief weapon <strong>in</strong>a Hobbesian war <strong>of</strong> all aga<strong>in</strong>st all (Gray 1993, pp. 211–212). e diffusion<strong>of</strong> costs while benefits are concentrated re<strong>in</strong>forces apathy among ord<strong>in</strong>aryvoters.Politicians <strong>the</strong>mselves count among <strong>the</strong> special <strong>in</strong>terest groups. Peoplewho drift <strong>in</strong>to politics tend to have relatively slighter qualificationsfor o<strong>the</strong>r work. ey are entrepreneurs pursu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> advantages <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>fice.ese are not material advantages alone, for some politicians seek powerto do good as <strong>the</strong>y underst<strong>and</strong> it. Gratify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir need to act <strong>and</strong> to feelimportant, legislators multiply laws to deal with discovered or contrivedproblems—<strong>and</strong> fears. Be<strong>in</strong>g able to raise vast sums by taxes <strong>and</strong> borrow<strong>in</strong>genhances <strong>the</strong>ir sense <strong>of</strong> power, <strong>and</strong> moral responsibility wanes (as Constant,1814–1815/1988, pp. 194–196, 271–272, already recognized almost twocenturies ago).Democratic politicians have notoriously short time horizons. (Hoppe2001 blames not just politicians <strong>in</strong> particular but democracy <strong>in</strong> general forhigh time preference—<strong>in</strong>difference to <strong>the</strong> long run—which contributesto crime, wasted lives, <strong>and</strong> a general decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> culture.)Why worry if popular policies will cause crises only when one is no longerrunn<strong>in</strong>g for reelection? Evidence <strong>of</strong> fiscal irresponsibility <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates <strong>in</strong>cludes chronic budget deficits, <strong>the</strong> explicit national debt, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>still huger excesses <strong>of</strong> future liabilities over future revenues on account<strong>of</strong> Medicare <strong>and</strong> Social Security. Yet politicians cont<strong>in</strong>ue <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g newplums. Conflict <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest like this far overshadows <strong>the</strong> petty k<strong>in</strong>ds thatnever<strong>the</strong>less arouse more outrage.Responsibility is diffused <strong>in</strong> democracy not only over time but alsoamong participants. Voters can th<strong>in</strong>k that <strong>the</strong>y are only exercis<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irright to mark <strong>the</strong>ir ballots, politicians that <strong>the</strong>y are only respond<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>wishes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir constituents. e <strong>in</strong>dividual legislator bears only a smallshare <strong>of</strong> responsibility fragmented among his colleagues <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r government<strong>of</strong>ficials.Democracy <strong>and</strong> liberty coexist <strong>in</strong> tension. Nowadays <strong>the</strong> United Statesgovernment restricts political speech. e pr<strong>of</strong>essed purpose <strong>of</strong> campaignf<strong>in</strong>ancereform is to limit <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest groups <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> money <strong>in</strong>politics, but <strong>in</strong>creased <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mass media <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>creased security<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>cumbent politicians are likelier results. A broader k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> tensionis that popular majorities can lend an air <strong>of</strong> legitimacy to highly


378 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyilliberal measures. “By <strong>the</strong> sheer weight <strong>of</strong> numbers <strong>and</strong> by its ubiquity<strong>the</strong> rule <strong>of</strong> 99 per cent is more ‘hermetic’ <strong>and</strong> more oppressive than <strong>the</strong>rule <strong>of</strong> 1 per cent” (Kuehnelt-Leddihn 1952, p. 88). When majority rule isthought good <strong>in</strong> its own right <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fiction prevails that “we” ord<strong>in</strong>arycitizens are <strong>the</strong> government, an elected legislature <strong>and</strong> executive can getaway with impositions that monarchs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past would scarcely have ventured.Louis XIV <strong>of</strong> France, autocrat though he was, would hardly havedared prohibit alcoholic beverages, conscript soldiers, <strong>and</strong> levy an <strong>in</strong>cometax (pp. 280–281)—or, we might add, wage war on drugs. Not only constitutionallimitations on a k<strong>in</strong>g’s powers but also his not hav<strong>in</strong>g an electoralm<strong>and</strong>ate is a restra<strong>in</strong>t.At its worst, <strong>the</strong> democratic dogma can abet totalitarianism. Historyrecords totalitarian democracies or democratically supported dictatorships.Countries oppressed by communist regimes <strong>in</strong>cluded words like “democratic”or “popular” <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>of</strong>ficial names. Totalitarian parties have portrayed<strong>the</strong>ir leaders as personify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> common man <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole nation.German National Socialism, as Kuehnelt-Leddihn rem<strong>in</strong>ds us, was nei<strong>the</strong>ra conservative nor a reactionary movement but a syn<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>of</strong> revolutionaryideas trac<strong>in</strong>g to before 1789 (Kuehnelt-Leddihn 1952, pp. 131,246–247, 268). He suggests that antimonarchical sentiments <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> background<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> French Revolution, <strong>the</strong> Spanish republic <strong>of</strong> 1931, <strong>and</strong> Germany’sWeimar Republic paved <strong>the</strong> way for Robespierre <strong>and</strong> Napoleon, forNegr<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Franco, <strong>and</strong> for Hitler (p. 90). W<strong>in</strong>ston Churchill reportedlyjudged that had <strong>the</strong> Kaiser rema<strong>in</strong>ed German Head <strong>of</strong> State, Hitler couldnot have ga<strong>in</strong>ed power, or at least not have kept it (International MonarchistLeague). “[M]onarchists, conservatives, clerics <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r ‘reactionaries’were always <strong>in</strong> bad grace with <strong>the</strong> Nazis” (p. 248). A nonelected part <strong>of</strong> government contributes to <strong>the</strong> separation <strong>of</strong> powers.By reta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g certa<strong>in</strong> constitutional powers or deny<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m to o<strong>the</strong>rs,it can be a safeguard aga<strong>in</strong>st abuses. is is perhaps <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> modernjustification <strong>of</strong> hereditary monarchy: to put some restra<strong>in</strong>t on politicians I hope that readers will allow me <strong>the</strong> stylistic convenience <strong>of</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g “k<strong>in</strong>g” to designatea reign<strong>in</strong>g queen also, as <strong>the</strong> word “kon<strong>in</strong>g” does <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Dutch constitution, <strong>and</strong> also <strong>of</strong>us<strong>in</strong>g “he” or “him” or “his” to cover “she” or “her” as context requires. “[T]he first <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dispensable condition for <strong>the</strong> exercise <strong>of</strong> responsibility is to separateexecutive power from supreme power. Constitutional monarchy atta<strong>in</strong>s this great


Chapter : A Libertarian Case for Monarchy 379ra<strong>the</strong>r than let <strong>the</strong>m pursue <strong>the</strong>ir own special <strong>in</strong>terests complacent <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> thought that <strong>the</strong>ir w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g elections demonstrates popular approval.When former president eodore Roosevelt visited Emperor Franz Joseph<strong>in</strong> 1910 <strong>and</strong> asked him what he thought <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> monarchy was <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>twentieth century, <strong>the</strong> emperor reportedly replied: “To protect my peoplesfrom <strong>the</strong>ir governments” (quoted <strong>in</strong> both “esen pro Monarchie”<strong>and</strong> Purcell 2003). Similarly, Lord Bernard Wea<strong>the</strong>rill, former speaker <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> House <strong>of</strong> Commons, said that <strong>the</strong> British monarchy exists not to exercisepower but to keep o<strong>the</strong>r people from hav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> power; it is a greatprotection for British democracy (<strong>in</strong>terview with Brian Lamb on C-Span,26 November 1999).e history <strong>of</strong> Engl<strong>and</strong> shows progressive limitation <strong>of</strong> royal power<strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> parliament; but, <strong>in</strong> my view, a welcome trend went too far.Almost all power, limited only by traditions fortunately cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g as anunwritten constitution, came to be concentrated not only <strong>in</strong> parliamentbut even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> leader <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> parliamentary majority. Democratizationwent ra<strong>the</strong>r too far, <strong>in</strong> my op<strong>in</strong>ion, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Cont<strong>in</strong>ental monarchies also.A monarch, not dependent on be<strong>in</strong>g elected <strong>and</strong> reelected, embodies cont<strong>in</strong>uity,as does <strong>the</strong> dynasty <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> biological process.Constitutional monarchy <strong>of</strong>fers us ... that neutral power so <strong>in</strong>dispensablefor all regular liberty. In a free country <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g is a be<strong>in</strong>g apart, superiorto differences <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion, hav<strong>in</strong>g no o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>terest than <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance<strong>of</strong> order <strong>and</strong> liberty. He can never return to <strong>the</strong> common condition, <strong>and</strong>is consequently <strong>in</strong>accessible to all <strong>the</strong> passions that such a condition generates,<strong>and</strong> to all those that <strong>the</strong> perspective <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g oneself once aga<strong>in</strong>with<strong>in</strong> it, necessarily creates <strong>in</strong> those agents who are <strong>in</strong>vested with temporarypower.It is a master stroke to create a neutral power that can term<strong>in</strong>atesome political danger by constitutional means (Constant 1814–1815/1988,pp. 186–187). In a settled monarchy—but no regime whatever can be guaranteedperpetual existence—<strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g need not worry about cl<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g topower. In a republic, “e very head <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> state, hav<strong>in</strong>g no title to his<strong>of</strong>fice save that which lies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> popular will, is forced to haggle <strong>and</strong> barga<strong>in</strong>like <strong>the</strong> lowliest <strong>of</strong>fice-seeker” (Mencken 1926, p. 181).aim. But this advantage would be lost if <strong>the</strong> two powers were confused” (Constant1814–1815/1988, p. 191).


380 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyDynastic cont<strong>in</strong>uity parallels <strong>the</strong> rule <strong>of</strong> law. e k<strong>in</strong>g symbolizes astate <strong>of</strong> affairs <strong>in</strong> which pr<strong>of</strong>ound political change, though eventually possible,cannot occur without ample time for consider<strong>in</strong>g it. e k<strong>in</strong>g st<strong>and</strong>s<strong>in</strong> contrast with legislators <strong>and</strong> bureaucrats, who are <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to th<strong>in</strong>k, by<strong>the</strong> very nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir jobs, that diligent performance means multiply<strong>in</strong>glaws <strong>and</strong> regulations. Cont<strong>in</strong>uity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> constitutional <strong>and</strong> legal regimeprovides a stable framework favorable to personal <strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess plann<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>and</strong> to <strong>in</strong>novation <strong>in</strong> science, technology, enterprise, <strong>and</strong>culture. Cont<strong>in</strong>uity is nei<strong>the</strong>r rigidity nor conservatism.e heir to <strong>the</strong> throne typically has many years <strong>of</strong> preparation <strong>and</strong> isnot dazzled by personal advancement when he f<strong>in</strong>ally <strong>in</strong>herits <strong>the</strong> <strong>of</strong>fice.Before <strong>and</strong> while hold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>fice he accumulates a fund <strong>of</strong> experience bothdifferent from <strong>and</strong> greater than what politicians, who come <strong>and</strong> go, canord<strong>in</strong>arily acquire. Even when <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g comes to <strong>the</strong> throne as a youth or,at <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r extreme, as an old man with only a few active years rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g,he has <strong>the</strong> counsel <strong>of</strong> experienced family members <strong>and</strong> advisers. If <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>gis very young (Louis XV, Alfonso XIII) or <strong>in</strong>sane (<strong>the</strong> elderly George III,Otto <strong>of</strong> Bavaria), a close relative serves as regent. e regent will havehad some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> opportunities to perform ceremonial functions <strong>and</strong> toaccumulate experience that an heir or reign<strong>in</strong>g monarch has. Some arguments occasionally employed for monarchy are questionable. If<strong>the</strong> monarch or his heir may marry only a member <strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>in</strong>cely family (asKuehnelt-Leddihn seems to recommend), chances are that he or she willmarry a foreigner, provid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ternational connections <strong>and</strong> a cosmopolitanway <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. Ano<strong>the</strong>r dubious argument (also used by Kuehnelt-Leddihn) is that <strong>the</strong> monarch will have <strong>the</strong> bless<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> perhaps be<strong>the</strong> head <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> state religion. Some arguments are downright absurd,for example: “Monarchy fosters art <strong>and</strong> culture. Austria was culturallymuch richer around 1780 than today! Just th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> Mozart!” (“esen proMonarchie”). Otto von Habsburg blames <strong>the</strong> risk that an <strong>in</strong>competent might occupy <strong>the</strong> throne onan <strong>in</strong>flexible legitimism—preoccupation with a particular dynasty—that displaced safeguardsfound <strong>in</strong> most classical monarchies. He recommends that <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g be assistedby a body represent<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> highest judicial authority, a body that could if necessaryreplace <strong>the</strong> heir presumptive by <strong>the</strong> next <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> succession (1958/1970, pp. 262, 264,266–267).


Chapter : A Libertarian Case for Monarchy 381But nei<strong>the</strong>r all arguments for nor all objections to monarchy are fallacious.e same is true <strong>of</strong> democracy. In <strong>the</strong> choice <strong>of</strong> political <strong>in</strong>stitutions,as <strong>in</strong> many decisions <strong>of</strong> life, all one can do is weigh <strong>the</strong> pros <strong>and</strong> cons <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> options <strong>and</strong> choose what seems best or least bad on balance.Some objections to monarchy apply to democracy also or o<strong>the</strong>rwise<strong>in</strong>vite comments that, while not actual refutations, do streng<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> case<strong>in</strong> its favor. Monarchy is charged with be<strong>in</strong>g government-from-above(Kuehnelt-Leddihn 1952, p. 276). But all governments, even popularlyelected ones, except perhaps small direct democracies like ancient A<strong>the</strong>ns,are ruled by a m<strong>in</strong>ority. (Robert Michels <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs recognized an “ironlaw <strong>of</strong> oligarchy”; Jenk<strong>in</strong> 1968, p. 282.) Although democracy allows <strong>the</strong>people some <strong>in</strong>fluence over <strong>the</strong> government, <strong>the</strong>y do not <strong>and</strong> cannot actuallyrun it. Constitutional monarchy comb<strong>in</strong>es some strengths <strong>of</strong> democracy<strong>and</strong> authoritarian monarchy while partially neutraliz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> defects<strong>of</strong> those polar options.Ano<strong>the</strong>r objection condemns monarchy as a divisive symbol <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>equality;it bars “an ideal society <strong>in</strong> which everyone will be equal <strong>in</strong> status, <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong> which everyone will have <strong>the</strong> right, if not <strong>the</strong> ability, to rise to <strong>the</strong> highestposition” (Gabb 2002, who replies that attempts to create such a societyhave usually ended <strong>in</strong> attacks on <strong>the</strong> wealthy <strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong> well-<strong>of</strong>f ).Michael Prowse (2001), call<strong>in</strong>g for periodic referendums on whe<strong>the</strong>r tokeep <strong>the</strong> British monarchy, <strong>in</strong>vokes what he considers <strong>the</strong> core idea <strong>of</strong>democracy: all persons equally deserve respect <strong>and</strong> consideration, <strong>and</strong> noone deserves to dom<strong>in</strong>ate o<strong>the</strong>rs. e royal family <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> aristocracy, with<strong>the</strong>ir titles, demeanor, <strong>and</strong> self-perpetuation, violate this democratic spirit.In a republican Brita<strong>in</strong>, every child might aspire to every public position,even head <strong>of</strong> state.So argu<strong>in</strong>g, Prowse stretches <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> democracy from a particularmethod <strong>of</strong> choos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>g rulers to <strong>in</strong>clude an egalitariansocial ethos. But monarchy need not obstruct easy relations amongpersons <strong>of</strong> different occupations <strong>and</strong> backgrounds; a suspicious egalitarianismis likelier to do that. In no society can all persons have <strong>the</strong> samestatus. A more realistic goal is that everyone have a chance to achieve dist<strong>in</strong>ction<strong>in</strong> some narrow niche important to him. Even <strong>in</strong> a republic, mostpeople by far cannot realistically aspire to <strong>the</strong> highest position. No oneneed feel humbled or ashamed at not ascend<strong>in</strong>g to an <strong>of</strong>fice that simplywas not available. A hereditary monarch can be like “<strong>the</strong> Alps” (“esenpro Monarchie”), someth<strong>in</strong>g just “<strong>the</strong>re.” Perhaps it is <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g’s goodluck, perhaps his bad luck, to have <strong>in</strong>herited <strong>the</strong> privileges but also <strong>the</strong>


382 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophylimitations <strong>of</strong> his <strong>of</strong>fice; but any question <strong>of</strong> unfairness pales <strong>in</strong> comparisonwith advantages for <strong>the</strong> country.Prowse compla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> divisiveness. But what about an election? It produceslosers as well as w<strong>in</strong>ners, disappo<strong>in</strong>ted voters as well as happy ones.A k<strong>in</strong>g, however, cannot symbolize defeat to supporters <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r c<strong>and</strong>idates,for <strong>the</strong>re were none. “A monarch mount<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> throne <strong>of</strong> his ancestorsfollows a path on which he has not embarked <strong>of</strong> his own will.” Unlikea usurper, he need not justify his elevation (Constant 1814–1815/1988, p. 88).He has no fur<strong>the</strong>r political opportunities or ambitions except to do his jobwell <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> good name <strong>of</strong> his dynasty. St<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g neutral aboveparty politics, he has a better chance than an elected leader <strong>of</strong> becom<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> personified symbol <strong>of</strong> his country, a focus <strong>of</strong> patriotism <strong>and</strong> even <strong>of</strong>affection.e monarch <strong>and</strong> his family can assume ceremonial functions thatelected rulers would o<strong>the</strong>rwise perform as time permitted. Separat<strong>in</strong>g ceremonialfunctions from campaign<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> policymak<strong>in</strong>g siphons <strong>of</strong>f glamoror adulation that would o<strong>the</strong>rwise accrue to politicians <strong>and</strong> especially todemagogues. e occasional Hitler does arouse popular enthusiasm, <strong>and</strong>his opponents must prudently keep a low pr<strong>of</strong>ile. A monarch, whose poweris preservative ra<strong>the</strong>r than active (pp. 191–192), is safer for people’s freedom.Prowse is irritated ra<strong>the</strong>r than impressed by <strong>the</strong> pomp <strong>and</strong> opulencesurround<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Queen. Cl<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g to outmoded forms <strong>and</strong> ascrib<strong>in</strong>g importanceto unimportant th<strong>in</strong>gs reeks <strong>of</strong> “collective bad faith” <strong>and</strong> “corrosivehypocrisy.” Yet a monarchy need not rest on pretense. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, mycase for monarchy is a utilitarian one, not appeal<strong>in</strong>g to div<strong>in</strong>e right or anysuch fiction. Not all ritual is to be scorned. Even republics have Fourth <strong>of</strong>July parades <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir counterparts. Ceremonial trapp<strong>in</strong>gs that may havebecome functionless or comical can evolve or be reformed. Not all monarchies,as Prowse recognizes, share with <strong>the</strong> British <strong>the</strong> particular trapp<strong>in</strong>gsthat irritate him.A case, admittedly <strong>in</strong>conclusive, can be made for titles <strong>of</strong> nobility(especially for close royal relatives) <strong>and</strong> for an upper house <strong>of</strong> parliament <strong>of</strong>limited powers whose members, or some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, hold <strong>the</strong>ir seats by <strong>in</strong>heritanceor royal appo<strong>in</strong>tment (e.g., Constant 1814–1815/1988, pp. 198–200).“e glory <strong>of</strong> a legitimate monarch is enhanced by <strong>the</strong> glory <strong>of</strong> thosearound him.... He has no competition to fear.... But where <strong>the</strong> monarchsees supporters, <strong>the</strong> usurper sees enemies” (p. 91; on <strong>the</strong> precarious position<strong>of</strong> a nonhereditary autocrat, compare Tullock 1987). As long as <strong>the</strong>nobles are not exempt from <strong>the</strong> laws, <strong>the</strong>y can serve as a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> framework


Chapter : A Libertarian Case for Monarchy 383<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> monarchy. ey can be a fur<strong>the</strong>r element <strong>of</strong> diversity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> socialstructure. ey can provide an alternative to sheer wealth or notoriety as asource <strong>of</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>and</strong> so dilute <strong>the</strong> fawn<strong>in</strong>g over celebrities characteristic<strong>of</strong> modern democracies. Ord<strong>in</strong>ary persons need no more feel humiliatedby not be<strong>in</strong>g born <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> nobility than by not be<strong>in</strong>g born heir to<strong>the</strong> throne. On balance, though, I am ambivalent about a nobility. ’ Michael Prowse’s compla<strong>in</strong>t about <strong>the</strong> pretended importance <strong>of</strong> unimportantth<strong>in</strong>gs suggests a fur<strong>the</strong>r reason why <strong>the</strong> monarch’s role shouldgo beyond <strong>the</strong> purely symbolic <strong>and</strong> ceremonial. e k<strong>in</strong>g should not berequired (as <strong>the</strong> Queen <strong>of</strong> Engl<strong>and</strong> is required at <strong>the</strong> open<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> parliament)merely to read words written by <strong>the</strong> cab<strong>in</strong>et. At least he shouldhave <strong>the</strong> three rights that Walter Bagehot identified <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> British monarchy:“<strong>the</strong> right to be consulted, <strong>the</strong> right to encourage, <strong>the</strong> right to warn.And a k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> great sense <strong>and</strong> sagacity would want no o<strong>the</strong>rs. He wouldf<strong>in</strong>d that his hav<strong>in</strong>g no o<strong>the</strong>rs would enable him to use <strong>the</strong>se with s<strong>in</strong>gulareffect” (Bagehot 1867/1966, p. 111).When Bagehot wrote, <strong>the</strong> Prime M<strong>in</strong>ister was bound to keep <strong>the</strong>Queen well <strong>in</strong>formed about <strong>the</strong> pass<strong>in</strong>g politics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nation. “She hasby rigid usage a right to compla<strong>in</strong> if she does not know <strong>of</strong> every great act<strong>of</strong> her M<strong>in</strong>istry, not only before it is done, but while <strong>the</strong>re is yet time toconsider it—while it is still possible that it may not be done.”A sagacious k<strong>in</strong>g could warn his prime m<strong>in</strong>ister with possibly greateffect. “He might not always turn his course, but he would always troublehis m<strong>in</strong>d.” Dur<strong>in</strong>g a long reign he would acquire experience that few <strong>of</strong>his m<strong>in</strong>isters could match. He could rem<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> prime m<strong>in</strong>ister <strong>of</strong> badresults some years earlier <strong>of</strong> a policy like one currently proposed. “e k<strong>in</strong>gwould <strong>in</strong>deed have <strong>the</strong> advantage which a permanent under-secretary hasover his superior <strong>the</strong> Parliamentary secretary—that <strong>of</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g shared <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous Parliamentary secretaries.... A pompous maneasily sweeps away <strong>the</strong> suggestions <strong>of</strong> those beneath him. But though am<strong>in</strong>ister may so deal with his subord<strong>in</strong>ate, he cannot so deal with his k<strong>in</strong>g”(Bagehot 1867/1966, pp. 111–112). A prime m<strong>in</strong>ister would be discipl<strong>in</strong>ed,<strong>in</strong> short, by hav<strong>in</strong>g to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> objective (not merely <strong>the</strong> political) merits<strong>of</strong> his policies to a neutral authority.e three rights that Bagehot listed should be <strong>in</strong>terpreted broadly,<strong>in</strong> my view, or extended. Constant (1814–1815/1988, p. 301) recommends


384 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>the</strong> right to grant pardons as a f<strong>in</strong>al protection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>nocent. e k<strong>in</strong>gshould also have power: to make some appo<strong>in</strong>tments, especially <strong>of</strong> hisown staff, not subject to veto by politicians; to consult with politicians<strong>of</strong> all parties to resolve an impasse over who might obta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> support oracquiescence <strong>of</strong> a parliamentary majority; <strong>and</strong> to dismiss <strong>and</strong> temporarilyreplace <strong>the</strong> cab<strong>in</strong>et or prime m<strong>in</strong>ister <strong>in</strong> extreme cases. (I assume aparliamentary system, which usually does accompany modern monarchy;but <strong>the</strong> executive could be elected separately from <strong>the</strong> legislators <strong>and</strong> evensubject to recall by special election.) Even dissolv<strong>in</strong>g parliament <strong>and</strong> call<strong>in</strong>gnew elections <strong>in</strong> an exceptional case is no <strong>in</strong>sult to <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>people. “On <strong>the</strong> contrary, when elections are free, it is an appeal madeto <strong>the</strong>ir rights <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>terests” (p. 197). e k<strong>in</strong>g should try torally national support <strong>in</strong> a constitutional crisis (as when K<strong>in</strong>g Juan Carlos<strong>in</strong>tervened to foil an attempted military coup <strong>in</strong> 1981). What if <strong>the</strong> hereditary monarch is a child or is <strong>in</strong>competent? en, asalready mentioned, a regency is available. What if <strong>the</strong> royal family, likesome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> W<strong>in</strong>dsors, flaunts unedify<strong>in</strong>g personal behavior? Both dangersare just as real <strong>in</strong> a modern republic. Politicians have a systematictendency to be <strong>in</strong>competent or worse. For a democratic politician,underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g economics is a h<strong>and</strong>icap. He ei<strong>the</strong>r must take unpopular(because misunderstood) st<strong>and</strong>s on issues or else speak <strong>and</strong> act dishonestly.e economically ignorant politician has <strong>the</strong> advantage <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gable to take vote-catch<strong>in</strong>g st<strong>and</strong>s with a more nearly clear conscience.Particularly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se days <strong>of</strong> television <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> fasc<strong>in</strong>ation with celebrities,<strong>the</strong> personal characteristics necessary to w<strong>in</strong> elections are quite differentfrom those <strong>of</strong> a public-spirited statesman. History does record greatstatesmen <strong>in</strong> less democratized parliamentary regimes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past. Nowadaysa Gresham’s Law operates: “<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ferior human currency drives <strong>the</strong>better one out <strong>of</strong> circulation” (Kuehnelt-Leddihn, pp. 115, 120). Ideal Consider <strong>the</strong> one Republican <strong>and</strong> n<strong>in</strong>e Democrats currently (October 2003) compet<strong>in</strong>gfor <strong>the</strong> U.S. presidency. e day after <strong>the</strong> televised debate among <strong>the</strong> Democrats <strong>in</strong>Detroit, Roger Hitchcock, substitute host on a radio talk show, asked: “Would you liketo have d<strong>in</strong>ner with any <strong>of</strong> those people? Would you hire any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m to manage yourconvenience store?” “e first lesson <strong>of</strong> economics is scarcity: ere is never enough <strong>of</strong> anyth<strong>in</strong>g to satisfyall those who want it. e first lesson <strong>of</strong> politics is to disregard <strong>the</strong> first lesson <strong>of</strong> economics”(Sowell 1994).


Chapter : A Libertarian Case for Monarchy 385democratic government simply is not an available option. Our best hopeis to limit <strong>the</strong> activities <strong>of</strong> government, a purpose to which monarchy cancontribute.Although some contemporary politicians are honorable <strong>and</strong> economicallyliterate, even simple honesty can worsens one’s electoral chances.H.L. Mencken wrote acidly <strong>and</strong> with characteristic exaggeration: “Noeducated man, stat<strong>in</strong>g pla<strong>in</strong>ly <strong>the</strong> elementary notions that every educatedman holds about <strong>the</strong> matters that pr<strong>in</strong>cipally concern government, couldbe elected to <strong>of</strong>fice <strong>in</strong> a democratic state, save perhaps by a miracle.... Ithas become a psychic impossibility for a gentleman to hold <strong>of</strong>fice under<strong>the</strong> Federal Union, save by a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> miracles that must tax <strong>the</strong>resourcefulness even <strong>of</strong> God.... [T]he man <strong>of</strong> native <strong>in</strong>tegrity is ei<strong>the</strong>rbarred from <strong>the</strong> public service altoge<strong>the</strong>r, or subjected to almost irresistibletemptations after he gets <strong>in</strong>” (Mencken 1926, pp. 103, 106, 110). Undermonarchy, <strong>the</strong> courtier need not “abase himself before sw<strong>in</strong>e,” “pretendthat he is a worse man than he really is.” His sovereign has a certa<strong>in</strong> respectfor honor. “e courtier’s sovereign ... is apt to be a man <strong>of</strong> honour himself” (Mencken 1926, p. 118, mention<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Prussia refused<strong>the</strong> German imperial crown <strong>of</strong>fered him <strong>in</strong> 1849 by a mere popular parliamentra<strong>the</strong>r than by his fellow sovereign pr<strong>in</strong>ces).Mencken conceded that democracy has its charms: “e fraud <strong>of</strong> democracy... is more amus<strong>in</strong>g than any o<strong>the</strong>r—more amus<strong>in</strong>g even, <strong>and</strong> bymiles, than <strong>the</strong> fraud <strong>of</strong> religion.... [e farce] greatly delights me. I enjoydemocracy immensely. It is <strong>in</strong>comparably idiotic, <strong>and</strong> hence <strong>in</strong>comparablyamus<strong>in</strong>g” (pp. 209, 211).One argument aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>in</strong>stitutions with a venerable history is a m<strong>in</strong>dlessslogan betray<strong>in</strong>g temporal prov<strong>in</strong>cialism, as if newer necessarily meantbetter: “Don’t turn back <strong>the</strong> clock.” Sounder advice is not to overthrowwhat exists because <strong>of</strong> abstract notions <strong>of</strong> what might seem logically orideologically neater. In <strong>the</strong> vernacular, “If it a<strong>in</strong>’t broke, don’t fix it.” It isprogress to learn from experience, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g experience with <strong>in</strong>adequatelyfiltered democracy. Where a monarchical element <strong>in</strong> government workswell enough, <strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> lies aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> republicans (cf. Gabb2002). Kuehnelt-Leddihn, writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> 1952 (p. 104), noted that “<strong>the</strong> royal,non-democratic alloy” has supported <strong>the</strong> relative success <strong>of</strong> several representativegovernments <strong>in</strong> Europe. Only a few nontotalitarian republics


386 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>the</strong>re <strong>and</strong> overseas have exhibited a record <strong>of</strong> stability, notably Switzerl<strong>and</strong>,F<strong>in</strong>l<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States. Constitutional monarchy cannot solve all problems <strong>of</strong> government;noth<strong>in</strong>g can. But it can help. Besides lesser arguments, two ma<strong>in</strong> ones recommendit. First, its very existence is a rem<strong>in</strong>der that democracy is not <strong>the</strong>sort <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> which more is necessarily better; it can help promote balancedth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. Second, by contribut<strong>in</strong>g cont<strong>in</strong>uity, dilut<strong>in</strong>g democracywhile support<strong>in</strong>g a healthy element <strong>of</strong> it, <strong>and</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> separation <strong>of</strong>government powers, monarchy can help protect personal liberty.Bagehot, Walter. e English Constitution. 1867, 1872. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell Paperbacks,1966.Barry, Norman. “What’s So Good About Democracy?” Ideas on Liberty 53 (May2003): 44–48.Campbell, Col<strong>in</strong> M. “Large Electorates <strong>and</strong> Decisive M<strong>in</strong>orities.” Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong><strong>Economy</strong> 107 (December 1999): 1199–1217.Constant, Benjam<strong>in</strong>. <strong>Political</strong> Writ<strong>in</strong>gs. 1814–1815. Translated <strong>and</strong> edited by BiancamariaFontana. Cambridge, U.K., <strong>and</strong> New York: Cambridge UniversityPress, 1988.Gabb, Sean. “In Defence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Monarchy.” Free Life Commentary, no. 83(9 December 2002). http://www.seangabb.co.uk/flcomm/flc083.htm.Gray, John. Post-Liberalism: Studies <strong>in</strong> <strong>Political</strong> ought. London <strong>and</strong> New York:Routledge, 1993.Habsburg, Otto von. “Monarchy or Republic.” 1958. In e Conservative Tradition<strong>in</strong> European ought, edited by Robert Schuett<strong>in</strong>ger, 258–267. New York:Putnam, 1970.Hayek, F.A. e <strong>Political</strong> Order <strong>of</strong> a Free People. Vol. 3 <strong>of</strong> Law, Legislation <strong>and</strong>Liberty. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1979.Hoppe, Hans-Hermann. Democracy: e God at Failed. New Brunswick, N.J.:Transaction Publishers, 2001. Compare Lewis <strong>and</strong> Woolsey 2003: “[O]f <strong>the</strong> nations that have been democraciesfor a very long time <strong>and</strong> show every sign that <strong>the</strong>y will rema<strong>in</strong> so, a substantial majorityare constitutional monarchies (<strong>the</strong> U.S. <strong>and</strong> Switzerl<strong>and</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>cipal exceptions).”


Chapter : A Libertarian Case for Monarchy 387International Monarchist League. “e Case for Monarchy.”Jenk<strong>in</strong>, omas P. “Oligarchy.” In International Encyclopedia <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Social Sciences,edited by David L. Sills, vol. 11: 281–283. New York: Macmillan <strong>and</strong> FreePress, 1968.Kuehnelt-Leddihn, Erik von. Liberty or Equality. Edited by John P. Hughes.London: Hollis & Carter, 1952. http://www.scribd.com/doc/3917515/KuehneltLeddihn-Liberty-or-Equality.Lewis, Bernard, <strong>and</strong> R. James Woolsey. “K<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Country.” Wall Street Journal,29 October 2003.Mencken, H.L. Notes on Democracy. New York: Knopf, 1926.Mises, Ludwig von. Nation, State, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>. 1919. New York: New York UniversityPress, 1983.Pa<strong>in</strong>e, omas. e Rights <strong>of</strong> Man. Part First, 1791, <strong>and</strong> Part Second, 1792. InTwo Classics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> French Revolution: Edmund Burke’s Reflections on <strong>the</strong> Revolution<strong>in</strong> France <strong>and</strong> Pa<strong>in</strong>e’s e Rights <strong>of</strong> Man, pp. 267–515. New York:Doubleday, Anchor Books, 1973, 1989.Prowse, Michael. “Why Brita<strong>in</strong> Should Hold ‘Royal Referendums’.” F<strong>in</strong>ancialTimes, 21–22 April 2001.Purcell, Frank. “All Hail <strong>the</strong> House <strong>of</strong> Habsburg!” Live Journal, 18 August 2003.http://arisbe.livejournal.com/42592.html.Schumpeter, Joseph A. Capitalism, Socialism, <strong>and</strong> Democracy. 1950. 3 ed. NewYork: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1962.Sowell, omas. Quoted (without <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> source) <strong>in</strong> “Endnotes.” CEIUpDate 7 ( July 1994): 8.“esen pro Monarchie.” http://rasput<strong>in</strong>.de/Monarch/<strong>the</strong>sen.html. Traditionund Leben e.V. http://www.pro-monarchie.de/Tullock, Gordon. Autocracy. Dordrecht <strong>and</strong> Boston: Kluwer, 1987.


Uchronia, or AlternativeHistory *e history that didn’t happen can be just as <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>the</strong> history thatdid.is article is a small example <strong>of</strong> its own topic. Except by chance, Iwouldn’t now be writ<strong>in</strong>g it. Not f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g what I wanted while brows<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>our library’s magaz<strong>in</strong>e aisles, I came across mention <strong>of</strong> “uchronie” <strong>in</strong> LeNouvel Observateur. e philosopher Charles Renouvier chose this wordas <strong>the</strong> title <strong>of</strong> his novel <strong>of</strong> 1857 <strong>and</strong> 1876; he co<strong>in</strong>ed it from Greek rootsmean<strong>in</strong>g “no-time.” He was follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> pattern set by St. omas More,whose Utopia derives from roots mean<strong>in</strong>g “no-place.” Utopia is a place thatdoes not exist; uchronia is a time that did not exist. Uchronian works—to<strong>in</strong>troduce <strong>the</strong> English adjective—are also called “what-if,” alternative, conjectural,or counterfactual history. ey consider what would have happenedif someth<strong>in</strong>g else had chanced to happen.Such works fall <strong>in</strong>to two categories. e dist<strong>in</strong>ction is fuzzy but useful.Writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first k<strong>in</strong>d, unlike actual history or a st<strong>and</strong>ard historicalnovel, are sheer fiction. ey are not speculations about real events; <strong>the</strong>yare stories that st<strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong>ir own. e Star Wars movies <strong>and</strong> Tolkien’stales are good examples. Ano<strong>the</strong>r is <strong>Is</strong>l<strong>and</strong>ia, a novel by Aust<strong>in</strong> TappanWright, published posthumously <strong>in</strong> 1942. Wright describes events <strong>and</strong>personalities <strong>in</strong> a country on a fictional cont<strong>in</strong>ent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sou<strong>the</strong>rn hemispherebefore World War I. e people <strong>of</strong> <strong>Is</strong>l<strong>and</strong>ia, while highly civilized<strong>and</strong> advanced <strong>in</strong> philosophy <strong>and</strong> psychology, prefer <strong>the</strong>ir old ways, reject<strong>in</strong>grailroads <strong>and</strong> most o<strong>the</strong>r modern technology <strong>and</strong> narrowly limit<strong>in</strong>gcontact with <strong>the</strong> outside world. e reader (this one, anyway) drifts with<strong>the</strong> author <strong>in</strong>to sympathy with <strong>the</strong> <strong>Is</strong>l<strong>and</strong>ian way <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g.*From Liberty 23 (September 2009): 31–34. I thank <strong>the</strong> editor, Stephen Cox, for suggestions<strong>and</strong> some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word<strong>in</strong>g.388


Chapter : Uchronia, or Alternative History 389Edward Bellamy’s Look<strong>in</strong>g Backward (1887) projects an opposite vision,one <strong>in</strong>tended as backward only <strong>in</strong> an ironic sense; it imag<strong>in</strong>es a prosperous<strong>and</strong> happy socialist utopia <strong>of</strong> 2000. is uchronia actually exerted some<strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>in</strong> its time, convert<strong>in</strong>g many readers to socialism because <strong>the</strong>ywanted to live <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world <strong>of</strong> Bellamy’s vision. A less satisfy<strong>in</strong>g example <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> first category <strong>of</strong> uchronian works is Hadrian VII (1904), a ra<strong>the</strong>r amateurishfantasy by Frederick Rolfe, <strong>the</strong> self-appo<strong>in</strong>ted Baron Corvo. Itshero is a frustrated would-be priest whom a deadlocked College <strong>of</strong> Card<strong>in</strong>alsimplausibly elects as pope, <strong>the</strong> second English pope <strong>in</strong> history. PopeHadrian radiates his benevolence right up to World War I or, ra<strong>the</strong>r, toits avoidance. His m<strong>in</strong>istrations successfully adjust <strong>the</strong> world’s importantpolitical conflicts. is story also had real-world effects. e oddness <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> book <strong>and</strong> its author <strong>in</strong>spired a famous work <strong>of</strong> literary detection, eQuest for Corvo (1934), <strong>in</strong> which A.J.A. Symons discovered how strange<strong>the</strong> “Baron” actually was.e second (<strong>and</strong> my preferred) category <strong>of</strong> uchronian literature is morestrictly what-if history. It concerns actual events or circumstances thatmight plausibly have been different. If: Or History Rewritten, edited byJ.C. Squire (1931), samples <strong>the</strong> genre with stories by many writers. PhillipGuedalla supposes that <strong>the</strong> Christian Reconquista <strong>of</strong> Spa<strong>in</strong> had somehownot gone far enough to absorb <strong>the</strong> Moorish K<strong>in</strong>gdom <strong>of</strong> Grenada, leav<strong>in</strong>git a power <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational affairs <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> twentieth century <strong>and</strong> presumablybeyond. Hendrik Willem van Loon supposes that <strong>the</strong> Dutch hadreta<strong>in</strong>ed Nieuw Amsterdam until, by a treaty with a curiously libertarianprovision, it jo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> United States <strong>in</strong> 1841. André Maurois supposesthat Louis XVI had been firm enough to keep Turgot, his liberaliz<strong>in</strong>gf<strong>in</strong>ance m<strong>in</strong>ister, until <strong>and</strong> beyond 1789 (when <strong>the</strong> French Revolutionbegan, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> real world), <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> dismiss<strong>in</strong>g him <strong>in</strong> 1776. Hillaire Bellocsupposes that <strong>the</strong> cart that blocked Louis’s path when he tried to fleefrom France <strong>in</strong> 1791 had gotten stuck before reach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> crucial spotat Varennes. Emil Ludwig asks what if German Emperor Frederick III,liberal-m<strong>in</strong>ded <strong>and</strong> married to a daughter <strong>of</strong> Queen Victoria, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong>dy<strong>in</strong>g after only n<strong>in</strong>ety-n<strong>in</strong>e days on <strong>the</strong> throne <strong>in</strong> 1888, had survived<strong>and</strong> exerted his moderat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence until 1914. W<strong>in</strong>ston Churchill, <strong>in</strong>a double twist, writes as a historian <strong>in</strong> a world <strong>in</strong> which Lee had actuallywon <strong>the</strong> battle <strong>of</strong> Gettysburg <strong>and</strong> who speculates about his not hav<strong>in</strong>gwon. Milton Waldman supposes that Booth’s shot missed L<strong>in</strong>coln.G.K. Chesterton imag<strong>in</strong>es Don John <strong>of</strong> Austria married to Mary Queen<strong>of</strong> Scots; Harold Nicholson, Byron enthroned as K<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Greece; <strong>and</strong>


390 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyH.A.L. Fisher, Napoleon escaped to America <strong>and</strong> become a prosperousplanter. Squire, <strong>the</strong> editor, postulates discovery <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> that Lord Baconwrote Shakespeare’s works.Such speculation need not be frivolity. Contrasts with what really happenedcan deepen our underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> actual history <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong>economics, psychology, political science, <strong>in</strong>ternational relations, militaryaffairs, <strong>the</strong>ology, medic<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> even natural science as applied by decisionmakers<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past. History for us was <strong>the</strong> unknown future for <strong>the</strong>m.And each <strong>of</strong> us has undoubtedly experienced choices <strong>in</strong> his own life verydifferently from <strong>the</strong> way <strong>in</strong> which a biographer would describe <strong>the</strong>m. Hewould know <strong>the</strong> results; we didn’t.One subcategory <strong>of</strong> conjectural history doesn’t much appeal to me.Like Guedalla’s Grenada scenario, it speculates about major trends orconditions that turned out different from <strong>the</strong> actual ones. What if <strong>the</strong>d<strong>in</strong>osaurs or <strong>the</strong> Roman Empire hadn’t disappeared? What if Europehad never discovered America? So sweep<strong>in</strong>g a conjecture is unsatisfy<strong>in</strong>gbecause it focuses on general frameworks <strong>of</strong> history <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> particularevents, ones that may have seemed unimportant <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves but hadmajor consequences. ( Just what might have enabled Grenada to survive<strong>the</strong> Reconquista?) Likewise, it seems out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> spirit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genre touse some event or nonevent as a take-<strong>of</strong>f po<strong>in</strong>t for sheer fiction, as aboutNapoleon’s imag<strong>in</strong>ary exploits <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> New World.Divergences between what did happen <strong>and</strong> what might have happenedsometimes trigger momentous dom<strong>in</strong>o or butterfly effects. Severalmay particularly <strong>in</strong>terest libertarians. What if <strong>the</strong> Civil War had beenavoided, <strong>and</strong> with it <strong>the</strong> federal government’s dom<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> monetarysystem? What if <strong>the</strong> Federal Reserve System had never been created?What if Chancellor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Exchequer W<strong>in</strong>ston Churchill had heededwarn<strong>in</strong>gs aga<strong>in</strong>st return<strong>in</strong>g Great Brita<strong>in</strong> to <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>in</strong> 1925at <strong>the</strong> no longer viable prewar parity? What if (as Milton Friedman <strong>and</strong>Anna Schwartz have speculated) Benjam<strong>in</strong> Strong, Governor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> FederalReserve Bank <strong>of</strong> New York, dom<strong>in</strong>ant figure <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Federal ReserveSystem, <strong>and</strong> a better <strong>in</strong>tuitive economist than most <strong>of</strong> his colleagues, hadnot died prematurely <strong>in</strong> 1928? What if Harry Gunnison Brown or Irv<strong>in</strong>gFisher had headed <strong>the</strong> System, or if his advice had prevailed around 1929?Would an ord<strong>in</strong>ary recession have turned <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> Great Depression, creat<strong>in</strong>gopportunities both for <strong>the</strong> New Deal <strong>and</strong> for Hitler? I th<strong>in</strong>k not.But we can carry speculations fur<strong>the</strong>r. What if Giuseppe Zangara’sshot at President-elect Roosevelt <strong>in</strong> February 1933 hadn’t killed Chicago’s


Chapter : Uchronia, or Alternative History 391Mayor Cermak <strong>in</strong>stead? What if <strong>the</strong> United States hadn’t adopted <strong>the</strong>silver-purchase program <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1930s, which benefited domestic silver<strong>in</strong>terests but ru<strong>in</strong>ed Ch<strong>in</strong>a’s monetary system <strong>and</strong> thus improved <strong>the</strong>chances <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Communists? What if von Papen <strong>and</strong> his associates, early<strong>in</strong> 1933, had not expected to manage Hitler <strong>and</strong> make him a safe choicefor Chancellor? What if Hitler had decided to f<strong>in</strong>ish <strong>of</strong>f Engl<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>1940–1941 before tackl<strong>in</strong>g Russia? What if FDR, seriously ill, had diedbefore <strong>the</strong> Yalta conference <strong>of</strong> February 1945—or earlier, while HenryWallace was still vice president? What if Hitler had died <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> nearly successfulattempt to assass<strong>in</strong>ate him <strong>in</strong> 1944? What if Lee Harvey Oswaldhad proved a poor marksman at Dallas <strong>in</strong> 1963? How would Gerald Ford<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> country have fared if he had not pardoned Richard Nixon? Orwhat would Nixon’s refusal <strong>of</strong> a pardon have meant? What if <strong>the</strong> tightvote <strong>in</strong> Florida <strong>in</strong> 2000 had gone <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way, as it might well havegone, were it not for hang<strong>in</strong>g chads, misaligned ballots, <strong>and</strong> accidentalvotes for Pat Buchanan? A Gore adm<strong>in</strong>istration would have been a disaster,but <strong>of</strong> a different sort from <strong>the</strong> disaster Bush brought us. And wouldtoday’s f<strong>in</strong>ancial crisis be less or more severe if <strong>the</strong> rescue <strong>of</strong> Long-TermCapital Management, orchestrated by <strong>the</strong> Federal Reserve <strong>in</strong> 1998, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>stitutions before <strong>and</strong> later hadn’t worsened <strong>the</strong> dilemma <strong>of</strong> moralhazard?Sure, history has its determ<strong>in</strong>istic aspects; Marx stressed technology.But <strong>the</strong> possibilities <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> many junctures <strong>of</strong> history discredit overemphasison determ<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> underl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> element <strong>of</strong> chance. Supposethat Pontius Pilate had saved Jesus Christ, forestall<strong>in</strong>g his crucifixion <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> resurrection story. Would Jesus still have become <strong>the</strong> focus <strong>of</strong> a religiondom<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g, for good <strong>and</strong> ill, most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Western world? Or wouldhe have rema<strong>in</strong>ed an it<strong>in</strong>erant preacher scarcely mentioned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> history<strong>of</strong> religion? Would one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mystery religions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Eastern Mediterraneanhave become dom<strong>in</strong>ant <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> Christianity?Consider an episode <strong>of</strong> British history. Queen Anne had 18 children,more or less, count<strong>in</strong>g miscarriages <strong>and</strong> stillbirths as well as live births. Ifbetter medical care had managed to save even one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se potential heirsbeyond Anne’s death <strong>in</strong> 1714, <strong>the</strong> Protestants <strong>of</strong> her family, <strong>the</strong> Stuarts (<strong>the</strong>Catholics among <strong>the</strong>m be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>eligible by law), would have reta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>British crown. But Anne died without leav<strong>in</strong>g a Protestant Stuart heir, so<strong>the</strong> crown passed to <strong>the</strong> distantly related House <strong>of</strong> Hanover. Hanoverianshad very different <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>and</strong> political traditions. It was among <strong>the</strong>mthat <strong>the</strong> British developed what came to be <strong>the</strong> characteristically modern


392 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyparty-<strong>and</strong>-prime-m<strong>in</strong>ister system. Would it have developed <strong>in</strong> a similarway under a Stuart succession?Here we are speculat<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> latent potential <strong>of</strong> people <strong>and</strong> movementsthat we can identify. But what about <strong>the</strong> multitude <strong>of</strong> what-if casesthat never had a chance to come to our attention? Were it not for <strong>the</strong>accident <strong>of</strong> dy<strong>in</strong>g early, how many men <strong>and</strong> women would have survivedto change <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> cultural <strong>and</strong> political history? is is a <strong>the</strong>me <strong>of</strong>Gray’s “Elegy Written <strong>in</strong> a Country Churchyard”:Perhaps <strong>in</strong> this neglected spot is laidSome heart once pregnant with celestial fire,H<strong>and</strong>s that <strong>the</strong> rod <strong>of</strong> empire might have swayed,Or waked to ecstasy <strong>the</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g lyre.Here, perhaps, speculation ceases with our lack <strong>of</strong> knowledge. Butevents that are too certa<strong>in</strong> are not fruitful subjects <strong>of</strong> speculation, ei<strong>the</strong>r.Historical struggles make poor examples <strong>of</strong> uchronia when <strong>the</strong> advantagewas decisively on one side. ey become more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g when <strong>the</strong> detailscould easily have gone <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way. “My k<strong>in</strong>gdom for a horse!” criesShakespeare’s Richard III at Bosworth Field. To me, even more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gthan battles that might have gone ei<strong>the</strong>r way are wars that might havegone ei<strong>the</strong>r way—<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong>y might have been avoided.If American war hawks had not misrepresented <strong>the</strong> explosion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Ma<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> Havana harbor <strong>in</strong> 1898, Spa<strong>in</strong> might well have rema<strong>in</strong>ed a substantialpower; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States might have avoided its deeper colonial<strong>and</strong> geopolitical burdens. Suppose that ho<strong>the</strong>ads had been less <strong>in</strong>fluential<strong>in</strong> Charleston <strong>in</strong> April 1861 or that Jefferson Davis had restra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>m.e Confederates could have been more patient, not fall<strong>in</strong>g for L<strong>in</strong>coln’sprovocative move to resupply Fort Sumter. Without <strong>the</strong>ir fir<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong>fort, L<strong>in</strong>coln could not have whipped up war fever <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> North. Howwould a few more months or even years <strong>of</strong> a Union garrison <strong>in</strong> Charlestonharbor have impaired Confederate <strong>in</strong>dependence, thus far succeed<strong>in</strong>g?After all, <strong>the</strong> garrison had been allowed to buy supplies <strong>in</strong> Charleston evenafter secession. Nei<strong>the</strong>r side expected four years <strong>of</strong> tragic bloodshed. eissue <strong>of</strong> slavery might have been resolved at much less cost for ei<strong>the</strong>r side.France <strong>in</strong> 1870 is an example <strong>of</strong> not tak<strong>in</strong>g “yes” (compliance) for ananswer. e Spanish provisional government had <strong>in</strong>vited a Hohenzollernpr<strong>in</strong>ce to become <strong>the</strong> country’s new k<strong>in</strong>g. e government <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> FrenchEmperor, Napoleon III, objected; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> German pr<strong>in</strong>ce, a member<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> house <strong>the</strong>n rul<strong>in</strong>g Prussia, withdrew. Events could easily have


Chapter : Uchronia, or Alternative History 393stopped <strong>the</strong>re, but <strong>the</strong>y didn’t. Not content with this diplomatic triumph,<strong>the</strong> French foreign m<strong>in</strong>istry tried to humiliate <strong>the</strong> Prussians fur<strong>the</strong>r. It<strong>in</strong>structed <strong>the</strong> French ambassador to accost Prussia’s K<strong>in</strong>g William I at aspa <strong>and</strong> press for written assurance that no such c<strong>and</strong>idacy would ever berenewed. e k<strong>in</strong>g politely refused. Bismarck, <strong>the</strong> Prussian prime m<strong>in</strong>ister,published <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g’s report <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> episode after tendentiously edit<strong>in</strong>git to give <strong>the</strong> impression to <strong>the</strong> French that <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>g had <strong>in</strong>sulted <strong>the</strong>irambassador <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> Prussians that <strong>the</strong> ambassador had been impoliteto <strong>the</strong>ir k<strong>in</strong>g. Empress Eugenie <strong>of</strong> France, a lead<strong>in</strong>g war hawk, expectedthat victory would fur<strong>the</strong>r consolidate <strong>the</strong> Napoleonic dynasty. So <strong>the</strong>French enthusiastically let <strong>the</strong>mselves be tricked <strong>in</strong>to declar<strong>in</strong>g war, eventhough <strong>the</strong>y were militarily unprepared <strong>and</strong> lacked even adequate maps<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> likely <strong>the</strong>aters <strong>of</strong> operations. Napoleon III lost his throne, <strong>the</strong>Bonapartist Second Empire collapsed, France lost Alsace-Lorra<strong>in</strong>e, revanchismeemerged as a political force <strong>in</strong> France, <strong>and</strong> danger <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r wardeveloped. What if soberer m<strong>in</strong>ds had prevailed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> French government?What if <strong>the</strong> Spaniards had <strong>in</strong>vited some non-German as <strong>the</strong>ir k<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place?As <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Second Empire h<strong>in</strong>ged on chance, so did its beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g.Louis-Napoleon Bonaparte, as he was <strong>the</strong>n known, staged a generallyunforeseen coup d’etat on December 2, 1851. His term as president <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> republic (won by name recognition) would soon expire, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> constitutionbarred his reelection. Hence he seized power. But his cruel strokemight well have failed, <strong>and</strong> with it <strong>the</strong> tra<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> events that led France <strong>and</strong>Germany to <strong>the</strong> wars <strong>of</strong> 1870 <strong>and</strong> 1914.e Great War was a tragic <strong>and</strong> unnecessary modern turn<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t.<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> its consequences—economic, political, military, <strong>and</strong> psychological.In 1914 no power desired or foresaw a war so long <strong>and</strong> bloody.Although a complicated network <strong>of</strong> alliances did pose danger, events on<strong>the</strong> scale that later developed were not predicted. ey did not stop with<strong>the</strong> armistice <strong>of</strong> 1918. World War II followed, largely as a consequence <strong>of</strong><strong>and</strong> sequel to <strong>the</strong> first war. One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> causal connections was <strong>the</strong> fact thatGermany’s defeat <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ensu<strong>in</strong>g Treaty <strong>of</strong> Versailles gave Hitler materialfor domestic propag<strong>and</strong>a. But what if advice not to punish Germanyso severely had prevailed at Versailles? Or what if Brita<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> France hadacted decisively when Hitler first violated <strong>the</strong> treaty <strong>in</strong> 1934–1936?e fateful significance <strong>of</strong> June 28, 1914—<strong>the</strong> date when <strong>the</strong> AustrianArchduke Franz Ferd<strong>in</strong><strong>and</strong> was assass<strong>in</strong>ated at Sarajevo <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>curta<strong>in</strong> began to rise for <strong>the</strong> world conflict <strong>of</strong> 1914–1918 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n <strong>of</strong>


394 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy1939–1945—led me, along with a friend’s young son who was accompany<strong>in</strong>gme to a conference <strong>in</strong> Italy, to make a side trip to Sarajevo. erewe saw where Gavrilo Pr<strong>in</strong>cip stood when fir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> shot that killed FranzFerd<strong>in</strong><strong>and</strong>—by a build<strong>in</strong>g where a laudatory commemorative plaque wassubsequently mounted <strong>and</strong> a museum established. I wondered: what if<strong>the</strong> Archduke’s car had not made a wrong turn? What if Pr<strong>in</strong>cip’s shothad missed, if even only by <strong>in</strong>ches? An assass<strong>in</strong>ation attempt had alreadyfailed earlier <strong>the</strong> same day, just barely. is one might also have failed.Still, <strong>the</strong> assass<strong>in</strong>ation did not make war <strong>in</strong>evitable. Suspect<strong>in</strong>g Serbiancomplicity, Austria-Hungary sent Serbia an ultimatum impos<strong>in</strong>gdrastic conditions: it must collaborate <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>and</strong> suppressfur<strong>the</strong>r terrorist agitation. Serbia came surpris<strong>in</strong>gly close to agree<strong>in</strong>g completely;but Austria-Hungary, unwill<strong>in</strong>g (like France <strong>in</strong> 1870) to take anear-yes for an answer, started a war, <strong>and</strong> alliances fed contagion. Whatif Austria-Hungary had been satisfied with <strong>the</strong> near-yes, or if Serbia hadtotally complied?Beyond <strong>the</strong> questions it poses, conjectural history can contribute tounderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g oneself as well as <strong>the</strong> roles <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> chance<strong>in</strong> human affairs. When I was <strong>in</strong> high school I bought Hugo’s Spanish Simplified<strong>and</strong> a few <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Haldeman-Julius Company’s cheap little books onreligion <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational language Esperanto. Miss Connor, myhistory teacher, steered me to <strong>the</strong> economics <strong>of</strong> Henry George <strong>and</strong> to abook about Italian history. ese little episodes affected my later life <strong>in</strong>unforeseeable ways. Miss Connor was what we would now call an outspokenleft-liberal; still, she was a conscientious <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>spir<strong>in</strong>g teacher.Without her <strong>in</strong>fluence, I might not have majored <strong>in</strong> economics <strong>in</strong> college<strong>and</strong> gone on for a Ph.D. <strong>in</strong> economics. Meanwhile, <strong>the</strong> little Haldeman-Julius books aroused my <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>in</strong> religion <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>ternational language,both <strong>of</strong> which I have discussed <strong>in</strong> Liberty (October 2007 <strong>and</strong> January/February2008).Perhaps most accidental, yet significant, was <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> Hugo’sSpanish book. I went on learn<strong>in</strong>g Spanish, entirely without any formalclasses. At Auburn University I jo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> “Friends <strong>of</strong> Guatemala,” a dormant<strong>the</strong>n resurrected weekly Spanish conversation group, <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong>whose name nobody could remember. All but two <strong>of</strong> our group’s memberssoon dropped out, but Luis Dopico <strong>and</strong> I carried on, eventuallyhav<strong>in</strong>g our Spanish conversations at d<strong>in</strong>ner once a week. I visited himonce <strong>in</strong> his home city <strong>in</strong> Spa<strong>in</strong>. He now lives <strong>in</strong> North Carol<strong>in</strong>a <strong>and</strong> hasdual citizenship. I talk with him by phone <strong>in</strong> Spanish for about an hour


Chapter : Uchronia, or Alternative History 395almost every Sunday, <strong>the</strong>n for about 15 m<strong>in</strong>utes <strong>in</strong> English with his wife,Stephanie Cr<strong>of</strong>ton. If I hadn’t been turned onto Spanish by Hugo’s book,I would never have made <strong>the</strong>se two close friendships. is is a prime example<strong>of</strong> a microstochastic event—an <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>omness on a very smallscale—with major consequences for me.And what if I had failed, like some <strong>of</strong> my colleagues, <strong>in</strong> a Japaneselanguage course dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> war? What if I had followed my fa<strong>the</strong>r’s (bad)advice, <strong>of</strong>fered because I had lost three years <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Army, to skip return<strong>in</strong>gto college <strong>and</strong> go directly <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess world? What if I had not happenedonto books by Ludwig von Mises <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Oberl<strong>in</strong> College library<strong>and</strong> by Wilhelm Röpke <strong>in</strong> a New York bookstore, works that greatly<strong>in</strong>fluenced my underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> libertarianism or quasilibertarianism?What if I had chosen <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>novation undersocialism as my dissertation topic <strong>in</strong> 1950–1952, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r topicI was consider<strong>in</strong>g, “An Evaluation <strong>of</strong> Freely Fluctuat<strong>in</strong>g Exchange Rates,”which I did choose? (I know I would have had trouble f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g much tosay about <strong>in</strong>novation under socialism.) What if I hadn’t taught at TexasA&M for one year <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Maryl<strong>and</strong> for five, mak<strong>in</strong>ga few close friends at <strong>the</strong> two schools? A year <strong>in</strong> Maryl<strong>and</strong>’s Europeanprogram came at just <strong>the</strong> right time <strong>of</strong> my life. What if an article <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ehad not brought me an <strong>in</strong>vitation to move to <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia <strong>in</strong>1957? By happen<strong>in</strong>g to take part <strong>in</strong> an Institute for Humane Studies program<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> summer <strong>of</strong> 1981, I met a valued academic collaborator, RobertGreenfield. In 1984, <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> buy<strong>in</strong>g a big house with a big mortgage asan <strong>in</strong>flation hedge tipped my agoniz<strong>in</strong>gly close decision toward mov<strong>in</strong>gfrom Virg<strong>in</strong>ia to Auburn University. (Yes, not only <strong>in</strong>flation but uncerta<strong>in</strong>tyabout it can disrupt even personal plann<strong>in</strong>g.) Speculation not onlyabout episodes <strong>in</strong> world history but also about turn<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>glelife can make for lively but serious conversation—with o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>and</strong> withoneself.I’ve saved for last an example <strong>of</strong> uchronia that, for two reasons, is myfavorite. Like many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> examples above <strong>and</strong> as best I can remember,I thought <strong>of</strong> it myself. More importantly, it is an extreme example <strong>of</strong> itstype; arguably, it even bears on <strong>the</strong> philosophical issue <strong>of</strong> free will <strong>and</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ism. Suppose that <strong>in</strong> 1818 Queen Victoria had been conceived asa male ra<strong>the</strong>r than a female. Her (or his) sex determ<strong>in</strong>ation was surely amicrostochastic event. Except only for this accident <strong>of</strong> sex, <strong>the</strong> crowns <strong>of</strong>Great Brita<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Hanover would have rema<strong>in</strong>ed united after <strong>the</strong> death<strong>of</strong> Victoria’s uncle, William IV, <strong>in</strong> 1837. Women could succeed to <strong>the</strong>


396 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophythrone <strong>of</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong>, but <strong>the</strong> medieval Salic Law excluded all females from<strong>the</strong> throne <strong>of</strong> Hanover so long as any male heirs were to be found. Soano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> Victoria’s uncles, Ernest Augustus, became k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Hanover,separat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> two crowns.Now, if <strong>the</strong> new monarch <strong>of</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong> had been a male, he would alsohave been k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Hanover. A k<strong>in</strong>gdom <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> heart <strong>of</strong> nor<strong>the</strong>rn Germanyshar<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> same English-speak<strong>in</strong>g, English-educated monarchwith Great Brita<strong>in</strong> would have greatly hampered Bismarck’s efforts towardGerman unification. e Seven Weeks War <strong>of</strong> 1866 (Prussia aga<strong>in</strong>st Austria),hav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> its background <strong>the</strong> 1864 war <strong>of</strong> Prussia <strong>and</strong> Austria aga<strong>in</strong>stDenmark over <strong>the</strong> north-German Schleswig-Holste<strong>in</strong> issue, might neverhave taken place. As its result, however, Hanover, an ally <strong>of</strong> defeated Austria,lost its <strong>in</strong>dependence <strong>in</strong> 1866 <strong>and</strong> was absorbed <strong>in</strong>to Prussia. WithoutVictoria’s conception as a female, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> wars <strong>of</strong> 1866 <strong>and</strong> 1870–1871, <strong>the</strong>establishment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German Empire, World War I, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Bolshevikrevolution <strong>of</strong> 1917 might never have occurred, at least not at <strong>the</strong>ir actualtimes <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir actual ways. Would our lives be different? It’s difficultto argue o<strong>the</strong>rwise.Small chance events can <strong>in</strong>deed sway history. is is how uchroniabecomes reality.


Hayek on <strong>the</strong> Psychology <strong>of</strong>Socialism <strong>and</strong> Freedom * ( )N<strong>in</strong>eteen eighty-four is <strong>the</strong> eighty-fifth anniversary <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> birth <strong>of</strong> FriedrichHayek, Nobel laureate <strong>and</strong> one <strong>of</strong> this century’s great economists.is year is also <strong>the</strong> fortieth anniversary <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s best-known book, eRoad to Serfdom.e Road to Serfdom was published at a critical time. e 1930s hadbeen a decade <strong>of</strong> exceptionally rapid <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic role <strong>of</strong> government<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Western democracies, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> United States <strong>and</strong>Brita<strong>in</strong>. In 1944, as <strong>the</strong> war was com<strong>in</strong>g to an end, <strong>the</strong> common, expectationwas that this trend would be resumed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> postwar period. eusual term for <strong>the</strong> postwar economic environment was “postwar plann<strong>in</strong>g,”mean<strong>in</strong>g plann<strong>in</strong>g by government.Dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> 1930s <strong>the</strong>re had been little objective <strong>in</strong>tellectual resistanceto <strong>the</strong> movement toward <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g government controls. In <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates resistance came from Republicans, Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Democrats, <strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>essorganizations <strong>and</strong> could be dismissed as partisan, nostalgic, or self<strong>in</strong>terested.Hayek’s book was <strong>the</strong> open<strong>in</strong>g—<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> most important—shot <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual resistance to <strong>the</strong> trend toward government control. Hayekargued that military victory over <strong>the</strong> Nazis <strong>and</strong> Fascists would not permanentlyensure <strong>the</strong> triumph <strong>of</strong> freedom. e repulsive features <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Nazi <strong>and</strong> Fascist regimes were not <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> peculiarly German <strong>and</strong>Italian characteristics. Ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y were <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> carry<strong>in</strong>g out fully<strong>the</strong> implications <strong>of</strong> a socialist way <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that was already present <strong>in</strong>Brita<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States. He warned that unless we rejected that way<strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g we could follow along <strong>the</strong> same road to serfdom.*From AEI Economist (November 1984): 1–5.397


398 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophye book was an immediate sensation. It had an enormous popularaudience, partly through a condensation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Reader’s Digest, <strong>and</strong> hasbeen translated <strong>in</strong>to some sixteen languages.If we are not now on <strong>the</strong> road to serfdom—<strong>and</strong> we do not seem tobe—some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> credit for that must go to Friedrich Hayek. In salute tohim we publish <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g article by a dist<strong>in</strong>guished student <strong>of</strong> Hayek’swork, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Lel<strong>and</strong> Yeager <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia. Now, forty years after its publication, is a good time to reconsider FriedrichHayek’s e Road to Serfdom (1944). George Orwell’s 1984 also deservesmention, s<strong>in</strong>ce Orwell had written a k<strong>in</strong>d review <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s book beforewrit<strong>in</strong>g his own. Someone read<strong>in</strong>g a book aga<strong>in</strong> after a long <strong>in</strong>terval is likely to receivea ra<strong>the</strong>r different message. is fact illustrates <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis that Hayek develops<strong>in</strong> e Sensory Order (published <strong>in</strong> 1952 but derived from a paperdrafted over thirty years earlier). I’d like to expla<strong>in</strong> my po<strong>in</strong>t, <strong>and</strong> alsohail Hayek’s <strong>in</strong>adequately remembered work <strong>in</strong> psychology, by first survey<strong>in</strong>gthat book. A fur<strong>the</strong>r l<strong>in</strong>k between his books <strong>of</strong> 1944 <strong>and</strong> 1952 isthat Hayek <strong>of</strong>ten deployed psychological <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong> e Road to Serfdomto expla<strong>in</strong>, for example, why certa<strong>in</strong> wrong ideas never<strong>the</strong>less have wideappeal. Fully appreciat<strong>in</strong>g Hayek’s work <strong>in</strong> economics <strong>and</strong> political sciencerequires know<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> his <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> psychology.’ Although e Sensory Order does not stress <strong>the</strong> connection, Hayek’s psychologicaldoctr<strong>in</strong>es do mesh well with his methodology <strong>in</strong> economics<strong>and</strong> his approach to practical affairs. A sharp dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>the</strong>ory<strong>and</strong> fact or between <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> practice is not tenable. All our actions, allour observations <strong>of</strong> fact, even all our supposedly ultimate or irreduciblesense perceptions are shot through with <strong>the</strong>ory. Even at <strong>the</strong> level closestto bare fact, <strong>the</strong>ory is <strong>in</strong>dispensable to mak<strong>in</strong>g sense out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world <strong>and</strong>even to perceiv<strong>in</strong>g it.We never perceive unique properties <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual objects but onlyproperties that objects have <strong>in</strong> common. Perception always <strong>in</strong>volves Hayek mentions Orwell’s review <strong>in</strong> a new foreword to e Road to Serfdom (Hayek1944/1956, p. viii n.).


Chapter : Hayek on <strong>the</strong> Psychology <strong>of</strong> Socialism <strong>and</strong> Freedom 399<strong>in</strong>terpretation ascrib<strong>in</strong>g impulses received to one or more classes. isclassification is at least rudimentary <strong>the</strong>ory. e qualities we attribute toexperienced objects belong, actually, to <strong>the</strong> relations by which we classify<strong>the</strong>m.Examples may help. When I hear a sound or see a patch <strong>of</strong> red, nei<strong>the</strong>rsimply exists as a dist<strong>in</strong>ct part <strong>of</strong> objective reality impress<strong>in</strong>g itself on mynervous system. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, my nervous system selects certa<strong>in</strong> aspects <strong>of</strong> realityaccessible to my sense organs, classifies <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>and</strong> organizes <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>tomy perception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sound or <strong>the</strong> red patch. Far from play<strong>in</strong>g a purelypassive role, my nervous system impresses order or character onto my perceptions<strong>and</strong> thus shapes <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> a way even creates <strong>the</strong>m.What aspects <strong>of</strong> reality can affect my sense organs <strong>and</strong> how its effectsshape <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong>to perceptions depend on <strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong> those organs, <strong>of</strong>my nervous system, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>of</strong> my entire body. e role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> physicalbody is obvious. Unlike a dog, I cannot perceive certa<strong>in</strong> smells orhigh-pitched sounds. Unlike me, <strong>the</strong> dog cannot recognize <strong>and</strong> so cannotperceive words <strong>in</strong> a conversation or on a pr<strong>in</strong>ted page.Biological processes <strong>and</strong> natural selection have presumably shapedorganisms <strong>in</strong> such ways that <strong>the</strong>ir perceptions possess an order correspond<strong>in</strong>gto whatever order may exist <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. Organisms that frequentlyconfused hot <strong>and</strong> cold, small <strong>and</strong> large, near <strong>and</strong> far, up <strong>and</strong> down,hunger <strong>and</strong> satiety, wolf <strong>and</strong> bush would be less likely to survive <strong>and</strong> reproducethan ones whose perceptions corresponded better to reality. Amonghigher organisms, actions conform<strong>in</strong>g to pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> logic would havegreater survival value than actions clash<strong>in</strong>g with logic.We see some possible truth, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>in</strong> Immanuel Kant’s contentionthat human be<strong>in</strong>gs can have knowledge prior to experience. Quibbl<strong>in</strong>g,we might narrow that contention down. People do not have any a prioriknowledge <strong>in</strong> an articulated form. What <strong>the</strong>y more plausibly have arepredispositions to behave as if <strong>the</strong>y had certa<strong>in</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> predispositionsto recognize <strong>and</strong> become able to articulate it.In Hayek’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation, experience is <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> knowledge, afterall, but it is not restricted to experience obta<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual organismitself. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it <strong>in</strong>cludes <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> species <strong>and</strong> its ancestorsas embodied, through biology <strong>and</strong> natural selection, <strong>in</strong> each <strong>in</strong>dividual’sgenetic <strong>and</strong> physiological makeup. e <strong>in</strong>dividual human be<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>herits <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> his ancestors not only through biological butalso through cultural processes, notably through language. Language<strong>in</strong>creases his capacity for discrim<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> deal<strong>in</strong>g with new experience.


400 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyLanguage is itself <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terwoven biological <strong>and</strong> culturalevolution.Still ano<strong>the</strong>r type <strong>of</strong> experience besides his own direct current experiencehelps shape <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual’s current perceptions. His own past experiencedoes so by hav<strong>in</strong>g affected physical <strong>and</strong> chemical conditions with<strong>in</strong>his body, such as nerve connections govern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> travel <strong>of</strong> impulses to<strong>and</strong> from <strong>the</strong> bra<strong>in</strong>. People do not first have sensations that are <strong>the</strong>n preservedby memory. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is as a result <strong>of</strong> physiological memory thatphysiological impulses received are converted <strong>in</strong>to sensations.We need not go <strong>in</strong>to what Hayek says fur<strong>the</strong>r about physiology <strong>and</strong>about what experiments do or would tend ei<strong>the</strong>r to support or to refute his<strong>the</strong>ory. It is worth mention<strong>in</strong>g, though, that while Hayek (like almost allscientists) is a mechanist as opposed to a vitalist, he is no reductionist. Hedoes not believe that <strong>the</strong> life sciences <strong>and</strong> social sciences can be “reduced”to physics <strong>and</strong> chemistry <strong>in</strong> such a way as to recommend banish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>language <strong>of</strong> see<strong>in</strong>g, hear<strong>in</strong>g, th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g, consciousness, purposes, <strong>in</strong>tentions,decisions, <strong>and</strong> actions <strong>and</strong> requir<strong>in</strong>g all propositions about such mattersto be phrased exclusively <strong>in</strong> physical <strong>and</strong> chemical terms <strong>in</strong>stead.Hayek argues, <strong>in</strong> short, that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual’s cognitive apparatus, shapedby his biological <strong>and</strong> cultural <strong>in</strong>heritances <strong>and</strong> by his own past experiences,br<strong>in</strong>gs a predisposition to each new situation to perceive it <strong>and</strong> organize itsaspects <strong>in</strong> particular ways. No such th<strong>in</strong>g operates as raw, pure, unfilteredperception. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> observer largely shapes what he perceives.Knowledge does <strong>in</strong>deed have an a priori aspect <strong>the</strong>n (though its nature<strong>and</strong> sources are not quite what Kant had supposed). It is not true thatall we know must be subject to confirmation or contradiction by senseexperience, that is, by current or future sense experience. At least part <strong>of</strong>what we know at any moment about <strong>the</strong> external world is implicit <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>means through which we can obta<strong>in</strong> experience.Many observations tend to support or illustrate Hayek’s <strong>the</strong>ory, or atleast to provide illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g parallels. George Stigler <strong>and</strong> Gary Becker(1977), <strong>in</strong> a well-known methodological article, tacitly accept someth<strong>in</strong>glike <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. ey warn aga<strong>in</strong>st hastily chalk<strong>in</strong>g up a change <strong>in</strong> a person’sbehavior to a change <strong>in</strong> his tastes. ey recommend postulat<strong>in</strong>g astable basic structure <strong>of</strong> tastes with<strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong> experiencemay alter <strong>the</strong> response even to o<strong>the</strong>rwise unchanged circumstances.A person may respond differently than before to a given set <strong>of</strong> opportunities,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g perhaps prices, if <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terval he has acquired, forexample, more “music appreciation capital.”


Chapter : Hayek on <strong>the</strong> Psychology <strong>of</strong> Socialism <strong>and</strong> Freedom 401When one uses a foreign language, particularly over <strong>the</strong> telephone,what he hears—not just underst<strong>and</strong>s, but even hears—depends on howwell he knows <strong>the</strong> language, that is, on his previous experience.Hayek’s <strong>the</strong>ory, along with Leon Fest<strong>in</strong>ger’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> cognitive dissonance,helps expla<strong>in</strong> why many people cannot recognize <strong>the</strong> worst source<strong>of</strong> cruelty, predation, <strong>and</strong> mortal peril <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world today <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>steaddump <strong>the</strong> blame onto those Western statesmen who do identify <strong>the</strong> evil<strong>and</strong> call for adequate defense. ose <strong>the</strong>ories also help expla<strong>in</strong> why certa<strong>in</strong>economists who trumpet <strong>the</strong>ir supposed empirical orientation never<strong>the</strong>lesscannot see which <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir favorite postulates are falsified by facts<strong>and</strong> cannot see how substantial or how slight <strong>the</strong> results are that <strong>the</strong>irfavorite methods have yielded. Admittedly, it may be I, not <strong>the</strong> people Iam criticiz<strong>in</strong>g, who is wrong; but <strong>the</strong>n my errors would still illustrate <strong>the</strong>central po<strong>in</strong>t that <strong>the</strong> experiences <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d set one br<strong>in</strong>gs to a cognitivesituation affect not only one’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> it but even what onecan see.Many writers have presumably been criticized, as I have, for views <strong>the</strong>yhad not expressed. eir readers evidently could not perceive, unfiltered,what <strong>the</strong>y were say<strong>in</strong>g. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> readers classified <strong>the</strong> material <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>irown preexist<strong>in</strong>g pigeonholes. ey <strong>the</strong>n reacted to what <strong>the</strong>ir fil<strong>in</strong>g systemsaccommodated, not just to any bare substance <strong>of</strong> what had been said.e message that a reader draws from a book follows partly from <strong>the</strong>experiences he br<strong>in</strong>gs to it, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g his past read<strong>in</strong>g. at is why a bookreread after a long <strong>in</strong>terval may make a different impression than before. at is how e Road to Serfdom has affected me. e book’s central messageis, <strong>of</strong> course, hard to miss: Socialism, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> collective ownership<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> means <strong>of</strong> production <strong>and</strong> central direction <strong>of</strong> economic life,entails loss <strong>of</strong> personal freedom. What came more strongly to my attentionis Hayek’s concern with political <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives <strong>and</strong> alsowith l<strong>in</strong>kages <strong>of</strong> ideas. S<strong>in</strong>ce I had also been sensitized <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> meanwhile toHayek’s <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> psychology, <strong>the</strong> same is true <strong>of</strong> his many psychological<strong>in</strong>sights.ese, <strong>in</strong> e Road to Serfdom, are <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>of</strong> “literary” psychology(“thymology,” as Ludwig von Mises called it) ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> technicaldiscipl<strong>in</strong>e. Hayek stresses <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> beliefs <strong>and</strong> attitudes <strong>and</strong>explores reasons why people hold <strong>the</strong>m.


402 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophySpecialists tend to be enthusiastic for central plann<strong>in</strong>g because <strong>the</strong>ytacitly assume that <strong>the</strong> planners will, like <strong>the</strong>mselves, be <strong>in</strong>telligent personshav<strong>in</strong>g sensible scales <strong>of</strong> values <strong>and</strong> so underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> special importance<strong>of</strong> each particular specialist’s favorite goal. (Examples might be education,environmental protection, high technology, mass transportation,or more nearly equal distribution <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong> wealth.) Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, anapparent consensus <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> plann<strong>in</strong>g is likely to be spurious, for <strong>the</strong>different enthusiasts will have different visions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> plan to adopt.What “gives <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for plann<strong>in</strong>g its strongest impetus,” says Hayek,is “<strong>the</strong> resentment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> frustrated specialist” (1944/1956, p. 55). Nos<strong>in</strong>gle economic factor has contributed more to help Fascist <strong>and</strong> NationalSocialist movements “than <strong>the</strong> envy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unsuccessful pr<strong>of</strong>essional man,<strong>the</strong> university-tra<strong>in</strong>ed eng<strong>in</strong>eer or lawyer, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘white-collared proletariat’<strong>in</strong> general, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> eng<strong>in</strong>e driver or compositor <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r members <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> strongest trade unions whose <strong>in</strong>come was many times <strong>the</strong>irs” (p. 116).Ano<strong>the</strong>r source <strong>of</strong> discontent with <strong>the</strong> market economy is a vagueresentment at <strong>of</strong>ten hav<strong>in</strong>g to pay a material cost to serve higher values—“life<strong>and</strong> health, beauty <strong>and</strong> virtue, honor <strong>and</strong> peace <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d.” Peopleresent “hav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> higher values <strong>of</strong> life brought <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> ’cash nexus’.”At bottom, <strong>and</strong> without realiz<strong>in</strong>g it, what <strong>the</strong>y resent is <strong>the</strong> economicproblem—<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>exorable fact <strong>of</strong> scarcity <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> need to make choices(pp. 97–98).Hayek describes <strong>the</strong> attitude, cultivated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Germany that eventuallyput Hitler <strong>in</strong> power, that someth<strong>in</strong>g disreputable attaches to tak<strong>in</strong>geconomic risks <strong>and</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>of</strong>it: “to employ a hundred people is representedas exploitation but to comm<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same number as honorable”(pp. 130–131).In a complex civilization with a developed market economy, manypeople will not underst<strong>and</strong> why <strong>the</strong>y must adjust to changes <strong>of</strong> unknownsource <strong>and</strong> nature, as by shift<strong>in</strong>g occupations, or why some th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>the</strong>ydesire should become harder to obta<strong>in</strong> than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> past. ey do not underst<strong>and</strong>that “<strong>the</strong> only alternative to submission to <strong>the</strong> impersonal <strong>and</strong> seem<strong>in</strong>glyirrational forces <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market is submission to an equally uncontrollable<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore arbitrary power <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r men” (p. 205).One famous piece <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s psychologiz<strong>in</strong>g is his chapter on “Why<strong>the</strong> Worst Get on Top.” In a system <strong>in</strong> which achiev<strong>in</strong>g wealth <strong>and</strong> positiondepends less than it does <strong>in</strong> a market economy on satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>wants <strong>of</strong> one’s fellows through voluntary transactions, ambitious peoplehave more scope for p<strong>and</strong>er<strong>in</strong>g to popular resentments <strong>and</strong> prejudices


Chapter : Hayek on <strong>the</strong> Psychology <strong>of</strong> Socialism <strong>and</strong> Freedom 403<strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> vanity <strong>and</strong> power-hunger <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir superiors. Opportunities for<strong>the</strong> unscrupulous, ruthless, <strong>and</strong> un<strong>in</strong>hibited (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g people not <strong>in</strong>hibitedby concern for truth) will be relatively greater. Hayek (p. 152) quotesFrank Knight: “<strong>the</strong> probability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> people <strong>in</strong> power be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividualswho would dislike <strong>the</strong> possession <strong>and</strong> exercise <strong>of</strong> power is on a level with<strong>the</strong> probability that an extremely tender-hearted person would get <strong>the</strong> job<strong>of</strong> whipp<strong>in</strong>g-master <strong>in</strong> a slave plantation.”It helps describe e Road to Serfdom to compare it with a bookpublished <strong>in</strong> Switzerl<strong>and</strong> four years later whose author repeatedly citesHayek: Walter Adolf Jöhr (1948), <strong>Is</strong>t e<strong>in</strong> freiheitlicher Sozialismus möglich?(<strong>Is</strong> Socialism with Freedom Possible?). Hayek’s is <strong>the</strong> longer book, thoughboth are short (248 pages plus <strong>in</strong>troductions versus 137 pages). Jöhr sticksmore closely to systematic analysis <strong>of</strong> what economic <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r aspects<strong>of</strong> society are or are not likely to be compatible with one ano<strong>the</strong>r; heaims ra<strong>the</strong>r narrowly at answer<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> question posed. His answer turnsout “No.” He cites, <strong>and</strong> rejects, published efforts to reconcile socialism<strong>and</strong> freedom by redef<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g one or both terms. He expla<strong>in</strong>s why acentrally directed economy would destroy economic freedoms, why economic<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r freedoms cannot be sharply separated, <strong>and</strong> why political<strong>and</strong> cultural freedoms would <strong>the</strong>refore suffer also. He shows whylosses <strong>of</strong> some freedoms are unlikely to be outweighed by ga<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs.Decentralized socialism <strong>and</strong> partial socialism would have difficulties <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>and</strong> would experience pressures to evolve toward fuller-fledgedsocialism.e two books are complementary. Hayek covers much <strong>the</strong> sameground as Jöhr, but <strong>in</strong> a looser, more discursive, less narrowly analyticalway; he argues more by pil<strong>in</strong>g up plausible <strong>in</strong>sights. He also ranges morewidely. He diagnoses more trends <strong>and</strong> draws more parallels. He po<strong>in</strong>tsout, for example, that <strong>the</strong> rise <strong>of</strong> fascism <strong>and</strong> Nazism was not a reactionaga<strong>in</strong>st socialist trends but ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ir extension.e <strong>in</strong>tensity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral emotions beh<strong>in</strong>d a movement like that <strong>of</strong>National Socialism or communism can probably be compared only tothose <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> great religious movements <strong>of</strong> history. Once you admit that<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual is merely a means to serve <strong>the</strong> ends <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> higher entitycalled society or <strong>the</strong> nation, most <strong>of</strong> those features <strong>of</strong> totalitarian regimeswhich horrify us follow <strong>of</strong> necessity.... When German philosophersaga<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong> represent <strong>the</strong> striv<strong>in</strong>g for personal happ<strong>in</strong>ess as itselfimmoral <strong>and</strong> only <strong>the</strong> fulfilment <strong>of</strong> an imposed duty as praiseworthy,<strong>the</strong>y are perfectly s<strong>in</strong>cere, however difficult this may be to underst<strong>and</strong>


404 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyfor those who have been brought up <strong>in</strong> a different tradition. (Hayek1944/1956, p. 149)Besides delv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to psychology, Hayek goes fur<strong>the</strong>r than Jöhr <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>history <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terconnections <strong>of</strong> ideas. He makes more allusions to people,events, <strong>and</strong> literature. He considers <strong>the</strong> allegedly <strong>in</strong>exorable decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong>competition <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed necessity <strong>of</strong> plann<strong>in</strong>g for that reason. Hedescribes <strong>the</strong> positive accomplishments <strong>of</strong> a price system. Anticipat<strong>in</strong>gchapter 6 <strong>of</strong> his e Constitution <strong>of</strong> Liberty (1960), he presents <strong>the</strong> casefor allow<strong>in</strong>g market <strong>in</strong>centives to guide <strong>the</strong> allocation <strong>of</strong> resources, effort,<strong>and</strong> risk-bear<strong>in</strong>g ra<strong>the</strong>r than try<strong>in</strong>g to make <strong>the</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>comecorrespond somehow to judgments <strong>of</strong> moral merit.e Road to Serfdom foreshadows many <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s later writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong>could serve as an <strong>in</strong>troduction <strong>and</strong> summary. Over his lifetime his workshows cont<strong>in</strong>uity. In his writ<strong>in</strong>gs, as I know <strong>the</strong>m, he has had to reversehimself on remarkably little. is is not to say that he is stuck <strong>in</strong> a rut,recit<strong>in</strong>g earlier formulations—not at all. His thought has developed, butlargely through his deepen<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> earlier <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>and</strong> extend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m tonew fields. With regard to <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>tervention he favors,he has evolved if anyth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a laissez-faire direction, as illustrated byhis proposals for tak<strong>in</strong>g even <strong>the</strong> monetary system out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> clutches <strong>of</strong>government.e Road to Serfdom expla<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> perverse consequences <strong>of</strong> governmentmeasures to shelter <strong>in</strong>dividual sectors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> adverseimpact <strong>of</strong> change. Already <strong>in</strong> 1944, Hayek had begun to grasp some po<strong>in</strong>tslater elaborated by Mancur Olson <strong>in</strong> his e Rise <strong>and</strong> Decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> Nations(1982). e longer a society enjoys peace <strong>and</strong> stability, <strong>the</strong> better organizedeconomic <strong>in</strong>terest groups become <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> more successful <strong>in</strong> lobby<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> government for special privilege <strong>and</strong> for protection aga<strong>in</strong>st domestic<strong>and</strong> foreign competition. Economies become sclerotic, with adverseconsequences for productivity, growth, <strong>and</strong> macroeconomic performance.Olson was able to expla<strong>in</strong> much recent economic history with this simple<strong>in</strong>sight.Hayek had already expla<strong>in</strong>ed how anticompetitive restrictions imposeall <strong>the</strong> more <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> change on occupations outside <strong>the</strong> favoredones.In consequence, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> prices, wages, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>comes, it isnow employment <strong>and</strong> production which have become subject to violentfluctuations.... Few catchwords have done so much harm as <strong>the</strong> ideal <strong>of</strong>


Chapter : Hayek on <strong>the</strong> Psychology <strong>of</strong> Socialism <strong>and</strong> Freedom 405a “stabilization” <strong>of</strong> particular prices (or wages), which, while secur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>come <strong>of</strong> some, makes <strong>the</strong> position <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rest more <strong>and</strong> more precarious.(1944/1956, p. 129; cf. p. 45).Hayek’s warn<strong>in</strong>g that socialism endangers freedom is widely recognizedas valid nowadays. Already <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> foreword to his 1956 edition, Hayekrecognized that “hot socialism is probably a th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past” <strong>and</strong> that a“hodge-podge <strong>of</strong> ill-assembled <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>in</strong>consistent ideals” labeled <strong>the</strong>Welfare State had “largely replaced socialism as <strong>the</strong> goal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reformers”(p. ix). Few prom<strong>in</strong>ent English-speak<strong>in</strong>g economists actually advocatesocialism any longer. Exceptions like J.K. Galbraith <strong>and</strong> Robert Lekachm<strong>and</strong>o come to m<strong>in</strong>d, but it is not clear—not to me, anyway—just what<strong>the</strong>y mean by socialism. Politicians still advocat<strong>in</strong>g socialism <strong>in</strong> developedcountries, like François Mitterr<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> France, no longer mean full-fledgedsocialism, but ra<strong>the</strong>r a welfare state, with redistributionist measures <strong>and</strong>only limited nationalization <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dustry. Hayek is right: hot socialismis dead.I do not say that people now reject socialism because <strong>the</strong>y have directlyabsorbed Hayek’s message. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, his arguments have been <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> air<strong>and</strong> have worked <strong>in</strong>directly. Experience at first or second or nth h<strong>and</strong>has oozed <strong>in</strong>to people’s consciousness. In <strong>the</strong> forty years s<strong>in</strong>ce 1944, <strong>the</strong>world has observed socialism <strong>in</strong> Soviet-bloc <strong>and</strong> third world countries.But it has not seen personal freedom coexist<strong>in</strong>g with full-fledged socialism.As Hayek wrote already <strong>in</strong> 1944, “‘liberal socialism’ as most people <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> Western world imag<strong>in</strong>e it is purely <strong>the</strong>oretical, while <strong>the</strong> practice <strong>of</strong>socialism is everywhere totalitarian” (p. 141). Failure to observe freedomunder socialism is no mere accident.If we <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> developed countries eventually w<strong>in</strong>d up socialist afterall, we will have done so un<strong>in</strong>tentionally. Especially <strong>in</strong> his later writ<strong>in</strong>gs(Hayek 1978 <strong>and</strong> 1979), Hayek has foreseen how this might happen.e irresponsibility flourish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> democratic politics could accommodateexcessive dem<strong>and</strong>s for special governmental favor <strong>and</strong> protectionaga<strong>in</strong>st competition, hamper enterprise, swell government budgets <strong>and</strong>deficits, br<strong>in</strong>g debt monetization <strong>and</strong> price <strong>in</strong>flation, <strong>and</strong> br<strong>in</strong>g counterproductiveattempts to fight <strong>in</strong>flation with direct controls. Capitalismcould seem to have failed, <strong>and</strong> opportunistic politicians would <strong>of</strong>fer governmentalremedies. Actually, what would have failed would be <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>flation-prone,<strong>in</strong>tervention-ridden economy <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> political system responsiblefor those ills.


406 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyHayek (1973/1979) has recognized such dangers <strong>and</strong> has recommendedpolitical reforms. Already <strong>in</strong> e Road to Serfdom he anticipated his later<strong>and</strong> fuller diagnoses <strong>of</strong> flaws <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> political system. He expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>nature <strong>of</strong> democracy <strong>and</strong> why one should not make a fetish <strong>of</strong> it (pp. 70–71),<strong>the</strong> impossibility <strong>of</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g out a coherent economic plan democratically(pp. 61–68), <strong>and</strong> why plann<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>in</strong>compatible with <strong>the</strong> rule <strong>of</strong> law(pp. 72–87).Will we still blunder <strong>in</strong>to socialism <strong>and</strong> totalitarianism through <strong>the</strong>back door—through exploitation <strong>of</strong> government power by special-<strong>in</strong>terestgroups run amok, overburden<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> government, rigidification <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economy,<strong>in</strong>flation <strong>and</strong> stagflation <strong>and</strong> misconceived measures aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong>m,slowdown <strong>of</strong> productivity growth, <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> general, a botch from whichdemagogues <strong>and</strong> power-seekers can make hay? Our chief hope is that wewill comb<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> absorb <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> F.A. Hayek <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> publicchoiceschool, led by James Buchanan, <strong>and</strong> put <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>to practice before<strong>the</strong> opportunity runs out.Hayek, F.A. e Sensory Order. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1952.. e Road to Serfdom. 1944. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press,Phoenix Books, 1956.. e Constitution <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1960.. New Studies <strong>in</strong> Philosophy, Politics, Economics, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong> Ideas.Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1978.. e <strong>Political</strong> Order <strong>of</strong> a Free People. Vol. 3 <strong>of</strong> Law, Legislation, <strong>and</strong> Liberty.1973. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1979.. A Tiger by <strong>the</strong> Tail. Compiled by Sudha R. Shenoy. San Francisco: CatoInstitute, 1979.Jöhr, Walter A. <strong>Is</strong>t e<strong>in</strong> Freiheitlicher Sozialismus Möglich? Bern: Francke, 1948.Olson, Mancur. e Rise <strong>and</strong> Decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> Nations. New Haven, Conn.: Yale UniversityPress, 1982.Stigler, George, <strong>and</strong> Gary Becker. “De Gustibus Non Est Disput<strong>and</strong>um.” AmericanEconomic Review 67 (March 1977): pp. 76–90.


Kirzner on <strong>the</strong> Morality <strong>of</strong>Capitalist Pr<strong>of</strong>it *<strong>Is</strong>rael Kirzner develops <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> moral legitimacy <strong>of</strong> capitalism<strong>and</strong> especially <strong>of</strong> entrepreneurial pr<strong>of</strong>it. is paper tries to echo orstreng<strong>the</strong>n Kirzner’s po<strong>in</strong>ts by relat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m more closely than he doesto <strong>the</strong> foundations <strong>of</strong> ethics. Although I have no reason to suppose so,Kirzner may conceivably resist be<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>ked with one version <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism,a version trac<strong>in</strong>g as far back <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> philosophy as DavidHume <strong>and</strong> even earlier, forthrightly expounded by Kirzner’s mentor Ludwigvon Mises <strong>and</strong> by Henry Hazlitt, <strong>and</strong> employed at least tacitly byFriedrich A. Hayek. If Kirzner should th<strong>in</strong>k I am try<strong>in</strong>g to draft him<strong>in</strong>to an unwelcome alliance, I can only apologize <strong>and</strong> only hope that hewill never<strong>the</strong>less accept my contribution to a dialogue that he himself hasactively advanced.’ As I just implied, Kirzner does not claim to be sett<strong>in</strong>g forth a novel ethicalposition or to be contribut<strong>in</strong>g to ethical <strong>the</strong>ory as dist<strong>in</strong>ct from economics(1992b, chap. 13; 1989, p. 98; but see 1979, p. 211). He does not tryto show that <strong>the</strong> critics <strong>of</strong> capitalism have used morally flawed criteria.For his immediate purposes, he accepts exist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> widely shared ethical<strong>in</strong>tuitions without challenge. He recognizes that someone might rejecthis conclusions, <strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> economics, on different ethical*From Advances <strong>in</strong> Austrian Economics, vol. 2A, eds. Peter J. Boettke <strong>and</strong> Mario J. Rizzo(Greenwich, Conn.: JAI Press, 1995), 197–209. See Hazlitt 1964 <strong>and</strong>, for discussion <strong>of</strong> Mises’s <strong>and</strong> Hayek’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs, Yeager 1993 <strong>and</strong>Yeager 1985.Kirzner does mention Mises’s utilitarianism (1989, pp. 63–64). Unfortunately, he seemsto imply that Mises was little concerned with ethics <strong>and</strong> defended capitalism simply on<strong>the</strong> grounds that it delivers <strong>the</strong> goods.407


408 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophygrounds. (is characterization <strong>of</strong> his views derives from 1992b, p. 209;1989, pp. 129–130; <strong>and</strong>, more broadly, from all his writ<strong>in</strong>gs listed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>references.)Kirzner argues, as positive economic analysis, that capitalism workso<strong>the</strong>rwise than its critics <strong>and</strong> most <strong>of</strong> its defenders believe. He traces<strong>the</strong> entrepreneur’s pure pr<strong>of</strong>it to generally unappreciated facts. e entrepreneurcreates wealth, practically ex nihilo, by discover<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> exploit<strong>in</strong>gopportunities. Kirzner sharply dist<strong>in</strong>guishes <strong>the</strong>se acts <strong>of</strong> discovery fromacts <strong>of</strong> deliberate production (1989, p. 166). Instead <strong>of</strong> tak<strong>in</strong>g resourcesaway from anyone else, <strong>the</strong> entrepreneur creates what did not exist before,benefit<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r persons as well as himself. e prior physical existence <strong>of</strong>a diamond discovered on a remote mounta<strong>in</strong> is irrelevant to <strong>the</strong> creative act<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral entitlement it engenders. Kirzner sees <strong>the</strong> discoverer/produceras entitled to <strong>the</strong> product not because he transformed <strong>and</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ed<strong>in</strong>puts over which he already held just title but because he genu<strong>in</strong>ely orig<strong>in</strong>atedit. No one has any right to deprive <strong>the</strong> creator <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> enjoyment <strong>of</strong>his creation (1989, pp. 150, 153).Of course, an entrepreneur does not create ex nihilo <strong>the</strong> entire marketvalue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> products <strong>of</strong> his discoveries. Typically, he comb<strong>in</strong>es hiscreativeness with <strong>the</strong> services <strong>of</strong> already exist<strong>in</strong>g resources <strong>and</strong> factors <strong>of</strong>production, pay<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir owners for <strong>the</strong>m. Kirzner focuses on <strong>the</strong> net value<strong>of</strong> results rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> entrepreneur beyond all necessary factor payments.is pure pr<strong>of</strong>it deriv<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> entrepreneur’s creation is <strong>the</strong>subject <strong>of</strong> Kirzner’s dist<strong>in</strong>ctive <strong>the</strong>ory.Allegedly, as Kirzner notes, discoveries depend on good luck, whichseems a weak basis for capitalist property rights. But luck does not operatealone; motivated alertness also enters <strong>in</strong>to discovery (1989, pp. 161–162;1992b, pp. 221ff.; F.A. Hayek speaks somewhere <strong>of</strong> F<strong>in</strong>digkeit).Kirzner does not ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that a factual account <strong>of</strong> discovery <strong>and</strong> creationby itself constitutes a justification <strong>of</strong> capitalism; he does not claimto be dissolv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> dichotomy between “is” <strong>and</strong> “ought.” He appeals notonly to economics but also, as he must, to moral <strong>in</strong>tuitions (about whichI say more below). Kirzner f<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong> “entitlement” <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> John Locke, John Bates Clark,<strong>and</strong> Robert Nozick not downright wrong but <strong>in</strong>complete or <strong>in</strong>adequate.ese <strong>the</strong>orists tacitly take <strong>the</strong> economic pie, or <strong>the</strong> resources used to


Chapter : Kirzner on <strong>the</strong> Morality <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Pr<strong>of</strong>it 409produce it, as given. ey deal with <strong>the</strong> supposed issue <strong>of</strong> justice <strong>in</strong> appropriat<strong>in</strong>gwhat already exists. Once, though, we recognize <strong>the</strong> creativeness<strong>of</strong> entrepreneurial discovery, “we can no longer be satisfied with a moralphilosophy which, <strong>in</strong> its consideration <strong>of</strong> property rights <strong>and</strong> property<strong>in</strong>stitutions, treats <strong>the</strong> world as if <strong>the</strong> future is an unend<strong>in</strong>g series <strong>of</strong> fullyperceived manna-deposits wait<strong>in</strong>g to be assigned <strong>and</strong> distributed” (1989,p. 150; cf. p. 161). As for pure pr<strong>of</strong>it, John Bates Clark’s purported marg<strong>in</strong>alproductivitydefense <strong>of</strong> capitalist distribution does not even claim to dealwith it.Nozick’s <strong>the</strong>ory is unsatisfactory <strong>in</strong> a fur<strong>the</strong>r way. It relies on JohnLocke’s justification <strong>of</strong> private appropriation <strong>of</strong> previously unowned resourcesfrom nature. e appropriator acquires just title by mix<strong>in</strong>g hisown labor with <strong>the</strong>m, labor assumed to be unquestionably his property.Locke hedges this justification with <strong>the</strong> proviso that <strong>the</strong> appropriatorleave “enough <strong>and</strong> as good” resources available for latecomers. is provisocan scarcely ever be met, however, s<strong>in</strong>ce appropriat<strong>in</strong>g resources froman unowned common stock br<strong>in</strong>gs closer a stage at which a subsequentappropriator simply could not leave “enough <strong>and</strong> as good” available forstill later would-be appropriators (1989, pp. 156–157). It is no answer topostulate that <strong>the</strong> resources are so superabundant <strong>in</strong> relation not only topresent human wants but even to all future wants that <strong>the</strong>y would neverbecome economically scarce. Few if any resources meet such a specification,leav<strong>in</strong>g Locke’s <strong>the</strong>ory relevant only to an imag<strong>in</strong>ary world. If anyresources were <strong>in</strong>exhaustibly abundant <strong>and</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>ed to rema<strong>in</strong> free goodsforever, <strong>the</strong>y would hardly be resources <strong>in</strong> an economic sense; <strong>and</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>m private property would be po<strong>in</strong>tless <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place. It is only <strong>in</strong> aworld <strong>of</strong> scarcity that private property matters.S<strong>in</strong>ce Kirzner’s doctr<strong>in</strong>e does not perta<strong>in</strong> to appropriation <strong>of</strong> alreadyexist<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs, it is unencumbered by any Lockean proviso (1992b, p. 225).In see<strong>in</strong>g that some hi<strong>the</strong>rto unrecognized <strong>and</strong> valueless aspect <strong>of</strong> naturemight be put to economic use, <strong>the</strong> alert entrepreneur <strong>in</strong> effect creates <strong>the</strong>result. He cannot deprive anyone <strong>of</strong> what did not previously exist. Noquestion arises <strong>of</strong> leav<strong>in</strong>g “enough <strong>and</strong> as good” for o<strong>the</strong>rs.David Schmidtz (1991, chap. 2) confronts <strong>the</strong> Lockean proviso <strong>in</strong> away different from but reconcilable with Kirzner’s. Schmidtz reformulatesit as justify<strong>in</strong>g an appropriation <strong>of</strong> resources from nature if it doesnot worsen <strong>and</strong> especially if it improves <strong>the</strong> opportunities open to o<strong>the</strong>rpersons. Institut<strong>in</strong>g private property does <strong>in</strong> general do so, while leav<strong>in</strong>gth<strong>in</strong>gs owned by no one or owned <strong>in</strong> common practically ensures <strong>the</strong>ir


410 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyru<strong>in</strong> through a “tragedy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> commons” (as Hard<strong>in</strong> 1968/1969 called it).A commons is tragic precisely when th<strong>in</strong>gs are economically scarce <strong>and</strong>leav<strong>in</strong>g “enough <strong>and</strong> as good” for everyone just is not possible. By avoid<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> tragedy, private property gives even people o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itial appropriatorsmore <strong>and</strong> better opportunities to prosper from specialization,trade, <strong>the</strong> prudent adm<strong>in</strong>istration <strong>of</strong> resources, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong>wealth.Beyond his own dist<strong>in</strong>ctive contributions, Kirzner well underst<strong>and</strong>so<strong>the</strong>r str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> justification <strong>of</strong> private property <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it. Purepr<strong>of</strong>it, or <strong>the</strong> lure <strong>of</strong> it, helps mobilize entrepreneurial alertness, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>galertness to potential wants <strong>of</strong> consumers, <strong>and</strong> helps transfer controlover resources out <strong>of</strong> relatively less <strong>in</strong>to relatively more competent h<strong>and</strong>s.Kirzner knows about decentralized decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> scatteredknowledge, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> productivity <strong>of</strong> a capitalist system. But he does notdwell on <strong>the</strong>se familiar <strong>the</strong>mes because he wants to answer criticisms <strong>of</strong>capitalism made on moral grounds. Defense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> capitalist system does not extend to whatever occurs with<strong>in</strong>it. Kirzner would contend (I am confident) that transfer-seek<strong>in</strong>g throughgovernment, even when done by entrepreneurs, is not capitalism. Bus<strong>in</strong>essalertness does not justify just anyth<strong>in</strong>g (1989, p. 177). We may moralizeaga<strong>in</strong>st traders who exploit <strong>the</strong> impossibility <strong>of</strong> sharply del<strong>in</strong>eat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>legal from <strong>the</strong> illegal, or even <strong>the</strong> moral from <strong>the</strong> immoral. No system canmake legal, moral, <strong>and</strong> actual behaviors fully co<strong>in</strong>cide. Part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rationale<strong>of</strong> ethics is that it can deal, flexibly, with <strong>in</strong>numerable <strong>in</strong>dividual cases thatcould not be foreseen <strong>in</strong> detail <strong>and</strong> for which detailed rules could not belaid out <strong>in</strong> advance.Kirzner is uneasy at <strong>the</strong> imag<strong>in</strong>ary case <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> several travelers <strong>in</strong>a desert who races ahead to appropriate a waterhole so he can charge <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>rs an exorbitant price for water (1979, pp. 222–223). He seems lessuneasy, though, than I would expect. Rac<strong>in</strong>g ahead implies already exist<strong>in</strong>gknowledge about <strong>the</strong> waterhole <strong>and</strong> its importance. Instead <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>ga creative discovery, <strong>the</strong> racer seizes a hold on his fellows by block<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mfrom an opportunity.More fundamentally, economic rivalry <strong>and</strong> market transactions arenot appropriate to all human relations. Not all behavior conform<strong>in</strong>g to<strong>the</strong> logic <strong>and</strong> ethics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> capitalist system is ethically acceptable for that


Chapter : Kirzner on <strong>the</strong> Morality <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Pr<strong>of</strong>it 411reason alone. Part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rationale <strong>of</strong> an ethical code is that it would beimpossible for <strong>the</strong> law to codify <strong>and</strong> enforce all desirable character traits<strong>and</strong> all desirable l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> behavior <strong>in</strong> all imag<strong>in</strong>able <strong>and</strong> unimag<strong>in</strong>able circumstances.e logic <strong>of</strong> an ethical code requires adher<strong>in</strong>g to its spiritra<strong>the</strong>r than to m<strong>in</strong>utely specified rules; it requires a certa<strong>in</strong> flexibility <strong>in</strong>its application. People’s moral obligations toward one ano<strong>the</strong>r depend onmany circumstances, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g what k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong> degree <strong>of</strong> solidarity or loyaltyamong <strong>the</strong>m are appropriate.In <strong>the</strong> impersonal market relations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nationwide <strong>and</strong> worldwide“great society” or “extended order” (as Hayek 1989 calls it), no specialsolidarity or loyalty is appropriate—noth<strong>in</strong>g beyond honorable deal<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> refra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g from ly<strong>in</strong>g, cheat<strong>in</strong>g, steal<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> coercion. e situationis different with<strong>in</strong> relatively small <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>timate groups—family, friends,<strong>and</strong> perhaps enthusiasts devoted to some shared cause. In such groups,<strong>the</strong> attitudes <strong>of</strong> solidarity <strong>and</strong> altruism, presumably <strong>in</strong>herited biologicallyfrom <strong>the</strong> prehistoric days <strong>of</strong> life <strong>in</strong> small hunter-ga<strong>the</strong>rer b<strong>and</strong>s, are moreappropriate. Even or especially with<strong>in</strong> an impersonal extended order, <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>timacy available with<strong>in</strong> small, close-knit groups has great psychologicalvalue. With<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, emulat<strong>in</strong>g market behavior, pursu<strong>in</strong>g narrow self<strong>in</strong>terest,<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g on cost/benefit calculations <strong>and</strong> careful measurements<strong>of</strong> quid pro quo would be destructive. Such market-oriented behaviorwould subvert <strong>the</strong> solidarity <strong>and</strong> loyalty appropriate to such groups <strong>and</strong>would tend to “crush” <strong>the</strong>m (Hayek 1989, p. 18).Venturers on an expedition through a hazardous desert, like explorers<strong>in</strong> Antarctica, are <strong>in</strong> a sense colleagues, even if <strong>the</strong>y happen not to belongto <strong>the</strong> same organized group, or so it seems to me. ey owe a certa<strong>in</strong>extra respect, solidarity, <strong>and</strong> loyalty to one ano<strong>the</strong>r. Character traits conduciveto recogniz<strong>in</strong>g this special obligation are praiseworthy on broadly<strong>the</strong> same utilitarian grounds that underp<strong>in</strong> ethical pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> general. Toturn <strong>the</strong> adventure <strong>in</strong>to a zero-sum struggle, to “race ahead” for a chanceto exploit one’s colleagues, manifests antisocial traits. To condone suchbehavior <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ethics <strong>of</strong> capitalism would ill serve both capitalism<strong>and</strong> ethics.In ano<strong>the</strong>r case, also, Kirzner implies some unease about <strong>the</strong> morallegitimacy <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it. He repeatedly (e.g., 1989, pp. 49–50) mentions PaulSamuelson’s example <strong>of</strong> a commodity speculator who reaps a big pr<strong>of</strong>it bylearn<strong>in</strong>g about a crop failure just m<strong>in</strong>utes before o<strong>the</strong>r traders do. Trueenough, speculators perform a socially useful function <strong>in</strong> acquir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formationrelevant to <strong>the</strong> tim<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> consumption <strong>of</strong> scarce goods <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>


412 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyus<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>in</strong>formation to affect prices appropriately. But just what justifies<strong>the</strong> big pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong> Samuelson’s slightly early speculator?If we agree that his w<strong>in</strong>dfall is unjustified, we agree with fuller knowledge<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> situation—after all, we ourselves thought it up—than people <strong>in</strong>a comparable real-world situation would possess before h<strong>in</strong>dsight becameavailable. Anyway, what do we morally disapprove <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong> such a case? Weprobably would feel revulsion at pr<strong>of</strong>it<strong>in</strong>g through somehow delay<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>availability <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation to o<strong>the</strong>rs. Obstruct<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> transfer <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formationis <strong>the</strong> opposite <strong>of</strong> productive.Someone who is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> bear<strong>in</strong>g risks, however, hop<strong>in</strong>g topr<strong>of</strong>it on average over time from his superior <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>cts <strong>and</strong> decisiveness,is render<strong>in</strong>g a public service. If on occasion he is alert enough or evenjust lucky enough to receive pr<strong>of</strong>itable <strong>in</strong>formation early, well, that is part<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> game. We could hardly expect speculators to operate if <strong>the</strong>y hadto st<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir losses from bad luck <strong>the</strong>mselves but were never allowed tokeep <strong>the</strong> fruits <strong>of</strong> good luck.Differences <strong>in</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> prices enter <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> question, faced byKirzner (e.g., 1989, p. 104), whe<strong>the</strong>r transactions made <strong>in</strong> ignorance <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> full potential values <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs exchanged are never<strong>the</strong>less trulyvoluntary. Robert Nozick (1974) l<strong>in</strong>ked <strong>the</strong> moral legitimacy <strong>of</strong> hold<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>of</strong> property to <strong>the</strong>ir acquisition <strong>in</strong> voluntary transactions. Suppose—myexample, not Kirzner’s—that an art dealer sees <strong>the</strong> great value <strong>of</strong> anold pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g brought to him by its un<strong>in</strong>formed owner. <strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> dealermorally justified <strong>in</strong> exploit<strong>in</strong>g its owner’s ignorance by buy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gcheap?Possibly he is, provided he had made it clear that he was a sharp tradergreedy even for questionable ga<strong>in</strong>s. Ord<strong>in</strong>arily, though, or so I underst<strong>and</strong>,art dealers at least tacitly represent <strong>the</strong>mselves as experts comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>roles <strong>of</strong> brokers, dealers on <strong>the</strong>ir own account, <strong>and</strong> de facto advisers; <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>y want to deserve a long-run reputation for honorable deal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> all<strong>the</strong>se pr<strong>of</strong>essional capacities. Ord<strong>in</strong>arily, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> dealer has some fiduciaryobligation to a novice who comes to him possibly for a bus<strong>in</strong>ess dealbut also partly for advice. More generally, it may be <strong>in</strong> a bus<strong>in</strong>ess firm’sown long-run <strong>in</strong>terest to lean over backwards <strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g honest, tell<strong>in</strong>g notjust <strong>the</strong> truth but <strong>the</strong> whole relevant truth. e just price is not an entirelynonsensical notion. (Kirzner is <strong>in</strong>deed aware, e.g., 1979, p. 209, <strong>of</strong> notions<strong>of</strong> honor, fiduciary responsibility, <strong>and</strong> just price.)Similar issues arise about <strong>the</strong> moral legitimacy <strong>of</strong> stock-market pr<strong>of</strong>itsderiv<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>in</strong>side <strong>in</strong>formation. Much depends on <strong>the</strong> details, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g


Chapter : Kirzner on <strong>the</strong> Morality <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Pr<strong>of</strong>it 413how <strong>the</strong> trader came by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> what fiduciary obligations hemight have to <strong>the</strong> various parties <strong>in</strong>volved.What policy implications follow from imag<strong>in</strong>ed cases like those <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> person who races ahead to <strong>the</strong> oasis, Samuelson’s commodity speculator,<strong>the</strong> art dealer, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sider trader? It would be extremely difficultto draw up specific rules that would suitably cover all such conceivablecases. Much behavior must be left to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formal pressures <strong>of</strong> moral judgments<strong>and</strong> reputation effects. We scarcely want—do we?—to establish agovernment authority charged with apprais<strong>in</strong>g everyone’s moral entitlementto each bit <strong>of</strong> his <strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong> with rectify<strong>in</strong>g allocations <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>comedeemed unjustified. Institutions <strong>and</strong> policies simply cannot be devised toguarantee ethically appeal<strong>in</strong>g detailed outcomes <strong>in</strong> each <strong>in</strong>dividual case.As Rutledge V<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g (1984) emphasizes, legislators do not have a h<strong>and</strong>leon ultimate outcomes; <strong>the</strong>y can only t<strong>in</strong>ker with rules <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions.A discoverer does not <strong>in</strong> general have an obligation to share <strong>the</strong> fruits<strong>of</strong> his discovery just because a rival would soon have made <strong>the</strong> same discoveryon his own anyway. In Kirzner’s example (1989, pp. 167–169), oneperson on a beach stealthily but legitimately snatches a spectacular seashellfrom beneath <strong>the</strong> nose <strong>of</strong> someone entranced by <strong>the</strong> sunset. He has not“blocked discovery” by <strong>the</strong> sunset-watcher; he has simply been more alert.In o<strong>the</strong>r cases, however, one transactor may have a moral duty todivulge <strong>in</strong>formation to ano<strong>the</strong>r, although failure to do so does not necessarilyentitle <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r person to claim that he was robbed or cheated(1989, p. 170). “ere appear to be a number <strong>of</strong> moral gradations, <strong>in</strong> regardto <strong>the</strong> reprehensibility <strong>of</strong> ga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g benefit by failure to disclose available<strong>in</strong>formation” (1989, pp. 170–171). Doubts about <strong>the</strong> decency <strong>of</strong> benefit<strong>in</strong>gfrom <strong>the</strong> removable ignorance <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs seem to recede <strong>the</strong> more impersonal<strong>the</strong> relation is between <strong>the</strong> parties (1989, p. 171). Although we maywell sympathize with persons whose ignorance is exploited, we shouldconsider that <strong>the</strong>y would probably be even less well <strong>in</strong>formed <strong>and</strong> lesswell-<strong>of</strong>f than under some system <strong>in</strong> which entrepreneurial pr<strong>of</strong>it were notallowed to provide <strong>the</strong> driv<strong>in</strong>g motivation (1989, p. 171). Let us step back from our dubious or borderl<strong>in</strong>e cases <strong>and</strong> focus on wealththat <strong>the</strong> holder <strong>in</strong>disputably has created or has received by <strong>in</strong>disputablyvoluntary transactions unta<strong>in</strong>ted by ignorance. Even <strong>the</strong>n, can we be surethat <strong>the</strong> holder is morally entitled to his wealth? Kirzner (1989, pp. 101–102)


414 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophymentions Robert Nozick’s (1974, pp. 161–163) hypo<strong>the</strong>tical example <strong>of</strong> WiltChamberla<strong>in</strong>, who arranges for spectators to pay an additional 25 centsearmarked for him beyond <strong>the</strong> regular price <strong>of</strong> admission to his basketballgames. Nozick holds Chamberla<strong>in</strong> fully entitled to this <strong>in</strong>come. Still,one might disagree. By pay<strong>in</strong>g voluntarily, <strong>the</strong> spectators are not necessarilyapprov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial arrangements <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> additional <strong>in</strong>equality<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come distribution that results; <strong>the</strong>y are not necessarily <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>gopposition to a supposed remedy through redistributionary taxation. e<strong>in</strong>dividual spectator might realize that he alone could not thwart <strong>the</strong> antiegalitarianresult by boycott<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> game, so he might as well attend if hevalues <strong>the</strong> performance sufficiently more than <strong>the</strong> ticket price plus Chamberla<strong>in</strong>’s25 cents. Partly because, <strong>in</strong> economists’ jargon, an externality isoperat<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> voluntar<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> transactions does not automaticallyconfer moral legitimacy on Chamberla<strong>in</strong>’s wealth. James Buchanan (1977,chap. 4) argues, <strong>in</strong> part, that Chamberla<strong>in</strong>’s large <strong>in</strong>come is an economicrent, itself largely attributable to <strong>the</strong> society <strong>in</strong> which he has <strong>the</strong> goodfortune <strong>of</strong> perform<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> that o<strong>the</strong>r, equally voluntary, arrangementscould distribute this rent much differently. Although I myself dislike <strong>the</strong>attitude <strong>of</strong> my hypo<strong>the</strong>tical spectator, nei<strong>the</strong>r that critic nor Buchanancommits a logical fallacy.In e Mirage <strong>of</strong> Social Justice (1976) <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r works, F.A. Hayek dismissed“social justice” as an empty pair <strong>of</strong> words. Although one mightspeak <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> justice or <strong>in</strong>justice <strong>of</strong> a deliberate parcel<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> an exist<strong>in</strong>gstock <strong>of</strong> goods, such an evaluation cannot perta<strong>in</strong> to <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>of</strong> distribution<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong> wealth that results, unplanned by anyone, from<strong>the</strong> market process <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>numerable decentralized decisions. (e result <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> market process is not even a “distribution” <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> strict, etymologicalsense.) One might as well discuss <strong>the</strong> justice or <strong>in</strong>justice <strong>of</strong> naturalphenomena.Although I have not looked up adverse reviews <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s work, Ican well imag<strong>in</strong>e a critic reply<strong>in</strong>g that it is unjust to leave a particular distribution<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong> wealth uncorrected, however spontaneous it is<strong>and</strong> however little it is anyone’s fault, if it can be corrected without unacceptableside effects. Bad luck, or unfair shakes from nature, can <strong>in</strong> somecircumstances <strong>and</strong> to some extent be remedied by be<strong>in</strong>g shared. Leav<strong>in</strong>gremediable bad luck never<strong>the</strong>less unremedied might reasonably—I do notsay conclusively—be deemed unfair.Defenders <strong>of</strong> capitalism will have to do better than simply dismissdiscussions <strong>of</strong> social justice <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>justice as hav<strong>in</strong>g no subject matter but


Chapter : Kirzner on <strong>the</strong> Morality <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Pr<strong>of</strong>it 415mirages. John Rawls (1971) may have been wrong <strong>in</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g about rectification<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural distribution <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>g forth his “differencepr<strong>in</strong>ciple” <strong>of</strong> distribution, but he was not writ<strong>in</strong>g nonsense.Let us milk <strong>the</strong> Wilt Chamberla<strong>in</strong> example fur<strong>the</strong>r. Chamberla<strong>in</strong>’slarge <strong>in</strong>come flows from no special moral merit; he just enjoys <strong>the</strong> goodluck <strong>of</strong> possess<strong>in</strong>g talents that happen to comm<strong>and</strong> a high price. We mightfur<strong>the</strong>r compla<strong>in</strong> about <strong>the</strong> bad taste among fans that confers big rewardson not particularly meritorious sports figures.In e Constitution <strong>of</strong> Liberty (1960, chap. 6) F.A. Hayek does face<strong>the</strong> criticism that a free-market economy confers material rewards <strong>in</strong> anunjust way. e market values <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> services <strong>of</strong> people <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir propertydepend on many circumstances <strong>and</strong> seldom correspond to people’s moralmerit. Some defenders <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market system deny <strong>the</strong> charge, reply<strong>in</strong>gthat <strong>the</strong> market does <strong>in</strong>deed, if only <strong>in</strong> a rough <strong>and</strong> ready way, distributerewards <strong>in</strong> proportion to merit. Hayek warns aga<strong>in</strong>st this reply:Any attempt to found <strong>the</strong> case for freedom on this argument is verydamag<strong>in</strong>g to it, s<strong>in</strong>ce it concedes that material rewards ought to be madeto correspond to recognizable merit <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n opposes <strong>the</strong> conclusionthat most people will draw from this by an assertion which is untrue. eproper answer is that <strong>in</strong> a free system it is nei<strong>the</strong>r desirable nor practicablethat material rewards should be made generally to correspond to whatmen recognize as merit <strong>and</strong> that it is an essential characteristic <strong>of</strong> a freesociety that an <strong>in</strong>dividual’s position should not necessarily depend on<strong>the</strong> views that his fellows hold about <strong>the</strong> merit he has acquired. (1960,pp. 94–95)Hayek goes on to exam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>of</strong> value <strong>and</strong> merit. He considers<strong>the</strong> advantages (connected with <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives) <strong>of</strong> lett<strong>in</strong>gmarket values guide people’s decisions about how to use <strong>the</strong>ir creativity<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir o<strong>the</strong>r abilities. He asks what <strong>in</strong>stitutions would be requiredfor try<strong>in</strong>g to implement <strong>the</strong> alternative pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> distribution accord<strong>in</strong>gto moral merit. He explores <strong>the</strong> psychological consequences <strong>of</strong> a state <strong>of</strong>affairs <strong>in</strong> which material rewards were supposed to be clear <strong>in</strong>dicators <strong>of</strong>moral merit. His exercise <strong>in</strong> comparative-<strong>in</strong>stitutional analysis leaves <strong>the</strong>thoughtful reader recoil<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> horror at <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> radically nonmarket-orientedmethods <strong>of</strong> distribution. His whole chapter 6 is worthponder<strong>in</strong>g at length.On ethical grounds, never<strong>the</strong>less, a critic might question whe<strong>the</strong>r aperson is truly entitled to whatever he has created through alert discovery


416 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyor created <strong>in</strong> some more literal <strong>and</strong> pedestrian way. One might even questiona person’s Lockean self-ownership <strong>of</strong> his own body. After all, JohnRawls (1971) argued that each person’s physical <strong>and</strong> mental capacities are<strong>in</strong> some respects a morally arbitrary gift <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> environment<strong>and</strong> so are properly at <strong>the</strong> disposal <strong>of</strong> society <strong>in</strong> general.I myself do not deny a person’s entitlement to his body <strong>and</strong> his creations;I do not agree with Rawls. I object, though, to prematurely rest<strong>in</strong>gjudgments on such issues on undiscussable sheer <strong>in</strong>tuitions. e judgments<strong>in</strong> question are not fundamental value judgments (to use a termthat will become clearer <strong>in</strong> what follows). ey are relatively specific judgmentsthat <strong>the</strong>mselves require ground<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> facts <strong>of</strong> reality <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> oneor more value judgments that are more nearly fundamental. Apprais<strong>in</strong>g capitalism on ethical grounds necessarily <strong>in</strong>volves both <strong>the</strong>facts about how <strong>the</strong> system operates <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ethical st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>the</strong>mselves.Kirzner specializes, quite legitimately, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> positive economics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>issue; but room rema<strong>in</strong>s to consider <strong>the</strong> sources <strong>and</strong> force <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prevail<strong>in</strong>gethical <strong>in</strong>tuitions taken for granted <strong>in</strong> his writ<strong>in</strong>gs reviewed here.Where did <strong>the</strong>se <strong>in</strong>tuitions come from? It seems plausible to trace<strong>the</strong>m to social <strong>and</strong> perhaps biological evolution: act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> accordance with<strong>the</strong>m conferred advantages on societies <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals. On <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong>F.A. Hayek (1989 <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r writ<strong>in</strong>gs), practices based on those <strong>in</strong>tuitionshave stood <strong>the</strong> test <strong>of</strong> social <strong>and</strong> perhaps biological evolution. Groupsadher<strong>in</strong>g to ethical precepts <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> behavior conduciveto survival <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> group <strong>and</strong> reproduction <strong>of</strong> its members do tendto flourish, while o<strong>the</strong>rs wi<strong>the</strong>r. Groups have a better chance to prosperunder traditions that conduce to <strong>the</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong> wealth <strong>and</strong> to trade,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g trade with outsiders. ese traditions concern private property,sav<strong>in</strong>g, voluntary exchange, truthfulness, promise-keep<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> contract.Favorable traditions ga<strong>in</strong> ground not only through transmission to successivegenerations but also by be<strong>in</strong>g imitated. Hayek knows that cultural natural selection works through trial <strong>and</strong> error <strong>and</strong>through mere tendencies toward eventual decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> societies with <strong>in</strong>expedient <strong>in</strong>stitutions<strong>and</strong> traditions—unless <strong>the</strong>y reform <strong>the</strong>mselves, perhaps by imitat<strong>in</strong>g more successfulsocieties. He <strong>the</strong>reby recognizes that errors do occur <strong>and</strong> can persist. He also knows thatdeliberate attention, with<strong>in</strong> a society, to how well or poorly its <strong>in</strong>stitutions are function<strong>in</strong>gplays a role <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> evolutionary process. Still, <strong>the</strong> process as a whole is not directed by a


Chapter : Kirzner on <strong>the</strong> Morality <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Pr<strong>of</strong>it 417Explanation <strong>of</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>s is not appraisal. Should one <strong>in</strong>deed approve<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuitions, precepts, <strong>and</strong> practices that conduce to <strong>the</strong> flourish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>groups <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals? Well, it is <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> value judgments—thisone <strong>in</strong>cluded—that <strong>the</strong>y cannot be established purely by facts <strong>and</strong> logic.Some element <strong>of</strong> sheer moral <strong>in</strong>tuition or emotion necessarily enters <strong>in</strong>to<strong>the</strong> story. A plausible sweep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tuition (though not an irreducibly fundamentalone) recommends what Ludwig von Mises <strong>and</strong> Henry Hazlitt, amongo<strong>the</strong>rs, have emphasized under <strong>the</strong> label social cooperation. Social cooperationcharacterizes a well-function<strong>in</strong>g society; it is <strong>the</strong> complex <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions,practices, shared ethical st<strong>and</strong>ards, <strong>and</strong> even attitudes that fosterpeace, security, specialization, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ga<strong>in</strong>s from trade <strong>and</strong> so ease fruitfulcooperation among <strong>in</strong>dividuals striv<strong>in</strong>g to make good lives for <strong>the</strong>mselves<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own diverse ways. Private property, <strong>the</strong> market, contractual liberty,voluntary associations, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> rule <strong>of</strong> law are key elements <strong>of</strong> it <strong>in</strong>successful modern societies. e idea, though not <strong>the</strong> actual term, goesback to David Hume <strong>and</strong> even to omas Hobbes, pioneers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> utilitariantradition. Social cooperation is much <strong>the</strong> same as what John Graycalls “civil society” <strong>and</strong> Michael Oakeshott called “civil association” (Gray1993, pp. 246, 275, <strong>and</strong> passim).A version <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism center<strong>in</strong>g on this concept appraises ethicalprecepts, k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> personal conduct, traits <strong>of</strong> character, <strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>and</strong>policy choices accord<strong>in</strong>g to how likely <strong>the</strong>y are to serve or subvert socialcooperation. It is practically <strong>the</strong> same th<strong>in</strong>g as a comparative-<strong>in</strong>stitutionsapproach to evaluation. An adherent <strong>of</strong> this doctr<strong>in</strong>e tries to contemplate<strong>and</strong> compare alternative sets <strong>of</strong> mutually compatible <strong>in</strong>stitutions. e criterion<strong>of</strong> social cooperation, toge<strong>the</strong>r with positive analysis <strong>in</strong> economics,psychology, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r discipl<strong>in</strong>es, recommends <strong>the</strong> precepts, attitudes,behaviors, <strong>and</strong> so forth conducive to an extended order, as Hayek callsit, <strong>and</strong> to many k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>timate relationships embedded <strong>in</strong> a healthyextended order. e criterion recommends truth-tell<strong>in</strong>g, promise-keep<strong>in</strong>g,justice, respect for persons <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual rights, respect for private property,<strong>the</strong> transfer <strong>of</strong> property by consent, <strong>and</strong> even, with<strong>in</strong> limits, honestpartiality towards oneself <strong>and</strong> one’s compatriots, friends, <strong>and</strong> associates.s<strong>in</strong>gle m<strong>in</strong>d or committee, <strong>and</strong> not all <strong>the</strong> knowledge operat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> it has been consciouslyarticulated.


418 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyBut social cooperation is only a nearly ultimate criterion. It is <strong>in</strong>strumentaltoward someth<strong>in</strong>g more completely ultimate, someth<strong>in</strong>g for whichno fur<strong>the</strong>r argument is possible, someth<strong>in</strong>g taken as desirable by sheer<strong>in</strong>tuition or emotion. at ultimately desirable “someth<strong>in</strong>g” is <strong>in</strong>dividuals’success <strong>in</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g, or fulfillment, or life appropriate to human potential. Nos<strong>in</strong>gle word is an adequate label; but when a s<strong>in</strong>gle word is required, <strong>the</strong>traditional choice is “happ<strong>in</strong>ess,” understood <strong>in</strong> a suitably stretched sense. Kirzner goes far toward justify<strong>in</strong>g capitalist pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>and</strong>distribution, as well as <strong>the</strong> system itself, by positive analysis comb<strong>in</strong>edwith appeal to simple <strong>and</strong> widely accepted ethical <strong>in</strong>tuitions. A person isentitled to what he himself creates or discovers <strong>and</strong> to what he obta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>a voluntary transaction from a previous owner whose title is undisputed.ese, however, are fairly specific <strong>in</strong>tuitions. When <strong>the</strong>y are questioned, asocial <strong>the</strong>orist rely<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong>m should be able to defend <strong>the</strong>m (conceivably Hayek (1989) appears to make survival, not happ<strong>in</strong>ess, <strong>the</strong> ultimate criterion. It doesseem plausible that <strong>the</strong> processes <strong>of</strong> biological <strong>and</strong> cultural selection have operated through<strong>the</strong> survival or elim<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>and</strong> groups, not through <strong>the</strong>ir happ<strong>in</strong>ess orunhapp<strong>in</strong>ess. Aga<strong>in</strong>, though, we must dist<strong>in</strong>guish between explanation <strong>and</strong> appraisal. In<strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> appraisal, we need not decide between survival <strong>and</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess as ultimatecriteria. S<strong>in</strong>ce social cooperation is prerequisite to both, it can serve as a surrrogate criterion.Only on a particularly rarefied level <strong>of</strong> philosophiz<strong>in</strong>g must we try to choose betweenrival ultimate criteria. Why is he entitled to his creation or discovery? A short answer, presumably, is thatsuch a rule holds down disputes <strong>and</strong> fosters social cooperation <strong>and</strong> creativity better thanany alternative would do.Kirzner calls his view <strong>of</strong> entitlement a “f<strong>in</strong>ders-keepers ethic” (e.g., 1992, p. 222; 1989,pp. 110–111, 166). While agree<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> substance <strong>of</strong> his doctr<strong>in</strong>e, I regret that label.In my own childhood experience, anyway, <strong>the</strong> full slogan was “f<strong>in</strong>ders keepers, losersweepers.” It conveyed a certa<strong>in</strong> grasp<strong>in</strong>gness comb<strong>in</strong>ed with a ra<strong>the</strong>r cynical unconcernfor whoever had lost or been unfairly done out <strong>of</strong> some item. Kirzner evokes <strong>the</strong> secondpart <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> slogan by mention<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>der’s entitlement to a co<strong>in</strong> that someone else hadlost <strong>in</strong> Times Square (1989, p. 153). I am confident, though, that Kirzner does not hold<strong>the</strong> attitude that <strong>the</strong> full slogan br<strong>in</strong>gs to my m<strong>in</strong>d.S<strong>in</strong>ce draft<strong>in</strong>g this paper <strong>and</strong> this note <strong>in</strong> particular, I have seen Ricketts’s 1992 paper.Ricketts aptly calls Kirzner’s “f<strong>in</strong>ders-keepers ethic” a “graspers-keepers ethic” (p. 80). Healso questions Kirzner’s position on <strong>the</strong> traveler who races ahead to appropriate <strong>the</strong> waterhole(pp. 76–78). Ricketts objects that Kirzner pays <strong>in</strong>adequate attention to <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong>property rights, even though his description <strong>of</strong> his imag<strong>in</strong>ary situation suggests that <strong>the</strong>waterhole, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g simply “unheld,” is already regarded as a communal asset that<strong>in</strong>dividuals are entitled to use.


Chapter : Kirzner on <strong>the</strong> Morality <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Pr<strong>of</strong>it 419modified <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir details) by fur<strong>the</strong>r positive analysis <strong>and</strong> by appeal to fur<strong>the</strong>r<strong>and</strong> more nearly fundamental ethical <strong>in</strong>tuitions. is fur<strong>the</strong>r analysiswill almost surely emphasize social cooperation <strong>and</strong> rely on a fundamentalvalue judgment aga<strong>in</strong>st misery <strong>and</strong> for happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>in</strong> a suitably stretchedsense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter term.Kirzner appears to adopt this utilitarian (<strong>in</strong>direct utilitarian) approach,which might also be called a comparative-<strong>in</strong>stitutions approach. Alternativesto it are conceivable—just barely, <strong>in</strong> my judgment. S<strong>in</strong>ce Kirznershows no sympathy for <strong>the</strong>m, however, <strong>the</strong>re is no need to review <strong>the</strong>mhere.e ultimate basis <strong>of</strong> Kirzner’s conclusions about entitlements to capitalistwealth <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it must be that a society operat<strong>in</strong>g with different(more collectivist) pr<strong>in</strong>ciples would function less well than a society embody<strong>in</strong>gbroadly classical liberal pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. It would “function less well”<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> afford<strong>in</strong>g its <strong>in</strong>dividual members <strong>in</strong>ferior prospects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>successful pursuit <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess.In conclusion, I quote one <strong>of</strong> several passages (1989, p. 177) suggest<strong>in</strong>gKirzner’s agreement with <strong>the</strong> position just sketched out:A defense <strong>of</strong> capitalist justice has not declared it <strong>in</strong>nocent <strong>of</strong> all moralflaws. It certa<strong>in</strong>ly has not declared all behaviour under historical capitalismto have been moral or even to have been just. A defense <strong>of</strong> capitalistjustice suggests, however, that <strong>the</strong> system that has been so extraord<strong>in</strong>arilyproductive <strong>in</strong> rais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>of</strong> human life need not be rejected out<strong>of</strong> h<strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> grounds <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>nate unfairness. Moral improvement maybe sought with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> capitalist framework, without harbor<strong>in</strong>g a guiltysense <strong>of</strong> participation <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>evitably <strong>and</strong> fundamentally flawed form <strong>of</strong>social organization.Buchanan, James M. Freedom <strong>in</strong> Constitutional Contract. College Station: TexasA&M University Press, 1977.Gray, John. Mill on Liberty: A Defence. London: Routledge, 1983. is approach is far from an “act utilitarianism” that would require mak<strong>in</strong>g each largeor small decision accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> apparent merits <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual case <strong>and</strong> withoutregard to fur<strong>the</strong>r pr<strong>in</strong>ciples or to <strong>in</strong>dividual rights. Such a crude version <strong>of</strong> utilitarianismhas by now, one hopes, become hardly more than a straw man beaten by superficial critics.What John Gray (1983) calls <strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism recognizes <strong>the</strong> great utility <strong>of</strong> abid<strong>in</strong>gby general pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>and</strong> not practic<strong>in</strong>g case-by-case expediency.


420 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy. Post-Liberalism: Studies <strong>in</strong> <strong>Political</strong> ought. London <strong>and</strong> New York:Routledge, 1993.Hard<strong>in</strong>, Garrett. “e Tragedy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Commons.” 1968. In Population, Evolution,<strong>and</strong> Birth Control, 2ⁿ ed., edited by Hard<strong>in</strong>, 367–381. San Francisco: Freeman,1969.Hayek, F.A. e Constitution <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press,1960.. e Mirage <strong>of</strong> Social Justice. Vol. 2 <strong>of</strong> Law, Legislation, <strong>and</strong> Liberty.Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1976.. e Fatal Conceit. Edited by W.W. Bartley, III. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong>Chicago Press, 1989.Hazlitt, Henry. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Morality. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>,1964.Kirzner, <strong>Is</strong>rael M. Perception, Opportunity, <strong>and</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>it. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong>Chicago Press, 1979.. Discovery <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Capitalist Process. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1985.. Discovery, Capitalism, <strong>and</strong> Distributive Justice. Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York:Basil Blackwell, 1989.. “Commentary” on Mart<strong>in</strong> Ricketts’s paper. In Austrian Economics: Tensions<strong>and</strong> New Directions, edited by Bruce J. Caldwell <strong>and</strong> Stephan Boehm,85–102. Boston: Kluwer, 1992a.. e Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>Market</strong> Process. London <strong>and</strong> New York: Routledge,1992b.Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, <strong>and</strong> Utopia. New York: Basic Books, 1974.Rawls, John. A eory <strong>of</strong> Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press <strong>of</strong> HarvardUniversity Press, 1971.Ricketts, Mart<strong>in</strong>. “Kirzner’s eory <strong>of</strong> Entrepreneurship—A Critique.” In AustrianEconomics: Tensions <strong>and</strong> New Directions, edited by Bruce J. Caldwell <strong>and</strong>Stephan Boehm, 67–84. Boston: Kluwer, 1992.Schmidtz, David. e Limits <strong>of</strong> Government: An Essay on <strong>the</strong> Public Goods Argument.Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1991.


Chapter : Kirzner on <strong>the</strong> Morality <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Pr<strong>of</strong>it 421V<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, Rutledge. On Apprais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Performance <strong>of</strong> an Economic System. NewYork: Cambridge University Press, 1984.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law.” In eMean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Ludwig von Mises, edited by Jeffrey M. Herbener, 321–344. Norwell,Mass., <strong>and</strong> Dordrecht, Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s: Kluwer, 1993. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted here aschapter .. “Utility, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Contract: Some Reflections on Hayek’s Work.” Ine <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> <strong>of</strong> Freedom: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> Honor <strong>of</strong> F.A. Hayek, edited by KurtR. Leube <strong>and</strong> Albert H. Zlab<strong>in</strong>ger, 61–80. Munich <strong>and</strong> Vienna: PhilosophiaVerlag, 1985.


Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics,Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law *’ Ludwig von Mises was a utilitarian <strong>and</strong> has been criticized for be<strong>in</strong>g one.Utilitarianism is a particular approach to ethics <strong>in</strong> personal life <strong>and</strong> publicaffairs. It compares alternative sets <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions, laws, traditions, patterns<strong>and</strong> maxims <strong>and</strong> rules <strong>of</strong> behavior, <strong>and</strong> traits <strong>of</strong> personal character.It approves <strong>of</strong> those that support <strong>and</strong> disapproves <strong>of</strong> those that subvert <strong>the</strong>k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> society that affords people relatively good opportunities to makesatisfy<strong>in</strong>g lives for <strong>the</strong>mselves. Institutions <strong>and</strong> practices <strong>and</strong> attitudes thatfacilitate fruitful cooperation among <strong>in</strong>dividuals as <strong>the</strong>y pursue <strong>the</strong>ir owndiverse specific ends score ahead <strong>of</strong> ones that make for destructive clashes.“Social cooperation” (so called by Mises <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>kers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> utilitarian<strong>and</strong> libertarian traditions) is so nearly essential to <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ success<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own diverse pursuits that it is a nearly ultimate criterion <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions,ethical precepts, character traits, <strong>and</strong> so forth. On this criterion,truth-tell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> promise-keep<strong>in</strong>g comm<strong>and</strong> approval. So does respectfor justice, property rights, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r human rights.ese words are m<strong>in</strong>e, not Mises’s; but his stance on economic policydoes rest on an ethical underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g like <strong>the</strong> one just sketched out. Miseswrote bluntly. e <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> social cooperation elaborated by British politicaleconomy from Hume to Ricardo, he says,consummated <strong>the</strong> spiritual, moral <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual emancipation <strong>of</strong> mank<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>augurated by <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> Epicureanism. It substitutedan autonomous rational morality for <strong>the</strong> heteronomous <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuitionistethics <strong>of</strong> older days. Law <strong>and</strong> legality, <strong>the</strong> moral code <strong>and</strong> social*From e Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Ludwig von Mises, ed. Jeffrey M. Herbener (Auburn, Ala., <strong>and</strong>Norwell, Mass.: Ludwig von Mises Institute <strong>and</strong> Kluwer, 1993), 321–344. A few pages havebeen cut out here.422


Chapter : Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law 423<strong>in</strong>stitutions are no longer revered as unfathomable decrees <strong>of</strong> Heaven.ey are <strong>of</strong> human orig<strong>in</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> only yardstick that must be applied to<strong>the</strong>m is that <strong>of</strong> expediency with regard to human welfare. e utilitarianeconomist does not say: Fiat justitia, pereat mundus. He says: Fiat justitia,ne pereat mundus. He does not ask a man to renounce his well-be<strong>in</strong>gfor <strong>the</strong> benefit <strong>of</strong> society. He advises him to recognize what his rightlyunderstood <strong>in</strong>terests are. In his eyes God’s magnificence does not manifestitself <strong>in</strong> busy <strong>in</strong>terference with sundry affairs <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ces <strong>and</strong> politicians,but <strong>in</strong> endow<strong>in</strong>g his creatures with reason <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> urge toward <strong>the</strong>pursuit <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess. (Mises 1949/1963, p. 147)e ultimate yardstick <strong>of</strong> justice is conduciveness to <strong>the</strong> preservation<strong>of</strong> social cooperation ... [,] for almost every man <strong>the</strong> great means for<strong>the</strong> atta<strong>in</strong>ment <strong>of</strong> all ends. An em<strong>in</strong>ently human common <strong>in</strong>terest, <strong>the</strong>preservation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensification <strong>of</strong> social bonds, is substituted for pitilessbiological competition, <strong>the</strong> significant mark <strong>of</strong> animal <strong>and</strong> plant life.Man becomes a social be<strong>in</strong>g.... O<strong>the</strong>r people become his fellows.... Associal cooperation is ... a means <strong>and</strong> not an end, no unanimity withregard to value judgments is required to make it work.... [S]ocial cooperationis for man a means for <strong>the</strong> atta<strong>in</strong>ment <strong>of</strong> all his ends.... e characteristicfeature <strong>of</strong> a free society is that it can function <strong>in</strong> spite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>fact that its members disagree <strong>in</strong> many judgments <strong>of</strong> value. (1979/1985,pp. 54–61)By its recognition that social cooperation is for <strong>the</strong> immense majoritya means for atta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g all <strong>the</strong>ir ends, [utilitarianism] dispels <strong>the</strong> notionthat society, <strong>the</strong> state, <strong>the</strong> nation, or any o<strong>the</strong>r social entity is an ultimateend <strong>and</strong> that <strong>in</strong>dividual men are <strong>the</strong> slaves <strong>of</strong> that entity. It rejects <strong>the</strong>philosophies <strong>of</strong> universalism, collectivism, <strong>and</strong> totalitarianism. In thissense it is mean<strong>in</strong>gful to call utilitarianism a philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualism.(1979/1985, p. 58)As Murray Rothbard has correctly po<strong>in</strong>ted out (1982, p. 212), no onecan ever advocate any policy whatsoever on a purely scientific, value-freebasis. Mises would agree. No one can approve or disapprove <strong>of</strong> a particularpolicy or <strong>of</strong> anyth<strong>in</strong>g at all without hold<strong>in</strong>g at least one ultimate orfundamental value judgment. A judgment is ultimate <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense that itsholder, <strong>in</strong> express<strong>in</strong>g it, has come to <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g able to give factual<strong>and</strong> logical reasons for his attitudes. For Mises <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r utilitarians, <strong>the</strong>fundamental value judgment is approval <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> disapproval <strong>of</strong>misery. (One can argue for or aga<strong>in</strong>st particular policies, lifestyles, <strong>and</strong> so On fundamental value judgments, see Paul Edwards 1965; Sidney S. Alex<strong>and</strong>er 1967,esp. pp. 105–107 <strong>and</strong> 114–115; <strong>and</strong> Amartya K. Sen 1970, esp. pp. 62–64.


424 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyforth by try<strong>in</strong>g to show that <strong>the</strong>y tend toward happ<strong>in</strong>ess or misery; butI cannot imag<strong>in</strong>e how one could argue for happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong>st misery<strong>the</strong>mselves. But if one could so argue, <strong>the</strong> argument would necessarily<strong>in</strong>voke some fur<strong>the</strong>r, deeper, value judgment, which would <strong>the</strong>n be <strong>the</strong>fundamental one.)Mises hastens to disavow hedonism <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> narrow sense: despite superficialcritics, “happ<strong>in</strong>ess” does not mean mere material, bodily pleasures.Advanced utilitarians, he says, <strong>in</strong>terpret pleasure <strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>, utility <strong>and</strong> disutility,<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> “purely formal” senses <strong>of</strong> those words, empty<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m <strong>of</strong> allspecific content. ey refer to whatever <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> fact try to achieveor avoid (Mises 1933/1960, pp. 52, 151; Mises 1979/1985, pp. 12–13; Mises1949/1963, p. 21). Mises recognizes that many people, especially creativeworkers, are not driven by material desires or narrow self-<strong>in</strong>terest alone.ey may also be express<strong>in</strong>g competence <strong>and</strong> strength <strong>and</strong> even heroism(Mises 1919/1983, pp. 193, 213). “ere are people whose only aim is toimprove <strong>the</strong> condition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own ego. ere are o<strong>the</strong>r people with whomawareness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> troubles <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir fellow men causes as much uneas<strong>in</strong>essas or even more uneas<strong>in</strong>ess than <strong>the</strong>ir own wants” (1949/1963, p. 14).Mises’s remarks about <strong>the</strong> merely formal content <strong>of</strong> “happ<strong>in</strong>ess” hardlysettle all questions about fundamental value judgments. Room rema<strong>in</strong>s fordiscuss<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> utilitarian criterion should be <strong>the</strong> true happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>dividuals or <strong>in</strong>stead, if <strong>the</strong>re is a difference, <strong>the</strong> satisfaction <strong>of</strong> whateverdesires <strong>in</strong>dividuals suppose <strong>the</strong>y have. Still, Mises is on <strong>the</strong> right track.“Happ<strong>in</strong>ess,” before be<strong>in</strong>g unpacked, is an <strong>in</strong>adequate term for <strong>the</strong> ultimateutilitarian value judgment. I can only take stabs at label<strong>in</strong>g whatis ultimately desirable: it is <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ success <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g good lives for<strong>the</strong>mselves, or fulfillment, or satisfaction, or life appropriate to humanpotentiality. No s<strong>in</strong>gle word is an adequate label; but when a s<strong>in</strong>gle wordis required as shorth<strong>and</strong>, “happ<strong>in</strong>ess” is <strong>the</strong> traditional choice.is formulation might be criticized as be<strong>in</strong>g all-encompass<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> vacuousness. Yet it is not vacuous: alternative criteria are conceivable.ey <strong>in</strong>clude conformity to <strong>the</strong> supposed will <strong>of</strong> God; or performance<strong>of</strong> duty for duty’s sake alone, with no analysis <strong>of</strong> consequencesenter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> identification <strong>of</strong> duties; or conformity to <strong>in</strong>tuited ethicalprecepts for conformity’s sake alone; or respect for <strong>in</strong>dividual rights thathave simply been postulated ra<strong>the</strong>r than argued for on utilitarian or anyo<strong>the</strong>r grounds, <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong> regardless <strong>of</strong> consequences; or conduciveness to<strong>the</strong> flourish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest or noblest specimens <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human race,however ord<strong>in</strong>ary people might <strong>the</strong>n fare (a view sometimes attributed,


Chapter : Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law 425rightly or wrongly, to Nietzsche). Or <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> “happ<strong>in</strong>ess”<strong>of</strong> people <strong>in</strong> general as <strong>the</strong> criterion <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> precepts <strong>and</strong> s<strong>of</strong>orth, one might conceivably urge <strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> oneself or some o<strong>the</strong>rspecific person.at <strong>the</strong>se alternatives are conceivable shows that <strong>the</strong> utilitarian criterionis not vacuous, while <strong>the</strong>ir implausibility streng<strong>the</strong>ns its own appeal.As a practical matter, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, utilitarianism does not h<strong>in</strong>ge on anyexact spell<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> its fundamental value judgment. Its fulfillment isserved by social cooperation—a well-function<strong>in</strong>g network <strong>of</strong> beneficialrelations among <strong>in</strong>dividuals. Institutions, precepts, <strong>and</strong> so forth may beappraised accord<strong>in</strong>g to how <strong>the</strong>y support or subvert this crucial means tohapp<strong>in</strong>ess, without constant appeal to any precise <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> “happ<strong>in</strong>ess”itself.With characteristic bluntness, Mises denies that utilitarian philosophyhas anyth<strong>in</strong>g to do with <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> natural rights. He has a po<strong>in</strong>t:respect for rights is ill served by a faulty defense. Rights are not merelyconferred by government; ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y derive from ethical precepts, which<strong>in</strong> turn have a rational underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g. Utilitarianism, Mises says, recommends“popular government, private property, tolerance, <strong>and</strong> freedomnot because <strong>the</strong>y are natural <strong>and</strong> just, but because <strong>the</strong>y are beneficial....[S]ocial cooperation <strong>and</strong> division <strong>of</strong> labor ... is beneficial.” With apparentapproval, Mises quotes Bentham: “Natural rights is simple nonsense:natural <strong>and</strong> imprescriptible rights, rhetorical nonsense.” In <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>gwhat ought to be right, Bentham “does not care about preconceived ideasconcern<strong>in</strong>g God’s or nature’s plans <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentions, forever hidden to mortalmen; he is <strong>in</strong>tent upon discover<strong>in</strong>g what best serves <strong>the</strong> promotion <strong>of</strong>human welfare <strong>and</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess” (1949/1963, p. 174).Mises occasionally slipped <strong>in</strong>to repeat<strong>in</strong>g slogans about “<strong>the</strong> greatesthapp<strong>in</strong>ess for <strong>the</strong> greatest number” (1919/1983, p. 183). Such a formulation,taken literally, has no precise mean<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>of</strong> course. All that Mises presumablymeant by it is that <strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess to be fur<strong>the</strong>red by social <strong>in</strong>stitutions<strong>and</strong> practices is <strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> people <strong>in</strong> general—<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> member<strong>of</strong> society chosen at r<strong>and</strong>om, <strong>in</strong> F.A. Hayek’s formulation (Hayek 1967,p. 163; Hayek 1976, pp. 129–130)—ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> differential happ<strong>in</strong>ess<strong>of</strong> specific persons or classes. Mises specifically repudiated any numericalutilitarianism such as critics enjoy attack<strong>in</strong>g. He denied that “it is<strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> economics to establish how <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong> society <strong>the</strong> greatestpossible satisfaction <strong>of</strong> all people or <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> greatest number could beatta<strong>in</strong>ed.... [T]here is no method which would allow us to measure <strong>the</strong>


426 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophystate <strong>of</strong> satisfaction atta<strong>in</strong>ed by various <strong>in</strong>dividuals” <strong>and</strong> make “comparison[s]between various people’s happ<strong>in</strong>ess”(Mises 1949/1963, p. 242).Mises’s utilitarianism has drawn criticism even from students <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs<strong>in</strong>spired by his work. I do not ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that Mises expounded <strong>the</strong>subtlest versions <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism, complete with dist<strong>in</strong>ctions betweenact utilitarianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> various “rule” or “<strong>in</strong>direct” versions. He waswrit<strong>in</strong>g before most philosophical treatments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se subtleties werepublished. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> subtleties were not essential to his ma<strong>in</strong>concerns, <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> applied economics. Still, his basic philosophicalstance is worth defend<strong>in</strong>g (Hazlitt 1964 <strong>of</strong>fers an admirably detaileddefense).One <strong>of</strong> his critics, Karen Vaughn regretted thatMises, unfortunately, attempted to refute <strong>the</strong> collectivists <strong>and</strong> authoritariansby accept<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir argument <strong>and</strong> argu<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> superiorability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free market to provide for <strong>the</strong> economic well-be<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> populace.... Such an attempt to defend freedom is dangerouson two counts. First, it is open to empirical refutation. (Vaughn 1976,p. 109)Second, such a defense is dangerous because <strong>of</strong> “nonmaterial items<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual utility functions” (1976, p. 109). Bureaucrats may enjoy controll<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> regulat<strong>in</strong>g. If <strong>the</strong>ir utilities should be taken <strong>in</strong>to account <strong>and</strong>if <strong>in</strong>terpersonal comparisons are not possible, how can we be sure that anonliberal system will not provide “maximum social welfare”?Vaughn seems to approve <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reported <strong>in</strong>tellectual outlook <strong>in</strong> seventeenth-centuryEngl<strong>and</strong>, when liberalism was emerg<strong>in</strong>g. en, she says,“freedom was considered ... desirable for its own sake [as] a natural condition<strong>of</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>gs.... It was a moral value that, as a bonus, also happenedto lead to <strong>the</strong> well-be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> society.” e utilitarian argument simplyprovided “additional fire power.” “By <strong>the</strong> time <strong>of</strong> John Stuart Mill,however, <strong>the</strong> argument became reversed, <strong>and</strong> freedom was espoused, notbecause it was a good <strong>in</strong> itself, but because it led to <strong>the</strong> ‘greatest good for<strong>the</strong> greatest number’” (p. 108).Possibly I have misunderstood her, but Vaughn does seem to say thatMises was wrong to develop arguments for freedom because <strong>the</strong>y mightconceivably be refuted <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> case for freedom <strong>the</strong>reby embarrassed. To


Chapter : Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law 427forestall embarrassment, it is better not to argue any case but simply topostulate freedom as a supreme value. Admittedly, someone who mountsno arguments need fear no refutations; but why, <strong>the</strong>n, should he expectanyone to pay attention? As for freedom’s supposedly just happen<strong>in</strong>g, as abonus, to promote “<strong>the</strong> well-be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> society,” Mises might well ask whatcould constitute that well-be<strong>in</strong>g except <strong>the</strong> well-be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals. Andhow, apart from enter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to or contribut<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>ir well-be<strong>in</strong>g, couldfreedom be a supreme value?Murray Rothbard repeatedly criticizes utilitarianism, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Mises’sformulations. One <strong>of</strong> his criticisms is similar to Vaughn’s. e utilitarianwill rarely adopt a pr<strong>in</strong>ciple as an absolute <strong>and</strong> consistent yardstick toapply to <strong>the</strong> varied concrete situations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> real world. He will onlyuse a pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, at best, as a vague guidel<strong>in</strong>e or aspiration, as a tendencywhich he may choose to override at any time.... [N]<strong>in</strong>eteenth-centurylaissez-faire liberals came to use laissez-faire as a vague tendency ra<strong>the</strong>rthan as an unblemished yardstick, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>and</strong> fatallycompromised <strong>the</strong> libertarian creed. To say that a utilitarian cannot be“trusted” to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> libertarian pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> every specific applicationmay sound harsh, but it puts <strong>the</strong> case fairly. A notable contemporaryexample is ... Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Milton Friedman who ... holds to freedom asaga<strong>in</strong>st state <strong>in</strong>tervention as a general tendency, but <strong>in</strong> practice allowsa myriad <strong>of</strong> damag<strong>in</strong>g exceptions, exceptions which serve to vitiate <strong>the</strong>pr<strong>in</strong>ciple almost completely. (Rothbard 1973, p. 24)is charge is first, <strong>and</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>consistently, utilitarian itself: utilitarianismtempts its adherents <strong>in</strong>to consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> sometimes even recommend<strong>in</strong>gunwise, nonlibertarian, policies. Second, <strong>the</strong> charge suggeststhat an alternative philosophical stance can guard its adherents fromfall<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to error. Unfortunately, no doctr<strong>in</strong>e can provide such built-<strong>in</strong>protection aga<strong>in</strong>st its be<strong>in</strong>g misunderstood or misused or improperly setaside. It is an illegitimate test <strong>of</strong> a doctr<strong>in</strong>e to expect it to do what nodoctr<strong>in</strong>e can do. Noth<strong>in</strong>g can substitute for <strong>the</strong> constant discipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> fact<strong>and</strong> logic.Rothbard called Mises “an opponent <strong>of</strong> objective ethics” (1976, p. 105).I wonder if this is a fair description. Certa<strong>in</strong>ly Mises was not an ethicalrelativist or nihilist, scornful <strong>of</strong> all judgments <strong>of</strong> right <strong>and</strong> wrong <strong>and</strong>complacent about however <strong>in</strong>dividuals might behave, even violat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>rights <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>in</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> narrow <strong>and</strong> short-run self-<strong>in</strong>terest. On <strong>the</strong>contrary, Mises was concerned with whe<strong>the</strong>r behavior <strong>and</strong> precepts <strong>of</strong>


428 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophybehavior tended to serve or subvert social cooperation <strong>and</strong> so serve or subverthapp<strong>in</strong>ess. Much scope exists for positive—objective—<strong>in</strong>vestigation<strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> likely consequences <strong>of</strong> various k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>and</strong> precepts <strong>of</strong> behavior,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> scope for purely subjective ethical judgments is correspond<strong>in</strong>glynarrow.Mises, says Rothbard, was will<strong>in</strong>g to make only one value judgment:“he jo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> majority <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> people <strong>in</strong> favor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir common peace,prosperity, <strong>and</strong> abundance”; he endorsed “<strong>the</strong> desirability <strong>of</strong> fulfill<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>subjectively desired goals <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> bulk <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> populace” (p. 105). Actually,Mises’s fundamental value judgment, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> simply favor<strong>in</strong>g whatevera majority wanted or thought it wanted, favored <strong>the</strong> actual happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong>people <strong>in</strong> general. Never<strong>the</strong>less, Rothbard poses a case <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> greatmajority wants to murder <strong>the</strong> redheads. “How could Mises rebut this proposedpolicy ei<strong>the</strong>r as a praxeologist or as a utilitarian liberal? I submit tha<strong>the</strong> could not do so” (p. 108). Or someone might “desire to see an <strong>in</strong>nocentperson suffer.... Yet a utilitarian must hold that [such preferences], fullyas much as <strong>the</strong> most <strong>in</strong>nocuous or altruistic preferences, must be <strong>in</strong>cluded<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantitative reckon<strong>in</strong>g” (1982, p. 213 n. 5).Who says so? Mises supposedly “cannot quarrel with <strong>the</strong> ethical nature<strong>of</strong> [people’s] chosen goals, for, as a utilitarian, he must conf<strong>in</strong>e himself to<strong>the</strong> one value judgment that he favors <strong>the</strong> majority achiev<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir chosengoals” (1982, p. 210). (Rothbard makes sweep<strong>in</strong>g references to Mises; but<strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> deal<strong>in</strong>g with his actual statements, he criticizes what Mises, asa utilitarian, supposedly must believe.) Now, what even half-way sophisticatedutilitarian ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that preferences <strong>and</strong> attitudes <strong>and</strong> charactertraits must be immune from appraisal? Mises, to my knowledge, neversaid any such th<strong>in</strong>g.A rules or <strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism is <strong>in</strong>deed concerned with how attitudes<strong>and</strong> even character traits, so far as <strong>the</strong>y are amenable to encouragementor discouragement, tend to affect <strong>the</strong> health <strong>of</strong> a society <strong>and</strong> so <strong>the</strong>happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> its members (on John Stuart Mill’s <strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism, seeGray 1983). For fear <strong>of</strong> adverse side-effects <strong>and</strong> for o<strong>the</strong>r reasons, a utilitari<strong>and</strong>oes not want to enlist <strong>the</strong> state’s coercive powers <strong>in</strong> suppress<strong>in</strong>g allunfortunate preferences <strong>and</strong> attitudes <strong>and</strong> traits; but this <strong>in</strong> no way meansthat he considers all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m equally worthy <strong>of</strong> respect <strong>and</strong> equally entitledto <strong>in</strong>fluence public policy. Nei<strong>the</strong>r as a utilitarian nor as a libertarian must is example <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> redheads turns up repeatedly <strong>in</strong> Rothbard’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs aga<strong>in</strong>st utilitarianism.


Chapter : Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law 429I myself, for example, deplore psychological <strong>and</strong> sociological <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rpositive <strong>in</strong>quiry <strong>in</strong>to what sorts <strong>of</strong> preferences <strong>and</strong> attitudes <strong>and</strong> lifestylestend <strong>in</strong> fact to serve or to undercut social cooperation <strong>and</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess. Butsay<strong>in</strong>g so <strong>in</strong> no way commits me to want<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> state to implement <strong>the</strong>supposed f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> such <strong>in</strong>quiries.e utilitarian, says Rothbard, “has no conception let alone <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong>justice.” With regard to property rights <strong>in</strong> particular, <strong>the</strong> utilitarian “mustfall back on <strong>the</strong> pragmatic, ad hoc view that all titles to private property currentlyexist<strong>in</strong>g at any time or place must be treated as valid <strong>and</strong> accepted asworthy <strong>of</strong> defense aga<strong>in</strong>st violation” (Rothbard 1982, p. 52). “[U]tilitarians... plac[e] an arbitrary <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>discrim<strong>in</strong>ate ethical bless<strong>in</strong>g upon every currentproperty title” (1982, pp. 58–59). If <strong>the</strong> tyrannical k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Ruritaniadissolves his rule but first divides up <strong>the</strong> whole country <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> privateproperty <strong>of</strong> himself <strong>and</strong> his relatives, “consistent utilitarians ... must bowto this subterfuge” (1982, p. 54).But where does Rothbard get this notion that utilitarianism requiresrespect for even patently spurious titles? Mises’s discussion <strong>in</strong> Socialism(1922/1951) is quite sophisticated <strong>and</strong> hardly bears out <strong>the</strong> suspicion tha<strong>the</strong> would defend even <strong>the</strong> ethically shabbiest status quo.To make <strong>the</strong> case for laissez faire <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> free-market economy, saysRothbard,one must go beyond economics <strong>and</strong> utilitarianism to establish an objectiveethics that affirms <strong>the</strong> overrid<strong>in</strong>g value <strong>of</strong> liberty <strong>and</strong> morally condemnsall forms <strong>of</strong> statism, from egalitarianism to <strong>the</strong> murder <strong>of</strong> redheads,as well as such goals as <strong>the</strong> lust for power <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> satisfaction <strong>of</strong>envy. To make <strong>the</strong> full case for liberty, one cannot be a methodologicalslave to every goal that <strong>the</strong> majority <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> public might happen tocherish. (Rothbard 1976, p. 109)But why would anyone want to make a case for liberty, <strong>the</strong> free market,<strong>and</strong> laissez faire <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong>st statism, envy, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> lust for powerexcept out <strong>of</strong> concern for <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> society <strong>and</strong>, more fundamentally,for <strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> its members? And how could anyone go aboutmak<strong>in</strong>g such a case except <strong>in</strong> some broadly utilitarian way? It seemsbackwards to desire a foundation for a particular policy stance before Rothbard 1982, p. 52,—but what about John Stuart Mill’s Utilitarianism, 1863/1968,chap. 5? Rothbard 1982, p. 60 n. 2, does cite Mises’s Socialism 1922/1932/1951, pp. 45–47.


430 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyhav<strong>in</strong>g some idea <strong>of</strong> its consequences. But Rothbard does th<strong>in</strong>k he hasano<strong>the</strong>r way.’ Rothbard identifies three broad types <strong>of</strong> philosophical basis for libertarianism,first is utilitarianism. Second is emotivism: it adopts liberty, or <strong>the</strong>libertarian nonaggression axiom, as its premise on purely subjective, emotionalgrounds. As Rothbard suggests, such a stance ab<strong>and</strong>ons <strong>the</strong> realm<strong>of</strong> rational discourse (1973, pp. 23–24).ird is Rothbard’s own approach, emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g natural rights embedded<strong>in</strong> natural law. Each entity, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> species man, has its owndist<strong>in</strong>ct nature.S<strong>in</strong>ce men can th<strong>in</strong>k, feel, evaluate, <strong>and</strong> act only as <strong>in</strong>dividuals, it becomesvitally necessary for each man’s survival <strong>and</strong> prosperity that he befree to learn, choose, develop his faculties, <strong>and</strong> act upon his knowledge<strong>and</strong> values. is is <strong>the</strong> necessary path <strong>of</strong> human nature; to <strong>in</strong>terfere with<strong>and</strong> cripple this process by us<strong>in</strong>g violence goes pr<strong>of</strong>oundly aga<strong>in</strong>st whatis necessary by man’s nature for his life <strong>and</strong> prosperity. (1973, pp. 25–26)To appeal to what is necessary for man’s life <strong>and</strong> prosperity, given hisnature, sounds like a utilitarian argument. Anyway, Rothbard beg<strong>in</strong>s with<strong>the</strong> right to self-ownership, with <strong>the</strong> axiom that each man or woman ownshis or her own body. Alternatives are conceivable, though barely. Onecaste <strong>of</strong> persons might belong to ano<strong>the</strong>r, an arrangement hardly compatiblewith an objective, impartial ethics. Or each person might owna t<strong>in</strong>y equal share <strong>of</strong> himself <strong>and</strong> all o<strong>the</strong>r persons. Try<strong>in</strong>g to managepeople’s lives on such a basis, however, would quickly br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>efficiency<strong>and</strong> starvation. (Here is ano<strong>the</strong>r tacitly utilitarian argument.) With <strong>the</strong>sealternatives ruled out, self-ownership rema<strong>in</strong>s (1973, pp. 26–28; <strong>and</strong> 1982,pp. 45–46).Rothbard’s second axiom concerns ownership <strong>of</strong> products <strong>and</strong> l<strong>and</strong>.Everyone has a right to <strong>the</strong> goods he has produced <strong>and</strong> to hi<strong>the</strong>rto unownedl<strong>and</strong> that he has transformed by his labor. A person does notacquire this “homestead<strong>in</strong>g” right <strong>in</strong> all <strong>the</strong> unowned l<strong>and</strong> that he mayclaim; his right is limited to <strong>the</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> he actually puts <strong>in</strong>touse. But once is enough. Here Rothbard avowedly follows <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e<strong>of</strong> John Locke, but with modifications; for example, he rejects <strong>the</strong> “Lockeanproviso” that homestead<strong>in</strong>g leave “enough <strong>and</strong> as good” l<strong>and</strong> available


Chapter : Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law 431for latecomers (1973, pp. 28–37; <strong>and</strong> 1982, pp. 46–50, 63–65, 240). Peoplemay <strong>of</strong> course acquire <strong>and</strong> dispose <strong>of</strong> ownership rights <strong>in</strong> goods <strong>and</strong> l<strong>and</strong>through honest trad<strong>in</strong>g.ese pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> property rights, especially <strong>of</strong> homestead<strong>in</strong>g, lookdetailed or specific enough to raise doubts about whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y are trulyaxioms. Don’t <strong>the</strong>y have some utilitarian underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g after all? Rothbarddoes make comments about ownership <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> similar to his commentsabout ownership <strong>of</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>gs.[I]f <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong> is to be used at all as a resource <strong>in</strong> any sort <strong>of</strong> efficient manner,it must be owned or controlled by someone or some group, <strong>and</strong> weare aga<strong>in</strong> faced with our three alternatives: ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong> belongs to<strong>the</strong> first user, <strong>the</strong> man who first br<strong>in</strong>gs it <strong>in</strong>to production; or it belongsto a group <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs; or it belongs to <strong>the</strong> world as a whole, with every<strong>in</strong>dividual own<strong>in</strong>g a quotal part <strong>of</strong> every acre <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong>.... In practice,aga<strong>in</strong>, it is obviously impossible for every person <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world to exerciseeffective ownership <strong>of</strong> his four-billionth portion (if <strong>the</strong> world populationis, say, four billion) <strong>of</strong> every piece <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world’s l<strong>and</strong> surface. (1973,pp. 33–34)Notice Rothbard’s references—utilitarian references—to efficiency,practicality, <strong>and</strong> effectiveness.Never<strong>the</strong>less, Rothbard ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that his “two axioms, <strong>the</strong> right <strong>of</strong>self-ownership <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> right to ‘homestead,’ establish <strong>the</strong> complete set <strong>of</strong>pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> libertarian system. e entire libertarian doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong>nbecomes <strong>the</strong> sp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> implications <strong>of</strong>this central doctr<strong>in</strong>e” (1973, p. 40). One peculiarity <strong>of</strong> this approach appears at <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposedaxiom that each person owns himself, his body. An argument phrased <strong>in</strong>such a peculiar way is suspect for that very reason. A utilitarian argumentcan readily show <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> property rights; but to put propertyrights at <strong>the</strong> very beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g, even ahead <strong>of</strong> considerations <strong>of</strong> human personality,seems odd <strong>in</strong>deed. Someone not <strong>in</strong>tent on a particular cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong>deductive reason<strong>in</strong>g would describe human nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> human conditionmore straightforwardly. He would probably speak not <strong>of</strong> each person’sown<strong>in</strong>g himself but <strong>of</strong> each person’s be<strong>in</strong>g his own self <strong>and</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>ghis own consciousness <strong>and</strong> purposes <strong>and</strong> capacity to feel pleasure <strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>,


432 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophysatisfaction <strong>and</strong> frustration. He would probably assert or argue for eachperson’s right to personal freedom. Property rights would come <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>argument, but not as its very foundation.A more pervasive peculiarity is <strong>the</strong> attempt, openly avowed—recall <strong>the</strong>quotation above—to sp<strong>in</strong> out positions on all sorts <strong>of</strong> specific issues from<strong>the</strong> two axioms about ownership <strong>of</strong> selves <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r property. (Althoughutilitarian po<strong>in</strong>ts occasionally creep <strong>in</strong>to Rothbard’s arguments, <strong>the</strong>y donot characterize his approach.) Rothbard’s positions on crime, extortion,blackmail, contracts, <strong>and</strong> bankruptcy provide strik<strong>in</strong>g examples, call<strong>in</strong>ghis whole approach <strong>in</strong>to question, as I shall try to show. For brevity, Iforgo comment<strong>in</strong>g on how self-confidently he sp<strong>in</strong>s out firm positionson abortion, boycotts, children’s rights, animal rights, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r issues.Aga<strong>in</strong>, my purpose is not to attack Rothbard but to defend Mises.Meanwhile, let us note, a utilitarian would not try to derive all sorts<strong>of</strong> specific judgments by deduc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> one direction only from a veryfew <strong>in</strong>itial axioms. Instead, he would check his tentative specific judgments<strong>and</strong> his tentative generalizations (rules) aga<strong>in</strong>st one ano<strong>the</strong>r. In away, judgments about specific cases would serve as data—tentative, corrigibledata—for reach<strong>in</strong>g generalizations. e utilitarian would st<strong>and</strong>ready to modify any or all <strong>of</strong> his specific <strong>and</strong> general judgments untilhe had achieved consistency among <strong>the</strong>m, as well as consistency withhis fundamental value judgment about happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> misery. He wouldseek consistency between his judgment about some specific provision <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> bankruptcy laws, for example, <strong>and</strong> his generalizations about honesty,promises, <strong>and</strong> property rights. At each stage, facts <strong>of</strong> reality, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> psychology <strong>and</strong> economics <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r discipl<strong>in</strong>es, would beeligible to enter <strong>in</strong>to his reason<strong>in</strong>g. Crime provides my first example <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> peculiar positions that Rothbarddeduces. He regards crime as, <strong>in</strong> effect, a private transaction betweenculprit <strong>and</strong> victim. Suppose someone mugs me. By his aggression, <strong>the</strong>mugger has violated my property right <strong>in</strong> my own person <strong>and</strong>, if he hastaken any valuables, my property right <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m also. I am entitled torestitution or compensation. If, however, I waive this right <strong>and</strong> forgive<strong>the</strong> mugger, <strong>the</strong>n I have made him a gift <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> use (or abuse) he has is method <strong>of</strong> seek<strong>in</strong>g consistency between specific judgments <strong>and</strong> general rules iswhat John Rawls, not himself an avowed utilitarian, has called <strong>the</strong> method <strong>of</strong> reflectiveequilibrium; Rawls 1971, esp. pp. 20–21, 48–51. Rothbard 1982, chap. 13. I hope it is legitimate to draw, also, on personal correspondencewith Rothbard.


Chapter : Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law 433made <strong>of</strong> my body <strong>and</strong> also, if I so choose, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> property he has taken.Because <strong>the</strong>se were m<strong>in</strong>e to give away, <strong>the</strong> situation becomes <strong>the</strong> same asif no crime had occurred. No authority has any right to prosecute him,on Rothbard’s view—not if I object (<strong>and</strong> if <strong>the</strong> mugger happened to killme, it is my heirs who have <strong>the</strong> option <strong>of</strong> forgiv<strong>in</strong>g him, subject to anyapplicable provisions <strong>of</strong> my will).But let’s face reality. In all probability <strong>the</strong> mugger did not <strong>in</strong>tend tomake his “transaction” with me <strong>in</strong> particular. It just happened to be I whowas <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> wrong place at <strong>the</strong> wrong time. By his actions <strong>and</strong> attitudes, <strong>the</strong>mugger is a threat to society, to people <strong>in</strong> general; he contributes to underm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> peace <strong>and</strong> security <strong>and</strong> social cooperation on which practicallyeveryone’s well-be<strong>in</strong>g depends. Because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> menace he constitutes, <strong>and</strong>for o<strong>the</strong>r reasons, he deserves to be restra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> punished. e accidentthat I ra<strong>the</strong>r than someone else was his victim does not entitle me to forgivehim <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby contribute to perpetuat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> general menace tha<strong>the</strong> <strong>and</strong> people like him pose. In fact—though this is not <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t—Iprobably do not want <strong>the</strong> option <strong>of</strong> forgiv<strong>in</strong>g him. Particularly <strong>in</strong> cases<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g crim<strong>in</strong>al organizations, <strong>the</strong> option to forgive would expose <strong>the</strong>victim to unwanted pressure. (It is not always true that a wider range <strong>of</strong>options is preferable to a narrow one. When I was teach<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> University<strong>of</strong> Virg<strong>in</strong>ia, I welcomed <strong>the</strong> rule that forbade me to change a grade,once reported, except to correct an actual error. at rule sheltered mefrom appeals to my compassion by students “need<strong>in</strong>g” a higher grade.)Now for extortion. Suppose a scoundrel pressures me to pay him100,000 or to sell him my bus<strong>in</strong>ess firm for a token price; o<strong>the</strong>rwise hewill beat me up—or perhaps he just threatens to kick me <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sh<strong>in</strong>s ortrample my tomato plants. In any case, he is violat<strong>in</strong>g my rights <strong>in</strong> myperson or property (for <strong>the</strong> threat, like <strong>the</strong> threatened act, is itself a violation).He is properly subject to restra<strong>in</strong>t or punishment. But supposehe makes a different threat, which I f<strong>in</strong>d more om<strong>in</strong>ous: he will spreadvicious lies to ru<strong>in</strong> my bus<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> my personal life. He may add, rightlyor wrongly, that his credibility with a wide circle <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluential contactswill make his lies especially effective. Yet <strong>in</strong> this case he is not properlysubject to legal restra<strong>in</strong>t, for he is violat<strong>in</strong>g no property right <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>e. Ihave no right to an unsullied reputation, no matter how much I may have<strong>in</strong> some sense earned it; for it is o<strong>the</strong>r people, not I, who have property On this <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> closely related topic <strong>of</strong> blackmail, see Rothbard 1982, chap. 16; heretoo I draw on personal correspondence.


434 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyrights <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> contents <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own m<strong>in</strong>ds, even <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir op<strong>in</strong>ions<strong>of</strong> me.It seems strange that a member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Austrian school <strong>of</strong> economists,who put such emphasis on <strong>the</strong> radically subjective nature <strong>of</strong> benefits <strong>and</strong>costs, goods <strong>and</strong> bads (Yeager 1987), should make such a momentousdist<strong>in</strong>ction between threats accord<strong>in</strong>g to whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y do or do not <strong>in</strong>volvephysical harm to persons or objects. But that is what Rothbard deducesfrom his two axioms.Rothbard takes a similar position on blackmail, def<strong>in</strong>ed as obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g ortry<strong>in</strong>g to obta<strong>in</strong> money or goods <strong>in</strong> exchange for silence on some matter. Aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> supposedly decisive question is who has a property right to <strong>the</strong>contents <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> blackmailer <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people with whomhe might share his <strong>in</strong>formation (or mis<strong>in</strong>formation). Not <strong>the</strong> victim—soruns Rothbard’s answer. It is irrelevant to Rothbard’s judgment that <strong>the</strong>victim might be better <strong>of</strong>f if <strong>the</strong> blackmailer had never been born. Rothbardbrushes aside <strong>the</strong> contention that <strong>the</strong> blackmailer’s activity might bejudged unproductive <strong>in</strong> some sense. Rights, not assessments <strong>of</strong> productivity,must prevail. A utilitarian side po<strong>in</strong>t enters <strong>in</strong>: <strong>the</strong> victim may bebetter <strong>of</strong>f with than without <strong>the</strong> opportunity to give <strong>the</strong> possessor <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formationan <strong>in</strong>centive not to blab. e presumption still holds that voluntarytransactions—<strong>in</strong> this case, an exchange <strong>of</strong> money for silence—benefits allconcerned. I would reply (not tak<strong>in</strong>g space here to develop <strong>the</strong> argument)that such a proposition about ga<strong>in</strong>s from trade is no more universallyvalid than <strong>the</strong> proposition about more options always be<strong>in</strong>g preferable t<strong>of</strong>ewer.Rothbard’s conception <strong>of</strong> property rights also determ<strong>in</strong>es his positionon what contracts are properly enforceable at law (1982, chap. 19). Supposea performer agrees with an impresario to take part <strong>in</strong> a concert tour for aspecified compensation, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> impresario proceeds with costly arrangements.Or suppose a retail<strong>in</strong>g cha<strong>in</strong> agrees to buy 100,000 tables over <strong>the</strong>follow<strong>in</strong>g two years at a specified price, <strong>the</strong>reby <strong>in</strong>duc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> manufacturerto construct a new factory to be able to deliver. Now, for no extenuat<strong>in</strong>greason (whatever one might be), <strong>the</strong> performer or <strong>the</strong> retailer defaults onhis part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> barga<strong>in</strong>, leav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> impresario or <strong>the</strong> manufacturer withheavy expenses that he can hardly recoup. In nei<strong>the</strong>r case, we stipulate, hasany money or o<strong>the</strong>r property yet changed h<strong>and</strong>s between <strong>the</strong> contract<strong>in</strong>g Rothbard 1982, chap. 16 <strong>and</strong> pp. 241–243; similar arguments appear <strong>in</strong> Block <strong>and</strong>Gordon 1985 <strong>and</strong> Block 1986.


Chapter : Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law 435parties. Tough luck, Rothbard says <strong>in</strong> effect; <strong>the</strong> aggrieved party shouldhave drawn up <strong>the</strong> contract more warily <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place. e law cannotproperly require <strong>the</strong> defaulter to keep his promise or pay compensation.e reason is that <strong>the</strong> default does not constitute steal<strong>in</strong>g property(remember, no money has been paid); <strong>the</strong> defaulter has violated no propertyright. If, however, <strong>the</strong> contract had read <strong>in</strong> such a way that defaultdid count as tak<strong>in</strong>g property by force or fraud, <strong>the</strong>n Rothbard’s judgmentwould be different.A utilitarian must wonder. Why, especially with “subjectivist” Austrianeconomists, should so great a difference h<strong>in</strong>ge on <strong>the</strong> relatively materialisticissue <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> when property had actually changed h<strong>and</strong>s?e opportunity for people to make enforceable contracts <strong>in</strong> which promisesserve as consideration for each o<strong>the</strong>r serves social cooperation, just asit underm<strong>in</strong>es it to urge peculiar axioms as reasons for tolerat<strong>in</strong>g defaulton such contracts.Rothbard condemns bankruptcy laws. ey “compel <strong>the</strong> discharge <strong>of</strong>a debtor’s voluntarily contracted debts, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby <strong>in</strong>vade <strong>the</strong> propertyrights <strong>of</strong> creditors. e debtor who refuses to pay his debt has stolen<strong>the</strong> property <strong>of</strong> his creditor.” Fraudulent concealment <strong>of</strong> assets makes <strong>the</strong><strong>of</strong>fense even worse. “But even if <strong>the</strong> default<strong>in</strong>g debtor is not able to pay,he has still stolen <strong>the</strong> property <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> creditor.” Bankruptcy laws “virtuallyconfer a license to steal upon <strong>the</strong> debtor.” Instead, <strong>the</strong> legal system shouldenforce payment through, for example, attachment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> debtor’s future<strong>in</strong>come (1982, p. 142).Of course default is regrettable. So is resort to bankruptcy; so is <strong>the</strong>poor plann<strong>in</strong>g or bad luck that results <strong>in</strong> its appear<strong>in</strong>g necessary. Butregrettable th<strong>in</strong>gs do happen. Instead <strong>of</strong> just condemn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m with simplisticaxioms, <strong>the</strong> utilitarian considers how best to forestall <strong>the</strong>m <strong>and</strong> howbest to deal with <strong>the</strong>m if <strong>the</strong>y do happen anyway. He asks how <strong>the</strong> worldwould work <strong>and</strong> how social cooperation would flourish or would suffer ifno legal means were available for distribut<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> assets <strong>of</strong> a hopelessly<strong>in</strong>debted debtor <strong>in</strong> an orderly way <strong>and</strong> for clear<strong>in</strong>g away obstacles to hisfuture productive activity. Murray Rothbard <strong>and</strong> Walter Block try to ward <strong>of</strong>f outrage over <strong>the</strong>ir positionson crime <strong>and</strong> blackmail <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r issues by dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g betweenrights <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> morality <strong>of</strong> exercis<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m <strong>and</strong> between law <strong>and</strong> morality


436 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy(1982, pp. 23–24; Block <strong>and</strong> Gordon 1985, pp. 47, 53; Block 1986, p. 73). Tosay that I have a right to exempt a mugger from prosecution is not at all tosay that I should do so. To say that it should not be illegal for a scoundrel toextort money from me by threaten<strong>in</strong>g to spread scurrilous stories, whe<strong>the</strong>rfalse or true, is not to deny that he is <strong>in</strong>deed a scoundrel. On <strong>the</strong> view <strong>of</strong>Rothbard <strong>and</strong> Block, apparently, two categories co<strong>in</strong>cide—<strong>the</strong> violation<strong>of</strong> rights <strong>and</strong> what should be illegal. Immorality is a separate question.Rothbard <strong>and</strong> Block apparently believe <strong>the</strong>y can hold to <strong>the</strong>ir dist<strong>in</strong>ctive<strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> rights <strong>and</strong> law while hold<strong>in</strong>g fairly st<strong>and</strong>ard ethical views <strong>and</strong>wax<strong>in</strong>g just as <strong>in</strong>dignant as any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> us over <strong>the</strong> forgiv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> muggers,extortion accomplished by threats <strong>of</strong> verbal as well as physical action,blackmail, <strong>and</strong> default on contractual promises.I wonder if <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>ories can be rescued so easily. e trouble is toodeep-seated: it stems from try<strong>in</strong>g to deduce all sorts <strong>of</strong> specific policy positionsfrom <strong>the</strong> two axioms about property, with no more than <strong>in</strong>cidentalattention to <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> alternative rules <strong>and</strong> policies.I see a closer relation between ethics <strong>and</strong> law than Rothbard <strong>and</strong> Blockdo. (Mises 1922/1951, pp. 397–399, makes sensible comments on this relation,as does Hazlitt 1964, chap. 9.) A long process <strong>of</strong> evolution <strong>and</strong> selectionhas yielded ethical precepts that, by <strong>and</strong> large, praise or condemnk<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> behavior <strong>and</strong> traits <strong>of</strong> character accord<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>the</strong>y tend to serveor subvert human survival, social cooperation, <strong>and</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess. By a similarprocess <strong>of</strong> evolution, which <strong>in</strong> some cultures <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> accretion <strong>of</strong>precedents set <strong>in</strong> court decisions, law has come to re<strong>in</strong>force <strong>the</strong> observance<strong>and</strong> penalize <strong>the</strong> violation <strong>of</strong> ethical precepts <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> relatively most clearcutcases. is evolved law has been codified <strong>and</strong> modified by legislatures.Ideally, <strong>the</strong>se str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> law proscribe acts that are “wrong <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves.”O<strong>the</strong>r str<strong>and</strong>s establish acts that are “wrong because <strong>the</strong>y are prohibited.”Ideally, <strong>the</strong>ir purpose is to improve each person’s opportunities to predicto<strong>the</strong>r people’s actions <strong>and</strong> so to mesh his own actions with <strong>the</strong>irs.Traffic laws are <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard example (driv<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> left side <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> roadis wrong not <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sically but because <strong>the</strong> law prohibits it <strong>and</strong> because <strong>the</strong>violation would now <strong>in</strong>fr<strong>in</strong>ge <strong>the</strong> warranted expectations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> rights<strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people <strong>and</strong> endanger <strong>the</strong>ir lives). Technicalities <strong>of</strong> real-estate<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>heritance law also provide examples <strong>of</strong> law <strong>in</strong>tended to improvecoord<strong>in</strong>ation.Here, though, we are emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> relation between law <strong>and</strong>ethics. Why shouldn’t re<strong>in</strong>forcement be total, with <strong>the</strong> law prohibit<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> punish<strong>in</strong>g absolutely all immoral behavior? Imag<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g such a state


Chapter : Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law 437<strong>of</strong> affairs—a utilitarian exercise—provides <strong>the</strong> answer. Legally prohibit<strong>in</strong>gall sorts <strong>of</strong> undesirable actions, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>appropriate sulk<strong>in</strong>ess, <strong>and</strong>legally requir<strong>in</strong>g all sorts <strong>of</strong> desirable actions, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g k<strong>in</strong>d words whenappropriate, would be downright impossible. e very attempt to makelaw completely co<strong>in</strong>cide with ethics, though doomed to failure, wouldbr<strong>in</strong>g an oppressive totalitarianism <strong>and</strong> would give <strong>the</strong> rulers vast opportunitiesto prosecute <strong>in</strong>dividuals selectively <strong>and</strong> arbitrarily. We shouldbe chary about apply<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> threaten<strong>in</strong>g violence, on which enforcement<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> law ultimately rests. Use <strong>and</strong> threat <strong>of</strong> force is tolerable onlywhen—but not whenever—<strong>the</strong> cases <strong>in</strong> which it is applied are clearlyspecified <strong>and</strong> when <strong>in</strong>dividuals can know how <strong>the</strong>y must behave to avoidhav<strong>in</strong>g force applied to <strong>the</strong>m. e law must content itself, <strong>the</strong>refore, withproscrib<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> punish<strong>in</strong>g acts that can be def<strong>in</strong>ed fairly def<strong>in</strong>itely <strong>and</strong>detected fairly straightforwardly, without unacceptable side effects.e greatest range <strong>of</strong> human behavior must rema<strong>in</strong> outside <strong>the</strong> directpurview <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> law—k<strong>in</strong>d words <strong>and</strong> charitable actions on <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>,perverted ambition, careless gossip, <strong>and</strong> malicious lies on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>.Encouragement <strong>and</strong> discouragement <strong>of</strong> most actions <strong>and</strong> attitudes mustbe left to <strong>the</strong> flexible, <strong>in</strong>formal, <strong>and</strong> decentralized application <strong>of</strong> ethicalprecepts. Ethics, by its very logic, must be flexible <strong>in</strong> its applicationto particular cases <strong>and</strong> capable <strong>of</strong> evolv<strong>in</strong>g as knowledge grows <strong>and</strong>conditions change (Hazlitt 1964, pp. 184–185). Whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> law shouldforbid certa<strong>in</strong> unethical actions, such as blackmail <strong>and</strong> default on contractualpromises, cannot sensibly be decided directly from first pr<strong>in</strong>ciplesalone. Utilitarian considerations must carry weight, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>importance <strong>of</strong> keep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> law def<strong>in</strong>ite <strong>and</strong> concentrated power constra<strong>in</strong>ed.Why don’t we want to go to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r extreme, with law so divorcedfrom ethics as not to exist at all? Not even actual anarchists like Rothbardwould go that far. (Rothbard expects law to persist even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence<strong>of</strong> government; private enterprises would ascerta<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> enforce it; 1973,chap. 11.) Allow<strong>in</strong>g even murder <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ft to go legally unpunished wouldput relatively ethical people at <strong>the</strong> mercy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unethical, <strong>and</strong> a Hobbesianwar <strong>of</strong> all aga<strong>in</strong>st all would rage. When it can be framed <strong>and</strong> appliedfairly def<strong>in</strong>itely, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> law has educative value: it can help teachethically ra<strong>the</strong>r dense people that certa<strong>in</strong> acts are wrong, or at least thatcommitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m puts <strong>the</strong>mselves at risk.On one po<strong>in</strong>t I emphatically agree with what I th<strong>in</strong>k is Rothbard’s<strong>and</strong> Block’s position: <strong>the</strong> law does not <strong>and</strong> should not be expected or


438 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophythought to determ<strong>in</strong>e morality. It is not true that whatever <strong>the</strong> law permitsis morally right <strong>and</strong> whatever it forbids morally wrong. Ethics is priorto law, logically <strong>and</strong> probably also historically. Ideally, law serves a goodsociety by re<strong>in</strong>forc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> precepts <strong>of</strong> morality <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> clear-cut cases,do<strong>in</strong>g so through <strong>the</strong> duly restricted exercise <strong>and</strong> threat <strong>of</strong> governmentalcoercion.Unfortunately, actual law is not ideal law. Particular laws can be unwise<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir conception <strong>and</strong> wicked <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir consequences <strong>and</strong> even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<strong>in</strong>tent. Laws should always be subject to appraisal on ethical grounds. Forreasons I won’t take space to develop here (see Yeager 1985, pp. 280–283), astrong presumption runs <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> obey<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> law, even laws one th<strong>in</strong>ksshould be changed. In cases <strong>of</strong> exceptionally wicked laws, however (a particularU.S. law <strong>of</strong> 1850 comes to m<strong>in</strong>d), ethical considerations may call fordisobedience. In some such cases, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, it may even be <strong>the</strong> lesserevil for judges to render decisions contrary to <strong>the</strong> actual law; at least I cansympathize with arguments to that effect.e forego<strong>in</strong>g is what sense I can make <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>of</strong> “naturallaw” or a “higher law.” So <strong>in</strong>terpreted, I do not disparage those concepts;<strong>the</strong>y are legitimate <strong>and</strong> important—enough so to deserve a sensibleground<strong>in</strong>g. Actual laws, merely by be<strong>in</strong>g actual, do not acquireethical force beyond what <strong>the</strong>ir content warrants <strong>and</strong> beyond <strong>the</strong> force<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> general presumption <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> obey<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m. Laws are alwaysproperly subject to appraisal not only <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir purposes, consequences,<strong>and</strong> side effects but also on broader ethical grounds. ey shouldord<strong>in</strong>arily be changed only by regular legislative <strong>and</strong> judicial processes;but <strong>in</strong> exceptional <strong>and</strong> extreme cases, to repeat, ethical considerationsmay properly lead ord<strong>in</strong>ary citizens <strong>and</strong> perhaps even judges to disobey<strong>the</strong>m.ese truths should not be perverted <strong>in</strong>to suppos<strong>in</strong>g that actual commonlaw or statutory law is not actual law after all if it is deemed contraryto some natural or higher law. For <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> clear th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g, we shouldma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctions between actual <strong>and</strong> ideal law <strong>and</strong> between law<strong>and</strong> ethics.Although, <strong>the</strong>n, I accept <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>sist on a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between law <strong>and</strong>ethics, m<strong>in</strong>e is not <strong>the</strong> one that Rothbard <strong>and</strong> Block make. ey <strong>in</strong>voke<strong>the</strong>irs, it seems to me, <strong>in</strong> an unsuccessful attempt to confer plausibilityon <strong>the</strong>ir highly questionable positions concern<strong>in</strong>g crime, blackmail, <strong>and</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r topics mentioned above. eir errors are not so easily plastered over,s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y stem from try<strong>in</strong>g to deduce all sorts <strong>of</strong> detailed positions from


Chapter : Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law 439two supposed axioms; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir errors threaten to spread from <strong>the</strong>ir legal<strong>the</strong>ory to <strong>the</strong>ir ethical <strong>the</strong>ory. I am tempted to deliver a sermon, particularly to Walter Block, author<strong>of</strong> Defend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Undefendable, who portrayed <strong>the</strong> pimp, <strong>the</strong> drug pusher,<strong>the</strong> litterbug, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r unsavory types as heroes (Block 1976; also Block1986 <strong>and</strong> Block <strong>and</strong> Gordon 1985). Much speaks <strong>in</strong> support <strong>of</strong> a society’sprevail<strong>in</strong>g ethical norms, <strong>the</strong> norms that support social cooperation. A certa<strong>in</strong>“squareness” is admirable. To recognize this is not to want to dictatepeople’s lifestyles. Still, honesty <strong>and</strong> civility, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a decent respect foro<strong>the</strong>r people’s rights <strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong>ir feel<strong>in</strong>gs, do deserve encouragement.e more generally people behave decently out <strong>of</strong> respect for <strong>in</strong>gra<strong>in</strong>edethical precepts, <strong>the</strong> less is <strong>the</strong> need or apparent need for apply<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>coercive force <strong>of</strong> law. For <strong>the</strong>se reasons, someone who wishes well formank<strong>in</strong>d should avoid writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a style that appears, though un<strong>in</strong>tentionally,to disparage traditional ethical values. I have reviewed Rothbard’s “natural rights” approach because it seems tobe <strong>the</strong> lead<strong>in</strong>g alternative to utilitarianism as a philosophical basis for policyespousal. (I do not regard <strong>the</strong> “contractarianism” <strong>of</strong> James Buchanan<strong>and</strong> his school as a genu<strong>in</strong>e alternative, for it seems to me to be a version <strong>of</strong>utilitarianism disguised by fictions; see my 1985.) In reject<strong>in</strong>g Rothbard’sapproach, I do not at all ridicule or dismiss <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> rights. It isvital to a healthy society <strong>and</strong> thus to happ<strong>in</strong>ess that rights (very roughly,<strong>the</strong> ones mentioned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> U.S. Declaration <strong>of</strong> Independence <strong>and</strong> Bill <strong>of</strong>Rights) be respected <strong>in</strong> public policy <strong>and</strong> private life. Conduct<strong>in</strong>g publicpolicy or liv<strong>in</strong>g one’s own life accord<strong>in</strong>g to what seems narrowly expedient<strong>in</strong> each particular case would be disastrous.e question that separates utilitarians from o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>orists <strong>of</strong> rightsis how to ground <strong>the</strong>m philosophically. Rothbard (1982) observes thatRobert Nozick (1974) does not give rights any ground<strong>in</strong>g; he simply <strong>in</strong>tuits<strong>the</strong>m. Rothbard does attempt a ground<strong>in</strong>g, which, however, fails, assuggested by <strong>the</strong> peculiar policy positions that his approach gr<strong>in</strong>ds out.e utilitarian, <strong>in</strong> contrast, compares alternative <strong>in</strong>stitutions; he <strong>in</strong>vestigateswhat conceptions <strong>of</strong> rights <strong>and</strong> justice, what rules, what restra<strong>in</strong>ts Rothbard’s 1982, by <strong>the</strong> way, is not really a book on ethics; it is a book advocat<strong>in</strong>g aparticular type <strong>of</strong> libertarian political philosophy.


440 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyon government, <strong>and</strong> what o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>stitutions are most conducive to a goodsociety <strong>and</strong> so to happ<strong>in</strong>ess.Obviously I am referr<strong>in</strong>g to so-called “rules” or “<strong>in</strong>direct” utilitarianism.e supposed utilitarian who goes around look<strong>in</strong>g for opportunitiesto frame <strong>and</strong> execute <strong>in</strong>nocent men to pacify rag<strong>in</strong>g mobs, or to tortureredheads for <strong>the</strong> amusement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> multitude, or to approve <strong>of</strong> rapewhen <strong>the</strong> rapist’s pleasure outweighs <strong>the</strong> victim’s distress, is an <strong>in</strong>vention<strong>of</strong> superficial critics. e shallow, act-oriented versions <strong>of</strong> utilitarianismoccasionally encountered may once have <strong>of</strong>fered critics a target, but onemust wonder why anyone still pursues worthless triumphs over doctr<strong>in</strong>esthat are hardly better than straw men.Never<strong>the</strong>less, cheap shots at utilitarianism cont<strong>in</strong>ue. Years ago, already,Mises noted <strong>the</strong> phenomenon.Hedonism, eudaemonism, <strong>and</strong> utilitarianism were condemned <strong>and</strong> outlawed,<strong>and</strong> whoever did not wish to run <strong>the</strong> risk <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> wholeworld his enemy had to be scrupulously <strong>in</strong>tent on avoid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> suspicionthat he <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed toward those heretical doctr<strong>in</strong>es. is must be kept <strong>in</strong>m<strong>in</strong>d if one wants to underst<strong>and</strong> why many economists went to greatpa<strong>in</strong>s to deny <strong>the</strong> connections between <strong>the</strong>ir teach<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> those <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism.(Mises 1933/1960)Mises was forthright, even courageous, <strong>in</strong> his utilitarianism. For thishis reputation cont<strong>in</strong>ues to suffer even among em<strong>in</strong>ent economists <strong>and</strong>social philosophers who <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r respects are carry<strong>in</strong>g on his work. I urge<strong>the</strong>m to reconsider. I am not say<strong>in</strong>g that Mises developed <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctionbetween <strong>the</strong> act <strong>and</strong> rules or <strong>in</strong>direct versions <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism <strong>and</strong> fullyarticulated <strong>the</strong> latter version. I am not say<strong>in</strong>g that he exam<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> demolished<strong>the</strong> axiomatic rights approach <strong>of</strong>fered as an alternative by some <strong>of</strong>his disciples. Do<strong>in</strong>g all this was not necessary for his work <strong>in</strong> economics.However, a sophisticated utilitarianism does fit with<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> extend <strong>the</strong>philosophical framework that Mises adopted. Hazlitt, for one, extendedit. Mises was on <strong>the</strong> right track.Alex<strong>and</strong>er, Sidney S. “Human Values <strong>and</strong> Economists’ Values.” In Human Values<strong>and</strong> Economic Policy, edited by Sidney Hook. New York: New York UniversityPress, 1967.Block, Walter. Defend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Undefendable. New York: Fleet, 1976.


Chapter : Mises <strong>and</strong> His Critics on Ethics, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Law 441. “Trad<strong>in</strong>g Money for Silence.” University <strong>of</strong> Hawaii Law Review 8(Spr<strong>in</strong>g 1986): 57–73.Block, Walter, <strong>and</strong> David Gordon. “Blackmail, Extortion <strong>and</strong> Free Speech.” Loyola<strong>of</strong> Los Angeles Law Review 19 (November 1985): 37–54.Edwards, Paul. e Logic <strong>of</strong> Moral Discourse. New York: Free Press, 1965.Gray, John. Mill on Liberty: A Defence. London <strong>and</strong> Boston: Routledge & KeganPaul, 1983.Hayek, Friedrich A. Studies <strong>in</strong> Philosophy, Politics <strong>and</strong> Economics. Chicago: University<strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1967.. e Mirage <strong>of</strong> Social Justice. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1976.Hazlitt, Henry. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Morality. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>,1964.Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism. 1863. In Selected Writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> John Stuart Mill,edited by Maurice Cowl<strong>in</strong>g. New York: New American Library, 1968.Mises, Ludwig von. Socialism: An Economic <strong>and</strong> Sociological Analysis. 1922. Newenlarged ed. Translated by J. Kahane. New Haven, Conn.: Yale UniversityPress, 1951.. Epistemological Problems <strong>of</strong> Economics. 1933. Translated by George Reisman.Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>, 1960.. Human Action. 1949. 2ⁿ ed. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press,1963.. Nation, State, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>. 1919. Translated by Lel<strong>and</strong> B. Yeager. NewYork: New York University Press, 1983.. eory <strong>and</strong> History. 1979. Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute,1985.Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, <strong>and</strong> Utopia. New York: Basic Books, 1974.Rawls, John. A eory <strong>of</strong> Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press <strong>of</strong> HarvardUniversity Press, 1971.Rothbard, Murray N. For a New Liberty. New York: Macmillan, 1973.. “Praxeology, Value Judgments, <strong>and</strong> Public Policy.” In e Foundations <strong>of</strong>Modern Austrian Economics, edited by Edw<strong>in</strong> G. Dolan. Kansas City, Kans.:Sheed <strong>and</strong> Ward, 1976.


442 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy. e Ethics <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Atlantic Highl<strong>and</strong>s, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1982.Sen, Amartya K. Collective Choice <strong>and</strong> Social Welfare. San Francisco: Holden-Day,1970.Vaughn, Karen I. “Critical Discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Four Papers.” In e Economics <strong>of</strong>Ludwig von Mises, edited by Laurence S. Moss. Kansas City, Kans.: Sheed<strong>and</strong> Ward, 1976.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal.” Cato Journal5 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g/Summer 1985): 259–294.. “Why Subjectivism?” Review <strong>of</strong> Austrian Economics 1 (1987): 5–31. Repr<strong>in</strong>tedhere as chapter .


e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’sHuman Action * <strong>Is</strong>rael Kirzner recently asked how Ludwig von Mises could claim to bepursu<strong>in</strong>g value-free science while at <strong>the</strong> same time show<strong>in</strong>g “enormouspassion” to communicate its truths (Kirzner 1998, pp. 582–586). “Passion”<strong>in</strong> that context implies moral judgment, a concern for truth over falsehood<strong>and</strong> right over wrong. I will embroider a bit on how Kirzner answered hisown question, which, by <strong>the</strong> way, recognizes <strong>the</strong> fact/value or is/ought dist<strong>in</strong>ction.Fur<strong>the</strong>r, I will review Mises’s <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> morality.As Kirzner argued, <strong>the</strong> passionate pursuit <strong>of</strong> value-free truths <strong>in</strong>volvesno contradiction. Mises wanted people to have <strong>the</strong> opportunity to pursuehapp<strong>in</strong>ess successfully. at opportunity presupposes what he called“social cooperation,” mean<strong>in</strong>g a secure <strong>and</strong> peaceful society <strong>in</strong> which peoplecan <strong>in</strong>teract to <strong>the</strong>ir mutual benefit while pursu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir own diversespecializations, projects, <strong>and</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> excellence. Such a society presupposespolicies that serve, ra<strong>the</strong>r than undercut, social cooperation; <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong> turn presuppose that policymakers <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> public have some underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> economics—value-free science. It is too much to expect thatmost people should actively underst<strong>and</strong> economics; perhaps it sufficesif <strong>the</strong>y have <strong>the</strong> humility to recognize <strong>the</strong>ir ignorance <strong>and</strong> refra<strong>in</strong> fromdestructively impos<strong>in</strong>g its consequences.Still, it is important that enough people do get economics straight <strong>and</strong>dissem<strong>in</strong>ate its teach<strong>in</strong>gs. at requires subtle <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>and</strong> a perspectivedifferent from those <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> layperson. Its conclusions are counter<strong>in</strong>tuitive,<strong>and</strong> fallacies pervade public op<strong>in</strong>ion. Most do not underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> law <strong>of</strong>*is lecture was presented as one <strong>in</strong> a series at Hillsdale College <strong>and</strong> published <strong>in</strong>Human Action: A 50-Year Tribute, ed. Richard M. Ebel<strong>in</strong>g (Hillsdale, Mich.: HillsdaleCollege Press, 2000).443


444 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyun<strong>in</strong>tended consequences. Economic ignorance is so widespread <strong>and</strong> itsconsequences so frighten<strong>in</strong>g that, as Kirzner said, reduc<strong>in</strong>g it “becomes agoal <strong>in</strong>vested with <strong>in</strong>dependent moral worth.” Economic education servesa human goal <strong>of</strong> such importance that “passionate concern becomes ... amorally natural phenomenon.” Kirzner <strong>in</strong>sists on “a fundamental differencebetween economic education” <strong>and</strong> promot<strong>in</strong>g “‘libertarian’ ideologyor rhetoric.” Passion need not <strong>and</strong> dare not “compromise <strong>the</strong> detachment<strong>and</strong> objectivity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> content <strong>of</strong> ... economic education” (1998, pp. 582–586).I will make one clarification. We cannot expect <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong> any scienceto be value-free <strong>and</strong> expect researchers to pursue <strong>the</strong>ir work withno heed to values. Values guide scientists toward questions that <strong>the</strong>y f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> worth <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g. Values guide <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> scientificf<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs. What can be value-free is <strong>the</strong> content <strong>of</strong> scientific propositions.e dist<strong>in</strong>ction between value-free <strong>and</strong> value-loaded perta<strong>in</strong>s not towhole fields <strong>of</strong> study or to pr<strong>of</strong>essional careers but to propositions, to sentences.Some value-free propositions are that snow is white, that dem<strong>and</strong>curves slope downward, that exp<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong> money beyondwhat people are will<strong>in</strong>g to hold at exist<strong>in</strong>g prices causes price <strong>in</strong>flation,<strong>and</strong> that private property <strong>and</strong> genu<strong>in</strong>e markets are necessary (as Mises<strong>and</strong> Hayek expla<strong>in</strong>ed) for economic calculation.Does <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g on a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between normative <strong>and</strong> positive propositionsdisparage ethics? No. Normative propositions can be argued for<strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong>st. All value judgments have descriptive as well as normative content,except only for fundamental value judgments. Examples <strong>of</strong> relativelyspecific judgments are that ly<strong>in</strong>g, cheat<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> steal<strong>in</strong>g are wrong. A fundamentaljudgment, <strong>in</strong> contrast <strong>and</strong> by def<strong>in</strong>ition, is one that one cannotargue for because one has reached <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> argu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> must appeal todirect observation or <strong>in</strong>tuition <strong>in</strong>stead. Probably <strong>the</strong> most familiar exampleis <strong>the</strong> judgment that misery is bad <strong>and</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess is good; scarcely anyonewould try to demonstrate that judgment.Utilitarianism rests on that one fundamental <strong>in</strong>tuition or, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words,on approval <strong>of</strong> human flourish<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>of</strong> people’s success <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g good livesfor <strong>the</strong>mselves, <strong>and</strong> disapproval <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> opposite conditions. is is a tamevalue judgment, to be sure; but comb<strong>in</strong>ed with positive knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>world <strong>and</strong> human affairs, it goes a long way <strong>in</strong> ethics. What fundamentalvalue judgment or criterion could be more plausible?


Chapter : e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’s Human Action 445One great <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>of</strong> Mises, follow<strong>in</strong>g David Hume <strong>and</strong> elaborated byHenry Hazlitt (1964), is that direct appeal to <strong>the</strong> criterion <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>essover misery is seldom necessary. A surrogate criterion is more tractable.Actions, <strong>in</strong>stitutions, rules, pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, customs, ideals, dispositions, <strong>and</strong>character traits count as good or bad accord<strong>in</strong>g to whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y supportor undercut social cooperation, which is prerequisite to <strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong>a society’s members. Economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r social <strong>and</strong> natural scienceshave much to say about what does support or undercut it.Hazlitt gives powerful reasons for repudiat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> variety <strong>of</strong> utilitarianismthat calls for whatever action seems most likely, on each particularoccasion, to contribute most to <strong>the</strong> sum total <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess. at br<strong>and</strong>,called “act-utilitarianism,” has now sunk almost to <strong>the</strong> status <strong>of</strong> a merestrawman. Even so, it rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> favorite target <strong>of</strong> superficial critics. Hazlittadvocates “rules-utilitarianism” <strong>in</strong>stead, which might better be named“<strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism.” I won’t spell out his reasons for espous<strong>in</strong>g thisversion <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism here. Suffice it to say that he rejects case-by-caseexpediency <strong>and</strong> calls for adherence, almost without exception, to traditionalprecepts <strong>of</strong> morality, ethical pr<strong>in</strong>ciples that do satisfy <strong>the</strong> utilitariancriterion. Utilitarian philosophers can give reasons, grounded <strong>in</strong> reality,for respect<strong>in</strong>g cherished values. Henry Hazlitt, <strong>and</strong> Mises before him, forthrightly <strong>and</strong> courageouslyavowed utilitarian ethics <strong>in</strong> a hostile <strong>in</strong>tellectual atmosphere. Let us lookmore closely at what Mises wrote. He identifies ethical doctr<strong>in</strong>es as normativediscipl<strong>in</strong>es concerned with what ought to be. Praxeology <strong>and</strong> economics,<strong>in</strong> contrast, recognize that ultimate ends are purely subjective.ey judge means by whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong>y are suitable to atta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> desiredends (Mises 1949/1966).Does Mises say that a widely accepted ethical code is essential to adecently function<strong>in</strong>g economy? I do not f<strong>in</strong>d that he says so explicitly—perhaps because <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t is almost too obvious to need say<strong>in</strong>g. He says soimplicitly, however, when he emphasizes that social cooperation, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>gmarket relations, is essential to prosperity <strong>and</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> when heexpounds <strong>the</strong> ethics <strong>of</strong> social cooperation.Chapter VIII <strong>of</strong> Human Action expla<strong>in</strong>s that <strong>the</strong> moral rules necessaryfor social cooperation constitute an autonomous, rationalistic, <strong>and</strong> voluntaristicethic. ey st<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> contrast with <strong>the</strong> heteronomous doctr<strong>in</strong>es both


446 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuitionism <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> revealed comm<strong>and</strong>ments (Mises 1949/1966, p. 833).Earlier we read, “Society <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> state are ... <strong>the</strong> primary means for all peopleto atta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ends that <strong>the</strong>y aim at <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own accord.” Society is <strong>the</strong>great means for atta<strong>in</strong>ment <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual’s ends (pp. 148, 165). edivision <strong>of</strong> labor <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> exchange <strong>of</strong> people’s specialized outputs enhanceproductivity. e pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> comparative advantage, which Mises calls<strong>the</strong> Ricardian Law <strong>of</strong> Association, goes far toward expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g how. In aworld without this enhancement <strong>of</strong> productivity, <strong>the</strong>re would be no sentiments<strong>of</strong> benevolence <strong>and</strong> good will (pp. 144, 159–164).e operation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market coord<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ actions. No specialorders or prohibitions are necessary. Noncooperation penalizes itself.e market economy does not ask anybody to deviate from those l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong>conduct that best serve his own <strong>in</strong>terests (pp. 734–736).Beyond <strong>the</strong> sphere <strong>of</strong> private property <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> market, organized societyhas built dams to protect private property <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> market aga<strong>in</strong>st violence,malice, <strong>and</strong> fraud (pp. 734–736). Such misbehavior does occur becausesome persons are too narrow-m<strong>in</strong>ded or too weak <strong>in</strong> moral strength<strong>and</strong> willpower to adjust <strong>the</strong>mselves on <strong>the</strong>ir own to <strong>the</strong> conditions <strong>of</strong> sociallife. ey yield to temptations; <strong>the</strong>y seek fleet<strong>in</strong>g advantage by actionsharmful to <strong>the</strong> smooth function<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> social system. Society couldnot exist if <strong>the</strong> majority were not ready to apply or threaten force to keep<strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>rs from destroy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> social order. Although anarchists overlookthis regrettable truth, <strong>the</strong> state is essential to crush <strong>the</strong> onslaughts<strong>of</strong> peace-breakers (p. 149). “[T]he only purpose <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> laws <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> socialapparatus <strong>of</strong> coercion <strong>and</strong> compulsion is to safeguard <strong>the</strong> smooth function<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> social cooperation” (p. 722).In some passages Mises is quite explicit about his utilitarianism. e<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> social cooperation elaborated by British political economy fromHume to Ricardo extended <strong>the</strong> Epicurean philosophy. “It substituted anautonomous rational morality for <strong>the</strong> heteronomous <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuitionist ethics<strong>of</strong> older days.” e only yardstick to be applied to law, <strong>the</strong> moral code,<strong>and</strong> social <strong>in</strong>stitutions is expediency with regard to human welfare. Godendowed “his creatures with reason <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> urge toward <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong>happ<strong>in</strong>ess” (p. 147).Mises presents a utilitarian case for democracy <strong>and</strong> classical liberalism.Liberalism is not itself a <strong>the</strong>ory, he says, but an application <strong>of</strong> economic<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ories to policy. It attaches a concrete—not purely formal—mean<strong>in</strong>gto happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> removal <strong>of</strong> uneas<strong>in</strong>ess. It supposes thatpeople prefer life, health, nourishment, <strong>and</strong> abundance to <strong>the</strong>ir opposites;


Chapter : e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’s Human Action 447<strong>and</strong> it teaches how to act <strong>in</strong> accordance with <strong>the</strong>se valuations (pp. 149–150,153–154).If an economist states that a certa<strong>in</strong> policy measure is bad, he is notpronounc<strong>in</strong>g a value judgment; he is simply say<strong>in</strong>g that it is <strong>in</strong>appropriatefor <strong>the</strong> desired goal (p. 883).Reformers want to replace what <strong>the</strong>y call selfishness, acquisitiveness,<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it-seek<strong>in</strong>g, Mises observes, with altruism, charity, <strong>and</strong> fear <strong>of</strong>God. But <strong>in</strong> urg<strong>in</strong>g people to substitute “considerations <strong>of</strong> public welfarefor those <strong>of</strong> private pr<strong>of</strong>it, one does not create a work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> satisfactorysocial order.... [H]ow should <strong>the</strong> ‘altruistic’ entrepreneur proceed?”(pp. 725–726).Flexibility <strong>of</strong> prices <strong>and</strong> wages is <strong>the</strong> vehicle <strong>of</strong> adjustment, improvement,<strong>and</strong> progress. ose who condemn price <strong>and</strong> wage changes as unjustare work<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st endeavors to make economic conditions more satisfactory(p. 728).<strong>Is</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it to be morally condemned? “e marvelous economic improvements<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> last two hundred years were an achievement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> capitalistswho provided <strong>the</strong> capital goods required <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> elite <strong>of</strong> technologists<strong>and</strong> entrepreneurs. e masses <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> manual workers were benefited bychanges which <strong>the</strong>y not only did not generate but which, more <strong>of</strong>ten thannot, <strong>the</strong>y tried to cut short” (p. 301).Mises identifies connections between <strong>in</strong>terventionism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> corruption<strong>of</strong> government <strong>of</strong>ficials. In adm<strong>in</strong>ister<strong>in</strong>g many <strong>in</strong>terventionist measures,for example, import licenses, favoritism simply cannot be avoided.Whe<strong>the</strong>r or not money changes h<strong>and</strong>s does not matter; licenses can beawarded to people who supply campaign help. “Corruption is a regulareffect <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terventionism.” Mises also identifies <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>dset <strong>of</strong> redistributionists.“ey reject all traditional notions <strong>of</strong> law <strong>and</strong> legality <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> name<strong>of</strong> a ‘higher <strong>and</strong> nobler’ idea <strong>of</strong> justice. Whatever <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>mselves do isalways right because it hurts those who selfishly want to reta<strong>in</strong> for <strong>the</strong>mselveswhat, from <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> this higher concept <strong>of</strong> justice, oughtto belong to o<strong>the</strong>rs” (pp. 734–736). ’ Beyond Human Action, Mises wrote on ethics elsewhere. In eory <strong>and</strong>History (1979/1985, pp. 54–61) we read:e ultimate yardstick <strong>of</strong> justice is conduciveness to <strong>the</strong> preservation <strong>of</strong>social cooperation.... [S]ocial cooperation is for man a means for <strong>the</strong>


448 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyatta<strong>in</strong>ment <strong>of</strong> all his ends.... As social cooperation is ... a means <strong>and</strong>not an end, no unanimity with regard to value judgments is required tomake it work.... e characteristic feature <strong>of</strong> a free society is that it canfunction <strong>in</strong> spite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that its members disagree <strong>in</strong> many judgments<strong>of</strong> value.Utilitarianism “dispels <strong>the</strong> notion that society, <strong>the</strong> state, <strong>the</strong> nation,or any o<strong>the</strong>r social entity is an ultimate end <strong>and</strong> that <strong>in</strong>dividual men are<strong>the</strong> slaves <strong>of</strong> that entity. It rejects <strong>the</strong> philosophies <strong>of</strong> universalism, collectivism,<strong>and</strong> totalitarianism. In this sense it is mean<strong>in</strong>gful to call utilitarianisma philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualism” (Mises 1979/1985, p. 28).In an essay <strong>of</strong> 1950 Mises wrote:Social cooperation under <strong>the</strong> division <strong>of</strong> labor is <strong>the</strong> ultimate <strong>and</strong> solesource <strong>of</strong> man’s success <strong>in</strong> his struggle for survival <strong>and</strong> his endeavors toimprove as much as possible <strong>the</strong> material conditions <strong>of</strong> his well-be<strong>in</strong>g.But as human nature is, society cannot exist if <strong>the</strong>re is no provisionfor prevent<strong>in</strong>g unruly people from actions <strong>in</strong>compatible with communitylife. In order to preserve peaceful cooperation, one must be ready toresort to violent suppression <strong>of</strong> those disturb<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> peace. (1990, p. 303)e follow<strong>in</strong>g comes from an essay <strong>of</strong> 1945:e sacrifice that a man or a group makes <strong>in</strong> renounc<strong>in</strong>g some short-runga<strong>in</strong>s, lest <strong>the</strong>y endanger <strong>the</strong> peaceful operation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> apparatus <strong>of</strong> socialcooperation, is merely temporary. It amounts to an ab<strong>and</strong>onment <strong>of</strong> asmall immediate pr<strong>of</strong>it for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>comparably greater advantages<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> long run.Such is <strong>the</strong> core <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral teach<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century utilitarianism.Observe <strong>the</strong> moral law for your own sake, nei<strong>the</strong>r out <strong>of</strong> fear <strong>of</strong>hell nor for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r groups, but for your own benefit. Renounceeconomic nationalism <strong>and</strong> conquest, not for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> foreigners <strong>and</strong>aliens, but for <strong>the</strong> benefit <strong>of</strong> your own nation <strong>and</strong> state.It was <strong>the</strong> partial victory <strong>of</strong> this philosophy that resulted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> marvelouseconomic <strong>and</strong> political achievements <strong>of</strong> modern capitalism....e scientific basis <strong>of</strong> this utilitarian ethics was <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> economics.Utilitarian ethics st<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> falls with economics.[But our age witnesses a] revolt aga<strong>in</strong>st rationalism, economics, <strong>and</strong> utilitariansocial philosophy; it is at <strong>the</strong> same time a revolt aga<strong>in</strong>st freedom,democracy, <strong>and</strong> representative government.[e anti-liberals call <strong>the</strong>ir adversaries names.] Rationalism is calledsuperficial <strong>and</strong> unhistoric. Utilitarianism is br<strong>and</strong>ed as a mean system


Chapter : e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’s Human Action 449<strong>of</strong> stockjobber ethics ... “peddler mentality,” “dollar philosophy.” [Economicsis scorned.] (1990, pp. 209–210)Writ<strong>in</strong>g probably <strong>in</strong> 1949 or 1950, Mises recognizes that science doesnot have <strong>the</strong> duty to tell people what to seek as <strong>the</strong>ir chief good. In assess<strong>in</strong>ga doctr<strong>in</strong>e, we have to ask only whe<strong>the</strong>r it is logically coherent or selfcontradictory<strong>and</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r its practical application will help people atta<strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ir desired ends. We have to consider doctr<strong>in</strong>es as recipes for action<strong>and</strong> apply no o<strong>the</strong>r st<strong>and</strong>ard than that <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y will work (1990,pp. 300–301).Utilitarianism has rejected all st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>of</strong> a heteronomous moral law,which has to be accepted <strong>and</strong> obeyed regardless <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequences aris<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>refrom. For [sic] <strong>the</strong> utilitarian po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view a deed is a crimebecause its results are detrimental to society <strong>and</strong> not because some peoplebelieve that <strong>the</strong>y hear <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir soul a mystical voice which calls it acrime. We do not talk about problems <strong>of</strong> ethics. (1990, p. 301)In various writ<strong>in</strong>gs Mises disavows hedonism <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> narrow sense. Notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>gsuperficial critics, “happ<strong>in</strong>ess” does not mean mere material,bodily pleasures. Advanced utilitarians, he says, <strong>in</strong>terpret pleasure <strong>and</strong>pa<strong>in</strong>, utility <strong>and</strong> disutility <strong>in</strong> “purely formal” senses, referr<strong>in</strong>g to whatever<strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> fact try to achieve or avoid (1933/1960, pp. 52, 151; 1979/1985,pp. 12–13; <strong>and</strong> 1949/1966, p. 21).Mises recognizes that many people, especially creative workers, are notdriven by material desires or narrow self-<strong>in</strong>terest alone. ey may also beexpress<strong>in</strong>g competence <strong>and</strong> strength <strong>and</strong> even heroism (1919/1983, pp. 193,213). Besides people concerned only with <strong>the</strong>ir own egos, <strong>the</strong>re are “peoplewith whom awareness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> troubles <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir fellow men causes as muchuneas<strong>in</strong>ess as or even more uneas<strong>in</strong>ess than <strong>the</strong>ir own wants” (1949/1966,p. 14).Mises occasionally slipped <strong>in</strong>to repeat<strong>in</strong>g slogans about “<strong>the</strong> greatesthapp<strong>in</strong>ess for <strong>the</strong> greatest number” (1919/1983, p. 183). Such a formulationhas no precise mean<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>of</strong> course. All that Mises presumablymeant by it is that <strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess to be fur<strong>the</strong>red by morality <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rsocial <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> practices is <strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> people <strong>in</strong> general—<strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om member <strong>of</strong> society—ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> differential happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong>specific persons or classes at <strong>the</strong> expense <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. Mises specifically repudiatedany idea—such as critics enjoy attack<strong>in</strong>g—<strong>of</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to maximizeany numerical aggregate <strong>of</strong> measurable <strong>in</strong>dividual utilities (1949/1966,p. 242).


450 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophySome passages from his Nation, State, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> document Mises’srejection <strong>of</strong> slogans <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuitions as a basis for policy <strong>and</strong> his focus onlikely consequences.Rationalist utilitarianism rules out nei<strong>the</strong>r socialism nor imperialism onpr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Accept<strong>in</strong>g it provides only a st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t from which one cancompare <strong>and</strong> evaluate <strong>the</strong> advantages <strong>and</strong> disadvantages <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> variouspossibilities <strong>of</strong> social order; one could conceivably become a socialist oreven an imperialist from <strong>the</strong> utilitarian st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t. But whoever has onceadopted this st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t is compelled to present his program rationally.(1919/1983, p. 211)Utilitarianism has been reproached for aim<strong>in</strong>g only to satisfy material<strong>in</strong>terests <strong>and</strong> for neglect<strong>in</strong>g higher human goals. It is true that liberalism<strong>and</strong> utilitarianism aim at <strong>the</strong> highest possible productivity <strong>of</strong> labor. But<strong>the</strong>y know “that human existence does not exhaust itself <strong>in</strong> material pleasures.ey strive for welfare <strong>and</strong> for wealth not because <strong>the</strong>y see <strong>the</strong> highestvalue <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m but because <strong>the</strong>y know that all higher <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner culturepresupposes outward welfare.... Utilitarian policy is <strong>in</strong>deed policy for thisearth. But that is true <strong>of</strong> all policy” (1919/1983, pp. 214–215).It is an absurd confusion <strong>of</strong> values <strong>and</strong> positive knowledge, Miseswrote, when <strong>in</strong>sistence on <strong>the</strong> economics relevant to some policy issueis criticized as “<strong>in</strong>sensitive.” If dispell<strong>in</strong>g economic fallacies “is <strong>in</strong>human,<strong>the</strong>n so is every expression <strong>of</strong> truth. If to say this is <strong>in</strong>human, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>physicians who exploded <strong>the</strong> myth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> heal<strong>in</strong>g power <strong>of</strong> m<strong>and</strong>rake were<strong>in</strong>human, too, because <strong>the</strong>y hurt <strong>the</strong> people employed <strong>in</strong> ga<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>and</strong>rake”(1990, p. 234).Mises used to say that various <strong>in</strong>terventionist measures could be rejectedon <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> economic analysis <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> value judgments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>iradvocates.[A]ll <strong>the</strong> methods <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terventionism are doomed to failure. is means:<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terventionist measures must needs result <strong>in</strong> conditions which from<strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own advocates are more unsatisfactory than <strong>the</strong>previous state <strong>of</strong> affairs <strong>the</strong>y were designed to alter. ese policies are<strong>the</strong>refore contrary to purpose. (1922/1981, p. 486) ’ For many decades, utilitarian ethics has had a bad press, not least <strong>in</strong> libertariancircles. It draws scorn as <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>dset <strong>of</strong> crass, grasp<strong>in</strong>g, unpr<strong>in</strong>cipled


Chapter : e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’s Human Action 451people. It supposedly <strong>in</strong>vites government hyperactivity aimed at maximiz<strong>in</strong>gsome misconceived aggregate welfare. Ethics <strong>and</strong> policy must begrounded <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>in</strong> noble <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuitively obvious pr<strong>in</strong>ciples such as unswerv<strong>in</strong>grespect for human dignity <strong>and</strong> human rights.Mises <strong>the</strong> utilitarian has drawn his share <strong>of</strong> criticism, even from some<strong>of</strong> his own disciples. I do not ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that Mises expounded <strong>the</strong> subtlestversion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e, dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g between act utilitarianism <strong>and</strong> rulesor <strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism. He wrote mostly before detailed philosophicaltreatments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se subtleties were published, <strong>and</strong>, anyway, <strong>the</strong>y were notcentral to his ma<strong>in</strong> concerns. Still, his basic philosophical stance is worthdefend<strong>in</strong>g. Confront<strong>in</strong>g it with <strong>the</strong> arguments <strong>of</strong> critics <strong>and</strong> would-be re<strong>in</strong>terpretershelps clarify it <strong>and</strong>, I th<strong>in</strong>k, streng<strong>the</strong>n its appeal.Murray Rothbard called Mises “an opponent <strong>of</strong> objective ethics” (1976,p. 105). is charge is scarcely fair. Certa<strong>in</strong>ly Mises was not an ethical relativistor nihilist, scorn<strong>in</strong>g all judgments <strong>of</strong> right <strong>and</strong> wrong <strong>and</strong> complacenteven when some <strong>in</strong>dividuals violate o<strong>the</strong>rs’ rights <strong>in</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> narrow<strong>and</strong> short-run self-<strong>in</strong>terest. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, he was concerned withwhe<strong>the</strong>r behavior <strong>and</strong> precepts <strong>and</strong> character traits tend to serve or subvertsocial cooperation <strong>and</strong> people’s happ<strong>in</strong>ess.Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Rothbard, Mises made one fundamental value judgment:He hoped that <strong>the</strong> bulk <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> population would get whatever it wantedor thought it wanted. But what if <strong>the</strong> great majority wants to murder redheadsor wants to see <strong>in</strong>nocent persons suffer for its own amusement? Autilitarian such as Mises would <strong>in</strong>clude such preferences “fully as much as<strong>the</strong> most <strong>in</strong>nocuous or altruistic preferences, ... <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantitative reckon<strong>in</strong>g”(1976, pp. 105, 108, 182, 210, 213). Instead <strong>of</strong> cit<strong>in</strong>g specific statementsby Mises, Rothbard criticizes what he supposes Mises, as a utilitarian,must believe.Murray Rothbard has called Mises “an opponent <strong>of</strong> objective ethics”<strong>and</strong> has even trotted out his own st<strong>and</strong>ard remark about possibly murder<strong>in</strong>gall <strong>the</strong> redheads to gratify a majority. Instead <strong>of</strong> cit<strong>in</strong>g specific statementsby Mises, however, Rothbard criticizes what he th<strong>in</strong>ks a utilitarianmust believe. Also, like Karen Vaughn, he criticizes Mises on <strong>the</strong> groundsthat he could not be trusted to hew to <strong>the</strong> libertarian l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> absolutely allcases. Actually, it seems backward to criticize ethical systems accord<strong>in</strong>gto whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y unswerv<strong>in</strong>gly support preconceived policy positions. Itis more sensible to appraise policies accord<strong>in</strong>g to how <strong>the</strong>y accord with awell-grounded ethics. (On <strong>the</strong>se criticisms, recall <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g chapter,number 25).


452 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyRothbard implies that utilitarians hold preferences <strong>and</strong> attitudes <strong>and</strong>character traits immune from appraisal. But Mises, to my knowledge,never said any such th<strong>in</strong>g. A rules or <strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism is <strong>in</strong>deed concernedwith how attitudes <strong>and</strong> character traits, so far as <strong>the</strong>y are opento <strong>in</strong>fluence, tend to affect <strong>the</strong> health <strong>of</strong> a society <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong>its <strong>in</strong>dividual members. For fear <strong>of</strong> adverse side effects <strong>and</strong> for o<strong>the</strong>r reasons,a utilitarian does not want to enlist <strong>the</strong> state’s coercive powers <strong>in</strong>suppress<strong>in</strong>g all unfortunate preferences <strong>and</strong> attitudes <strong>and</strong> traits; but this<strong>in</strong> no way means that he considers all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m equally worthy <strong>of</strong> respect<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence on policy.O<strong>the</strong>r criticism is policy-oriented. Rothbard objected that <strong>the</strong> utilitarianwill rarely apply an absolute pr<strong>in</strong>ciple to real-world situations. e utilitarianregards pr<strong>in</strong>ciple as no more than a vague <strong>and</strong> overridable guidel<strong>in</strong>e.He “cannot be ‘trusted’ to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> libertarian pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> every specificapplication” (1973, p. 24). Karen Vaughn regretted that Mises accepted <strong>the</strong>collectivists’ <strong>and</strong> authoritarians’ terms <strong>of</strong> debate by stress<strong>in</strong>g how efficiently<strong>the</strong> free market provides well-be<strong>in</strong>g. Such a defense <strong>of</strong> freedom is doublydangerous. “First, it is open to empirical refutation.” Second, <strong>the</strong> utilitariancalculus might tip <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> a nonliberal system if it counted <strong>the</strong> bureaucrats’enjoyment from controll<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> regulat<strong>in</strong>g. A less risky course simplypostulates freedom as supremely “desirable for its own sake” <strong>and</strong> as “amoral value that, as a bonus, also happen[s] to lead to <strong>the</strong> well-be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>society” (1976, pp. 108–109).But it seems backward to criticize ethical systems accord<strong>in</strong>g to whe<strong>the</strong>r<strong>the</strong>y unswerv<strong>in</strong>gly support preconceived policy positions. It is more sensibleto appraise policies accord<strong>in</strong>g to how <strong>the</strong>y accord with a well-groundedethics. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, such criticisms dist<strong>in</strong>guish sharply, if sometimes onlyimplicitly, between ethically pr<strong>in</strong>cipled <strong>and</strong> utilitarian approaches to policy.ey <strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>the</strong> latter as unpr<strong>in</strong>cipled, case-by-case direct calculation<strong>of</strong> ga<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> losses <strong>of</strong> utility. Actually, far from reject<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciples,utilitarianism seeks <strong>the</strong>ir sound basis.On <strong>the</strong> charge that utilitarians cannot be trusted to hew to <strong>the</strong> libertarianl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> absolutely all cases, compare Mises’s remark:It may be that socialism represents a better form <strong>of</strong> organization <strong>of</strong> humanlabor. Let whoever asserts this try to prove it rationally. If <strong>the</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>should succeed, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> world, democratically united by liberalism, willnot hesitate to implement <strong>the</strong> communist community. In a democraticstate, who could oppose a reform that would be bound to br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> greatestga<strong>in</strong> to by far <strong>the</strong> overwhelm<strong>in</strong>g majority? <strong>Political</strong> rationalism does


Chapter : e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’s Human Action 453not reject socialism on pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. But it does reject <strong>in</strong> advance <strong>the</strong> socialismthat h<strong>in</strong>ges not on cool underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g but ra<strong>the</strong>r on unclear feel<strong>in</strong>gs,that works not with logic but ra<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> mysticism <strong>of</strong> a gospel <strong>of</strong>salvation, <strong>the</strong> socialism that does not proceed from <strong>the</strong> free will <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>majority <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> people but ra<strong>the</strong>r from <strong>the</strong> terrorism <strong>of</strong> wild fanatics.(1919/1983, p. 221)Mises means that rationalism does reject socialism, yes, but from <strong>the</strong>scientific comparison <strong>of</strong> alternative systems. One widely admired doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> supposed rivalry with utilitarianism<strong>in</strong>sists on adherence to natural law <strong>and</strong> natural rights. Rothbard triesto derive many detailed propositions about ethics <strong>and</strong> law from his conception<strong>of</strong> rights, purportedly derived <strong>in</strong> turn from John Locke’s axioms<strong>of</strong> self-ownership <strong>and</strong> homestead<strong>in</strong>g (1973; 1982). (Yet even for <strong>the</strong>se he<strong>of</strong>fers utilitarian arguments, without acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> label.) John J.Piderit (1993), a Georgetown University economist, argues for what hecalls a natural-law approach: correct reason ascerta<strong>in</strong>s what actions are“natural” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore ethically acceptable by reflect<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> nature<strong>of</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>the</strong>ir shared aspirations <strong>and</strong> fundamental values, <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>teractions <strong>in</strong> community. Yet Piderit can scarcely mean that whateveris natural is right <strong>and</strong> good. Civilization is largely an exercise <strong>in</strong>tam<strong>in</strong>g natural behavior. Of course, any acceptable doctr<strong>in</strong>e must conformto nature <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> not requir<strong>in</strong>g impossible actions or behaviorenforceable only at excessive cost. Respect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> facts <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong>human <strong>in</strong>teraction does not dist<strong>in</strong>guish <strong>the</strong> natural-law approach fromutilitarianism.Natural-law doctr<strong>in</strong>e does make sense if it means merely that all sorts<strong>of</strong> behavior <strong>and</strong> precepts, notably <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g laws made by legislatures <strong>and</strong>judges, are open to appraisal on moral grounds. Noth<strong>in</strong>g becomes ethicallyacceptable merely by enactment <strong>in</strong>to positive law. at <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong>natural law does not rule out a utilitarian ground<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> morality. But if <strong>the</strong>doctr<strong>in</strong>e says that whatever is morally right (or wrong) has all (or none) <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> force <strong>of</strong> positive law, it fatuously denies a live dist<strong>in</strong>ction.As for natural (or human or <strong>in</strong>dividual) rights, <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g that seemsto fit <strong>the</strong> typical context is this: A right is a person’s entitlement to o<strong>the</strong>rs’treatment <strong>of</strong> him that is b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g on those o<strong>the</strong>rs with compell<strong>in</strong>g moralforce. Some rights are positive entitlements, like a child’s right to support


454 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyby his parents or each party’s right to performance by <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r party toa contract. e rights mentioned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Declaration <strong>of</strong> Independence arenegative rights, rights to forbearances, rights not to be coerced or victimizedby o<strong>the</strong>r persons, notably <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g agents <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> state. One reasonwhy negative rights are especially str<strong>in</strong>gent is that <strong>the</strong>y are relatively easyto honor—simply by not <strong>in</strong>terfer<strong>in</strong>g.Rights, be<strong>in</strong>g moral entitlements, presuppose an ethical system or tradition<strong>and</strong> cannot provide its very ground<strong>in</strong>g. On what pr<strong>in</strong>ciples or <strong>in</strong>tuitionsprovide <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> rights, “<strong>the</strong> rhetoric <strong>of</strong> rights sheds no lightwhatever” (Hare 1989, chaps. 7–9, p. 194). Richard Epste<strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ds a utilitarianground<strong>in</strong>g for natural law <strong>and</strong> natural rights, sensibly <strong>in</strong>terpreted,<strong>and</strong> even for <strong>the</strong> Lockean axioms <strong>of</strong> self-ownership or personal autonomy<strong>and</strong> homestead<strong>in</strong>g or first possession (1989, pp. 713–751, 769–773; <strong>and</strong> 1995,pp. 30, 55, 68, 311–313, <strong>and</strong> passim).Mak<strong>in</strong>g natural rights <strong>the</strong> very foundation <strong>of</strong> ethics substitutes <strong>in</strong>tuitionfor factual research <strong>and</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, some str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong>“rights talk” debase political discussion, mak<strong>in</strong>g absolutistic <strong>and</strong> moralisticdem<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> subvert<strong>in</strong>g a creative search for mutually beneficial accommodations.In <strong>the</strong> words <strong>of</strong> Donald Liv<strong>in</strong>gston, <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g David Hume, corruptmodes <strong>of</strong> philosophiz<strong>in</strong>g are undercutt<strong>in</strong>g whatever fragments <strong>of</strong>sensus communis could discipl<strong>in</strong>e radical self-determ<strong>in</strong>ation. Philosophicalresentment spawnsan endless stream <strong>of</strong> self-created victims. Someone’s self determ<strong>in</strong>ation ismet with <strong>the</strong> violent protest that someone else’s rights have been violated.Ever more numerous rights are generated to protect ever more numerousdesires.... “I want”... has become an argument <strong>of</strong> practical reason....us a form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Hobbesian state <strong>of</strong> nature is renewed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mostadvanced civilization, <strong>and</strong> society is held toge<strong>the</strong>r not by <strong>the</strong> enjoyment<strong>and</strong> cultivation <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>herited sensus communis but by legalism enforcedby an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly consolidated <strong>and</strong> bureaucratic modern state. Consolidationmust occur as power is transferred from dismantled, <strong>in</strong>dependentsocial authorities to <strong>the</strong> center <strong>in</strong> order to service an ever-<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g number<strong>of</strong> ant<strong>in</strong>omic <strong>in</strong>dividual rights. (1998, pp. 398–399)As Mises says, declarations about disagreements h<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g on irreconcilably<strong>and</strong> unnegotiably different worldviewsdescribe <strong>the</strong> antagonism as more po<strong>in</strong>ted than it really is. In fact, forall parties committed to pursuit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> people’s earthly welfare <strong>and</strong> thus


Chapter : e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’s Human Action 455approv<strong>in</strong>g social cooperation, questions <strong>of</strong> social organization <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>conduct <strong>of</strong> social action are not problems <strong>of</strong> ultimate pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>world views, but ideological issues. ey are technical problems withregard to which some arrangement is always possible. No party wouldwitt<strong>in</strong>gly prefer social dis<strong>in</strong>tegration, anarchy, <strong>and</strong> a return to primitivebarbarism to a solution which must be bought at <strong>the</strong> price <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sacrifice<strong>of</strong> some ideological po<strong>in</strong>ts. (1949/1966, p. 181) Mises’s own position on natural law <strong>and</strong> rights is an embarrassment forsome <strong>of</strong> his disciples. Nature is alien to <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> right <strong>and</strong> wrong,he observes, question<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> an eternally established st<strong>and</strong>ard.Right <strong>and</strong> wrong are utilitarian judgments. As for natural law, peoplededuce clash<strong>in</strong>g implications from <strong>the</strong>ir arbitrary notions <strong>of</strong> it. “De legeferenda <strong>the</strong>re is no such a th<strong>in</strong>g as justice. e notion <strong>of</strong> justice can logicallyonly be resorted to de lege lata.” In enact<strong>in</strong>g or chang<strong>in</strong>g laws, <strong>the</strong>issue is not justice but social expediency <strong>and</strong> social welfare. “ere is nei<strong>the</strong>rright nor wrong outside <strong>the</strong> social nexus.... e idea <strong>of</strong> justice alwaysrefers to social cooperation” (Mises 1949/1966, pp. 720–721).Utilitarian philosophy <strong>and</strong> classical economics have noth<strong>in</strong>g to dowith <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> natural rights, says Mises. All that matters for <strong>the</strong>mis social utility. Mises even quotes Bentham on <strong>the</strong> “nonsense” <strong>of</strong> naturalrights. Utilitarians recommend democratic government, private property,freedom, <strong>and</strong> equality under <strong>the</strong> law not on illusory grounds <strong>of</strong> naturallaw <strong>and</strong> human equality but because <strong>the</strong>y are beneficial (1949/1966,p. 475).Elsewhere, Mises <strong>in</strong>sisted, “Utilitarian Liberalism had noth<strong>in</strong>g to dowith <strong>the</strong>se natural rights fictions. e Utilitarians <strong>the</strong>mselves must be creditedwith <strong>the</strong> merit <strong>of</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g once <strong>and</strong> for all refuted <strong>the</strong>m” (1990, p. 228).To quote Henry Hazlitt, who wrote largely under Mises’s <strong>in</strong>spiration,<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>violability <strong>of</strong> rights rests “not ... on some mystical yet self-evident‘law <strong>of</strong> nature’... [but] ultimately (though it will shock many to hear this)on utilitarian considerations” (1964, p. 264).Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> formulations quoted above are sharper than I myselfwould have expressed <strong>the</strong>m, but Mises was noth<strong>in</strong>g if not forthright. Preciselybecause human rights <strong>and</strong> human dignity are important values, <strong>the</strong>y A 1945 essay comment<strong>in</strong>g on ideas not only <strong>of</strong> natural law, but also <strong>of</strong> governmentby social contract.


456 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophydeserve a more solid ground<strong>in</strong>g than mere <strong>in</strong>tuitions reported <strong>in</strong> noblesound<strong>in</strong>glanguage. Mises <strong>of</strong> course did not reject natural law <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>scientific sense; <strong>and</strong> he did not reject natural law <strong>and</strong> human rights as ethicalprecepts if <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> tame sense that I sketched outearlier, <strong>the</strong> sense compatible with utilitarianism. What Mises rejected was<strong>the</strong> exaggerated, foundationalist, almost mystical status that some writershave accorded to <strong>the</strong>m. ’ - Hans-Hermann Hoppe presents a curious supposed alternative to utilitarianethics (1988a, pp. 56–76; 1988b, pp. 20–22; <strong>and</strong> contribution to asymposium, “Hoppe’s Rights eory” 1988, pp. 4–53, 53–54). He purportedlydispenses with any appeal to value judgments at all, even such a tameone as wish<strong>in</strong>g people happy ra<strong>the</strong>r than miserable lives. He does not haveto try to get an “ought” from an “is” because <strong>the</strong> libertarian policy positionrests entirely on logic <strong>and</strong> facts <strong>and</strong> not at all on value judgments.Reason, Hoppe says, can prove moral laws valid a priori. It makesexplicit what <strong>the</strong> sheer fact <strong>of</strong> discussion already implies. e libertarianprivate-property ethic can be justified morally <strong>and</strong> by argumentation<strong>and</strong> without <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g any value judgments. Propos<strong>in</strong>g any alternativeethic contradicts what <strong>in</strong>heres <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> very act <strong>of</strong> engag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> argumentation;nonlibertarian proposals are falsified by <strong>the</strong> very act <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>m.Argumentation—discussion—requires employ<strong>in</strong>g scarce means, privatelyowned. Argumentation presupposes that <strong>the</strong> participants recognizeeach one’s exclusive control over one’s own body. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,argumentation could not be susta<strong>in</strong>ed for any length <strong>of</strong> time withoutprivate property <strong>in</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs beyond one’s own body, property ultimatelytrac<strong>in</strong>g to Lockean homestead<strong>in</strong>g. Without private property def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>objective, physical terms, life, act<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> proposition-mak<strong>in</strong>g would beimpossible. “By be<strong>in</strong>g alive <strong>and</strong> formulat<strong>in</strong>g any proposition, <strong>the</strong>n, onedemonstrates that any ethic except <strong>the</strong> libertarian ethic is <strong>in</strong>valid.” Hoppefur<strong>the</strong>r says he has proved “that it is impossible to propositionally justifynonlibertarian property pr<strong>in</strong>ciples without fall<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to contradictions. A section is omitted below because it confronts a re<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> Mises toostra<strong>in</strong>ed to be worth <strong>the</strong> space needed to refute it. For <strong>the</strong> omitted material, see <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>alversion <strong>of</strong> this chapter.


Chapter : e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’s Human Action 457Empirical evidence has absolutely no bear<strong>in</strong>g on it.” He explicitly rejectsutilitarianism; his approach is an alternative (“Hoppe’s Rights eory”1988).Murray Rothbard had been preach<strong>in</strong>g for over thirty years that economistscannot arrive at any policy conclusion <strong>in</strong> a strictly value-free way;<strong>the</strong>y have to come up with some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> ethical system. en Rothbardsaid that Hoppe had proven him wrong. “[H]e has deduced an anarcho-Lockean rights ethic from self-evident axioms.... Hoppe has managedto establish <strong>the</strong> case for anarcho-capitalist-Lockean rights <strong>in</strong> an unprecedentedlyhard-core manner, one that makes my own natural law/naturalrights position seem almost wimpy <strong>in</strong> comparison.... [I]t is impossibleto disagree with <strong>the</strong> anarcho-Lockean rights ethic without fall<strong>in</strong>g immediately<strong>in</strong>to self-contradiction <strong>and</strong> self-refutation.” Hoppe appeals to <strong>the</strong>concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “ethics <strong>of</strong> argumentation.” “[A]ny argument whatsoever ...must imply self-ownership <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> body <strong>of</strong> both <strong>the</strong> arguer <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> listeners,as well as a homestead<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> property right so that <strong>the</strong> arguers <strong>and</strong> listenerswill be alive to listen to <strong>the</strong> argument <strong>and</strong> carry it on” (contribution to<strong>the</strong> symposium on “Hoppe’s Rights eory,” 1988).Hoppe seems to say that espous<strong>in</strong>g nonlibertarian policy positionscommits self-refutation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same sense that I would be refut<strong>in</strong>g myselfif I wrote a letter say<strong>in</strong>g that it is impossible to write a letter or madean oral statement say<strong>in</strong>g it is impossible for anybody to speak. e selfcontradiction<strong>of</strong> a nonlibertarian ethic may be more complicated <strong>and</strong>require more attention to expose, but it still is a self-contradiction, <strong>and</strong><strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same general type. e exposure <strong>of</strong> self-contradiction is a neat k<strong>in</strong>d<strong>of</strong> argument <strong>and</strong> has great appeal—when it works.In <strong>the</strong> present case, it just does not work. Hoppe simply asserts, butdoes not demonstrate, a logical contradiction. Be<strong>in</strong>g emphatic <strong>and</strong> repetitiousis not enough. A slaveowner <strong>and</strong> his slave might conceivably engage<strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>tellectual discussion, even about <strong>the</strong> moral status <strong>of</strong> slavery itself,without ei<strong>the</strong>r necessarily fall<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to self-contradiction. One reason for mention<strong>in</strong>g Hoppe’s <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r alternatives to Mises’sutilitarianism (<strong>and</strong>, more broadly, to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism <strong>of</strong> DavidHume, Mises, <strong>and</strong> Henry Hazlitt) is to show that utilitarianism is notso plastic <strong>and</strong> all-encompass<strong>in</strong>g as to be vacuous. e existence <strong>of</strong> rivalpositions defuses that charge. One envisages a just society <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong>


458 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyJohn Rawls (1971), who rejects view<strong>in</strong>g justice as a mere means to happ<strong>in</strong>ess.O<strong>the</strong>r rival doctr<strong>in</strong>es center on duty or religion. Still o<strong>the</strong>rs positconformity to traditional ethical precepts, even if only <strong>in</strong>tuition, ra<strong>the</strong>rthan analysis <strong>of</strong> consequences, has tested <strong>the</strong> precepts; or respect for <strong>in</strong>dividualrights that have simply been postulated ra<strong>the</strong>r than argued for; orconduciveness to <strong>the</strong> special flourish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> few highest <strong>and</strong> noblestspecimens <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human race. One might also conceivably make <strong>the</strong> criterion<strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess not <strong>of</strong> people <strong>in</strong> general but <strong>of</strong> oneself discrim<strong>in</strong>atorilyor <strong>of</strong> some o<strong>the</strong>r specific person or class.Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se ostensibly rival doctr<strong>in</strong>es, <strong>and</strong> perhaps o<strong>the</strong>rs that donot now come to m<strong>in</strong>d, may turn out, on exam<strong>in</strong>ation, not to be trulyrival doctr<strong>in</strong>es. e criteria <strong>the</strong>y appeal to ei<strong>the</strong>r may not be as ultimate ashapp<strong>in</strong>ess or may be equivalent to it after all. (In putt<strong>in</strong>g forth his axioms<strong>of</strong> self-ownership <strong>and</strong> Lockean homestead<strong>in</strong>g, even Rothbard <strong>in</strong>troducesutilitarian considerations.) Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se doctr<strong>in</strong>es, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>,really are different. eir very existence shows that utilitarianism is notvacuous. If <strong>the</strong>y are too unattractive to be realistic contenders, that factfur<strong>the</strong>r supports utilitarianism.e most urged alternatives to utilitarianism turn out to be varieties <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>tuitionism, which Mises quite properly spoke out aga<strong>in</strong>st. Let me quote<strong>and</strong> paraphrase from his Socialism. (First I should expla<strong>in</strong> a term that Misesuses. Eudaemonistic ethics is, loosely speak<strong>in</strong>g, a system that applies <strong>the</strong>criterion <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess.) Philosophers had been argu<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> ultimateGood for a long time, Mises wrote, before modern <strong>in</strong>vestigation settledit. All <strong>the</strong> arguments used <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> an anti-eudaemonistic ethics wereunable to dissociate <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> Morality from that <strong>of</strong> Happ<strong>in</strong>ess. eva<strong>in</strong> efforts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se philosopherswere necessary to expose <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>in</strong> all its wide ramifications <strong>and</strong>so enable a conclusive solution to be reached.... [T]he tenets <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuitionistethics ... are irreconcilable with scientific method [<strong>and</strong>] havebeen deprived <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir very foundations.... [E]udaemonistic ideas lieconcealed <strong>in</strong> every tra<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> aprioristic-<strong>in</strong>tuitive ethical thought.... Everyethical system built upon <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> duty ... is f<strong>in</strong>ally obliged to yield somuch to Eudaemonism that its pr<strong>in</strong>ciples can no longer be ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed.In <strong>the</strong> same way every s<strong>in</strong>gle requirement <strong>of</strong> aprioristic-<strong>in</strong>tuitive ethicsdisplays ultimately an eudaemonistic character. (1922/1981, p. 360)


Chapter : e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’s Human Action 459e fact/value or is/ought dist<strong>in</strong>ction, which I <strong>in</strong>troduced at <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g,is <strong>in</strong>deed a sound one. Never<strong>the</strong>less, “ought” judgments can be discussed<strong>and</strong> soundly made (except only for fundamental value judgments,<strong>and</strong> even for <strong>the</strong>m, considerations can be adduced that <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>e peopleto accept <strong>the</strong>m; Mill 1863/1968, chap. 1). e soundest, most appeal<strong>in</strong>gapproach to value judgments <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong>ir use, as <strong>in</strong> policy recommendations,has been shown by Hume, Mises, Hazlitt, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r writers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>irtradition (or <strong>in</strong> parallel, as by R.M. Hare). is approach is <strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism.Mises was forthright, even courageous, <strong>in</strong> espous<strong>in</strong>g utilitarianism <strong>and</strong>repudiat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tuitionist alternatives. For this his reputation cont<strong>in</strong>ues tosuffer even among disciples who o<strong>the</strong>rwise are carry<strong>in</strong>g on his work. I urge<strong>the</strong>m to reconsider. I am not say<strong>in</strong>g that Mises developed <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctionbetween <strong>the</strong> act version <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> rules or <strong>in</strong>direct version <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism<strong>and</strong> fully articulated <strong>the</strong> latter. I am not say<strong>in</strong>g that he anticipated <strong>and</strong>demolished <strong>in</strong> advance <strong>the</strong> axiomatic or <strong>in</strong>tuitionist rights approach thatsome <strong>of</strong> his disciples would urge. Do<strong>in</strong>g all that was not possible <strong>in</strong> histime <strong>and</strong> was not necessary for his work <strong>in</strong> economics. However, a sophisticatedutilitarianism does fit <strong>in</strong> with <strong>and</strong> extend his philosophical framework.Henry Hazlitt, for one, extended it. Mises was on <strong>the</strong> right track.Epste<strong>in</strong>, Richard A. “e Utilitarian Foundations <strong>of</strong> Natural Law” <strong>and</strong> “Postscript:Subjective Utilitarianism.” Harvard Journal <strong>of</strong> Law & Public Policy 12(1989): 713–751, 769–773.. Simple Rules for a Complex World. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard UniversityPress, 1995.Hare, R.M. <strong>Essays</strong> on <strong>Political</strong> Morality. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989.Hazlitt, Henry. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Morality. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>,1964.Hoppe, Hans-Hermann. “From <strong>the</strong> Economics <strong>of</strong> Laissez Faire to <strong>the</strong> Ethics<strong>of</strong> Libertarianism.” In Man, <strong>Economy</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Liberty: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> Honor <strong>of</strong> MurrayN. Rothbard, edited by Walter Block <strong>and</strong> Llewellyn H. Rockwell, Jr., 56–76.Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1988a.


460 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy. “e Ultimate Justification <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Private Property Ethic.” Liberty 2(September 1988b): 20–22.“Hoppe’s Rights eory: Breakthrough or Buncombe?” A symposium by variousauthors, with a response by Hoppe. Liberty 2 (November 1988): 4–53, 53–54.Kirzner, <strong>Is</strong>rael. “e Nature <strong>and</strong> Significance <strong>of</strong> Economic Education.” e Freeman48 (October 1998): 582–586.Liv<strong>in</strong>gston, Donald W. Philosophical Melancholy <strong>and</strong> Delirium: Hume’s Pathology<strong>of</strong> Philosophy. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1998.Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism. 1863. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Selected Writ<strong>in</strong>gs, edited byMaurice Cowl<strong>in</strong>g, 243–304. New York: New American Library, 1968.Mises, Ludwig von. Nation, State, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economy</strong>. 1919. Translated by Lel<strong>and</strong> B.Yeager. New York: New York University Press, 1983.. Socialism: An Economic <strong>and</strong> Sociological Analysis. 1922. Translated byJ. Kahane. Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 1981.. Epistemological Problems <strong>of</strong> Economics. 1933. Translated by George Reisman.Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>, 1960.. Human Action. 1949. 3 ed. Chicago: Regnery, 1966.. e Ultimate Foundation <strong>of</strong> Economic Science. 1962. 2ⁿ ed. Kansas City,Kans.: Sheed Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, 1977.. eory <strong>and</strong> History. 1979. Repr<strong>in</strong>ted Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von MisesInstitute, 1985.. Money, Method, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Market</strong> Process. <strong>Essays</strong> selected by Margit vonMises. Edited <strong>and</strong> with an <strong>in</strong>troduction by Richard M. Ebel<strong>in</strong>g. Norwell,Mass.: Kluwer, 1990.Piderit, John J. e Ethical Foundations <strong>of</strong> Economics. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.: GeorgetownUniversity Press, 1993.Rawls, John. A eory <strong>of</strong> Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press <strong>of</strong> HarvardUniversity Press, 1971.Rothbard, Murray N. For a New Liberty. New York: Macmillan, 1973.. “Praxeology, Value Judgments, <strong>and</strong> Public Policy.” In e Foundations<strong>of</strong> Modern Austrian Economics, edited by E.G. Dolan. Kansas City, Kans.:Sheed <strong>and</strong> Ward, 1976.


Chapter : e Moral Element <strong>in</strong> Mises’s Human Action 461. e Ethics <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Atlantic Highl<strong>and</strong>s, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1982.Vaughn, Karen. “Critical Discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Four Papers.” In e Economics <strong>of</strong>Ludwig von Mises, edited by L.S. Moss, 101–110. Kansas City, Kans.: Sheed<strong>and</strong> Ward, 1976.


Can a Liberal Be anEgalitarian? *An answer to <strong>the</strong> question posed by my title depends, obviously, on howits terms are def<strong>in</strong>ed.I shall deny that a liberal can consistently advocate government actionto chop down high <strong>in</strong>comes or especially favorable opportunities out <strong>of</strong>zeal for a closer approach to material equality as a goal <strong>in</strong> its own right. Instead <strong>of</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> term “liberal” as it is used <strong>in</strong> modern Americanpolitics, I use it, as Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Mises <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> “Austrian” <strong>and</strong> “Chicago” economistsdo, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> traditional sense. Liberalism is a doctr<strong>in</strong>e that rejects anysupposed social or national purpose transcend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> purposes <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals.Instead, it seeks to allow each <strong>in</strong>dividual a wide range <strong>of</strong> freechoice among purposes <strong>and</strong> pursuits. (While emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> goals <strong>of</strong>each <strong>in</strong>dividual, it <strong>in</strong> no way denies <strong>the</strong> healthy fact that he may largelyrelate his own <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>and</strong> satisfactions to those <strong>of</strong> many people beyondhimself.) Liberalism calls for preserv<strong>in</strong>g, adopt<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> devis<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> social,political, <strong>and</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions likeliest to m<strong>in</strong>imize <strong>the</strong> frictions that<strong>in</strong>evitably arise to some extent among <strong>the</strong> pursuits <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> specific freedoms<strong>of</strong> different <strong>in</strong>dividuals. Yet it cannot give an equal bless<strong>in</strong>g to whatevergoals <strong>in</strong>dividuals might have. Malicious enjoyment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> misfortunes<strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people, or envy, or a sheer delight <strong>in</strong> meddl<strong>in</strong>g—all arehard to square with liberalism. is judgment holds even when such tastesare gratified through voluntary transactions among all persons concerned.More about this later.*From Toward Liberty, vol. II, Festschrift for Ludwig von Mises (Menlo Park, Calif.:Institute for Humane Studies, 1971), 422–440. Here, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> article’s title <strong>and</strong> throughout,<strong>the</strong> word “egalitarian” replaces <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al “equalitarian.” I shall obviously be deal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> value judgments. While it is impossible to classify valuejudgments scientifically as right or wrong, it is possible to <strong>in</strong>vestigate relations among<strong>the</strong>m, reveal<strong>in</strong>g compatibilities <strong>and</strong> clashes <strong>and</strong> striv<strong>in</strong>g for a consistent <strong>and</strong> economicalarticulation. Show<strong>in</strong>g people that certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir less fundamental value judgments clashdemonstrates <strong>the</strong> need for a more careful rank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> articulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir values.462


Chapter : Can a Liberal Be an Egalitarian? 463As for egalitarianism, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g it explicitly, I want to dist<strong>in</strong>guishbetween level<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>and</strong> level<strong>in</strong>g down. Consider a m<strong>in</strong>ority <strong>of</strong>people whose wealth or <strong>in</strong>come or opportunities are distress<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>in</strong>feriorto those <strong>of</strong> most people. Redistribution to help <strong>the</strong>m, perhaps through<strong>the</strong> government budget, is level<strong>in</strong>g up. With that I have no quarrel <strong>in</strong>pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Such relief <strong>of</strong> actual poverty—<strong>of</strong> def<strong>in</strong>itely sub-modal circumstances—isnot meddlesomeness. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is an effort to remedy a situationalmost universally recognized as bad. (is is not to say that monks<strong>and</strong> nuns <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r ascetics should be barred from choos<strong>in</strong>g a life <strong>of</strong>poverty.) Involuntary but eradicable poverty is a blemish, mak<strong>in</strong>g a societyless attractive for practically everyone who comes <strong>in</strong> contact with or evenis keenly aware <strong>of</strong> it. Its elim<strong>in</strong>ation would be <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> recognized <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>of</strong> almost everyone.Redistribution to level down unusually great wealth or <strong>in</strong>comes or unusuallyfavorable opportunities is quite a different th<strong>in</strong>g. Great wealth is<strong>the</strong> opposite <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g that almost everyone would consider bad forhimself. It, or <strong>the</strong> opportunity to achieve it, broadens <strong>the</strong> range <strong>of</strong> alternativesopen to people, as we can recognize without suppos<strong>in</strong>g that materialabundance must form <strong>the</strong> very core <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good life. Ideally, a liberal wouldlike each person to have <strong>the</strong> opportunity for it if that is what he wants. Apolicy aimed at level<strong>in</strong>g down <strong>the</strong> exceptionally wealthy few would deprivesome people <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir good fortune—a good fortune that a liberal wouldwelcome for everyone—because o<strong>the</strong>r people are less fortunate. If everyonecannot be very lucky, no one shall be. is attitude may be a humanone; but it is an unlovely one, unworthy <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g sanctified <strong>in</strong> publicpolicy.But do any people who consider <strong>the</strong>mselves traditional liberals reallyadvocate level<strong>in</strong>g down as dist<strong>in</strong>guished from level<strong>in</strong>g up? Does any liberalreally favor tax progression <strong>of</strong> such a degree that direct benefits topoor people are doubtful or trivial? It is true that this idea seldom appearsunequivocally <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>t. But it crops up <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>in</strong> discussions. And it seemsto underlie <strong>the</strong> ubiquitous slogan that “Equality is an end <strong>in</strong> its own right.”Henry Simons, who ranks as one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sa<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Chicago School, hasexpressed his preferencefor ra<strong>the</strong>r steep progression. e tax system should be used systematicallyto correct excessive economic <strong>in</strong>equality <strong>and</strong> to preclude <strong>in</strong>ord<strong>in</strong>ate,endur<strong>in</strong>g differences among families or economic strata <strong>in</strong> wealth, power,<strong>and</strong> opportunities. (1950, p. 144)


464 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyAccord<strong>in</strong>g to Simons,Sound meliorative measures must yield not mere level<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>comes butlevel<strong>in</strong>g accretions <strong>of</strong> capacity, capital, <strong>and</strong> possessed power.Equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity is an ideal that free societies should constantlypursue, even at much cost <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r ends. (1948, p. 6)Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Allan T. Peacock,Liberal support for such measures as progressive taxation does not reston <strong>the</strong> utilitarian belief that an extra pound is more “valuable” or will“afford a greater utility” to a poor man than to a rich man. It rests on apositive dislike <strong>of</strong> gross <strong>in</strong>equality. (Quoted <strong>in</strong> Hayek 1960, p. 518)Frank H. Knight has repeatedly likened social life to a “game” or “contest,”has talked about <strong>the</strong> “distribution <strong>of</strong> prizes,” has mused on what arrangementstend to make <strong>the</strong> contest “<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to participants <strong>and</strong> spectators,”<strong>and</strong> has considered <strong>the</strong> imposition <strong>of</strong> “h<strong>and</strong>icaps.” His thought isso rich <strong>and</strong> complex that a reader cannot be sure whe<strong>the</strong>r Knight reallyfavors some degree <strong>of</strong> level<strong>in</strong>g down for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> equality as an end<strong>in</strong> its own right. Qualifications can also be found <strong>in</strong> Simons’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs.But whatever <strong>the</strong> correct <strong>in</strong>terpretations may be, Knight <strong>and</strong> Simons havefurnished <strong>in</strong>tellectual stimulation for some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir more forthrightly egalitarianChicago School disciples. Ideas <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d under considerationabound, <strong>of</strong> course, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> works <strong>of</strong> writers who do not even claim to betraditional liberals.I wonder whe<strong>the</strong>r liberals who speak <strong>of</strong> equality as an end <strong>in</strong> its ownright have really exam<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>ir values thoroughly. Why is equality an end?Perhaps some people honestly have no idea <strong>of</strong> how to answer this questionbecause <strong>the</strong>y consider equality as an ultimate desideratum that <strong>the</strong>y cannotdescribe as a means <strong>of</strong> serv<strong>in</strong>g any more basic values. But this positionmust be rare. Most egalitarians presumably consider equality a means tomore basic values with which <strong>the</strong> connection is obvious.What might <strong>the</strong>se still more basic values be? One might be <strong>the</strong> avoidance<strong>of</strong> concentrated power. But great wealth is not great power. Be<strong>in</strong>g For example, <strong>in</strong> Knight 1936, pp. 60–66, 292–293, 302–304. e ones to be considered here still are not absolutely basic. An absolute valuewould presumably be someth<strong>in</strong>g comprehensive <strong>and</strong> vague such as “human happ<strong>in</strong>ess”or “human self-fulfillment.” Not only economics but also political science, sociology, psychology,philosophy, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r discipl<strong>in</strong>es presumably have much to contribute to <strong>in</strong>vestigation<strong>of</strong> which <strong>in</strong>termediate ends, or <strong>the</strong> policies <strong>and</strong> social <strong>and</strong> political <strong>and</strong> economic


Chapter : Can a Liberal Be an Egalitarian? 465wealthy does not enable a person to coerce o<strong>the</strong>rs or to restrict <strong>the</strong> opportunitiesopen to <strong>the</strong>m. His ability to <strong>of</strong>fer <strong>the</strong>m f<strong>in</strong>ancially attractive dealsis not <strong>the</strong> same as power to deprive <strong>the</strong>m <strong>of</strong> alternatives <strong>the</strong>y would havehad anyway. e situation would be different if one person or group, or avery few <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se, accounted for a large enough fraction <strong>of</strong> national <strong>in</strong>comeor wealth to possess monopoly power <strong>in</strong> deal<strong>in</strong>g with o<strong>the</strong>r people. en,however, <strong>the</strong> unsatisfactory condition would be precisely this monopolypower <strong>and</strong> it would confuse <strong>the</strong> issue to talk about <strong>in</strong>equality <strong>in</strong>stead.When a country has several thous<strong>and</strong> separate <strong>in</strong>dividuals or families <strong>of</strong>great wealth, it is almost a contradiction <strong>in</strong> terms to speak <strong>of</strong> concentration<strong>of</strong> wealth or power <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir h<strong>and</strong>s. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> severalthous<strong>and</strong> pillars <strong>of</strong> economic strength, many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m able <strong>and</strong> some<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m will<strong>in</strong>g to support causes <strong>and</strong> persons that may be unpopular with<strong>the</strong> general public <strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> government, may be <strong>of</strong> great value <strong>in</strong> preserv<strong>in</strong>ga free society.Ano<strong>the</strong>r motive for egalitarianism might be <strong>the</strong> belief that a marg<strong>in</strong>aldollar adds less to <strong>the</strong> utility <strong>of</strong> a rich person than <strong>of</strong> someone else <strong>and</strong>that redistribution might accord<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>in</strong>crease total social utility. Besidestak<strong>in</strong>g some old-fashioned str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>the</strong>ory too seriously, thisargument bl<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>the</strong> ethical question whe<strong>the</strong>r an <strong>in</strong>voluntary transfer canbe justified by <strong>the</strong> mere fact or conjecture that <strong>the</strong> ga<strong>in</strong>ers ga<strong>in</strong> more than<strong>the</strong> losers lose. A more plausible version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> argument is that <strong>the</strong> surplus<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rich can be taken for such socially important purposes as build<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> runn<strong>in</strong>g schools <strong>and</strong> hospitals. In consider<strong>in</strong>g this argument, we mustdist<strong>in</strong>guish between two cases, though <strong>the</strong> analysis does not h<strong>in</strong>ge on anyexact divid<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>e between <strong>the</strong>m. First, suppose that those who benefitfrom <strong>the</strong> schools <strong>and</strong> hospitals are so poor that <strong>the</strong>y could not pay for<strong>the</strong>m without trench<strong>in</strong>g pa<strong>in</strong>fully on consumption <strong>of</strong> still more urgentnecessities: <strong>the</strong>y could not pay by ord<strong>in</strong>ary private purchase <strong>of</strong> school<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> hospitalization, through premiums on private or governmental <strong>in</strong>surance,by taxes, or <strong>in</strong> any o<strong>the</strong>r way. e problem is <strong>the</strong>n one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir actualpoverty, <strong>and</strong> rhetoric about schools <strong>and</strong> hospitals <strong>in</strong> particular beclouds<strong>the</strong> issue. Most liberals would favor measures to relieve actual poverty;but precisely because it is <strong>in</strong> almost everyone’s <strong>in</strong>terest to live <strong>in</strong> a societyarrangements adopted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir pursuit, do <strong>and</strong> which do not conduce to <strong>the</strong> irreduciblybasic end <strong>of</strong> human happ<strong>in</strong>ess. ese beneficiaries are <strong>of</strong> course likely to <strong>in</strong>clude people beyond those who actuallyuse <strong>the</strong> schools <strong>and</strong> hospitals—<strong>the</strong> externalities <strong>in</strong>volved are familiar—<strong>and</strong> I am not necessarilyimply<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> entire cost should be charged to <strong>the</strong> actual users alone.


466 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyfree <strong>of</strong> actual poverty, it is not clear—at least, not without fur<strong>the</strong>r argument—why<strong>the</strong> cost should be concentrated on a rich m<strong>in</strong>ority. Secondly,suppose that <strong>the</strong> beneficiaries <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> schools <strong>and</strong> hospitals are not especiallypoor <strong>and</strong> could afford to pay for <strong>the</strong>ir services <strong>in</strong> one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> waysmentioned. Why, <strong>the</strong>n, should a rich m<strong>in</strong>ority have to pay a share <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> costs out <strong>of</strong> proportion to <strong>the</strong>ir share <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> benefits? So far as <strong>the</strong>beneficiaries <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> schools <strong>and</strong> hospitals escape <strong>the</strong> cost, <strong>the</strong>y have moneyleft over to spend on o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs. Redistributive taxation may thus <strong>in</strong>effect make <strong>the</strong> rich help pay for <strong>the</strong> cloth<strong>in</strong>g, automobiles, enterta<strong>in</strong>ment,<strong>and</strong> liquor <strong>of</strong> people who are not poor. Perhaps this is defensible;but what, <strong>the</strong>n, becomes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> special emotional aura <strong>of</strong> schools <strong>and</strong>hospitals?Perhaps egalitarianism is an extension <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> liberal case for relief<strong>of</strong> actual poverty. For, redistributionists might argue, <strong>the</strong> divid<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>ebetween poverty <strong>and</strong> adequate <strong>in</strong>come is vague. Even persons <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> modalor typical <strong>in</strong>come brackets may suffer relative poverty; <strong>the</strong>y may be uncomfortableabout not be<strong>in</strong>g able to live on <strong>the</strong> same material plane as <strong>the</strong>wealthy m<strong>in</strong>ority. If reliev<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> discomfort <strong>of</strong> actual poverty is urgent,<strong>the</strong>n reliev<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> mental discomfort <strong>of</strong> relative poverty may be somewhatadvantageous. In reply, it may be po<strong>in</strong>ted out that while a l<strong>in</strong>e betweenpoverty <strong>and</strong> material comfort cannot be drawn precisely, a general basisfor <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction exists. In <strong>the</strong> United States, <strong>the</strong> persons to be consideredactually poor are a fairly small m<strong>in</strong>ority <strong>in</strong> material circumstanceswell below what is typical. Redistribution to benefit this poor m<strong>in</strong>orityis different <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple from level<strong>in</strong>g down a rich m<strong>in</strong>ority <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposed<strong>in</strong>terest <strong>of</strong> a modal majority. Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, not def<strong>in</strong>ite tax schedules, iswhat is at issue here. A fur<strong>the</strong>r aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> issue is whe<strong>the</strong>r public policyshould recognize <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> relative poverty <strong>and</strong> should dignify whateveruneas<strong>in</strong>ess some people may feel about <strong>the</strong> better fortune <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs bybas<strong>in</strong>g tax legislation upon it. It is not enough to consider what attitudesmay <strong>in</strong> fact prevail, caus<strong>in</strong>g mental pa<strong>in</strong> or pleasure; social philosophersalso have <strong>the</strong> job <strong>of</strong> consider<strong>in</strong>g what sorts <strong>of</strong> attitudes should or shouldnot be encouraged because <strong>the</strong>y do or do not tend to promote a good society,coherently conceived. Admittedly I cannot cite a clear statement <strong>of</strong> this position. e grounds for egalitarianismor redistributionism are so generally regarded as self-evident that a critic must tryto figure out for himself just how <strong>the</strong> redistributionist case might look if spelled out <strong>in</strong>detail <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> strongest version he can conceive. is is what I am try<strong>in</strong>g to do, ra<strong>the</strong>r thanconcoct<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> refut<strong>in</strong>g flimsy arguments as a debat<strong>in</strong>g tactic.


Chapter : Can a Liberal Be an Egalitarian? 467Perhaps <strong>the</strong> redistributionist case rests less on any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> forego<strong>in</strong>garguments than on <strong>in</strong>choate notions about what makes for a healthy tone<strong>of</strong> society—notions about avoid<strong>in</strong>g social dist<strong>in</strong>ctions <strong>and</strong> feel<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>feriority<strong>and</strong> about promot<strong>in</strong>g solidarity <strong>and</strong> bro<strong>the</strong>rhood. Slogans aboutequality as part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> democratic ideal support this conjecture. I admittedlywould consider it a good th<strong>in</strong>g—though I would be hard pressed toexpla<strong>in</strong> just why—if <strong>the</strong> distributions <strong>of</strong> physical <strong>and</strong> mental talent <strong>and</strong>energy, personal ambition <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ation, <strong>in</strong>herited property, advantageousfamily backgrounds, <strong>and</strong> so forth meshed with <strong>the</strong> derived dem<strong>and</strong>sfor material <strong>and</strong> human factors <strong>of</strong> production <strong>in</strong> such a way that <strong>the</strong> personal<strong>in</strong>comes created on <strong>the</strong> free market were not conspicuously unequal.Spontaneous equality <strong>of</strong> this sort could perhaps be fur<strong>the</strong>red by measuresto break down any contrived restrictions on economic opportunity.Spontaneous equality would still contrast sharply with deliberately level<strong>in</strong>gdown <strong>the</strong> rich. Deliberate level<strong>in</strong>g would be likely to do <strong>the</strong> reverse<strong>of</strong> overcom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>centives to envy, embarrassments to social <strong>in</strong>tercourse,<strong>and</strong> obstacles to bro<strong>the</strong>rhood <strong>and</strong> mutual respect. e degree <strong>of</strong> envy <strong>and</strong>so forth would probably not correlate at all closely with <strong>the</strong> size <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>equalitiesrema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g under an avowed program <strong>of</strong> equalization; sometimes <strong>the</strong>smallest dist<strong>in</strong>ctions are <strong>the</strong> most keenly resented. More important, <strong>the</strong>idea <strong>of</strong> deliberate level<strong>in</strong>g seems dangerously ak<strong>in</strong> to ideas that all menare not equal <strong>in</strong> those respects which concern <strong>the</strong> State, that men withdifferent <strong>in</strong>comes are different <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tolerable ways, <strong>and</strong> that differences <strong>in</strong>people’s material wealth <strong>and</strong> lifestyle—differences go<strong>in</strong>g beyond <strong>the</strong> discomforts<strong>of</strong> actual poverty—are conditions to emphasize, to be suspicious<strong>of</strong>, <strong>and</strong> to take action about. To work aga<strong>in</strong>st poverty is admirable, but tobe concerned about o<strong>the</strong>r people’s exceptional good fortune <strong>and</strong> to wantto <strong>in</strong>terfere strikes me as hardly compatible with a coherent liberalism.People are all too ready, anyway, to pass judgment on <strong>the</strong>ir fellows. eyare all too ready to display <strong>in</strong>tolerance, bitterness, Puritanism, a busybodyspirit, <strong>and</strong> suspicion <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir personalities <strong>and</strong> lifestyles.Many redistributionists, it is true, are moved by humanitarian motives;<strong>the</strong>y do not want to promote suspiciousness or p<strong>and</strong>er to resentment. But“good <strong>in</strong>tentions are not enough.” e spirit <strong>of</strong> live-<strong>and</strong>-let-live, so crucialto a free society, is fragile. Any policy that dignifies <strong>and</strong> re<strong>in</strong>forces <strong>the</strong>less lovely traits <strong>of</strong> human nature, however un<strong>in</strong>tentionally, deserves badmarks on this score.e leveler philosophy may rest <strong>in</strong> part on <strong>the</strong> feel<strong>in</strong>g that extremelyhigh <strong>in</strong>comes are undeserved. Of course not all large <strong>in</strong>comes derive from


468 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyhard work, <strong>in</strong>genuity, or alertness <strong>in</strong> meet<strong>in</strong>g consumer tastes. Large <strong>in</strong>comesobta<strong>in</strong>ed by force, fraud, restra<strong>in</strong>t on competition, or dishonestadvertis<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> salesmanship are <strong>in</strong>deed open to question. More precisely,it is <strong>the</strong> illegal or immoral activities <strong>the</strong>mselves that deserve attention; t<strong>of</strong>ocus on <strong>the</strong> sheer size <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>comes beclouds <strong>the</strong> issue. Large<strong>in</strong>comes due to <strong>in</strong>heritance <strong>of</strong> talent or energy or beauty or connectionsor wealth, or to sheer luck, pose a trickier question: why should some notparticularly virtuous people enjoy luxury while millions <strong>of</strong> harder-work<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> worthier people must scrape to make ends meet? In partial reply, onemay ask ano<strong>the</strong>r question: If <strong>the</strong> processes <strong>of</strong> allocat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> services <strong>of</strong>persons <strong>and</strong> property <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> most <strong>in</strong>tense consumer dem<strong>and</strong>yield very large <strong>in</strong>comes for some not especially deserv<strong>in</strong>g persons <strong>and</strong> for<strong>the</strong>ir heirs, who is actually hurt <strong>and</strong> entitled to compla<strong>in</strong>? In an <strong>in</strong>novat<strong>in</strong>g,enterpris<strong>in</strong>g society, total real <strong>in</strong>come is not a fixed pie; larger slicesfor some do not necessarily mean smaller slices for o<strong>the</strong>rs. Perhaps peoplewith lower <strong>in</strong>comes are harmed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong>ir taxes wouldbe lower if <strong>the</strong> rich paid still higher taxes. But this “harm” is differentfrom harm positively <strong>in</strong>flicted by <strong>the</strong> rich. As for rich persons <strong>in</strong>nocent<strong>of</strong> illegal or immoral activities, <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y justify or forgo <strong>the</strong>irexceptional <strong>in</strong>comes raises fundamental questions about what prerogatives<strong>of</strong> organized society are compatible with liberalism. Like busybod<strong>in</strong>ess, itis perhaps a human trait to begrudge one’s fellows whatever exceptionalgood luck may come <strong>the</strong>ir way—I say “perhaps” because <strong>the</strong> general publicdoes not seem to bear grudges aga<strong>in</strong>st lottery w<strong>in</strong>ners <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong>exceptionally glamorous rich—but grudges about good luck are unworthy<strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g dignified as <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> public policy.Note that I am not accept<strong>in</strong>g—<strong>in</strong>stead, I explicitly reject—<strong>the</strong> “marg<strong>in</strong>alproductivity ethics” <strong>of</strong> John Bates Clark <strong>and</strong> his followers, a doctr<strong>in</strong>erightly dissected by Frank Knight <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r liberal economists. e merefact that a man’s own work or <strong>the</strong> services <strong>of</strong> his property happen to havean exceptionally high market value does not mean that he is especiallydeserv<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> any ethical sense, <strong>of</strong> an exceptionally large <strong>in</strong>come. <strong>Market</strong>value is not a measure <strong>of</strong> ethical merit, <strong>and</strong> people <strong>in</strong> general would behappier if this fact were explicitly recognized. My concern is with whatsort <strong>of</strong> a politico-economic system would replace capitalism if productivity<strong>and</strong> market-value considerations were set aside as a basis <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>comedistribution. More specifically, <strong>in</strong> this paper, I am concerned about <strong>the</strong> On this po<strong>in</strong>t, see Hayek 1960, chap. 6.


Chapter : Can a Liberal Be an Egalitarian? 469implicit redistributionist conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> State as an agency that, whilenot allott<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>the</strong>ir fates outright, at least takes a decisive h<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong> readjust<strong>in</strong>g that allotment. I am ra<strong>the</strong>r horrified at <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Stateas a dispenser <strong>of</strong> “justice” <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> concrete, material sense, <strong>and</strong> as a Godthat passes judgment on what people deserve <strong>and</strong> steps <strong>in</strong> not merely toallay <strong>the</strong> unfortunate consequences <strong>of</strong> bad luck but also to strip people <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> fruits <strong>of</strong> what it considers too much good luck.Before return<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity, I shiftnow from exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g possible str<strong>and</strong>s <strong>in</strong> a rationale <strong>of</strong> level<strong>in</strong>g down toexpress<strong>in</strong>g some actual doubts. A much-discussed problem <strong>in</strong> politicalethics arises when people who expect material or psychological ga<strong>in</strong> fromredistributionary taxation act as judges <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own cause. By impos<strong>in</strong>ghigher tax rates than <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>mselves are will<strong>in</strong>g to pay, <strong>the</strong> majority <strong>of</strong>voters ask a rich m<strong>in</strong>ority to “work more days out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> year for <strong>the</strong> government”than <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>mselves are will<strong>in</strong>g to do. As Hayek (1960, p. 314) hassaid, “at a majority, merely because it is a majority, should be entitled toapply to a m<strong>in</strong>ority a rule which does not apply to itself is an <strong>in</strong>fr<strong>in</strong>gement<strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>in</strong>ciple much more fundamental than democracy itself, a pr<strong>in</strong>cipleon which <strong>the</strong> justification <strong>of</strong> democracy rests.” is “discrim<strong>in</strong>ation” argument <strong>in</strong>furiates redistributionists, who suspectthat its user’s heart is bleed<strong>in</strong>g for people who will have more <strong>in</strong>come<strong>and</strong> wealth per head, even after taxes, than <strong>the</strong>ir alleged despoilers. ecritic has a hard time prov<strong>in</strong>g that his real worry is over <strong>the</strong> attitude thatmight makes right—<strong>the</strong> sheer might <strong>of</strong> numerous votes.e “discrim<strong>in</strong>ation” argument would lose much <strong>of</strong> its force if level<strong>in</strong>gdown were enacted not merely by an overall majority but also by a majority<strong>of</strong> even those persons who would have to pay <strong>the</strong> exceptionally hightax rates. But <strong>the</strong>n why not rely on voluntary redistribution? One reason,apparently, is <strong>the</strong> “public-good” character <strong>of</strong> redistribution: <strong>the</strong> typical richperson might be will<strong>in</strong>g to redistribute only if all o<strong>the</strong>r rich persons did <strong>the</strong>same; only compulsion could achieve <strong>the</strong> general redistribution assumed I am aware that a case <strong>of</strong> sorts can be made out for redistributive taxation as ak<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> mutual <strong>in</strong>surance arrangement: not know<strong>in</strong>g how rich or poor <strong>the</strong>y will be <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> future, <strong>in</strong>dividual voters may agree to a scheme that will redistribute <strong>in</strong>come awayfrom <strong>the</strong>m if <strong>the</strong>y turn out to be rich but <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir favor if <strong>the</strong>y turn out to be poor.One trouble with this argument is that voters do <strong>in</strong> fact have a pretty good idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ircurrent <strong>and</strong> future positions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> national <strong>in</strong>come distribution. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> argumenthardly applies to <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> level<strong>in</strong>g down for its own sake, level<strong>in</strong>g carriedto <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t where additional tax revenue for redistribution to <strong>the</strong> poor is relatively<strong>in</strong>significant.


470 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyto be desired by <strong>the</strong> rich <strong>the</strong>mselves. But if this coerced action would benoble <strong>and</strong> praiseworthy, would it not be still more so for each rich personto redistribute <strong>in</strong>dependently? A generous act is tarnished by be<strong>in</strong>g madecompulsory <strong>and</strong> by satisfaction <strong>in</strong> see<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r persons coerced along withoneself. ose who failed to respond to a campaign for voluntary redistribution—Iam sett<strong>in</strong>g aside, for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> argument, doubts about <strong>the</strong>desirability <strong>of</strong> even such a campaign—could be left unmolested as monumentsto <strong>the</strong> toleration <strong>of</strong> eccentricity so essential <strong>in</strong> a free society. Apartfrom <strong>the</strong> matter <strong>of</strong> voluntary action versus coercion, much can be said fordistribution from numerous <strong>in</strong>dividual sources <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> a great variety<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent purposes ra<strong>the</strong>r than through <strong>the</strong> monolithic agency<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> State.e doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> coercive redistribution has a subtle aff<strong>in</strong>ity with materialism.Why should it disturb us that some people are very wealthy? Ifwe are unwill<strong>in</strong>g to tolerate great superiorities <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>come <strong>and</strong> wealth, howdo we feel about superiorities <strong>in</strong> talent, physical <strong>and</strong> mental strength <strong>and</strong>health, <strong>in</strong>fluence through family connections <strong>and</strong> personal friendships,ability <strong>and</strong> time to appreciate conversation <strong>and</strong> art <strong>and</strong> music <strong>and</strong> sports,amount <strong>of</strong> formal education, experience ga<strong>in</strong>ed through travel, <strong>and</strong> s<strong>of</strong>orth? People’s circumstances can be different <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>numerable ways. Whydo redistributionists s<strong>in</strong>gle out material <strong>in</strong>equality unless <strong>the</strong>y th<strong>in</strong>k thatmoney is—<strong>and</strong> should be—<strong>the</strong> prime measure <strong>of</strong> a man’s capacity to enjoylife <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> his worth to himself <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people, his social status, <strong>and</strong>his personal dignity? e reason cannot be that material <strong>in</strong>equality is <strong>the</strong>only k<strong>in</strong>d susceptible <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g leveled down. We could partially level outadvantages <strong>of</strong> early tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g by requir<strong>in</strong>g all children to attend democraticallyst<strong>and</strong>ardized public schools. (Even some self-styled liberals are perverseenough to recommend compulsory military tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g for similar reasons.)We could level down physical attractiveness by requir<strong>in</strong>g everybodyto wear masks <strong>and</strong> shapeless uniforms, or we could put especially heavytaxes on beauty as well as on bra<strong>in</strong>s.Auréle Kolnai has perceptively said:<strong>the</strong> true Christian is <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to feel a certa<strong>in</strong> disda<strong>in</strong> for <strong>the</strong> wealthy<strong>in</strong>asmuch as he disda<strong>in</strong>s wealth, more or less factitious goods <strong>of</strong> which<strong>the</strong> rich man is a slave, while <strong>the</strong> believer <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> “social gospel” will callfor <strong>the</strong> elim<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wealthy for <strong>the</strong> ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> all because wealth seemsto him to be <strong>the</strong> sole good that counts. (1946, p. 7)In <strong>the</strong> old liberal democratic conception, a poor man seemed <strong>in</strong>vestedwith human dignity, had a claim to honour <strong>and</strong> was entitled to freedom


Chapter : Can a Liberal Be an Egalitarian? 471no less than a prosperous one; <strong>the</strong> refurbished ideology denies him <strong>the</strong>capacity for freedom unless or until he is also made wealthy. (1949, p. 82)In doubt<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> material equality will achieve any<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> more decent motives <strong>of</strong> its proponents, I can quote Frank Knighton my side:<strong>the</strong> significance <strong>of</strong> consumption itself is largely symbolic; <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>equalitywhich really “hurts” is <strong>the</strong> unequal distribution <strong>of</strong> dignity, prestige, <strong>and</strong>power. Nei<strong>the</strong>r abstract reason<strong>in</strong>g nor <strong>the</strong> evidence <strong>of</strong> experience affordsground for belief that, given <strong>the</strong> moral drive toward such values as <strong>the</strong>dom<strong>in</strong>ant motive <strong>in</strong> society, democratic political process could fail todistribute <strong>the</strong>m even more unequally still than does competitive bus<strong>in</strong>ess.(1936, pp. 308–309)Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, pursuit <strong>of</strong> an unatta<strong>in</strong>able material equality will fosterattitudes <strong>and</strong> political behavior <strong>in</strong>compatible with a quasi-equality <strong>of</strong> amore human <strong>and</strong> more nearly atta<strong>in</strong>able type. Ideally, people should nothave to be ranked above or below each o<strong>the</strong>r accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> fields <strong>in</strong>which <strong>the</strong>ir accomplishments lie. Each person should have a chance toexcel <strong>in</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g, with <strong>the</strong> different types <strong>of</strong> excellence regarded as <strong>in</strong>commensurable.Adventure, scholarship, conviviality, self-effac<strong>in</strong>g service tomank<strong>in</strong>d—all should be as respectable as <strong>the</strong> amass<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> fortunes. People<strong>of</strong> modest talents or ambitions who do rout<strong>in</strong>e work <strong>and</strong> content<strong>the</strong>mselves with <strong>in</strong>expensive pleasures should be regarded as contribut<strong>in</strong>gto a desirable diversity <strong>in</strong> personalities, modes <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> styles<strong>and</strong> goals <strong>of</strong> life. A teacher could cont<strong>in</strong>ue associat<strong>in</strong>g without embarrassmentwith congenial former colleagues or students who had becomebus<strong>in</strong>ess tycoons not because progressive taxation had lopped <strong>of</strong>f <strong>the</strong>irlarger monetary <strong>in</strong>comes but because scholarly values <strong>and</strong> monetary valueswere regarded as <strong>in</strong>commensurate but <strong>of</strong> equal dignity. As HerbertW. Schneider has noted, <strong>the</strong> equality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> egalitarians implies measurement;he emphasizes, <strong>in</strong>stead, what he calls “<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>commensurability <strong>of</strong>human be<strong>in</strong>gs” (1956, p. 97; cf. pp. 100, 118).“All men are created equal” <strong>and</strong> statements like that are obviously notmeant literally. ey use poetic language legitimate <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir contexts. eyare meant as normative prescriptions for social actions <strong>and</strong> attitudes. eyexpress disapproval <strong>of</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to classify <strong>in</strong>dividuals as more or less worthy,more or less entitled to pursue happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own ways, <strong>and</strong> more or My quot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se passages is not meant as an endorsement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> attitude <strong>of</strong> “<strong>the</strong>true Christian.”


472 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyless entitled to have <strong>the</strong>ir views or <strong>in</strong>terests considered <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>public policy.We should not exalt materialism, but nei<strong>the</strong>r should we despise it.Just as a healthy society needs statesmen, humanitarians, es<strong>the</strong>tes, <strong>and</strong>eggheads, so it also needs money-m<strong>in</strong>ded Philist<strong>in</strong>es. It takes all k<strong>in</strong>ds<strong>of</strong> (decent) people to make a world. Each person’s freedom to choose <strong>the</strong>niche <strong>in</strong> life that best accords with his own talents <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ations ga<strong>in</strong>sfrom <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people to fill o<strong>the</strong>r niches.Erosion <strong>of</strong> monetary <strong>in</strong>centives unleashes pressures toward conformity.One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual’s best protections aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> arbitrary whims<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess firm employ<strong>in</strong>g him is <strong>the</strong> fact that his employer <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>remployers are seek<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>in</strong> a competitive market. Policy that weakens<strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it motive or <strong>the</strong> competitiveness <strong>of</strong> markets is likely to reduce <strong>the</strong>cost to employers <strong>of</strong> tyranniz<strong>in</strong>g over employees. (is fact, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> academicworld, leads teachers to dem<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r forms <strong>of</strong> protection.) Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,to <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong> tax structure leads companies to compensate<strong>the</strong>ir executives <strong>in</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>in</strong> freely spendable money—stockoptions, club memberships, pleasure travel <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> guise <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess travel,use <strong>of</strong> company cars, planes, apartments, vacation lodges, <strong>and</strong> expenseaccounts—to this extent bus<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> private lives become <strong>in</strong>term<strong>in</strong>gled.We see <strong>the</strong> rise <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Organization Man. From <strong>the</strong> liberal po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view,this state <strong>of</strong> affairs seems questionable not only or not even especiallyfor <strong>the</strong> Organization Men <strong>the</strong>mselves but also for members <strong>of</strong> society <strong>in</strong>general.I <strong>of</strong>fer as a mere conjecture one more doubt about egalitarianism. Especiallyif it is dignified by serv<strong>in</strong>g as a basis for public policy, <strong>the</strong> philosophythat encourages people to brood about whe<strong>the</strong>r wealthier people “deserve”<strong>the</strong>ir material abundance, <strong>and</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>mselves are not “entitled”to a larger share, may well have someth<strong>in</strong>g to do with crime. Even relativelypoor people are likely to suffer <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> long run from <strong>the</strong> far-reach<strong>in</strong>gconsequences <strong>of</strong> a philosophy that underm<strong>in</strong>es respect for personal safety<strong>and</strong> property rights.e postponed topic <strong>of</strong> equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity serves as a transitionto <strong>the</strong> conclud<strong>in</strong>g sections <strong>of</strong> this paper. Ideally, everyone should havea decent start <strong>in</strong> life, free from <strong>the</strong> cumulative disadvantages <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>itialpoverty. But should <strong>the</strong> State go so far as to try to deprive fortunateyoung people <strong>of</strong> whatever advantages <strong>the</strong>y might enjoy from bodily ormental or f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>heritance or from family background <strong>and</strong> contacts?Much could be done, after all, towards <strong>of</strong>fsett<strong>in</strong>g even <strong>the</strong> nonf<strong>in</strong>ancial


Chapter : Can a Liberal Be an Egalitarian? 473aspects <strong>of</strong> exceptionally favorable opportunity. Any really close approachto equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity is, however, impossible. Liberals should shuna slogan—“equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity”—whose implementation is impossible,especially s<strong>in</strong>ce even an attempt to implement it approximatelywould entail totalitarianism. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, it is hard to see equality <strong>of</strong>opportunity as a desideratum dist<strong>in</strong>ct from equality <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come or status,s<strong>in</strong>ce unequal atta<strong>in</strong>ments <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>come or status must be due ei<strong>the</strong>rto unequal luck or to unequal endowments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> abilities <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ationsconducive to achiev<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>come or status. From an egalitarian st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t,<strong>in</strong>equality <strong>of</strong> results would show that unequal luck had not beenproperly compensated for or that opportunities had not been properlyequalized.From <strong>the</strong> liberal st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t, <strong>the</strong> whole discussion would be simplifiedby call<strong>in</strong>g for adequacy ra<strong>the</strong>r than equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity. Removal <strong>of</strong>actual poverty <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> caste <strong>and</strong> race restrictions that arbitrarily hamperpeople <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own goals is quite different from chopp<strong>in</strong>gdown advantages.Why, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, might anyone want to chop down advantages ra<strong>the</strong>rthan merely remove disadvantages? I wonder whe<strong>the</strong>r one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> objectives<strong>of</strong> egalitarians who consider <strong>the</strong>mselves liberals might not be to make <strong>the</strong>outcome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> market process a more nearly plausible <strong>in</strong>dicator <strong>of</strong> personalworth. eir liken<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> life to a “game” or “race” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir talk <strong>of</strong>impos<strong>in</strong>g “h<strong>and</strong>icaps” to make <strong>the</strong> game “<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g” certa<strong>in</strong>ly suggests so(recall Frank Knight, quoted above). Everyone is to have <strong>the</strong> same purpose<strong>in</strong> life, overrid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> diverse purposes that <strong>in</strong>dividuals might o<strong>the</strong>rwisehave; <strong>and</strong> this common purpose is to succeed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> game. Everyone is toengage <strong>in</strong> it, if necessary be drafted <strong>in</strong>to it. e score will be kept, especially<strong>in</strong> money <strong>and</strong> status. No one will have an excuse for not tak<strong>in</strong>g thisrivalry seriously, for proper h<strong>and</strong>icaps will have been imposed. By persuad<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>mselves that <strong>the</strong> “game” has been made “fair,” <strong>the</strong> self-styled liberalegalitarians will have more <strong>of</strong> a supposed basis than ever for <strong>in</strong>dulg<strong>in</strong>g apropensity to pass judgment on <strong>the</strong>ir fellows, smugly dispens<strong>in</strong>g praise<strong>and</strong> scorn.is view <strong>of</strong> society as an organized activity, with <strong>the</strong> government asa busybody game-master or social director impos<strong>in</strong>g h<strong>and</strong>icaps <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwisetry<strong>in</strong>g to drum up “<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g” rivalry, strikes me as pr<strong>of</strong>oundlyanti-liberal. It is putt<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs backwards to regard <strong>the</strong> game—or <strong>the</strong>market <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> textbooks—as a supreme value <strong>in</strong> its own right, with <strong>the</strong>diverse values <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals tak<strong>in</strong>g second place.


474 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyHere I have admittedly drifted <strong>in</strong>to consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> possible motives<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> egalitarians. Question<strong>in</strong>g motives is <strong>of</strong>ten bad form. It is rank anti<strong>in</strong>tellectualism,<strong>in</strong> particular, to dismiss purportedly factual or logical propositionsby a mere sneer at <strong>the</strong> alleged motives <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir propounders. Butwhen policy goals <strong>and</strong> conceptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good society are at issue, motivesare at <strong>the</strong> core <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussion. If we ask why someone advocates certa<strong>in</strong>policies, <strong>the</strong> reason is that we are try<strong>in</strong>g to underst<strong>and</strong> his conception<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good society. e tastes gratified by level<strong>in</strong>g policies—<strong>the</strong> tastefor mak<strong>in</strong>g a goal out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> social <strong>and</strong> economic game itself, <strong>the</strong> tastefor smugly pass<strong>in</strong>g judgment on o<strong>the</strong>r persons, <strong>the</strong> taste for sheer meddl<strong>in</strong>g—clashwith <strong>the</strong> spirit <strong>of</strong> liberalism.Am I deny<strong>in</strong>g that liberalism accords equal esteem to all tastes <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>dividuals, regardless <strong>of</strong> what <strong>the</strong>y are? Should liberalism discrim<strong>in</strong>atebetween worthy <strong>and</strong> unworthy tastes, ones that “ought” <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs that“ought not” to count <strong>in</strong> a liberal social order? Yes. As a conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>good society, liberalism cannot, with consistency, give its bless<strong>in</strong>g to allk<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> taste, <strong>in</strong>different to <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> society that emerges <strong>in</strong> response. Ifsocial philosophy has any role at all, it is to <strong>in</strong>vestigate <strong>and</strong> promote consensusabout what social <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> policies <strong>and</strong> attitudes are conduciveto human happ<strong>in</strong>ess. Its job is to pa<strong>in</strong>t a coherent picture <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> goodsociety. It cannot just <strong>of</strong>fer a ticket <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> a picture, a ticket read<strong>in</strong>gthat <strong>the</strong> good society looks like whatever a substantially unanimous op<strong>in</strong>ionth<strong>in</strong>ks it looks like. ere may be no substantially unanimous op<strong>in</strong>ion.Prevalent op<strong>in</strong>ion may be unenlightened. Social philosophy shirks itsjob when it <strong>of</strong>fers no positive guidance. Quite properly, de Tocqueville<strong>and</strong> John Stuart Mill <strong>in</strong>veighed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> liberalism not only aga<strong>in</strong>stgovernmental tyranny but also aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> conformist pressures <strong>of</strong> publicop<strong>in</strong>ion.Suppose one man were to buy <strong>the</strong> fawn<strong>in</strong>g submissiveness <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r,or even <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r’s submission to torture, to gratify <strong>the</strong> sadism <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first.Can liberalism bless such transactions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free market? Ofcourse not. Voluntary though <strong>the</strong>y may be, <strong>the</strong>y gratify <strong>and</strong> encourage attitudessubversive <strong>of</strong> an endur<strong>in</strong>g liberal social order. Practical reasons, tobe sure, tell aga<strong>in</strong>st mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m illegal. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, public policyshould not provide examples that sanctify tyrannical <strong>and</strong> meddlesomeprivate tastes. Policymakers should recognize that State actions today maywell <strong>in</strong>fluence what private attitudes prevail tomorrow.Does liberalism sanctify illiberal practices freely agreed upon? Doestolerance <strong>in</strong>clude toleration <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tolerance? Does democracy imply <strong>the</strong>


Chapter : Can a Liberal Be an Egalitarian? 475right <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> people to vote democracy out <strong>and</strong> dictatorship <strong>in</strong>? Such questionsare rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> logical paradoxes discussed by Bertr<strong>and</strong>Russell <strong>and</strong> untangled by his dist<strong>in</strong>ction between levels <strong>of</strong> discourse. Wehave to be clear whe<strong>the</strong>r we are talk<strong>in</strong>g “<strong>in</strong>” or “about” language, “with<strong>in</strong>”or “about” democracy, “with<strong>in</strong>” or “about” liberalism. An action or policythat embodies or sanctifies meddlesomeness cannot properly be called liberalmerely by postulat<strong>in</strong>g that it is freely agreed to, perhaps <strong>in</strong> some markettransaction or by some democratic procedure. Liberalism is def<strong>in</strong>ed,<strong>in</strong>stead, by <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> motivation <strong>and</strong> probable consequences <strong>of</strong> policies<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions. For <strong>the</strong> word to have any content, we must recognize<strong>the</strong> possibility that people may freely choose <strong>the</strong> negation <strong>of</strong> liberalism. Todef<strong>in</strong>e liberal policies <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> negotiat<strong>in</strong>g procedures or <strong>of</strong> degree <strong>of</strong>agreement is to empty <strong>the</strong> word <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g. e choices that emerge frompolitical or market processes may quite conceivably not be coherent; <strong>the</strong>ymay not fit <strong>in</strong> with a coherent picture <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good society. One reasonamong many is that <strong>the</strong> choices may not be sufficiently enlightened. Adecision-mak<strong>in</strong>g process is no substitute for a social philosophy. If totalitarianismwere adopted by unanimous consent, would this decision be aliberal one? Of course not, for liberalism values arrangements that enable<strong>in</strong>dividuals to pursue <strong>the</strong>ir own diverse ends with a m<strong>in</strong>imum <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terferencewith each o<strong>the</strong>r.In conclusion, I recognize that some would-be levelers <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come,wealth, <strong>and</strong> opportunity are honorable men. ey do not believe thatnumerical might makes right; <strong>the</strong>y do not want to aggr<strong>and</strong>ize <strong>the</strong> power<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> State; <strong>the</strong>y do not p<strong>and</strong>er to envy; <strong>the</strong>y do not make money <strong>the</strong> measure<strong>of</strong> all th<strong>in</strong>gs; <strong>the</strong>y do not savor <strong>the</strong> prospect <strong>of</strong> feel<strong>in</strong>g superior to <strong>the</strong>losers <strong>in</strong> a suitably h<strong>and</strong>icapped contest. But <strong>in</strong> apprais<strong>in</strong>g a l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> policy,it is not enough to satisfy oneself about <strong>the</strong> motives <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> more honorableamong its proponents; one must also consider what type <strong>of</strong> society ittends to promote. One must consider that a policy may exert some <strong>of</strong> itseffects over a long period <strong>of</strong> time through its <strong>in</strong>fluence on what attitudesprevail. If I am a good judge <strong>of</strong> my own motives, I oppose fiscal level<strong>in</strong>gbecause I want <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> society that respects but puts no special emphasison material values, one that allows niches for people with diverse drives<strong>and</strong> goals <strong>in</strong> life, one characterized by tolerant attitudes, <strong>and</strong> one whose is is one among many reasons for reject<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> currently fashionable concept <strong>of</strong>“Pareto optimality” as a touchstone for economic policy. ere is no substitute for consider<strong>in</strong>ghow <strong>the</strong> probable consequences <strong>of</strong> each contemplated policy will mesh or will clashwith one’s conception <strong>of</strong> a good society.


476 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>in</strong>stitutions facilitate voluntary cooperation while m<strong>in</strong>imiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> scopefor clashes among <strong>the</strong> freedoms <strong>of</strong> its members.Hayek, F.A. e Constitution <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press,1960.Knight, Frank H. e Ethics <strong>of</strong> Competition. 2ⁿ ed. New York: Harper, 1936.Kolnai, Auréle. “Le culte de l’homme commun et la gloire des humbles.” Lavaléologique et Philosophique 2, no. 1 (1946).. “Privilege <strong>and</strong> Liberty.” Laval éologique et Philosophique 5, no. 1 (1949).Schneider, Herbert W. ree Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Public Morality. Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton: IndianaUniversity Press, 1956.Simons, Henry. Economic Policy for a Free Society. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1948.. Federal Tax Reform. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1950.


Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong>Policy Espousal * is paper defends one version <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism aga<strong>in</strong>st supposed alternativesto it as a policy criterion. First it reviews <strong>the</strong> natural rights doctr<strong>in</strong>e,contractarianism, <strong>and</strong> criticisms <strong>of</strong> each. Several sections state <strong>and</strong> defenda broad version <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism. Examples follow <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>gs about rights<strong>and</strong> contract that tacitly accept utilitarianism. A summary concludes <strong>the</strong>paper. Clear-cut examples <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> antiutilitarian rights doctr<strong>in</strong>e are rare. One reason,apparently, is that doctr<strong>in</strong>es ostensibly <strong>of</strong> that k<strong>in</strong>d are <strong>in</strong> fact tacitlyutilitarian—a po<strong>in</strong>t developed later. Murray Rothbard (1973, pp. 23–25)observes that most libertarians have adopted natural rights <strong>and</strong> rejectedboth emotivism <strong>and</strong> utilitarianism as <strong>the</strong> foundation for <strong>the</strong>ir nonaggressionpr<strong>in</strong>ciple. eir basic axiom is <strong>the</strong> “right to self-ownership,” absoluteproperty <strong>in</strong> one’s own body. Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, everyone has <strong>the</strong> right toperform actions necessary for surviv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> flourish<strong>in</strong>g without coercivemolestation. Rothbard <strong>the</strong>n develops a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> property <strong>in</strong> nonhumanobjects by appeal<strong>in</strong>g to John Locke’s concept <strong>of</strong> a person’s rightful ownership<strong>of</strong> previously unused natural resources that he first transforms byhis labor (1973, pp. 26ff.). “ese two axioms, <strong>the</strong> right <strong>of</strong> self-ownership<strong>and</strong> right to ‘homestead,’ establish <strong>the</strong> complete set <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>libertarian system” (p. 40).*From Cato Journal 5 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g/Summer 1985): 259–294. Some sections overlap o<strong>the</strong>rchapters <strong>of</strong> this book <strong>and</strong> have been deleted or shortened here.477


478 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyRights <strong>the</strong>orists reject <strong>the</strong> approach that would take a st<strong>and</strong> on eachspecific policy issue, such as deregulation <strong>of</strong> a particular <strong>in</strong>dustry or imposition<strong>of</strong> wage <strong>and</strong> price controls or government credit allocation, accord<strong>in</strong>gto <strong>the</strong> apparent merits <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual case; <strong>the</strong>y reject narrowly focusedcost-benefit calculations. Instead <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g framed by case-by-case expediency,policy should conform to persons’ rights.And those rights should not be defended on a utilitarian basis, fordo<strong>in</strong>g so supposedly opens <strong>the</strong> door to all sorts <strong>of</strong> pragmatic dem<strong>and</strong>sfor government <strong>in</strong>tervention. e utilitarian, Rothbard compla<strong>in</strong>s (1973,p. 24), will rarely adopt a pr<strong>in</strong>ciple as an absolute <strong>and</strong> consistent yardstick.Instead, he regards it as a vague guidel<strong>in</strong>e or aspiration or tendency thatmay well be overridden. Milton Friedman, for example, although devotedto <strong>the</strong> free market as a general tendency, <strong>in</strong> practice allows many damag<strong>in</strong>gexceptions to freedom aga<strong>in</strong>st state <strong>in</strong>tervention (Rothbard 1973,p. 24). Utilitarianism—or ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>in</strong> my view, its exaggerated pragmatistversion—contrasts sharply with a pure doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> rights. Rights <strong>the</strong>oristsderive positions even on quite specific policy issues from a very few propositionstaken as axiomatic.Unfortunately, <strong>the</strong> door is open to <strong>in</strong>terventionist dem<strong>and</strong>s anyway.Libertarians cannot keep it closed by issu<strong>in</strong>g methodological pronouncementsor by report<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>tuitions about endangered rights. A purerights position, unta<strong>in</strong>ted by utilitarian aspects, might serve for ward<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong>f illegitimate or undesirable <strong>in</strong>terventions if it enjoyed general acceptance.Although it might be convenient if a particular doctr<strong>in</strong>e were true<strong>and</strong> generally accepted, that convenience alone is no evidence, unfortunately,that <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e is <strong>in</strong> fact true. To make <strong>the</strong> best <strong>of</strong> reality, which<strong>of</strong>ten is <strong>in</strong>convenient, we must face it as it is.In reality, no doctr<strong>in</strong>e will automatically protect us from bad <strong>in</strong>terventions.Abuse <strong>of</strong> utilitarian arguments cannot be prevented by reject<strong>in</strong>gutilitarianism tout court. Instead, one must enter <strong>in</strong>to discussion withone’s pragmatist opponents, demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g how act<strong>in</strong>g on an excessivelynarrow utilitarianism violates rights as <strong>in</strong>telligibly conceived <strong>and</strong> conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>glydefended <strong>and</strong> so impedes <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess. What I am reject<strong>in</strong>g is a pure rights doctr<strong>in</strong>e scornful <strong>of</strong> any utilitarianunderp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g. I accept a pro-rights doctr<strong>in</strong>e, provided that propositionsabout rights are recognized not as positive propositions <strong>of</strong> fact <strong>and</strong> logic


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 479but ra<strong>the</strong>r as normative propositions. A def<strong>in</strong>ite list <strong>of</strong> rights is unnecessaryhere. Suffice to say that rights are persons’ entitlements to freedom fromcoercive <strong>in</strong>terference by <strong>the</strong>ir fellows <strong>and</strong> by government; <strong>the</strong>y concernlife, liberty, property, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess. (When embodied <strong>in</strong>constitutions or statutes, <strong>of</strong> course, normative propositions like that takeon an additional, legal, status.)To identify assertions <strong>of</strong> rights as value judgments is emphatically notto disparage <strong>the</strong>m as mere expressions <strong>of</strong> emotion or whim. It is <strong>in</strong>stead<strong>the</strong> claim <strong>of</strong> imprescriptible ontological status for <strong>the</strong>m that disparages<strong>the</strong>m by expos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m to easy ridicule, as <strong>in</strong> Jeremy Bentham’s remark(1843/1973, p. 269) about “nonsense upon stilts.” Although <strong>the</strong>y are normative,assertions <strong>of</strong> rights can be supported by appeal to facts <strong>of</strong> humannature <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r aspects <strong>of</strong> reality <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> psychology, economics,<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r discipl<strong>in</strong>es.As <strong>the</strong> philosopher Paul Edwards (1965) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> economists SidneyAlex<strong>and</strong>er (1967, esp. pp. 105–107, 114–115) <strong>and</strong> A.K. Sen (1970,esp. pp. 62–64) have argued explicitly <strong>and</strong> as many o<strong>the</strong>r writers haverecognized, fact <strong>and</strong> logic can be brought to bear <strong>in</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to clearup disagreement over all but fundamental value judgments. (Support<strong>in</strong>gconsiderations appear <strong>in</strong> Adler 1970.) It can be a constructive enterpriseto try to clear up disagreement over specific or nonfundamentalvalues. (Examples are <strong>the</strong> judgments that Jones should be sent to jail,that ly<strong>in</strong>g, cheat<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> steal<strong>in</strong>g are wrong, that private property is adesirable <strong>in</strong>stitution, <strong>and</strong> that specified rights should be recognized <strong>and</strong>respected.) It is anti-<strong>in</strong>tellectual simply to chalk disagreement up to irresolvableemotional differences. We can give <strong>and</strong> discuss reasons for valuejudgments.Reasons for <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong>st specific value judgments might <strong>in</strong>clude positiveanalysis show<strong>in</strong>g why accept<strong>in</strong>g some tends to promote <strong>and</strong> accept<strong>in</strong>go<strong>the</strong>rs to subvert a society <strong>of</strong> a k<strong>in</strong>d conducive to its members’ successfulpursuits <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess. An important objective element, utilitarian<strong>in</strong> a broad sense, thus enters <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> v<strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> human rights.Only when we f<strong>in</strong>ally have noth<strong>in</strong>g left to appeal to beyond some suchfundamental value judgment as one favor<strong>in</strong>g happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> abhorr<strong>in</strong>gmisery have we exhausted <strong>the</strong> relevance <strong>of</strong> facts <strong>and</strong> logic, <strong>in</strong>vestigation<strong>and</strong> discussion. But bona fide disagreements <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> real world seldomif ever center on fundamental values, openly avowed. For practicalpurposes <strong>of</strong> policymak<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> fact-value dist<strong>in</strong>ction fadesaway.


480 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy e most immaculately antiutilitarian version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rights doctr<strong>in</strong>e boilsdown all too soon to simply promulgat<strong>in</strong>g rights <strong>and</strong> even to ana<strong>the</strong>matiz<strong>in</strong>gdisagreement as a sign <strong>of</strong> moral deficiency. Some antiutilitarian proponents<strong>of</strong> rights (Rothbard 1973, Rothbard 1982, Gewirth 1978, Mack1978, Paul 1978) do <strong>of</strong>fer arguments, after all, but arguments <strong>of</strong> peculiarlyabstract k<strong>in</strong>ds—appeal<strong>in</strong>g (as already noted) to self-ownership <strong>and</strong> Lockeanhomestead<strong>in</strong>g or, alternatively, to what one must say about rights toavoid logical error.Consider, for example, what Alan Gewirth does with his Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong>Generic Consistency, which, “unlike utilitarian <strong>and</strong> material deontological<strong>the</strong>ories, ... conta<strong>in</strong>s with<strong>in</strong> itself <strong>the</strong> ground <strong>of</strong> its necessity; it is selfjustify<strong>in</strong>g”(1978, quotation from p. 203). Certa<strong>in</strong> rights must be respectedif each person, a purposive be<strong>in</strong>g, is to strive effectively for his purposes.He cannot consistently claim <strong>the</strong>se rights for himself while deny<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mto persons affected by his actions when <strong>the</strong> very reasons he gives for claim<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> rights for himself also apply to those o<strong>the</strong>r persons. He would beutter<strong>in</strong>g logically contradictory propositions. In effect he would be say<strong>in</strong>g:All persons for whom such-<strong>and</strong>-such reasons hold, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g me, havesuch-<strong>and</strong> such rights; yet he would deny, when expedient for himself, thato<strong>the</strong>r persons have those rights even though <strong>the</strong> stated reasons do hold for<strong>the</strong>m also.I question <strong>the</strong> supposed logical contradiction. An egoist might considerit expedient to claim certa<strong>in</strong> rights for himself <strong>and</strong> deny <strong>the</strong>m to o<strong>the</strong>rswhen he can get away with it. He is not necessarily accept<strong>in</strong>g certa<strong>in</strong> statementsabout rights as objectively true; he is not committ<strong>in</strong>g logical error.Instead, he considers it expedient to encourage o<strong>the</strong>r persons to hold certa<strong>in</strong>beliefs about rights, beliefs <strong>in</strong> which those o<strong>the</strong>rs might perceive contradictionsif <strong>the</strong>y were astute enough. If he can <strong>the</strong>reby fur<strong>the</strong>r his ownpurposes, why should he care about <strong>the</strong> contradictions <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r persons’beliefs? (In tak<strong>in</strong>g up what he calls “<strong>the</strong> Machiavellian case,” pp. 196–198,Gewirth does try, but <strong>in</strong>effectually, to rebut a counterargument similar tobut not <strong>the</strong> same as m<strong>in</strong>e.) We might consider <strong>the</strong> person a scoundrel, butthat is not <strong>the</strong> same as his be<strong>in</strong>g a poor logician.Eric Mack (1978) tries to derive <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> rights from <strong>the</strong> propositionthat coercion is deontically wrong—wrong because <strong>of</strong> its very character<strong>and</strong> not just because <strong>of</strong> its consequences. Because each person is anend <strong>in</strong> himself, it is deontically wrong for o<strong>the</strong>rs to cause his actions to


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 481be out <strong>of</strong> accord with his own purposes, which is what coercion does. edeontic wrongness <strong>of</strong> coercion condemns any destruction <strong>of</strong> freedom byit. Contractual rights <strong>and</strong> property rights can also be v<strong>in</strong>dicated by recognition<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir violation as essentially coercive. Mack recognizes that utilitarianreasons for respect<strong>in</strong>g rights could be grafted onto his argumentbut ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that his argument does not depend on <strong>the</strong>m., e examples already given illustrate how antiutilitarian ethicists stop short,before a utilitarian would, with mere propound<strong>in</strong>g or with appeal to irreducible<strong>in</strong>tuition (even if <strong>the</strong>y do not use <strong>the</strong> term). But what is <strong>in</strong>tuitionbased on? Perhaps on an unarticulated recognition <strong>of</strong> consequences—tacitutilitarianism. Conceivably humans have an <strong>in</strong>nate propensity, elaboratedby natural selection, to develop such <strong>in</strong>tuitions. If so, <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong>hav<strong>in</strong>g or not hav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m must have figured <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> biological process.Why not, <strong>the</strong>n, strive to clarify those <strong>in</strong>tuitions by discipl<strong>in</strong>ed observation<strong>and</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g? It seems <strong>in</strong>adequate to rest everyth<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> assertion,for example, that <strong>in</strong>dividuals, as ends <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves, simply should not becoerced. Such a l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> argument does not take adequate account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>social context <strong>in</strong> which questions about rights arise. e utilitarian, however,does press on with an empirically oriented <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>in</strong>to whatsorts <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> practices do <strong>and</strong> what sorts do not accord wellwith human nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> human condition.Supposed axioms about rights cannot serve as <strong>the</strong> ultimate foundation<strong>of</strong> one’s conception <strong>of</strong> desirable social arrangements. Instead, propositionsabout rights must be argued for, along with o<strong>the</strong>r propositionsabout what makes for a good society. John Gray (1983, esp. pp. 59–60, 66,68) ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that John Stuart Mill <strong>in</strong> effect sought—successfully, Grayimplies—to provide a utilitarian underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g for respect for rights.Ano<strong>the</strong>r ethicist-economist who does so is Henry Hazlitt (1964,pp. 286–287). With<strong>in</strong> necessary qualifications, he says,legal rights are or ought to be <strong>in</strong>violable. And so, <strong>of</strong> course, should moralrights be.is <strong>in</strong>violability does not rest on some mystical yet self-evident “law <strong>of</strong>nature.” It rests ultimately (though it will shock many to hear this) on utilitarianconsiderations. But it rests, not on ad hoc utilitism [sic], on expediency<strong>in</strong> any narrow sense, but on rule utilitism, on <strong>the</strong> recognition that


482 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>the</strong> highest <strong>and</strong> only permanent utility comes from an unyield<strong>in</strong>g adherenceto pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Only by <strong>the</strong> most scrupulous respect for each o<strong>the</strong>r’simprescriptible rights can we maximize social peace, order, <strong>and</strong> cooperation.Elsewhere Hazlitt (1978, pp. 22–23) describes natural rights as “simply<strong>the</strong> rights that people ought to have.” He notes <strong>the</strong> idea that rights ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>sanctity <strong>and</strong> respect by be<strong>in</strong>g called “natural,” as if <strong>the</strong>y were “someth<strong>in</strong>gbuilt <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> universe, prior to creation, prior to existence.” Actually, “naturalrights” is “a mystical phrase. It’s simply an unnecessary concept.”Before not<strong>in</strong>g expositions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rights doctr<strong>in</strong>e that are tacitly utilitarian,we must consider <strong>the</strong> latter doctr<strong>in</strong>e. First, though, a review <strong>of</strong>ano<strong>the</strong>r rival doctr<strong>in</strong>e is <strong>in</strong> order.A “contractarian” approach or attitude toward public policy has won respectfulattention. Its most forceful <strong>and</strong> prolific advocate has been JamesM. Buchanan. (See <strong>the</strong> bibliography <strong>and</strong>, for some criticism, Gordon 1976<strong>and</strong> Samuels 1976.) Buchanan <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r contractarians <strong>of</strong>ten also cite JohnRawls (1971) with approval.Contractarians exalt <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual over “society,” agreement over coercion,<strong>and</strong> application <strong>of</strong> consent as <strong>the</strong> overrid<strong>in</strong>g criterion <strong>of</strong> desirabilitynot merely to small-scale <strong>in</strong>terpersonal relations but also <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> large—to<strong>the</strong> broad framework <strong>of</strong> social, political, <strong>and</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions. Asocial contract—if not an actual one, at least a “conceptual” one—figuresprom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir vision.Quotations from James Buchanan will help convey <strong>the</strong> contractarians’case <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir objections to <strong>the</strong> allegedly opposed “truth-judgment”approach.To <strong>the</strong> contractarian that law is legitimate, <strong>and</strong> just, which might haveemerged from a genu<strong>in</strong>e social contract <strong>in</strong> which he might have participated.at law is illegitimate, <strong>and</strong> unjust, which f<strong>in</strong>ds no such contractualbasis. (1977, p. 127)My po<strong>in</strong>t is ma<strong>in</strong>ly that <strong>of</strong> emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> process, as opposedto end-state results.... For Rawls, as for contractarians generally, thatwhich emerges from contractual agreement is just. (1977, p. 1)at is “good” which “tends to emerge” from <strong>the</strong> free choices <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualswho are <strong>in</strong>volved. It is impossible for an external observer to lay


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 483down criteria for “goodness” <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> process through whichresults or outcomes are atta<strong>in</strong>ed. e evaluation is applied to <strong>the</strong> means<strong>of</strong> atta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g outcomes, not to outcomes as such. (1975a, p. 6)Many more passages <strong>of</strong> similar import can be found <strong>in</strong> Buchanan’swrit<strong>in</strong>gs. He would have us approve or disapprove <strong>of</strong> states <strong>of</strong> affairs orsets <strong>of</strong> rules not primarily by consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir substance but overrid<strong>in</strong>glyby apprais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> process employed to reach decisions about <strong>the</strong>m. at idea seems odd to me. It resembles <strong>the</strong> idea that whatever peoplefreely choose is <strong>in</strong> fact good for <strong>the</strong>m. Broome (1978) exposes this fallacy.One <strong>of</strong> his examples concerns “Jane,” who, perhaps out <strong>of</strong> a sense <strong>of</strong> dutysomehow absorbed from her surround<strong>in</strong>gs, chooses to sacrifice an <strong>in</strong>dependentlife <strong>of</strong> her own to care for her aged mo<strong>the</strong>r. It does not necessarilyfollow that Jane’s free choice best serves her own <strong>in</strong>terest or fulfillmentor happ<strong>in</strong>ess or even that it maximizes her <strong>and</strong> her mo<strong>the</strong>r’s utilities comb<strong>in</strong>ed.Broome is simply warn<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st an <strong>in</strong>valid <strong>in</strong>ference, <strong>of</strong> course,<strong>and</strong> not say<strong>in</strong>g that some authority should impose on Jane <strong>the</strong> lifestyle itth<strong>in</strong>ks best for her.Price <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> welfare economics may legitimately, as blackboardexercises or for o<strong>the</strong>r purposes, assume that people make choices so asto maximize <strong>the</strong>ir utilities on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite utility functions. It doesnot <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> least follow, however, that freedom <strong>of</strong> choice is <strong>the</strong> very criterion<strong>of</strong> what to choose. A libertarian might deplore forcible <strong>in</strong>terference with<strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> addictive drugs. Yet this attitude does not commit him to <strong>the</strong>view that drugs serve <strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>of</strong> those who choose to take <strong>the</strong>m. Hewould not be <strong>in</strong>consistent <strong>in</strong> want<strong>in</strong>g to legalize <strong>the</strong>m while consider<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>ir use harmful <strong>and</strong> deplorable.Similarly, voluntary agreement is not itself <strong>the</strong> criterion <strong>of</strong> what toagree on. To value voluntary agreement <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> democratic process <strong>in</strong> noway commits an economist or social philosopher to value whatever <strong>in</strong>stitutionsor policies such processes may gr<strong>in</strong>d out. Why should he feel obligedto withhold any criticism? Decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g procedure is itself properly anobject <strong>of</strong> approval or disapproval, but it cannot sensibly be taken as <strong>the</strong>sole criterion <strong>of</strong> what to decide.Ra<strong>the</strong>r than suppose that proper procedure exhausts <strong>the</strong> content <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>good society, it would seem reasonable to emphasize proper procedure asan important part <strong>of</strong> that conception. But it is hard to see how a procedure


484 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophycan be deemed good utterly apart from some consideration <strong>of</strong> its likelyresults.As Scott Gordon observed <strong>in</strong> review<strong>in</strong>g e Limits <strong>of</strong> Liberty, Buchananwas try<strong>in</strong>g to derive “moral pr<strong>in</strong>ciples without <strong>the</strong> aid <strong>of</strong> any moralpremise” by carry<strong>in</strong>g over positive analysis <strong>of</strong> collective decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>to fundamental political philosophy. Buchanan might reply that he doeshave a moral premise, a weak one favor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividualism. Anyway, <strong>in</strong>Gordon’s view (1976, p. 583), Buchanan’s attempt to get normative conclusionsfrom analysis that is entirely (or almost entirely) positive “cannotsucceed.... [T]ry as one will, that troublesome word ‘ought’ cannot beexcised from political philosophy <strong>and</strong> no degree <strong>of</strong> sophisticated ‘is’ cantake its place.”Striv<strong>in</strong>g for clarity may justify some harshness. Except <strong>in</strong> brief <strong>and</strong>untypical passages, Buchanan obscures his employment <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> shirks hisresponsibility for values that he, like anyone, must be employ<strong>in</strong>g whenhe recommends anyth<strong>in</strong>g, even when what he recommends is processra<strong>the</strong>r than substance as <strong>the</strong> criterion for apprais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong>policies.Viktor Vanberg (n.d.) also raises apt questions about a supposedlypurely procedural criterion. Can we appraise a process or a set <strong>of</strong> rulessolely by <strong>the</strong> procedure <strong>of</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> chang<strong>in</strong>g it, <strong>and</strong> so on? Howdo we avoid <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite regress? <strong>Is</strong>n’t some substantive criterion needed somewhere?Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, doesn’t an “agreement test” unavoidably muddletoge<strong>the</strong>r observations <strong>of</strong> people’s preferences <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>ories abouthow alternative <strong>in</strong>stitutions would work? (Vanberg attributes <strong>the</strong> latterpo<strong>in</strong>t to Karen Vaughn. As Vaughn has also said somewhere, or so Iam told, choos<strong>in</strong>g constitutional pr<strong>in</strong>ciples is not as easy as choos<strong>in</strong>g atoaster.) One implication, I should th<strong>in</strong>k, is that economists <strong>and</strong> socialphilosophers have a legitimate role expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> preach<strong>in</strong>g what socialarrangements <strong>the</strong>y consider best, <strong>and</strong> why.“Contractarianism gets its name,” says one commentator (Pettit 1980,pp. 147–148), “from <strong>the</strong> device which it uses to filter out people’s enlightenedpreferences.” It identifies just social arrangements as those thatanswer to people’s preferences—not <strong>the</strong> sort recorded by ord<strong>in</strong>ary vot<strong>in</strong>g,however, but ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> preferences that people would have if <strong>the</strong>y werenot <strong>in</strong>fluenced by narrow self-<strong>in</strong>terest <strong>and</strong> bias.But on what grounds would people—people <strong>in</strong> real life <strong>and</strong> evenor especially people stripped <strong>of</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctive self-<strong>in</strong>terests, as by be<strong>in</strong>gplaced beh<strong>in</strong>d a Rawlsian “veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance”—prefer one set <strong>of</strong> social


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 485arrangements over o<strong>the</strong>rs? On what basis can a social philosopher hope todist<strong>in</strong>guish between laws or constitutions that could <strong>and</strong> those that couldnot have been agreed upon under ei<strong>the</strong>r actual or idealized conditions?e only plausible basis, I submit, is that people stripped <strong>of</strong> narrow self<strong>in</strong>terestwould consider <strong>the</strong> preferred arrangements as com<strong>in</strong>g closer to animpartial conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good society, that is, as be<strong>in</strong>g more conduciveto happ<strong>in</strong>ess, than <strong>the</strong> alternatives. A contractarian might say: No; impartialpeople would prefer those arrangements because <strong>the</strong>y were fair. Butwhy is fairness so desirable? Ei<strong>the</strong>r because it just is, because a compell<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>tuition <strong>in</strong>sists on it, because <strong>the</strong> question is not fur<strong>the</strong>r discussable; orelse because people’s treat<strong>in</strong>g each o<strong>the</strong>r fairly is conducive to <strong>the</strong>ir effectivepursuit <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess.I assert not that contractarianism is flatly wrong but that it disguises itsaff<strong>in</strong>ities with utilitarianism by repulsive <strong>and</strong> unnecessary fictions (aboutwhich I shall have more to say). “ ”Yet Buchanan sharply contrasts his contractarian vision with <strong>the</strong> “truthjudgment”approach, as he disparag<strong>in</strong>gly labels a position ak<strong>in</strong> to <strong>the</strong> utilitarianismdefended here. is scorned approach tends to “assume that<strong>the</strong>re is a unique explanation, a unique set <strong>of</strong> rules which def<strong>in</strong>es <strong>the</strong> elements<strong>of</strong> a good society <strong>and</strong> which, once discovered, will come to be generallyaccepted by <strong>in</strong>formed <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectually honest men” (1977, p. 75; <strong>the</strong>words quoted occur <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences, but <strong>the</strong> context leaves littledoubt that Buchanan is characteriz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> approach he condemns).Buchanan dist<strong>in</strong>guishes fur<strong>the</strong>r between his own approach <strong>and</strong> its rival.His contractarian conception is analogous to market activity, a search foragreement to <strong>the</strong> mutual benefit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> participants. e truth-judgmentapproach is analogous to <strong>the</strong> deliberations <strong>of</strong> a jury (1984, pp. 29–30). Earlier(1975a, p. 164) he had dist<strong>in</strong>guished, similarly, between <strong>the</strong> politician<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> judge. e politician seeks consensus <strong>and</strong> acceptable compromises.He is not engaged <strong>in</strong> a search for some one “true” judgment, <strong>and</strong> he is notproperly behav<strong>in</strong>g if he seeks to fur<strong>the</strong>r some well-def<strong>in</strong>ed ideal drawnfrom <strong>the</strong> bra<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> his academic mentors. e judge is <strong>in</strong> a dist<strong>in</strong>ctlydifferent position. He does seek “truth,” not compromise.As applied to politics, Buchanan deplores <strong>the</strong> judge or jury conception.It conduces to <strong>in</strong>tolerance by those who th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong>y have atta<strong>in</strong>ed political


486 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophytruth. Implicitly <strong>the</strong>y claim <strong>the</strong> right to impose truth on persons mired <strong>in</strong>error (1977, pp. 76–77). eir view entailsa demonstrated will<strong>in</strong>gness to impose nonvoluntary changes on <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>gpattern <strong>of</strong> entitlements <strong>in</strong> social order.... Once truth is found, <strong>the</strong>reis no moral argument to be raised aga<strong>in</strong>st its implementation. Consent ismean<strong>in</strong>gless <strong>in</strong> this context. Opposition can be variously characterized asstemm<strong>in</strong>g from ignorance, folly, or <strong>the</strong> exercise <strong>of</strong> selfish <strong>in</strong>terest. In anycase, <strong>the</strong> views <strong>of</strong> those who actively oppose <strong>the</strong> truth-carry<strong>in</strong>g zealotsare not treated as worthy <strong>of</strong> respect. And any requirement to compromisewith such views arises only because <strong>the</strong> reformists might o<strong>the</strong>rwiselack <strong>the</strong> power to impose “truth” unilaterally. (1977, pp. 143–144)Buchanan (1975a, p. 167) sees many social philosophers exhibit<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>tellectual <strong>and</strong> moral arrogance. An attempt to describe <strong>the</strong> social good<strong>in</strong> detail seems to carry with it an implied will<strong>in</strong>gness to impose thisgood, <strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>of</strong> observed or prospective agreement among persons.By contrast, [his] natural proclivity as an economist is to placeultimate value on process or procedure, <strong>and</strong> by implication to def<strong>in</strong>e as“good” that which emerges from agreement among free men, <strong>in</strong>dependently<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic evaluation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> outcome itself.Passages abound <strong>in</strong> which Buchanan dwells on this <strong>the</strong>me <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> arrogance,<strong>the</strong> itch to play God, <strong>of</strong> those who presume to employ <strong>the</strong>ir ownvalue judgments <strong>in</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to frame a coherent conception <strong>of</strong> a good society.For contractarians, process <strong>and</strong> consent, not outcome or substance,form <strong>the</strong> criterion <strong>of</strong> goodness or desirability <strong>in</strong> human <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong>relations. “‘<strong>Truth</strong>,’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al analysis, is tested by agreement. And if mendisagree, <strong>the</strong>re is no ‘truth’” (1977, p. 113). “A scientist may advance anargument to <strong>the</strong> effect that a proposition is ‘true.’ His argument ... maysucceed <strong>in</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g a consensus among his fellow scientists. But <strong>the</strong>‘truth’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition emerges only from this agreement <strong>and</strong> not fromsome orig<strong>in</strong>al objective reality” (1977, p. 145 n.)., , is extreme relativism is remarkable, yet Buchanan f<strong>in</strong>ds adopt<strong>in</strong>g it necessaryto avoid authoritarianism with regard to truth. Actually, <strong>the</strong>se arenot <strong>the</strong> only alternatives.Harry Davis (1967–1968) has described a third position dist<strong>in</strong>ct from<strong>the</strong> two between which Buchanan evidently th<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>the</strong> choice must lie.


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 487e first <strong>of</strong> those is <strong>the</strong> authoritarian position <strong>of</strong> one who believes he possessesan <strong>in</strong>fallible pipel<strong>in</strong>e to objective truth. at is <strong>the</strong> position <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>baseball umpire who <strong>in</strong>sists that he calls balls <strong>and</strong> strikes as <strong>the</strong>y objectivelyare. e second is a relativist-nom<strong>in</strong>alist position <strong>of</strong> reject<strong>in</strong>g all absolutes<strong>and</strong> embrac<strong>in</strong>g a radical relativism or skepticism. An umpire hold<strong>in</strong>g thisview says that pitches are nei<strong>the</strong>r balls nor strikes until he calls <strong>the</strong>m. ethird position, “fallibilism,” comb<strong>in</strong>es metaphysical or ethical objectivismwith epistemological relativism. e fallibilist umpire says, “I call ’em as <strong>Is</strong>ee ’em.” On this view, it makes sense to seek objective truths about reality,even <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g truths about what is morally valuable <strong>and</strong> politicallydesirable. Yet no person or group is entitled to claim <strong>in</strong>fallible possession<strong>of</strong> such knowledge. Each searcher contributes what he can, aware that hiscontribution is <strong>in</strong>complete <strong>and</strong> perhaps erroneous. In science, culture, <strong>and</strong>philosophy, fallibilism calls for free discussion open to <strong>the</strong> competition <strong>of</strong>all ideas, evidences, <strong>and</strong> arguments. (Davis recognizes fallibilism as a centralconcept <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> Charles S<strong>and</strong>ers Peirce. See also Wiener1968 <strong>and</strong> Peirce 1955.)Far from be<strong>in</strong>g subversive <strong>of</strong> constructive discussion, a will<strong>in</strong>gness tostate clearly what one believes <strong>and</strong> why, expos<strong>in</strong>g one’s views to <strong>in</strong>spection<strong>and</strong> possible refutation, is essential to it.e fallibilist position adopts <strong>the</strong> scientific attitude <strong>and</strong> method. Belief<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gfulness or at least <strong>the</strong> heuristic value <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong>objective truth to be sought through research <strong>and</strong> discussion need notentail arrogance, elitism, <strong>and</strong> an eagerness forcibly to impose one’s beliefs.Belief, for example, that one type <strong>of</strong> society is more conducive to humanhapp<strong>in</strong>ess than ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> no way entails an eagerness to implementone’s vision by force. A concern for process <strong>and</strong> for how decisions aremade <strong>and</strong> implemented, an extreme aversion to hav<strong>in</strong>g policies, even goodones, rammed down one’s own throat or down o<strong>the</strong>r people’s throats,may well be a major element <strong>in</strong> one’s conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good society.An adherent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> truth-judgment approach may well harbor thisstrong concern for due process; it is not <strong>the</strong> private property <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> contractarians.Yet <strong>the</strong> contractarians tend to suppose that a policy not comm<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>ga strong consensus <strong>in</strong> its favor (or whose adoption would not at least be <strong>in</strong>accordance with an underly<strong>in</strong>g constitution deemed to comm<strong>and</strong> unanimousconsent) is <strong>the</strong>reby revealed to be bad or undesirable. (Passages tothis effect <strong>in</strong> Buchanan <strong>and</strong> Tullock 1962 are quoted <strong>in</strong> Yeager 1978, p. 200<strong>and</strong> n. 17.)


488 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophye contractarians overlook a vital dist<strong>in</strong>ction: What is undesirable <strong>in</strong>such a case is not necessarily <strong>the</strong> policy itself but ra<strong>the</strong>r its imposition byantidemocratic means. It is not necessarily <strong>in</strong>consistent or antidemocraticor elitist for an economist or social philosopher, while deplor<strong>in</strong>g imposition<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> policy, to cont<strong>in</strong>ue advocat<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>and</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to expla<strong>in</strong> its virtues.In short, <strong>the</strong> nihilistic relativism <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> contractarians is by no means <strong>the</strong>only alternative to a repulsive authoritarianism. Contractarians underst<strong>and</strong>, <strong>of</strong> course, that specific policy measures cannot<strong>in</strong> practice be enacted only with unanimous consent. ey <strong>the</strong>reforetry to f<strong>in</strong>d constitutional authority for non-unanimous enactments. econstitution need not necessarily be a written document; it may consist <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> fundamental features <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g society. at broad constitutionis deemed to comm<strong>and</strong> substantially unanimous consent by virtue <strong>of</strong> itsactual existence <strong>and</strong> people’s liv<strong>in</strong>g under it. (See, for example, Buchanan<strong>and</strong> Tullock 1962, pp. 254, 260–261.) Yet David Hume had long beforemocked such notions <strong>of</strong> passive, tacit consent with his much-quoted example<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shanghaied sailor who, merely by refra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g from jump<strong>in</strong>goverboard, does not <strong>the</strong>reby consent to <strong>the</strong> capta<strong>in</strong>’s supposed authorityover him (“Of <strong>the</strong> Orig<strong>in</strong>al Contract,” repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Hume 1752/1965,p. 263).Buchanan <strong>and</strong> Tullock (1962, pp. 260–261) conceived <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “social contract”asa dynamic one.... We do not conceive <strong>the</strong> “constitution” as hav<strong>in</strong>g beenestablished once <strong>and</strong> for all. We conceive <strong>the</strong> contractual aspects to becont<strong>in</strong>uous, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> a set <strong>of</strong> organizational rules is assumedto embody consensus. We th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual as engag<strong>in</strong>g cont<strong>in</strong>uouslyboth <strong>in</strong> everyday operational decisions with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> conf<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong>established organizational rules <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> choices concerned with changes<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> rules <strong>the</strong>mselves, that is, constitutional choices. e implicitrule for secur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> adoption <strong>of</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se organizational rules(changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> social contract) must be that <strong>of</strong> unanimity.is is because only through <strong>the</strong> secur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> unanimity canany change be judged desirable on <strong>the</strong> acceptance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualisticethic.In later writ<strong>in</strong>gs Buchanan also treats a supposed implicit social contractas if it had actual force. He refers (1975a, p. 96) to <strong>the</strong> “exist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 489ongo<strong>in</strong>g implicit social contract, embodied <strong>and</strong> described <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> status quo.” At greater length (1975a, pp. 84–85), he argues that<strong>the</strong> status quo must be evaluated as if it were legitimate contractually, evenwhen an orig<strong>in</strong>al contract may never have been made, when currentmembers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> community sense no moral or ethical obligation to adhereto <strong>the</strong> terms that are def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> status quo, <strong>and</strong> ... when sucha contract, if it ever existed, may have been violated many times over....Does <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> any one or all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se negations remove legitimacyfrom <strong>the</strong> status quo?Aga<strong>in</strong> it is necessary to repeat <strong>the</strong> obvious. e status quo def<strong>in</strong>es thatwhich exists. Hence, regardless <strong>of</strong> its history, it must be evaluated as ifit were legitimate contractually. <strong>in</strong>gs “might have been” different <strong>in</strong>history, but th<strong>in</strong>gs are now as <strong>the</strong>y are.e <strong>in</strong>terpretation conveyed by <strong>the</strong> forego<strong>in</strong>g quotations f<strong>in</strong>ds support<strong>in</strong> a book by one <strong>of</strong> Buchanan’s former students. e social-contract <strong>the</strong>ory<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> state, R<strong>and</strong>all Holcombe (1983) expla<strong>in</strong>s, is an attempt to describe<strong>the</strong> legitimacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> government’s power. It views society as “a type <strong>of</strong> club,where all <strong>in</strong>dividuals conceptually agree to become members <strong>and</strong> adhere to<strong>the</strong> club rules.” Actually, <strong>in</strong>dividuals are born <strong>in</strong>to society <strong>and</strong> must adhereto its rules whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y agree to or not. “Here, <strong>the</strong> social contract <strong>the</strong>ory<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> state must fall back upon <strong>the</strong> conceptual agreement <strong>of</strong> all members<strong>of</strong> society. e state operates as if all members <strong>of</strong> society had agreed to itsrules—as if <strong>the</strong>re is unanimous approval <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> constitution” (Holcombe1983, pp. 124–125; compare passages <strong>of</strong> similar import on pp. 9, 123, 125–126,134).Holcombe does not accept Buchanan’s formulations wholly withoutreservation. “S<strong>in</strong>ce all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> society did not actually agreeto a social contract, ... some type <strong>of</strong> conceptual agreement must be fabricatedif <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory is to have any connection with reality” (1983, p. 155).e words “must be fabricated” deserve emphasis.e writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> Buchanan <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r contractarians (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Holcombe1983, esp. chap. 8) bristle with words like “conceptual” <strong>and</strong> “conceptually”—“conceptuallyagree,” “conceptual agreement,” “conceptual socialcontract,” “conceptual unanimous approval,” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> like. e very use <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> words <strong>in</strong>dicates that a “conceptual” agreement is not an actual one, thata “conceptually” true proposition is not actually true. It is no mere joke tosay that “conceptually” is an adverb stuck <strong>in</strong>to contractarians’ sentences toimmunize <strong>the</strong>m from challenge on <strong>the</strong> grounds <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir not be<strong>in</strong>g true.


490 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyBuchanan (1975b, pp. 123, 125) dist<strong>in</strong>guishes between constitutional<strong>and</strong> postconstitutional stages <strong>of</strong> decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> envisages agreementor “conceptual” agreement at <strong>the</strong> constitutional stage as authoriz<strong>in</strong>g“apparent coercion” <strong>and</strong> “apparent redistribution” at <strong>the</strong> postconstitutionalstage. By such fictions, realities like actual coercion <strong>and</strong> actual redistributionare <strong>in</strong>terpreted away. ey vanish <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> merely “apparent”by be<strong>in</strong>g deemed <strong>in</strong> accordance with some agreement that may itselfbe merely “conceptual.”Even punishment, <strong>in</strong> Buchanan’s view (1975a, p. 192 n.) implementsa contract. “In a genu<strong>in</strong>e contractarian <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>the</strong>re is no problem raisedconcern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ‘right’ <strong>of</strong> some persons to punish o<strong>the</strong>rs, s<strong>in</strong>ce, <strong>in</strong> effect,<strong>in</strong>dividuals who f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> implicit social contract that anysocial order presupposes have presumably chosen to be punished as <strong>the</strong>law directs when <strong>the</strong>y violate law.” Here <strong>the</strong> word “presumably” seems tomean “conceptually” <strong>in</strong> Buchanan’s sense.Fur<strong>the</strong>r evidence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> contractarians’ reliance on fictions is thatBuchanan <strong>and</strong> many o<strong>the</strong>r commentators accept John Rawls’s (1971) characterization<strong>of</strong> his own method as contractarian. Actually, no social contractat all is <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> Rawls’s derivation <strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> justice.Instead, Rawls employs elaborate fictions (about deliberations beh<strong>in</strong>d a“veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance”) <strong>in</strong> more or less disguis<strong>in</strong>g—perhaps even from himself—histotal reliance on his own <strong>in</strong>tuitions. (It astonishes me how manyem<strong>in</strong>ent scholars swallow Rawls’s own characterization <strong>of</strong> his approach.Among <strong>the</strong> apparent m<strong>in</strong>ority who do identify what Rawls actually doesare Hare n.d., <strong>and</strong> Gray 1978.)No one need object to fictions if <strong>the</strong>y are heuristically useful—if <strong>the</strong>ystimulate <strong>the</strong> flow <strong>of</strong> ideas. Nor is it necessarily objectionable to employfictions <strong>and</strong> figures <strong>of</strong> speech for expository <strong>and</strong> stylistic purposes. Buta doctr<strong>in</strong>e should not depend on <strong>the</strong>m. Ideas that defy expression <strong>in</strong>straightforward, nonmetaphorical language <strong>in</strong>cur deserved doubt by thatvery fact.Contractarians might streng<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>ir case by occasionally present<strong>in</strong>git, if <strong>the</strong>y can, without resort to <strong>the</strong>ir favorite fictions. In do<strong>in</strong>g so,however, <strong>the</strong>y would be bound to erase sharp dist<strong>in</strong>ctions between <strong>the</strong>irapproach <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> supposedly despicable truth-judgment approach. eversion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter advocated <strong>in</strong> this paper does lead to much <strong>the</strong> same<strong>in</strong>dividualistic values as contractarianism, but its conceptual apparatus <strong>and</strong>expository style are quite different—more straightforward, <strong>and</strong> charier <strong>of</strong>fictions.


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 491 Utilitarianism is rout<strong>in</strong>ely caricatured <strong>and</strong> scorned nowadays, <strong>and</strong> someversions do deserve scorn. It is said to be lowbrow, crass, <strong>and</strong> subversive <strong>of</strong>personal rights. e Benthamites, says Joseph Schumpeter (1954, pp. 133,407–408), created “<strong>the</strong> shallowest <strong>of</strong> all conceivable philosophies <strong>of</strong> life.”at assessment might well apply if utilitarianism really did recommendthat people spend <strong>the</strong>ir lives pursu<strong>in</strong>g immediate pleasure. e utilitarianismdefended <strong>in</strong> this paper, however, concerns <strong>the</strong> appraisal <strong>of</strong> socialarrangements—policy espousal, as Philbrook (1953) would say.Jeffrie G. Murphy (1977, p. 232) criticized a version that he attributed,wrongly, to John Stuart Mill:is <strong>the</strong>ory is so obviously morally bankrupt that very few contemporarymoral philosophers take it at all seriously.... [It] fails to pay attention to... important autonomy values ... <strong>and</strong> thus fails to articulate a satisfactoryconception <strong>of</strong> justice or respect for persons. It does not ... rule out <strong>the</strong>sacrifice <strong>of</strong> persons for <strong>the</strong> general good.Walter Gr<strong>in</strong>der (1978, pp. 9–10) bewails “<strong>the</strong> tired <strong>and</strong> woefully pragmaticdoctr<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> end-state utilitarianism—<strong>the</strong> cursed Benthamism <strong>in</strong> allits permutations, that has proved <strong>the</strong> bane <strong>of</strong> liberty’s existence for almost200 years. Dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> 19th century, utilitarianism almost s<strong>in</strong>gle h<strong>and</strong>edlyshort-circuited <strong>the</strong> great classical liberal revolution.” Frank S. Meyer (1962,pp. 1–2, 32–33) perceived a fatal flaw <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosophical underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>of</strong> utilitarianism. N<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century liberalism “deserted its heritage <strong>of</strong>defense <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> person” <strong>and</strong> “denied <strong>the</strong> validity <strong>of</strong> moral endsfirmly based on <strong>the</strong> constitution <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g. ereby, with this denial <strong>of</strong> anultimate sanction for <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>violability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> person, liberalism destroyed<strong>the</strong> very foundations <strong>of</strong> its defense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> person as primary <strong>in</strong> political <strong>and</strong>social matters.” To utilitarians, “Human be<strong>in</strong>gs considered as <strong>the</strong> objects <strong>of</strong>operations are no more nor less than objects. Kant’s imperative is reversed.Our humanitarians <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> welfare society take as <strong>the</strong>ir maxim: treat noperson as an end, but only as a means to arrive at a general good.”e criterion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> greatest sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> utilities <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals is collectivistic,as John Rawls says; it regards <strong>in</strong>dividuals as process<strong>in</strong>g stations forconvert<strong>in</strong>g goods <strong>and</strong> services <strong>and</strong> experiences <strong>in</strong>to <strong>in</strong>crements to aggregatesocial utility. e ideal utilitarian legislator, <strong>in</strong> allocat<strong>in</strong>g rights <strong>and</strong>duties <strong>and</strong> scarce means <strong>of</strong> satisfaction, makes decisions similar to those <strong>of</strong>a maximiz<strong>in</strong>g entrepreneur or consumer; his correct decision is essentially


492 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophya matter <strong>of</strong> efficient adm<strong>in</strong>istration. “is view <strong>of</strong> social cooperation is <strong>the</strong>consequence <strong>of</strong> extend<strong>in</strong>g to society <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> choice for one man,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n, to make this extension work, conflat<strong>in</strong>g all persons <strong>in</strong>to onethrough <strong>the</strong> imag<strong>in</strong>ative acts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> impartial sympa<strong>the</strong>tic spectator. Utilitarianismdoes not take seriously <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between persons” (Rawls1971, p. 27; cf. pp. 178–192, 449, 450, 572–573).is last objection ties up with reference to <strong>the</strong> nonoperationality <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> aggregate-utility criterion. Can one conceive <strong>of</strong> operationally mean<strong>in</strong>gfulrules for sacrific<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividuals for <strong>the</strong> greater good <strong>of</strong> “society”?How good, how conducive to <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess, would a societywith such rules be? And how would <strong>the</strong> utilities <strong>of</strong> different persons bemeasured <strong>and</strong> compared <strong>and</strong> added anyway? (Perhaps <strong>the</strong> clearest example<strong>of</strong> accept<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> maximum-aggregate utility criterion is Edgeworth1881/1961. Edgeworth already po<strong>in</strong>ted out, p. 136, as Rawls did later, thatthis version <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism requires extreme altruism; it connotes “Vivrepour autrui.”)Act-utilitarianism, as dist<strong>in</strong>guished from rules-utilitarianism, is particularlyobjectionable. It calls on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual to choose, <strong>in</strong> each separatecase, <strong>the</strong> action appear<strong>in</strong>g likely to contribute to <strong>the</strong> greatest excess<strong>of</strong> pleasure or happ<strong>in</strong>ess or good over <strong>the</strong> opposite. No notion <strong>of</strong> rightsor pr<strong>in</strong>ciples should bar such a calculation, for respect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m is not an<strong>in</strong>dependent objective. Respect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m is f<strong>in</strong>e when it happens <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual case to serve <strong>the</strong> greatest total excess <strong>of</strong> pleasure over pa<strong>in</strong>, butthat excess alone rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al criterion.Perhaps <strong>the</strong> clearest recent example <strong>of</strong> want<strong>in</strong>g each case h<strong>and</strong>led on itsown merits, with no presumption <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> respect<strong>in</strong>g rights or pr<strong>in</strong>ciples,occurs <strong>in</strong> Joseph Fletcher’s Situation Ethics (1966). Fletcher departs fromact-utilitarianism as ord<strong>in</strong>arily conceived only <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g “love” ra<strong>the</strong>r thanhapp<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>the</strong> criterion <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> altruism it calls for more blatant<strong>and</strong> cloy<strong>in</strong>g. Even this substitution makes little difference, s<strong>in</strong>ce Fletcher<strong>in</strong>terprets “love” as conduciveness to well-be<strong>in</strong>g, especially <strong>of</strong> persons o<strong>the</strong>rthan oneself. In <strong>the</strong> coalition that he recommends between <strong>the</strong> love ethic<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> utilitarianism he attributes to Bentham <strong>and</strong> Mill, “<strong>the</strong> hedonisticcalculus becomes <strong>the</strong> agapeic calculus, <strong>the</strong> greatest amount <strong>of</strong> neighborwelfare for <strong>the</strong> largest number <strong>of</strong> neighbors possible.” Fletcher “holds flatlythat <strong>the</strong>re is only one pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, love, without any prefabricated recipes forwhat it means <strong>in</strong> practice, <strong>and</strong> that all o<strong>the</strong>r so called pr<strong>in</strong>ciples or maximsare relative to particular, concrete situations! If it has any rules, <strong>the</strong>y areonly rules <strong>of</strong> thumb.” “e situationist holds that whatever is <strong>the</strong> most


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 493lov<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> situation is <strong>the</strong> right <strong>and</strong> good th<strong>in</strong>g” (quotations frompp. 95, 36, 65 respectively).No wonder critics reject utilitarianism understood as someth<strong>in</strong>g likethat. It betrays remarkable arrogance to take it for granted that <strong>the</strong> actor<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual case, tacitly endowed with <strong>the</strong> omniscience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> actutilitarianor act-agapeic philosopher himself, can foresee all <strong>the</strong> immediate<strong>and</strong> remote <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong> direct <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>direct consequences <strong>of</strong> his actions,even <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g those work<strong>in</strong>g through re<strong>in</strong>forc<strong>in</strong>g or underm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciples<strong>and</strong> habits <strong>and</strong> through affect<strong>in</strong>g persons’ moral characters, <strong>and</strong> canassess <strong>the</strong> good <strong>and</strong> bad values <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong>se consequences <strong>and</strong> strike a balance.As Peter S. Prescott (1973) has said, “what was recently called ‘situationethics’ can be def<strong>in</strong>ed as action based on <strong>in</strong>v<strong>in</strong>cible trust <strong>in</strong> one’s ownmoral perspective.”An extreme act-utilitarianism or situation ethics might <strong>in</strong>deed countenancefram<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> execut<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>nocent man to pacify an angry mob<strong>and</strong> so avoid worse outrages—to mention <strong>the</strong> example so rout<strong>in</strong>ely trottedout (for example, by McCloskey 1969, p. 181; compare Rothbard 1973,pp. 24–25, on <strong>the</strong> execution <strong>of</strong> all redheads to delight <strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> population). John Rawls comments perceptively on this sort <strong>of</strong> attack on a strawmanversion <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism. Rawls (1955/1968), writ<strong>in</strong>g before McCloskey(1969) <strong>and</strong> before his own book <strong>of</strong> 1971, attributed <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard horribleexample to E.F. Carritt. Rawls (1955/1968, pp. 76–78) also answered <strong>the</strong>question, raised <strong>in</strong> a similar ve<strong>in</strong>, whe<strong>the</strong>r it is acceptable to break one’spromise when <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g so appear good on balance. every po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> promis<strong>in</strong>g “is to abdicate one’s title to act <strong>in</strong> accordance withutilitarian <strong>and</strong> prudential considerations <strong>in</strong> order that <strong>the</strong> future may betied down <strong>and</strong> plans coord<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> advance.... e promisor is boundbecause he promised: weigh<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> case on its merits is not open to him.”e <strong>in</strong>stitution <strong>of</strong> promis<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> promise-keep<strong>in</strong>g itself has obvious utilitarianadvantages. at <strong>the</strong> promisor’s obligation may be overridden <strong>in</strong>exceptional hard cases does not mean that <strong>the</strong> obligation does not existat all.How conducive to happ<strong>in</strong>ess would a society be, Rawls (1955/1968)asks <strong>in</strong> effect, <strong>in</strong> which truth <strong>and</strong> rights were treated as contemptuouslyas <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> hackneyed horrible example? More specifically, <strong>in</strong> what context


494 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophymight a judgment be made <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> sacrific<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>nocent victim topacify <strong>the</strong> mob? It is vague to say that it would be a good idea if somebodydid someth<strong>in</strong>g to save many <strong>in</strong>nocent lives by sacrific<strong>in</strong>g one. Howcould such acts be <strong>in</strong>stitutionalized? Just who would be authorized, <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong> what circumstances <strong>and</strong> under what rules, to <strong>in</strong>flict “telishment” (bywhich Rawls apparently means ostensible punishment <strong>in</strong>flicted for ulteriorpurposes)? Several reasons are obvious, <strong>and</strong> Rawls suggests some,why an <strong>in</strong>stitution <strong>of</strong> telishment could hardly be justified on utilitariangrounds.Does this dismissal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> telishment case simply postulate out <strong>of</strong> existence<strong>the</strong> difficulties that it is meant to illustrate? Am I deny<strong>in</strong>g that anys<strong>in</strong>gle case could ever arise <strong>in</strong> which sacrific<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>nocent person mightappear to promise greater good on <strong>the</strong> whole? Well, can one ever be confidentthat such a case has <strong>in</strong> fact arisen? e consequences <strong>of</strong> suppos<strong>in</strong>gso <strong>and</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g accord<strong>in</strong>gly are unfathomable. Approv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> violation <strong>of</strong>rights whenever <strong>the</strong> decisionmaker th<strong>in</strong>ks it would be beneficial on <strong>the</strong>whole would re<strong>in</strong>force unhealthy temptations <strong>and</strong> undercut <strong>the</strong> very concept<strong>of</strong> rights. A society tolerat<strong>in</strong>g such violations would hardly be one<strong>in</strong> which people enjoyed relatively favorable opportunities to make goodlives for <strong>the</strong>mselves. Tak<strong>in</strong>g account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> associated <strong>in</strong>stitutions, habits,attitudes, <strong>and</strong> personality traits, as well as <strong>the</strong> fact that each person has alife <strong>and</strong> consciousness <strong>and</strong> purposes <strong>of</strong> his own, requires reject<strong>in</strong>g such asociety. Endorsement <strong>of</strong> personal rights <strong>in</strong>stead follows precisely on utilitariangrounds.In <strong>the</strong> abstract, though hardly <strong>in</strong> conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g detail, one can contrive acase <strong>in</strong> which an act ord<strong>in</strong>arily deemed wrongful would have a net balance<strong>of</strong> good consequences, even with any underm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> respect for rules <strong>and</strong>rights counted on <strong>the</strong> negative side <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> assessment. Perhaps <strong>the</strong> wrongfulact can be kept secret, <strong>and</strong> its victim would have died soon <strong>of</strong> agoniz<strong>in</strong>gdisease anyway. e contrived assumptions would rule out such adverseconsequences as impairment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> agent’s attitudes <strong>and</strong> moral character.e assumptions would render <strong>the</strong> proposition about <strong>the</strong> acceptability <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwise wrong act an empty tautology. If <strong>the</strong> act really would leadto <strong>the</strong> greatest net utility, absolutely all th<strong>in</strong>gs accurately considered, <strong>and</strong>if <strong>the</strong> greatest net utility is one’s criterion <strong>of</strong> what ought to be done, <strong>the</strong>n<strong>the</strong> act ought to be done. But <strong>in</strong> what actual context could <strong>the</strong>se ifs bemet? When could one have absolutely all <strong>the</strong> relevant knowledge <strong>of</strong> consequences,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> violation <strong>of</strong> valued pr<strong>in</strong>ciples,certa<strong>in</strong>ty that one’s knowledge was accurate <strong>and</strong> complete, <strong>and</strong> certa<strong>in</strong>ty


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 495<strong>of</strong> one’s accuracy <strong>in</strong> weigh<strong>in</strong>g oppos<strong>in</strong>g considerations? e assumptionsrequired negate <strong>the</strong> real-world context that <strong>in</strong> fact recommends rules-utilitarianismover act-utilitarianism.Suppose for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> argument, never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>and</strong> quite implausibly,that a clear case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulated k<strong>in</strong>d did arise. Suppose, fur<strong>the</strong>r, thatarrang<strong>in</strong>g compensation acceptable to <strong>the</strong> prospective victim or victimswas for some reason impossible <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> decision fell onme. en I would have to face up to that case. I cannot commit myself <strong>in</strong>advance, ignorant <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> specific facts, to <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g on observance <strong>of</strong> rules<strong>and</strong> rights even though <strong>the</strong> heavens should crumble. And nei<strong>the</strong>r could aself-styled antiutilitarian champion <strong>of</strong> rights. A sounder version <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism than <strong>the</strong> one rout<strong>in</strong>ely pilloried hasbeen called rules-utilitarianism or <strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism. ( John Gray, 1983,esp. pp. 11–15, 31–32, 38–39, 46–47, attributes an <strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism toJohn Stuart Mill <strong>and</strong> tries to dist<strong>in</strong>guish it from rules-utilitarianism; forpresent purposes <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction is <strong>in</strong>essential.)Accord<strong>in</strong>g to McCloskey, however, rules-utilitarianism arises fromawareness that <strong>the</strong> act version will not do; yet it is only pseudo-utilitarianism.It opts for “irrational” conformity to rules even though no <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sicmoral significance attaches to <strong>the</strong>m <strong>and</strong> even when conform<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>mbr<strong>in</strong>gs greater total evil. e rules-utilitarian prefers conformity to a rule tomaximization <strong>of</strong> good. If he replies that “his is <strong>the</strong> best way <strong>of</strong> promot<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> greatest good, he is ab<strong>and</strong>on<strong>in</strong>g rule for act utilitarianism” (McCloskey1969, p. 188).Why, though, does McCloskey speak <strong>of</strong> irrational conformity to rules?Rules serve human welfare. Utilitarianism <strong>of</strong> course recognizes dilemmacases—<strong>the</strong>y figure <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> human predicament—<strong>in</strong> which applicable rulesclash <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> which some must be overridden to permit conform<strong>in</strong>g to o<strong>the</strong>rsmore dem<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular case. To recognize such cases is notto lapse back <strong>in</strong>to act-utilitarianism or situation ethics. e rules versiondoes stress <strong>the</strong> advantages <strong>of</strong> habituation to rules <strong>and</strong> does caution aga<strong>in</strong>stexcessive read<strong>in</strong>ess to override a rule (especially aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> temptation tomake an exception <strong>in</strong> one’s own favor). If <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> fram<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>nocentman to pacify <strong>the</strong> mob so shocks us, it is because we rightly f<strong>in</strong>d it sohard to imag<strong>in</strong>e cases <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> rule <strong>of</strong> justice should be <strong>the</strong> one to beoverridden. e quality <strong>of</strong> McCloskey’s debat<strong>in</strong>g tactics is evident <strong>in</strong> his


496 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyexample (p. 191) <strong>of</strong> choos<strong>in</strong>g between abid<strong>in</strong>g by Australia’s drive-on-<strong>the</strong>leftrule <strong>and</strong> collid<strong>in</strong>g with a car <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> wrong lane.As for rules hav<strong>in</strong>g no “<strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic” moral significance, well, what is sosuspect about <strong>the</strong>re not be<strong>in</strong>g irreducible ultimates for which no argumentscan be <strong>of</strong>fered? Of course utilitarianism does not <strong>and</strong> cannot <strong>in</strong>sistthat rules be followed for <strong>the</strong>ir own sakes. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, rules are <strong>in</strong>strumentalto a good society <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby to people’s happ<strong>in</strong>ess. To treat rulesas absolute ultimates would underm<strong>in</strong>e respect for <strong>the</strong>m by mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mappear ridiculous.Let us consider <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> justice <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>justice a bit fur<strong>the</strong>r. Victimiz<strong>in</strong>gan <strong>in</strong>nocent person or m<strong>in</strong>ority for <strong>the</strong> supposed greater ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong>o<strong>the</strong>rs is <strong>in</strong>deed unjust. But we need not stop short with report<strong>in</strong>g our<strong>in</strong>tuition to that effect; we can give reasons for our judgment. We do notdowngrade justice by not regard<strong>in</strong>g it as an undiscussable ultimate. Injusticesubverts social cooperation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess. Sir JamesMacIntosh argued (V<strong>in</strong>diciae Gallicae, quoted <strong>in</strong> Halévy 1955, p. 185) that<strong>the</strong> extreme usefulness <strong>of</strong> general pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> justice makes <strong>the</strong>m morallyobligatory.Justice is expediency, but it is expediency, speak<strong>in</strong>g by general maxims,<strong>in</strong>to which reason has concentrated <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> man k<strong>in</strong>d.... WhenI assert that a man has a right to life, liberty, &c. I only mean to annunciatea moral maxim founded on general <strong>in</strong>terest, which prohibits any attackon <strong>the</strong>se possessions.... [A Declaration <strong>of</strong> Rights is an expedient] to keepalive <strong>the</strong> Public vigilance aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> usurpation <strong>of</strong> partial <strong>in</strong>terests, byperpetually present<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> general right <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> general <strong>in</strong>terest to <strong>the</strong>Public eye.John Stuart Mill (Mill 1968, p. 299) said: “Justice is a name for certa<strong>in</strong>classes <strong>of</strong> moral rules which concern <strong>the</strong> essentials <strong>of</strong> human well-be<strong>in</strong>gmore nearly, <strong>and</strong> are <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>of</strong> more absolute obligation, than any o<strong>the</strong>rrules for <strong>the</strong> guidance <strong>of</strong> life.” As an approach to underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g what sorts <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual conduct <strong>and</strong>especially what <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> policies are desirable, rules- or <strong>in</strong>directutilitarianism amounts to much <strong>the</strong> same th<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>the</strong> comparative-<strong>in</strong>stitutionsor good-society approach. ese all have an aff<strong>in</strong>ity with <strong>the</strong> “truthjudgment”approach disparaged by James Buchanan.


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 497For present purposes it matters little whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se different labelsapply to exactly <strong>the</strong> same doctr<strong>in</strong>e; if not identical, <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>es do share acommon orientation. eir adherents try to form a conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> goodsociety by contemplat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> compar<strong>in</strong>g alternative sets <strong>of</strong> mutually compatiblesocial <strong>in</strong>stitutions. eir ideal is whatever arrangements best facilitate<strong>the</strong> success <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals seek<strong>in</strong>g to make good lives for <strong>the</strong>mselves<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own diverse ways. (Strictly speak<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>ir ultimate criterion ishuman happ<strong>in</strong>ess, however best served. It is a researchable <strong>and</strong> discussableempirical judgment that happ<strong>in</strong>ess is served by <strong>in</strong>stitutions that facilitatevoluntary cooperation, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g ones that secure <strong>the</strong> rights mentioned <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> U.S. Declaration <strong>of</strong> Independence.)is approach recognizes <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> mutually beneficial cooperationamong <strong>in</strong>dividuals—through peace <strong>and</strong> security <strong>and</strong> through <strong>the</strong>ga<strong>in</strong>s from specialization <strong>and</strong> exchange. (Adam Smith po<strong>in</strong>ted out thatman is a social animal: he makes contracts. As Scott Gordon, 1976, p. 586,notes perceptively, “<strong>the</strong> most important feature <strong>of</strong> that word is <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>alletter, which makes it plural. ere is a world <strong>of</strong> difference between <strong>the</strong>conception <strong>of</strong> society as consist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> contracts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> conception <strong>of</strong> it asbased upon a contract.”)e approach recommended here appraises particular pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, rules,<strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>and</strong> policies accord<strong>in</strong>g to whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y are likely to serveor subvert social cooperation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense just <strong>in</strong>dicated. (e concept ifnot <strong>the</strong> term is prom<strong>in</strong>ent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosophies <strong>of</strong> omas Hobbes <strong>and</strong>,as F.A. Hayek has emphasized, <strong>of</strong> David Hume. See Hobbes, Leviathan,1651/1952, chap. 15, <strong>and</strong> Kemp 1970. e term “social cooperation” is prom<strong>in</strong>ent<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> Herbert Spencer, Ludwig von Mises, <strong>and</strong> HenryHazlitt.)Social cooperation counts as a near-ultimate criterion, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is an<strong>in</strong>dispensable means to <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ effective pursuit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own happ<strong>in</strong>ess<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own diverse ways (Hazlitt 1964, esp. p. 36). Cooperation isfacilitated by rules that improve people’s chances <strong>of</strong> predict<strong>in</strong>g each o<strong>the</strong>r’sbehavior <strong>and</strong> achiev<strong>in</strong>g coord<strong>in</strong>ation. Voluntary cooperation accords betterthan coercion with each person’s hav<strong>in</strong>g purposes <strong>and</strong> ideals <strong>of</strong> hisown <strong>and</strong> with his hav<strong>in</strong>g only one life to live. Emphasis on voluntarycooperation warns aga<strong>in</strong>st authoriz<strong>in</strong>g any agency to impose unfair sacrificeson <strong>in</strong>dividuals for <strong>the</strong> supposed greater good <strong>of</strong> a greater number.But this approach does not simply postulate voluntary cooperation<strong>and</strong> deplore coercion. It <strong>in</strong>vestigates <strong>and</strong> compares <strong>the</strong> types <strong>of</strong> societylikely to emerge from hav<strong>in</strong>g alternative sets <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> rules <strong>and</strong>,


498 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy<strong>in</strong> particular, from whe<strong>the</strong>r or not personal rights are recognized <strong>and</strong>respected.e term “utilitarianism” as used here applies to any critical exam<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>of</strong> social rules <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>the</strong>ir function<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir implicationsfor happ<strong>in</strong>ess. In this wide sense, F.A. Hayek says (1976, pp. 17–18),anyone prepared to exam<strong>in</strong>e exist<strong>in</strong>g values ra<strong>the</strong>r than accept <strong>the</strong>munquestion<strong>in</strong>gly is a utilitarian; Aristotle, omas Aqu<strong>in</strong>as, <strong>and</strong> DavidHume would so count.In reject<strong>in</strong>g act-utilitarianism for rules-utilitarianism—but <strong>the</strong> termsare not his—Hayek expla<strong>in</strong>s (1969, pp. 45–46) why it may be rational to disregardknown particular circumstances when mak<strong>in</strong>g decisions. Accidental<strong>and</strong> partial bits <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation might not change <strong>the</strong> probability that ifwe knew <strong>and</strong> could process all <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong> circumstances, <strong>the</strong>net advantage would lie on <strong>the</strong> side <strong>of</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> applicable rule. Weshould not decide each case on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> limited number <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualfacts that we happen to know.One reason for abid<strong>in</strong>g by rules, <strong>the</strong>n, is that we simply cannot assessall <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>and</strong> costs <strong>and</strong> benefits—direct <strong>and</strong> remote, immediate<strong>and</strong> delayed—<strong>of</strong> alternative actions <strong>in</strong> each particular case. One mightobject that this position is anti-<strong>in</strong>tellectual, mak<strong>in</strong>g a virtue <strong>of</strong> ignorance.How can we know that advances <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> technology may not makepossible those allegedly impossible assessments? Part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> answer, I conjecture,is that <strong>the</strong> critic has not really seen <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t. Rules-utilitarianismdoes not glorify ignorance. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it perceives <strong>the</strong> rationality <strong>of</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g,<strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> cases <strong>and</strong> aspects <strong>of</strong> life, on generally applicable abstract pr<strong>in</strong>ciples<strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> on <strong>the</strong> fragmentary <strong>and</strong> probably accidentally biased bits<strong>of</strong> concrete <strong>in</strong>formation that one may happen to possess. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,complexity <strong>and</strong> ignorance by no means form <strong>the</strong> entire case for rulesutilitarianism.Act<strong>in</strong>g by rule or on pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong>ten contributes to overcom<strong>in</strong>gignorance, namely people’s ignorance <strong>of</strong> each o<strong>the</strong>r’s probable behavior.General acceptance <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples contributes to predictability <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>world <strong>and</strong> thus to people’s chances <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir activities to <strong>the</strong>irmutual benefit.As a utilitarian <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> tradition <strong>of</strong> Hume ra<strong>the</strong>r than Bentham, Hayekdoes not envision maximization <strong>of</strong> some aggregate <strong>of</strong> numerical measures.He says (1976, pp. 129–130) that <strong>the</strong> aim <strong>in</strong> develop<strong>in</strong>g or alter<strong>in</strong>g rules<strong>of</strong> just conduct “should be to improve as much as possible <strong>the</strong> chances <strong>of</strong>anyone selected at r<strong>and</strong>om.” He speaks <strong>of</strong> chances ra<strong>the</strong>r than probabilities“because <strong>the</strong> latter term suggests numerical magnitudes which will not be


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 499known.” Equivalently, “<strong>the</strong> best society would be that <strong>in</strong> which we wouldprefer to place our children if we knew that <strong>the</strong>ir position <strong>in</strong> it would bedeterm<strong>in</strong>ed by lot” (1976, p. 132; similar passages occur <strong>in</strong> 1967, p. 163; 1978,pp. 62–63; 1976, p. 114).Hayek’s formulations are similar to those <strong>of</strong> John C. Harsanyi, anavowed utilitarian, who considers a person contemplat<strong>in</strong>g alternative socialarrangements <strong>in</strong> ignorance or at least <strong>in</strong> disregard <strong>of</strong> what his personalsituation would be. On Harsanyi’s <strong>the</strong>ory, that person “wouldhave to choose <strong>the</strong> social situation yield<strong>in</strong>g him a higher expected utility,which <strong>in</strong> this case would mean choos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> situation provid<strong>in</strong>g ahigher average utility level to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> society.”(Harsanyi 1976, chap. 5, p. 67; cf. Harsanyi 1955/1973, pp. 276–277. IfHarsanyi’s method resembles Rawls’s 1971 notion <strong>of</strong> choice beh<strong>in</strong>d aveil <strong>of</strong> ignorance, <strong>the</strong> similarity goes to show that such a conception <strong>of</strong>impartiality need not be a dist<strong>in</strong>ctively contractarian one, as Rawls seemsto th<strong>in</strong>k.)e version <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism here attributed to Hayek, among o<strong>the</strong>rs,might also, as already suggested, be called a comparative-<strong>in</strong>stitutionsor good-society approach. Although Hayek repeatedly emphasizes howspontaneously evolved rules <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions may serve an order that tendsto reduce conflicts <strong>and</strong> ease cooperation among persons pursu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irown diverse ends, he does not discourage look<strong>in</strong>g critically at those rules<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> sometimes deliberately modify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m.Consciously design<strong>in</strong>g a society from scratch, however, is not a liveoption. No one knows enough for such an undertak<strong>in</strong>g. rough trial <strong>and</strong>error <strong>and</strong> survival <strong>of</strong> what works, our exist<strong>in</strong>g society <strong>in</strong>corporates muchunarticulated knowledge. row<strong>in</strong>g that knowledge away merely because<strong>of</strong> its be<strong>in</strong>g unarticulated <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore unappreciated would be reckless.We should have a certa<strong>in</strong> humility <strong>in</strong> undertak<strong>in</strong>g reform—so Hayek <strong>in</strong>effect argues—but not reject all thought <strong>of</strong> reform. e comparative-<strong>in</strong>stitutions str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism does not try to groundgovernment <strong>and</strong> political obligation <strong>in</strong> contractarian fictions. e notion<strong>of</strong> consent—tacit consent—may have heuristic value, admittedly; but argumentsus<strong>in</strong>g it should, if sound, be amenable to translation <strong>in</strong>to straightforwardEnglish. In such arguments, tacit consent alludes to considerateness,reciprocity, <strong>and</strong> self-esteem, all <strong>of</strong> which are valuable on broadly


500 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyutilitarian grounds. Most <strong>of</strong> us believe that we should ord<strong>in</strong>arily practice<strong>the</strong> everyday little courtesies toward one ano<strong>the</strong>r, accept<strong>in</strong>g trivial <strong>in</strong>conveniencesfor ourselves to spare o<strong>the</strong>rs substantial ones. Ord<strong>in</strong>arily, forexample, we do not compla<strong>in</strong> about reasonable noise <strong>in</strong>cidental to usefulactivity (“reasonable” is admittedly a weasel word here); for we ourselvesbenefit from a society <strong>in</strong> which such noise is tolerated. e po<strong>in</strong>t is notthat we <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs have agreed, or are “deemed” to have agreed, to suffernoise. Such a fiction is unnecessary. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, each <strong>of</strong> us refra<strong>in</strong>s from compla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gabout reasonable noise <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> expectation <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs’ similar forbearance<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> social cooperation from which we allbenefit.Each <strong>of</strong> us would be uneasy constantly <strong>and</strong> belligerently <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g onour “rights,” refus<strong>in</strong>g consideration <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs at <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> even <strong>the</strong> slightestmomentary <strong>in</strong>convenience, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g that o<strong>the</strong>rs ei<strong>the</strong>r refra<strong>in</strong> fromactivities exert<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> slightest adverse externality or else pay compensation.at would be a nerve-wrack<strong>in</strong>g way to live. We would be <strong>in</strong>consistent<strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tolerant <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>considerate <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs while expect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mto be tolerant <strong>and</strong> considerate <strong>of</strong> us. Such behavior would emit messagesto o<strong>the</strong>rs about our own character.For most <strong>of</strong> us, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, it serves our self-esteem to th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> ourselvesas consistent, considerate persons who play fair <strong>and</strong> who supportra<strong>the</strong>r than subvert a decent society. Each <strong>of</strong> us benefits from courtesy<strong>and</strong> ease <strong>in</strong> relations with our fellows. It does not serve our self-esteem or<strong>in</strong>terest to undercut that spirit. us, we need not <strong>in</strong>terpret tolerant <strong>and</strong>considerate behavior toward o<strong>the</strong>rs as compliance with a contract.Much <strong>the</strong> same considerations argue for respect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> legitimacy<strong>of</strong> government <strong>and</strong> an obligation to obey its laws. e argument alsoexpla<strong>in</strong>s why <strong>the</strong> legitimacy <strong>and</strong> obligation are not total. Most <strong>of</strong> usfeel obliged to obey a reasonably decent government on <strong>the</strong> groundsthat do<strong>in</strong>g so contributes to our own <strong>and</strong> our fellows’ welfare—<strong>in</strong> view<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Hobbesian alternative. Consideration <strong>of</strong> our fellows, which ord<strong>in</strong>arilyserves our self-esteem, requires our not contribut<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> subversion<strong>of</strong> a generally useful <strong>in</strong>stitution (which government is, eventhough a “necessary evil”). Unfairly arrogat<strong>in</strong>g special privilege to oneself,pick<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> choos<strong>in</strong>g which laws to obey, <strong>and</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g exceptions<strong>in</strong> one’s own favor does someth<strong>in</strong>g toward underm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> legitimacy<strong>and</strong> authority <strong>of</strong> a government from which we ourselves derive net advantages.(I dist<strong>in</strong>guish, <strong>of</strong> course, between a government that is decenton <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>and</strong>, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, a tyrannical one that ought, on


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 501<strong>the</strong> same grounds <strong>of</strong> concern for ourselves <strong>and</strong> our fellows, to be overthrown.)On grounds <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g one’s own <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r persons’ happ<strong>in</strong>ess as servedthrough social cooperation, <strong>the</strong>n, one can make a case for people’s () accord<strong>in</strong>geveryday courtesies to one ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> () practic<strong>in</strong>g considerateness<strong>and</strong> reciprocity <strong>in</strong> yet ano<strong>the</strong>r way, through respect<strong>in</strong>g politicalobligation toward a reasonably decent government.Much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g ties <strong>in</strong> with possible answers to what Br<strong>and</strong>Blanshard calls <strong>the</strong> fundamental question <strong>of</strong> political <strong>the</strong>ory: “Why shouldI obey <strong>the</strong> law? An adequate answer to that question would carry with it<strong>the</strong> answer to such questions as, Why should <strong>the</strong>re be a government at all?What are <strong>the</strong> grounds <strong>of</strong> its rights aga<strong>in</strong>st me <strong>and</strong> my rights aga<strong>in</strong>st it <strong>and</strong>how <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple are those rights to be limited?” (Blanshard 1961, chap. 14,“Reason <strong>and</strong> Politics,” quotation from p. 376).Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> first <strong>the</strong>ory that Blanshard reviews, political rights<strong>and</strong> duties are based on noth<strong>in</strong>g. is anarchist view is “doctr<strong>in</strong>aire idealism<strong>of</strong> a pa<strong>the</strong>tically irresponsible sort” (1961, p. 378). Second is <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>ethat might makes right; it sets ethics aside. e third appeals to div<strong>in</strong>eauthority, <strong>the</strong> fourth, <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> Hobbes <strong>and</strong> Rousseau, to a socialcontract.Contractarianism begs <strong>the</strong> question, Blanshard expla<strong>in</strong>s. If, before enter<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> social contract, I do not have an obligation to keep contracts,<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> social contract to keep future contracts is not b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g, norare future contracts supposedly made under it. But if I do have an obligation<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place to keep contracts or to honor certa<strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r duties,<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory is superfluous.Fifth is <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Declaration <strong>of</strong> Independence: <strong>the</strong> selfevidenttruths that men have certa<strong>in</strong> unalienable rights, that governmentsare <strong>in</strong>stituted to secure <strong>the</strong>se rights, <strong>and</strong> that if a government becomesdestructive <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>the</strong> people have <strong>the</strong> right to alter or abolish it. isdoctr<strong>in</strong>e, says Blanshard, comes close to <strong>the</strong> correct one. He does not deny<strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> natural rights rest<strong>in</strong>g on no government <strong>and</strong> no convention<strong>and</strong> identifiable by reason, but he doubts that <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> selfevidencestates <strong>the</strong>ir true ground. Natural rights can break down: casesare conceivable <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> community can legitimately exercise coercion.All sorts <strong>of</strong> rights would be desirable—here I am embroider<strong>in</strong>g onBlanshard a bit—if recogniz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m did not cost too much <strong>in</strong> variousways. Now, consider<strong>in</strong>g costs means go<strong>in</strong>g beyond what is supposedly selfevident.


502 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophySixth comes Blanshard’s doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> “rational will”:that men have a common moral end which is <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir rationalwill, that <strong>the</strong> state is a contrivance that <strong>the</strong>y have worked out [that hasevolved, Hayek would probably say] to help <strong>the</strong>m realize that end, <strong>and</strong>that its authority over <strong>the</strong>m rests on its be<strong>in</strong>g necessary for that end. Ifit is politically obligatory at times to obey a law that one regards as bad,that is because <strong>the</strong> state could not be run at all if <strong>the</strong> citizens could pick<strong>and</strong> choose which laws <strong>the</strong>y would obey. Ultimately, <strong>the</strong>refore, politicalobligation, even that <strong>of</strong> obey<strong>in</strong>g a morally bad law, is a moral obligation;<strong>and</strong> when, as occasionally happens, it become [sic] a duty to disobey, <strong>the</strong>ground is still <strong>the</strong> same. (1961, p. 395)Four propositions elaborate this doctr<strong>in</strong>e:First we can dist<strong>in</strong>guish with<strong>in</strong> our own m<strong>in</strong>ds between <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> ouractual or immediate will, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> our rational will, which is whaton reflection would commend itself as <strong>the</strong> greatest good. Secondly, thisrational end is <strong>the</strong> same for all men. irdly, this end, because a commonend, is <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> our rights aga<strong>in</strong>st each o<strong>the</strong>r. Fourthly, <strong>the</strong> justification<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> state, <strong>and</strong> its true <strong>of</strong>fice, lie <strong>in</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> realization <strong>of</strong>this end.... [T]he <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> a rational will provides a natural <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligibleground both for obedience <strong>in</strong> normal cases <strong>and</strong> for disobedience<strong>in</strong> abnormal cases. (pp. 395, 402)Briefly <strong>in</strong>terpreted, Blanshard’s rational-will doctr<strong>in</strong>e says that <strong>the</strong> obligationto support government is b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g because—<strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> extentthat—it serves social cooperation. e obligation to support ra<strong>the</strong>r thansubvert social cooperation rests, <strong>in</strong> turn, on ord<strong>in</strong>ary ethical precepts. (Ido not ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>, however, that Blanshard would himself accept <strong>the</strong> utilitarianlabel.)We have no need for contractarian fictions. I might well obey <strong>the</strong> laws<strong>of</strong> an absolute monarchy, <strong>and</strong> even consider such obedience <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> general<strong>in</strong>terest <strong>and</strong> morally obligatory, while disapprov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> that government’snondemocratic character <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> its actions. A restatement is worth attempt<strong>in</strong>g. We go along with <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g form <strong>of</strong>government <strong>and</strong> generally obey its laws because, first, we have no real alternative.For an <strong>in</strong>dividual, revolt would be fruitless <strong>and</strong> mov<strong>in</strong>g abroad too


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 503costly. (Besides, where would we go?) We <strong>in</strong>dividuals have not agreed evento hav<strong>in</strong>g a government at all, much less to <strong>the</strong> particular constitution <strong>in</strong>force. We have not even been asked whe<strong>the</strong>r we agree (<strong>and</strong> ask<strong>in</strong>g us nowwould be a mockery). Ra<strong>the</strong>r, we <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> current generation f<strong>in</strong>d ourselvesliv<strong>in</strong>g under a form <strong>of</strong> government <strong>and</strong> under laws that have evolved overtime without our <strong>in</strong>dividually hav<strong>in</strong>g had any effective say. Government<strong>and</strong> laws are not primarily results <strong>of</strong> an organized <strong>and</strong> deliberate process<strong>of</strong> collective decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g, certa<strong>in</strong>ly not <strong>of</strong> one <strong>in</strong> which we <strong>the</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>ghave taken decisive part.A second reason for acquiescence is that we f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g systempreferable to general lawlessness. Peace <strong>and</strong> security <strong>and</strong> a stable legalframework serve social cooperation <strong>and</strong> thus happ<strong>in</strong>ess. We <strong>in</strong>dividualsbenefit from o<strong>the</strong>rs’ abid<strong>in</strong>g by <strong>the</strong> law <strong>and</strong> feel that we <strong>in</strong> turn shoulddo <strong>the</strong> same. We feel that it would be morally wrong to make exceptions<strong>in</strong> our own favor at o<strong>the</strong>rs’ expense. In self-defense we apply forceaga<strong>in</strong>st crim<strong>in</strong>als who flout such <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral code as has been re<strong>in</strong>forcedby law.e most—which is perhaps too much—that can be said for a socialcontract<strong>the</strong>ory is that most <strong>of</strong> us abide by <strong>the</strong> law <strong>and</strong> refra<strong>in</strong> from unconstitutionalsubversion <strong>of</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g government <strong>in</strong> expectation or <strong>in</strong> consideration<strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs’ do<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> same. But this very nebulous contract, if it isa contract at all, is <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same sort as <strong>the</strong> one <strong>in</strong> accordance with whichwe generally observe ord<strong>in</strong>ary ethical precepts. We ord<strong>in</strong>arily show someconsideration for o<strong>the</strong>r people <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir rights because we expect <strong>the</strong>m toshow similar consideration for us <strong>and</strong> because behav<strong>in</strong>g with this consistency<strong>and</strong> decency serves our own self-esteem. Considerateness for eacho<strong>the</strong>r yields ga<strong>in</strong>s from trade.It would really be reach<strong>in</strong>g, however, to <strong>in</strong>terpret this sort <strong>of</strong> implicittrad<strong>in</strong>g as a social contract, <strong>and</strong> particularly as a contract whereby each <strong>of</strong>us has consented to <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g constitution <strong>and</strong> is thus deemed to haveconsented to government decisions made <strong>in</strong> accordance with <strong>the</strong> constitution.It is an exaggeration to call <strong>the</strong> government’s laws <strong>and</strong> actions <strong>the</strong>result <strong>of</strong> collective decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> any literal sense. Let’s face it: governmentdecisions are made by government <strong>of</strong>ficials (<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> composite <strong>of</strong>those decisions undergoes some un<strong>in</strong>tended drift over time); we ord<strong>in</strong>arycitizens are not <strong>the</strong> government.Under democracy, it is true, we have some <strong>in</strong>fluence on those decisionsthrough vot<strong>in</strong>g, through help<strong>in</strong>g shape public op<strong>in</strong>ion, <strong>and</strong> thusthrough <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>g what decisions public <strong>of</strong>ficials will consider <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir


504 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophyown <strong>in</strong>terest. But our control over government is less precise <strong>and</strong> effectivethan our control over economic activity through our “vot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>marketplace.” Some analogy does hold between political <strong>and</strong> economicdecisions, but we should not delude ourselves about how closely it holds.<strong>Is</strong> <strong>the</strong> state a product <strong>of</strong> its citizens’ voluntary consent, a mechanismvoluntarily established to attend to <strong>the</strong>ir common concerns? Nonsense. Ihave no choice about be<strong>in</strong>g subjected to its laws. True enough, I am gladthat <strong>the</strong> state exists; I prefer it to anarchy; but <strong>the</strong> state is <strong>the</strong>re whe<strong>the</strong>rI want it or not. My welcom<strong>in</strong>g certa<strong>in</strong> arrangements does not mean that<strong>the</strong>y are not compulsory. I am glad to have seat belts <strong>in</strong> my car <strong>and</strong> wouldprobably have bought <strong>the</strong>m will<strong>in</strong>gly if I had had a free choice, but <strong>the</strong> factrema<strong>in</strong>s that I did not have a free choice <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> belts were <strong>in</strong>stalledunder compulsion <strong>of</strong> law.Far from <strong>the</strong> state’s be<strong>in</strong>g a voluntary arrangement, <strong>the</strong>n, its essence iscompulsion. It relies as a last resort on its power to seize goods <strong>and</strong> persons,to imprison, <strong>and</strong> to execute. If obedience to government is not compulsory,<strong>the</strong>n what is? What does <strong>the</strong> word “compulsory” mean? What happens to<strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>the</strong> voluntary <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> compulsory?To say this is not to glorify <strong>the</strong> compulsory aspects <strong>of</strong> government.I concede <strong>the</strong>ir necessity only with regret. I want to keep <strong>the</strong>m tightlyrestra<strong>in</strong>ed, as <strong>the</strong> cause <strong>of</strong> human liberty requires. One serves that causepoorly if one deludes oneself <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that government embodies freeexchange <strong>and</strong> that compliance with its orders is voluntary. Hard-headednessor tough-m<strong>in</strong>dedness better serves one’s values.While libertarians want to extend <strong>the</strong> voluntary aspects <strong>of</strong> society<strong>and</strong> government, <strong>the</strong>y should not delude <strong>the</strong>mselves about reality <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> human condition. Society <strong>and</strong> government are not <strong>and</strong> cannot be<strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> a social contract. eir justification rests on o<strong>the</strong>r considerations.e key element <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case for democracy, as I see it, is that democracylessens <strong>the</strong> necessity or desirability <strong>of</strong> violent rebellion. It makes <strong>the</strong>alternative, discussion, relevant. If a policy or a law really is oppressivelybad, citizens <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir political representatives may come to underst<strong>and</strong>why <strong>and</strong> may change it peacefully. is case for democracy is a far cry fromassert<strong>in</strong>g that all decisions made under democratic government are <strong>the</strong>reforemade <strong>in</strong> accordance with each citizen’s will, or his real will, or are tobe “considered” as hav<strong>in</strong>g been so made. We need not appeal to any fictionabout unanimous constitution agreement to waive unanimous agreementon specific issues.


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 505 Even several rights <strong>the</strong>orists who disavow utilitarianism do tacitly employa version similar to <strong>the</strong> one recommended <strong>in</strong> this paper. I ask <strong>the</strong>m toconduct a mental experiment. Suppose, just for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> argument, itcould be demonstrated that <strong>in</strong>sistence on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>violability <strong>of</strong> human rightsas <strong>the</strong>y conceive <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m would lead to general misery, whereas a pragmaticpolicy <strong>of</strong> respect<strong>in</strong>g rights or not as conditions seemed to recommendwould lead to general happ<strong>in</strong>ess. Would those <strong>the</strong>orists still <strong>in</strong>siston <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>violability <strong>of</strong> rights as <strong>the</strong> supreme goal to be upheld even at <strong>the</strong>cost <strong>of</strong> prevalent human misery?Perhaps <strong>the</strong>y would reply that this is a preposterous supposition <strong>and</strong>that respect for rights promotes human fulfillment <strong>and</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess, whereasa pragmatic attitude toward rights is an obstacle. Well, I th<strong>in</strong>k so too. Butunless <strong>the</strong> rights advocates do answer “yes” to <strong>the</strong> question, <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g onrights even at <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> general misery, <strong>the</strong>y are tak<strong>in</strong>g a broadly utilitarianstance. If <strong>the</strong>y answer as I th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong>y must, <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g on rightsbecause <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good consequences <strong>of</strong> uphold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> bad consequences<strong>of</strong> disregard<strong>in</strong>g or overrid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m. At <strong>the</strong> back <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir m<strong>in</strong>ds, atleast, <strong>the</strong>y must have some notion <strong>of</strong> a workable social order as an <strong>in</strong>dispensablemeans to happ<strong>in</strong>ess.Why do I care about <strong>the</strong> word “utilitarian”? Why am I anxious to p<strong>in</strong>that label onto everyone? Well, I do not care about <strong>the</strong> word as such. (AndI do dist<strong>in</strong>guish between versions <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism, although I do not f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>the</strong> supposed dist<strong>in</strong>ction between utilitarianism <strong>and</strong> consequentialism <strong>of</strong>much importance.) However, when a doctr<strong>in</strong>e that plausibly <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> accordwith established usage bears <strong>the</strong> label “utilitarian” comes under attack, itserves clear th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> communication to defend that doctr<strong>in</strong>e under itsown name ra<strong>the</strong>r than cast about for a new one. Play<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> latter game islike try<strong>in</strong>g to defend capitalism by <strong>in</strong>vent<strong>in</strong>g a new name for it. e gameseems to admit that <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e or system defended really is so odiousthat it must be referred to only by euphemisms.Robert Nozick, who avowedly just postulates rights without develop<strong>in</strong>gan argument for <strong>the</strong>m, provides an example <strong>of</strong> tacit utilitarianism <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> way he h<strong>and</strong>les <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> blackmail. Murray Rothbard, ano<strong>the</strong>rrights <strong>the</strong>orist, had put blackmail on a par with any o<strong>the</strong>r economic transaction;it would not be illegal <strong>in</strong> a free society (1962, vol. 1: p. 443 n. 49).Nozick counters that blackmail is wrong, ak<strong>in</strong> to <strong>the</strong> protection racket.He takes a step toward assess<strong>in</strong>g its effect on <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> society by


506 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophynot<strong>in</strong>g that it, like <strong>the</strong> racket, is an unproductive activity, whereas bonafide protective services are productive (Nozick 1974, pp. 85–86). (Rothbard1977, pp. 53–55, rejects Nozick’s dist<strong>in</strong>ction, but with arguments that strikeme as feeble, even though <strong>the</strong>y too are <strong>in</strong> part, unavowedly, utilitarian.)Tacit utilitarianism creeps <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> risky activities also.Suppose that your neighbor h<strong>and</strong>les explosives recklessly or plays Russianroulette with a cannon mounted on a turntable. Even if he has liability<strong>in</strong>surance, he harms you, probably by rais<strong>in</strong>g your own <strong>in</strong>surance rates,lower<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> your property, <strong>and</strong> strik<strong>in</strong>g fear <strong>and</strong> apprehension<strong>in</strong>to you. You might plausibly argue that your neighbor is <strong>in</strong>fr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g onyour rights, even though no explosion or cannon ball happens to damageyour house. Rothbard appears to brush aside such problems by ask<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>effect: If “fear” <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs’ “risky” activities is allowed to justify action aga<strong>in</strong>st<strong>the</strong>m, won’t any tyranny become justified? What about <strong>the</strong> greater risk <strong>of</strong>hav<strong>in</strong>g a state empowered to control activities it deems risky? (Rothbard1977, esp. pp. 48–50. e particular example used here is m<strong>in</strong>e, not Rothbard’sor Nozick’s, but it suits <strong>the</strong> general tenor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir discussion.)Nozick (1974, pp. 74–75, 78), on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, c<strong>and</strong>idly recognizesthat “Actions that risk cross<strong>in</strong>g ano<strong>the</strong>r’s boundary pose serious problemsfor a natural-rights position.... Impos<strong>in</strong>g how slight a probability <strong>of</strong> aharm that violates someone’s rights also violates his rights? ... It is difficultto imag<strong>in</strong>e a pr<strong>in</strong>cipled way <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> natural-rights tradition can draw<strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e to fix which probabilities impose unacceptably great risks upono<strong>the</strong>rs.” Many k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> actions do impose some degree <strong>of</strong> risk on o<strong>the</strong>rs.A society that prohibited <strong>the</strong>m all unless <strong>the</strong> actors had adequate means oradequate <strong>in</strong>surance to pay for possible harm would “ill fit a picture <strong>of</strong> a freesociety as one embody<strong>in</strong>g a presumption <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> liberty, under whichpeople permissibly could perform actions so long as <strong>the</strong>y didn’t harm o<strong>the</strong>rs<strong>in</strong> specified ways.”—Aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> good-society approach, utilitarianism!O<strong>the</strong>r utilitarian str<strong>and</strong>s are evident <strong>in</strong> Nozick’s book. His flexibilityabout property rights is an example. He supposes that a natural disasterdestroys <strong>the</strong> entire supply <strong>of</strong> water except one man’s, which is sufficient foreveryone. Under <strong>the</strong>se circumstances, o<strong>the</strong>r persons may take <strong>the</strong> wateror at least are not obliged to pay whatever exorbitant price its owner maydem<strong>and</strong>. Nozick appeals to <strong>the</strong> Lockean proviso that one man’s appropriation<strong>of</strong> a resource is justified only if it leaves enough <strong>and</strong> as good <strong>of</strong> thatresource for o<strong>the</strong>rs. He is not, <strong>in</strong> his own view, say<strong>in</strong>g that recognizedproperty rights may be overridden. Instead, “Considerations <strong>in</strong>ternal to<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> property itself, to its <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> acquisition <strong>and</strong> appropriation,


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 507provide <strong>the</strong> means for h<strong>and</strong>l<strong>in</strong>g such cases” (1974, pp. 180–181). Nozickadds ano<strong>the</strong>r example: “Similarly, an owner’s property right <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> onlyisl<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> an area does not allow him to order a castaway from a shipwreck<strong>of</strong>f his isl<strong>and</strong> as a trespasser, for this would violate <strong>the</strong> Lockean proviso.”It is mere word play, however, to wonder whe<strong>the</strong>r rights are overriddenor are def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place to be appropriate even for <strong>the</strong> catastrophecase. Nozick misapplies <strong>the</strong> Lockean proviso anyway, s<strong>in</strong>ce it concernssomeone’s orig<strong>in</strong>al acquisition <strong>of</strong> property, not its retention <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>face <strong>of</strong> changed circumstances <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r persons (Hodson 1977, esp. pp. 221,224–227).Nozick tacitly appeals to utilitarian considerations <strong>in</strong> fram<strong>in</strong>g his conception<strong>of</strong> property rights <strong>in</strong> a sufficiently complicated <strong>and</strong> flexible way toallow <strong>the</strong> actions that <strong>in</strong>tuition <strong>and</strong> utility would suggest <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> catastrophecase. He would have us permit acts that threaten to cross our boundaries—looselyspeak<strong>in</strong>g, violate our property rights—when certa<strong>in</strong> conditionsare satisfied, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g those <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> case <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> benefits <strong>in</strong>harm prevented or good produced far outweigh <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> fully compensat<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> person whose boundaries are crossed (Rab<strong>in</strong>owitz 1977, p. 93).Lawrence A. Scaff (1977, p. 202) looks beh<strong>in</strong>d Nozick’s assertion thatmoral <strong>the</strong>ory has priority <strong>in</strong> political discussions <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ds his language<strong>of</strong> moral <strong>the</strong>ory consist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “economic terms, calculations, categories,<strong>and</strong> assumptions. Moral discourse is suffused with cost-benefit analysis.us, even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> morality, all values carry a price tag.”Nozick (p. 79) adduces similar considerations <strong>in</strong> recommend<strong>in</strong>g costbenefitanalysis <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> test <strong>of</strong> compensation (actual or merely potential?)<strong>in</strong> decisions on which pollut<strong>in</strong>g activities to forbid <strong>and</strong> which to permit.He recognizes (p. 182) that he cannot derive a def<strong>in</strong>ite position on patentsfrom considerations <strong>of</strong> rights alone. Although a patent does not depriveo<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>of</strong> what would not exist if not for <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ventor’s work, knowledge<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> patented <strong>in</strong>vention does tend to discourage <strong>in</strong>dependent efforts tore<strong>in</strong>vent it. “Yet ... <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>vention, sometime latersomeone else would have come up with it. is suggests plac<strong>in</strong>g a timelimit on patents, as a rough rule <strong>of</strong> thumb to approximate how long itwould have taken, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>vention, for <strong>in</strong>dependentdiscovery.”Tibor Machan, avowedly a rights <strong>the</strong>orist, is ano<strong>the</strong>r tacit utilitarian.Instead <strong>of</strong> simply postulat<strong>in</strong>g or <strong>in</strong>tuit<strong>in</strong>g rights, he <strong>in</strong>quires <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> politicalpr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> a good society—good for man’s pursuit <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess orperhaps excellence, given his nature <strong>and</strong> his character as a moral agent.


508 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyMachan seeks to demonstrate that s<strong>in</strong>ce “each person is responsible toachieve his own happ<strong>in</strong>ess, that society that is suited for him is one <strong>in</strong>which his <strong>in</strong>dividual liberty is fully secured.... [I]t is only <strong>in</strong> such a freesociety that <strong>the</strong> moral agency, <strong>the</strong> freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> dignity, <strong>of</strong> each personcan be respected. us only <strong>in</strong> that k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> community can <strong>the</strong> morallife flourish” (1975, p. 100).Machan asks why someone who has <strong>the</strong> option <strong>of</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r tak<strong>in</strong>g fromano<strong>the</strong>r person or produc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> trad<strong>in</strong>g on his own should support <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>stitution <strong>of</strong> private property. He suggests essentially utilitarian answers,reasons why respect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitution <strong>of</strong> ownership is generally advantageouseven for <strong>the</strong> person <strong>in</strong> question. He concludes “that ownershipis a morally appropriate <strong>in</strong>stitution for human be<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> general.... [T]orely on his own work (<strong>and</strong>/or trade, creativity, <strong>in</strong>genuity, etc.) is betterfor <strong>the</strong> person than to live <strong>of</strong>f <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs” by steal<strong>in</strong>g or confiscat<strong>in</strong>g(pp. 133–134). F<strong>in</strong>ally, Machan’s approv<strong>in</strong>g characterization <strong>of</strong> AynR<strong>and</strong>’s doctr<strong>in</strong>e is tacitly utilitarian. R<strong>and</strong>, he says, defends “capitalismas morally right because human be<strong>in</strong>gs can work (trade, create, risk) for<strong>the</strong>ir own good only when <strong>and</strong> where it prevails.” She advocates it as “asystem that is good for human be<strong>in</strong>gs, morally good for <strong>the</strong>m, to choosefor <strong>the</strong>mselves” (Machan 1975, p. 136).Even Murray Rothbard has at least once (1973, pp. 23–25) lapsed <strong>in</strong>toa tacit utilitarianism, see<strong>in</strong>g it as “vitally necessary for each man’s survival<strong>and</strong> prosperity that he be free to learn, choose, develop his faculties, <strong>and</strong>act upon his knowledge <strong>and</strong> values.... [T]o <strong>in</strong>terfere with <strong>and</strong> cripple thisprocess by us<strong>in</strong>g violence goes pr<strong>of</strong>oundly aga<strong>in</strong>st what is necessary byman’s nature for his life <strong>and</strong> prosperity.” In <strong>the</strong> contractarian camp, John Rawls <strong>in</strong> effect says we should ask: “If agroup <strong>of</strong> ideally rational be<strong>in</strong>gs came toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> order to pick rules to govern<strong>the</strong>ir mutual relations, which rules would <strong>the</strong>y be compelled (by <strong>the</strong>power <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir rationality) to pick?” (restatement by Murphy 1977, p. 233).Well, what do those be<strong>in</strong>gs rationally take <strong>in</strong>to account? Facts <strong>of</strong> reality<strong>and</strong> applicable economic <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ories, presumably, toge<strong>the</strong>r with avalue judgment <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess, especially <strong>the</strong>ir own. Rawls assumesthat <strong>the</strong> parties negotiat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al position already accept a “th<strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good,” accord<strong>in</strong>g to which “liberty <strong>and</strong> opportunity, <strong>in</strong>come<strong>and</strong> wealth, <strong>and</strong> above all self-respect are primary goods,” goods conducive


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 509to happ<strong>in</strong>ess for persons almost regardless <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir specific personalitytraits <strong>and</strong> plans <strong>of</strong> life. is list <strong>of</strong> primary goods “is one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> premisesfrom which <strong>the</strong> choice <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> right is derived” (Rawls 1971,pp. 397, 433–434, <strong>and</strong> passim).When Rawls considers what pr<strong>in</strong>ciples would help make primarygoods available <strong>and</strong> so serve persons’ pursuit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir life plans, he is appeal<strong>in</strong>gto broadly utilitarian considerations. e same is true when he rhapsodizesover <strong>the</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> public commitment to avowed pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong>justice: “deliberate <strong>in</strong>justice <strong>in</strong>vites submission or resistance. Submissionarouses <strong>the</strong> contempt <strong>of</strong> those who perpetuate <strong>in</strong>justice <strong>and</strong> confirms <strong>the</strong>ir<strong>in</strong>tention, whereas resistance cuts <strong>the</strong> ties <strong>of</strong> community” (p. 384). In discuss<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> envy, Rawls notes <strong>the</strong> advantages <strong>of</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g a plurality<strong>of</strong> associations <strong>and</strong> many noncompar<strong>in</strong>g groups. His “pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong>justice are not likely to arouse ... envy ... to a troublesome extent.... Whata social system must not do clearly is to encourage propensities <strong>and</strong> aspirationsit is bound to repress <strong>and</strong> disappo<strong>in</strong>t. So long as <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>of</strong>special psychologies elicited by society ei<strong>the</strong>r supports its arrangementsor can be reasonably accommodated by <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>the</strong>re is no need to reconsider<strong>the</strong> choice <strong>of</strong> a conception <strong>of</strong> justice.... [T]he pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> justiceas fairness pass this test” (1971, pp. 536–537, 541; Rawls’s discussion <strong>of</strong> envycovers pp. 530–541). Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, Rawls’s whole method <strong>of</strong> reflective equilibrium—test<strong>in</strong>gtentative pr<strong>in</strong>ciples by how <strong>the</strong>y are likely to work out<strong>in</strong> practice <strong>and</strong> adjust<strong>in</strong>g both pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>and</strong> judgments about particularcases to achieve consistency between <strong>the</strong>m—is a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism.Rawls himself rejects this label. He recognizes that <strong>the</strong> parties <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>orig<strong>in</strong>al position might adopt some form <strong>of</strong> utility pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> social cooperation. Still, he says, it would be “a mistaketo call <strong>the</strong>se pr<strong>in</strong>ciples—<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y appear—utilitarian.In fact, <strong>the</strong> case for <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> justice is streng<strong>the</strong>ned if <strong>the</strong>y wouldbe chosen under different motivation assumptions.” Contract <strong>the</strong>ory couldeventually lead “to a deeper <strong>and</strong> more roundabout justification <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism”(1971, pp. 181–182). In say<strong>in</strong>g so, Rawls is forgett<strong>in</strong>g that his notion<strong>of</strong> a contract negotiated <strong>in</strong> an orig<strong>in</strong>al position is utter fiction.Buchanan’s w<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> contractarianism has already been described sufficientlyto suggest how it is tacitly utilitarian. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to its tenets, aneconomist is entitled to recommend a policy only tentatively, only as ahypo<strong>the</strong>sis that it is <strong>in</strong> accord with a unanimously made contract, or that itconceptually comm<strong>and</strong>s agreement, or that it could comm<strong>and</strong> agreement,presumably after a sufficient amount <strong>of</strong> sufficiently enlighten<strong>in</strong>g public


510 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophydiscussion. Well, on what basis could <strong>the</strong> economist expect or hope for<strong>the</strong> necessary degree <strong>of</strong> agreement? e probable effects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> contemplatedpolicy must surely figure prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> answer.Contractarians like Buchanan dist<strong>in</strong>guish between propound<strong>in</strong>g hypo<strong>the</strong>sesabout what policies could ideally comm<strong>and</strong> agreement <strong>and</strong> recommend<strong>in</strong>gpolicies because <strong>the</strong>y are expected to enhance social cooperation<strong>and</strong> so serve human happ<strong>in</strong>ess. e dist<strong>in</strong>ction seems operationallyempty to me.e pure doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> natural or human rights cuts analysis short ei<strong>the</strong>rby merely postulat<strong>in</strong>g rights as axioms or by questionably deriv<strong>in</strong>g rightsfrom supposedly axiomatic propositions that <strong>in</strong> fact require fur<strong>the</strong>r exam<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>the</strong>mselves. In truth we cannot <strong>in</strong>fer one <strong>in</strong>fallibly best set <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions<strong>and</strong> policies from one or more first pr<strong>in</strong>ciples whose implicationsare guaranteed never to clash. It is a “great illusion” <strong>in</strong> political philosophyto seek “solutions to <strong>in</strong>soluble problems.... [T]here is more than one basicpr<strong>in</strong>ciple that appeals to moral sense <strong>and</strong> for which good argument can bemade.... We live <strong>in</strong> a morally messy world. But it is <strong>the</strong> one we are stuckwith” (Gordon 1976, p. 589).Contractarianism rests on farfetched fictions. Or if it does not exactlyrest on <strong>the</strong>m, its rhetoric does abound <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m; <strong>and</strong> if it is stripped <strong>of</strong>its fictions <strong>and</strong> translated <strong>in</strong>to straightforward language, contractarianismturns out to be not much different from a form <strong>of</strong> utilitarianism.We can hardly make progress <strong>in</strong> social philosophy or policy analysis byadopt<strong>in</strong>g fictions as our first pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. While wish<strong>in</strong>g to enhance <strong>the</strong> voluntary<strong>and</strong> market-like aspects <strong>of</strong> government, for example, we must notbl<strong>in</strong>d ourselves to its essentially coercive character. Instead <strong>of</strong> beguil<strong>in</strong>gourselves with attractive myths, we can better serve our fundamental valuesby try<strong>in</strong>g to compare alternative sets <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions, alternative big pictures,avoid<strong>in</strong>g excessively narrow <strong>and</strong> short-run focus. Investigation, analysis,<strong>and</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> features <strong>and</strong> probable consequences <strong>of</strong> contemplated<strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> policies all are <strong>in</strong>dispensable aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> searchfor agreement—assum<strong>in</strong>g, for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> argument, that agreement were<strong>the</strong> touchstone <strong>of</strong> policy. Actually, agreement itself cannot form <strong>the</strong> decisivelyappeal<strong>in</strong>g substance <strong>of</strong> a state <strong>of</strong> affairs capable <strong>of</strong> comm<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g it.Discussion <strong>in</strong> search <strong>of</strong> agreement relies ideally on <strong>in</strong>vestigation, reason<strong>in</strong>g,<strong>and</strong> check<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> comparison—<strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary scientific process.


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 511is process is poles apart from dictatorship <strong>and</strong> from appeals to <strong>in</strong>fallible<strong>in</strong>sight. In this process, we can communicate better <strong>and</strong> guard betteraga<strong>in</strong>st misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>gs if we employ straightforward language.Conceivably <strong>the</strong> rights doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> contractarianism are not <strong>the</strong> onlyalternatives to <strong>the</strong> approach to policy espousal that I recommend. Ifso, those o<strong>the</strong>r alternatives deserve fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>and</strong> discussion.Meanwhile, I submit, a rules-utilitarianism or <strong>in</strong>direct utilitarianism—<strong>in</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r words, a good-society/comparative-<strong>in</strong>stitutions approach—turnsout to be <strong>the</strong> only one that st<strong>and</strong>s up under critical <strong>in</strong>spection.Adler, Mortimer J. e Time <strong>of</strong> Our Lives. New York: Holt, R<strong>in</strong>ehart, <strong>and</strong> W<strong>in</strong>ston,1970.Alex<strong>and</strong>er, Sidney S. “Human Values <strong>and</strong> Economists’ Values.” In Human Values<strong>and</strong> Economic Policy, edited by Sidney Hook. New York: New York UniversityPress, 1967.Bentham, Jeremy. “A Critical Exam<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Declaration <strong>of</strong> Rights.” 1843.In Bentham’s <strong>Political</strong> ought, edited by Bhikhu Parekh, 257–290. New York:Barnes & Noble, 1973.Blanshard, Br<strong>and</strong>. Reason <strong>and</strong> Goodness. New York: Macmillan, 1961.Broome, John. “Choice <strong>and</strong> Value <strong>in</strong> Economics.” Oxford Economic Papers, n.s.30 (November 1978): 313–333.Buchanan, James M. “Who Should Distribute What <strong>in</strong> a Federal System?” InRedistribution rough Public Choice, edited by H. Hochman <strong>and</strong> G. Peterson.New York: Columbia University Press, 1974.. e Limits <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1975a.. “Utopia, <strong>the</strong> M<strong>in</strong>imal State, <strong>and</strong> Entitlement.” Review <strong>of</strong> Anarchy, State,<strong>and</strong> Utopia, by Robert Nozick. Public Choice 23 (Fall 1975b): 121–126.. Freedom <strong>in</strong> Constitutional Contract. College Station: Texas A&M UniversityPress, 1977.. “Sources <strong>of</strong> Opposition to Constitutional Reform.” In ConstitutionalEconomics, edited by Richard B. McKenzie. Lex<strong>in</strong>gton, Mass.: Lex<strong>in</strong>gtonBooks, 1984.. “Natural <strong>and</strong> Artifactual Man.” Manuscript.


512 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy. “Why Does Justice Have Value?” Manuscript.Buchanan, James M., <strong>and</strong> Gordon Tullock. e Calculus <strong>of</strong> Consent. Ann Arbor:University <strong>of</strong> Michigan Press, 1962.Davis, Harry B. “Toward Justify<strong>in</strong>g Democracy.” e Key Reporter 33 (W<strong>in</strong>ter1967–1968): 2–4, 8.Edgeworth, Francis Y. Ma<strong>the</strong>matical Psychics. London: Kegan Paul, 1881. Photorepr<strong>in</strong>t, New York: Kelley, 1961.Edwards, Paul. e Logic <strong>of</strong> Moral Discourse. New York: Free Press, 1965.Fletcher, Joseph. Situation Ethics. 1 British ed. London: SCM Press, 1966.Gewirth, Alan. Reason <strong>and</strong> Morality. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1978.Gordon, Scott. “e New Contractarians.” Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> 84 ( June1976): 573–590.Gray, John N. “Social Contract, Community <strong>and</strong> Ideology.” In Democracy, Consensus& Social Contract, edited by Pierre Birnbaum, Jack Lively, <strong>and</strong> Gera<strong>in</strong>tParry. London <strong>and</strong> Beverly Hills: Sage Publications, 1978.. Mill on Liberty: A Defense. London <strong>and</strong> Boston: Routledge & KeganPaul, 1983.Gr<strong>in</strong>der, Walter. “Cross Currents.” Libertarian Review (May 1978): 9–10.Halévy, Élie. e Growth <strong>of</strong> Philosophic Radicalism. Translated by Mary Morris.Boston: Beacon Press, 1955.Hare, R.M. “Rawls’ eory <strong>of</strong> Justice.” In Read<strong>in</strong>g Rawls, edited by NormanDaniels. New York: Basic Books, n.d. (circa 1974).Harsanyi, John C. “Card<strong>in</strong>al Welfare, Individualistic Ethics <strong>and</strong> InterpersonalComparisons <strong>of</strong> Utility.” 1955. In Economic Justice, edited by E.S. Phelps,266–285. Baltimore: Pengu<strong>in</strong> Books, 1973.. <strong>Essays</strong> on Ethics, Social Behavior, <strong>and</strong> Scientific Explanation. Dordrecht<strong>and</strong> Boston: D. Reidel Publish<strong>in</strong>g Company, 1976.Hayek, Friedrich A. e Constitution <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1960.. Studies <strong>in</strong> Philosophy, Politics <strong>and</strong> Economics. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong>Chicago Press, 1967.


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 513. Freiburger Studien. Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen: Mohr, 1969.. New Studies <strong>in</strong> Philosophy, Politics, Economics, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong> Ideas.Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1978.. Law, Legislation <strong>and</strong> Liberty. Vols. 1–3. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress, 1976.Hazlitt, Henry. e Foundations <strong>of</strong> Morality. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>,1964.. “An LR Interview.” Libertarian Review (November 1978): 22–23.Hobbes, omas. Leviathan. 1651. In Great Books <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Western World, vol. 23.Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, 1952.Hodson, John D. “Nozick, Libertarianism, <strong>and</strong> Rights.” Arizona Law Review 19,no. 1 (1977): 212–227.Holcombe, R<strong>and</strong>all G. Public F<strong>in</strong>ance <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Political</strong> Process. Carbondale <strong>and</strong>Edwardsville: Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Ill<strong>in</strong>ois University Press, 1983.Hume, David. “Of <strong>the</strong> Orig<strong>in</strong>al Contract.” 1752. In Hume’s Ethical Writ<strong>in</strong>gs, editedby A. MacIntyre. New York: Collier Books, 1965.Kemp, J. Ethical Naturalism: Hobbes <strong>and</strong> Hume. London: Macmillan, 1970.Machan, Tibor. Human Rights <strong>and</strong> Human Liberties. Chicago: Nelson Hall, 1975.Mack, Erie. “An Outl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> a eory <strong>of</strong> Rights.” Manuscript, 1978.McCloskey, H.J. Meta-Ethics <strong>and</strong> Normative Ethics. e Hague: Mart<strong>in</strong>us Nijh<strong>of</strong>f,1969.Meyer, Frank S. In Defense <strong>of</strong> Freedom. Chicago: Regnery, 1962.Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism. 1863. In Selected Writ<strong>in</strong>gs, edited by M. Cowl<strong>in</strong>g.New York: New American Library, 1968.Mises, Ludwig von. Human Action. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press,1949.. eory <strong>and</strong> History. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1957.Murphy, Jeffrie C. “Rights <strong>and</strong> Borderl<strong>in</strong>e Cases.” Arizona Law Review 19, no. 1(1977): 228–241.Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, <strong>and</strong> Utopia. New York: Basic Books, 1974.


514 Part II: Politics <strong>and</strong> PhilosophyPaul, Jeffrey. “On <strong>the</strong> Foundations <strong>of</strong> Natural Rights.” Manuscript, 1978.Peirce, Charles S. “e Scientific Attitude <strong>and</strong> Fallibilism.” In Philosophical Writ<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>of</strong> Peirce, edited by Justus Buchler, 42–59. New York: Dover, 1955.Pettit, Philip. Judg<strong>in</strong>g Justice. London <strong>and</strong> Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul,1980.Philbrook, Clarence. “‘Realism’ <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal.” American Economic Review43 (December 1953): 846–859.Prescott, Peter S. Review <strong>of</strong> eophilus North, by ornton Wilder. Newsweek,22 October 1973.Rab<strong>in</strong>owitz, Joshua T. “Emergent Problems <strong>and</strong> Optimal Solutions.” ArizonaLaw Review 19, no. 1 (1977): 61–157.Rawls, John. “Two Concepts <strong>of</strong> Rules.” 1955. In Contemporary Utilitarianism,edited by M.D. Bayles, 59–98. Garden City: Anchor Books, 1968.. A eory <strong>of</strong> Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press <strong>of</strong> Harvard UniversityPress, 1971.Rothbard, Murray. Man, <strong>Economy</strong>, <strong>and</strong> State. 2 vols. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>,1962.. For a New Liberty. New York: Macmillan, 1973.. “Robert Nozick <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Immaculate Conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> State.” Journal<strong>of</strong> Libertarian Studies 1 (W<strong>in</strong>ter 1977).. e Ethics <strong>of</strong> Liberty. Atlantic Highl<strong>and</strong>s, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1982.Samuels, Warren J. “e Myths <strong>of</strong> Liberty <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Realities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> CorporateState: A Review Article.” Journal <strong>of</strong> Economic <strong>Is</strong>sues 10 (December 1976):923–942.Scaff, Lawrence A. “How Not to Do <strong>Political</strong> eory: Nozick’s Apology for <strong>the</strong>M<strong>in</strong>imal State.” Arizona Law Review 19, no. 1 (1977): 193–211.Schumpeter, Joseph A. History <strong>of</strong> Economic Analysis. New York: Oxford UniversityPress, 1954.Sen, Amartya K. Collective Choice <strong>and</strong> Social Welfare. San Francisco: Holden-Day,1970.Spencer, Herbert. e Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> Ethics. 1897. 2 vols. Indianapolis: Liberty Classics,1978.


Chapter : Rights, Contract, <strong>and</strong> Utility <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal 515Vanberg, Viktor. “Liberty, Efficiency <strong>and</strong> Agreement: e Normative Element<strong>in</strong> Libertarian <strong>and</strong> Contractarian Social Philosophy.” Manuscript, GeorgeMason University, n.d. (circa 1984 or 1985).Wiener, Philip P. “Charles S<strong>and</strong>ers Peirce.” In International Encyclopedia <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Social Sciences, vol. 11: 511–513. New York: Macmillan, 1968.Yeager, Lel<strong>and</strong> B. “Pareto Optimality <strong>in</strong> Policy Espousal.” Journal <strong>of</strong> LibertarianStudies 2 (Fall 1978): 199–216.. “Utility, Rights, <strong>and</strong> Contract: Some Reflections on Hayek’s Work.” Ine <strong>Political</strong> <strong>Economy</strong> <strong>of</strong> Freedom: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> Honor <strong>of</strong> F.A. Hayek, edited by KurtB. Leube <strong>and</strong> Albert H. Zlab<strong>in</strong>ger. Munich <strong>and</strong> Vienna: Philosophia Verlag,1984–1985.


IndexAAbortion issue, example <strong>of</strong> special<strong>in</strong>terests, Absorption approach, balance-<strong>of</strong>payments,Academic gameeconomics, –methodology <strong>and</strong> rigor, Activism. See also Regulation<strong>and</strong> democracy, hobbyists, judicial activism, Alex<strong>and</strong>er, Sidney S., elasticities,Allais, Mauriceacademic <strong>in</strong>centives <strong>and</strong> games,changes <strong>in</strong> tastes, taxes or policies,, <strong>in</strong>flation, l<strong>and</strong>: diversion <strong>and</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness towait, –savers <strong>and</strong> money, Allocation effects, <strong>in</strong>flation, America. See United States <strong>of</strong>AmericaAnarcho-capitalist-Lockean rights,Anderson, Benjam<strong>in</strong> M., goldst<strong>and</strong>ard, Appropriation. See Entitlements;Social justice; TaxationArmchair <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g, George, Arts, public fund<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>, Austria, gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, , Austrian School <strong>of</strong> Economics,–attention to process, bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle, complementary schools, coord<strong>in</strong>ation, criticisms <strong>of</strong>, –George, –, macroeconomics, marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas, –neoclassical economics, –strengths, –Authoritarianism, relativism, fallibilism,–Axiomsrights, Rothbard: rights, –BBalance-<strong>of</strong>-payments, tautology,–Bartley, William Warren, III,justificationism, Bellamy, Edward, uchronia, Biology, tautologies, Blackmail, Rothbard: propertyrights, Blanshard, Br<strong>and</strong>, political rights<strong>and</strong> duties, Block, Walter, morality <strong>and</strong> law,–Bohr, Niels, pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> complementarity,516


Index 517Booms. See Bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycleBoyle, Joseph M., determ<strong>in</strong>ism:self-referential problem <strong>of</strong>,Brita<strong>in</strong>, Hutt on postwar Brita<strong>in</strong>,Brockway, George, Keynes, Broome, John, contractarianism, Brown, E.H. Phelps, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory equationsystems, Buchanan, Jamesacademic <strong>in</strong>centives <strong>and</strong> games,–contractarianism, , neoclassical economics, social contract, –truth judgment, Budget constra<strong>in</strong>tslimits on government expenditures,as tautologies, Bureaucracy<strong>and</strong> government regulation, political economy, Bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycleeconometrics, macroeconomics, –, money: Hutt, CCagan, Philip, money: econometrics,Calculationknowledge, –Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek, socialism, Campbell, C.A., descriptive <strong>and</strong>prescriptive laws, Capitalcapital formation: money <strong>and</strong>,–<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory: subjectivism,–l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational capitalmovements, macroeconomics, will<strong>in</strong>gness to wait, Capital-import-<strong>and</strong>-export argumentsfor trade <strong>in</strong>tervention,general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, Capitalism, Kirzner: morality <strong>of</strong>capitalism <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it, –Cassel, Gustavgeneral equilibrium <strong>the</strong>oryequation systems, subjectivism, Causalitydeterm<strong>in</strong>ism, general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, Chamberl<strong>in</strong>, T.C., compet<strong>in</strong>ghypo<strong>the</strong>ses, Chance, ethics, –Churchill, W<strong>in</strong>ston, on voters <strong>and</strong>democracy, Citation <strong>in</strong>dexes, measur<strong>in</strong>g academicexcellence, , Classical school. See also NewClassical schoolClassification, tautologies, Clower, Robertcoord<strong>in</strong>ation, on general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, Keynes, , , methodology, Coase-Buchanan concept <strong>of</strong> cost, Coase, R.H., pric<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> socialism,Cognitive dissonance, Collateral effects, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Collectibles, Comparable worth fallacy, subjectivism,Compet<strong>in</strong>g hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, methodology,–Complementarily, pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong>,


518 IndexComplexityethics, –general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, Concepts, role <strong>in</strong> economics, Constitutional monarchy, versusdemocracy, –Consumersconsumer-surplus: generalequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, consumers’ sovereignty: subjectivism,knowledge <strong>and</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation, Contagion. See Bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycleContractarianismabout, –fictions, –tacit utilitarianism, –Contracts, utilitarianism: rights,contract <strong>and</strong> utility <strong>in</strong> policyespousal, –Conventions, science, Cooperation, political economy,–Coord<strong>in</strong>ationGeorge, –<strong>in</strong>tertemporal, macroeconomics, –<strong>and</strong> subjectivism, –Costs. See also Opportunity costCoase-Buchanan concept <strong>of</strong>, general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>of</strong> government regulation, Courts. See Judicial processCredit, <strong>and</strong> money, Credit-allocation, subjectivism, Credit-default swaps, Crowd<strong>in</strong>g out, government regulation<strong>and</strong>, –Crypticism, subjectivism, Custom unions, trade, Customer service, Kle<strong>in</strong>: how toensure hotel reservations arehonored, DDarrow, Clarence, determ<strong>in</strong>ism asfatalism, Davenport, H.J., monetary <strong>of</strong>depression, Decentralization, Austrian Economics,Decreas<strong>in</strong>g-cost, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Deficit f<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>g, subjectivism, Democracy. See also United States <strong>of</strong>America<strong>and</strong> liberty, –process, versus constitutional monarchy,–Democratic markets, Witmann,–Dependence effect, Galbraith, Descriptive <strong>and</strong> prescriptive laws,Determ<strong>in</strong>ismabout, extreme positions <strong>and</strong> partialdeterm<strong>in</strong>ism, –irrefutability <strong>of</strong>, –Schlick, –self-referential problem <strong>of</strong>, Discrim<strong>in</strong>ation argument, redistribution,Disequilibriummethodology, monetary <strong>the</strong>ory, , , <strong>the</strong>ories: Hutt, –Diversion, l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness towait, –Draft, military draft <strong>and</strong> subjectivism,Duhem, Pierre, models, Dynamic subjectivism, Lachmann,Dynasties. See Constitutionalmonarchy


Index 519EEconometrics, methodology,–Economics<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, –tautologies, –Economies-<strong>of</strong>-scale, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Efficiencysocialism, –subjectivism, Egalitarianism, <strong>and</strong> liberalism,–Ehrenhalt, Alan, U.S. politicalsystem, –Elasticities, balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments<strong>and</strong> exchange rates, Endogeneity, money, Energy crisis <strong>of</strong> 1974 <strong>and</strong> 1979,subjectivism <strong>and</strong>, Energy <strong>in</strong>dustry, example <strong>of</strong> crowd<strong>in</strong>gout, Enthoven, Ala<strong>in</strong>, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory equation systems,Entitlements, Kirzner, –EntrepreneurshipAustrian Economics on, Kirzner: morality <strong>of</strong> capitalism<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it, –Equation <strong>of</strong> exchange, –Equation systemsequilibrium <strong>and</strong> socialism, –general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, –Equilibrium. See also Disequilibrium;General equilibrium<strong>the</strong>oryKeynes, , methodology, , neoclassical economics, simultaneous equations <strong>and</strong>socialism, –Ersatz st<strong>and</strong>ards, –Essentialism, about, Ethics, –chance, –complexity, –determ<strong>in</strong>ism, , –ethical judgments <strong>and</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ism:Slote, free will, –, –Kirzner: morality <strong>of</strong> capitalism<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it, –Mises: ethics, rights <strong>and</strong> law,–political economy, Rothbard <strong>and</strong> Block: ethics <strong>and</strong>law, –Schlick on, –Euken, Walter, <strong>the</strong>ory, Exchange rateselasticities, fluctuat<strong>in</strong>g, Expectations, subjectivism, , , Exports, versus imports, External-economy arguments forprotection, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Extortion, Rothbard: propertyrights, FFallacy-monger<strong>in</strong>g, methodology,–Fallibilism, authoritarianism, relativism,–Fatalism, determ<strong>in</strong>ism as, Fluctuat<strong>in</strong>g exchange rates, Fragmentationgovernment regulation, policy drift <strong>and</strong> governmentregulation, France, alternative histories, Frank, Robert, <strong>in</strong>tersection <strong>of</strong>economics, psychology <strong>and</strong>ethics, Free willabout,


520 Indexdeterm<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> free will:Schlick, –ethics, –Freedom. See also LibertyHayek, –Fry, Maxwell J., l<strong>and</strong>: changes <strong>in</strong>tastes, taxes or policies, Fundamentalist Keynesianismabout, sav<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>and</strong> money,GGalbraith, J.K., dependence effect,General equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, –.See also Equilibriumabout, arguments <strong>in</strong> favor, –criticism, –equation systems, –fallacies clarified by, –Mises, Walras’s Law, General eory (Keynes), –,, Generic Consistency, Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong>,George, Henry, –Austrian School <strong>of</strong> economics,–<strong>in</strong>dependence <strong>of</strong>, knowledge, coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong>unplanned order, –methodology, –social philosophy, –socialism, value <strong>the</strong>ory, –Germany, alternative histories, Gerwirth, Alan, Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong>Generic Consistency, Giere, Ronald, models, Glazer, Nathan, judicial activism,Gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, –appeal <strong>of</strong>, –arguments pro <strong>and</strong> con, –attitudes, –climates <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion, –Hutt, noneconomic motives, –Government. See also Deficit f<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>g;Policy; Regulationbudget constra<strong>in</strong>ts, growth <strong>of</strong>, Hutt, utilitarian conception <strong>of</strong>, –Granger-causality tests, Great Brita<strong>in</strong>, alternative histories,Gr<strong>in</strong>der, Walter, utilitarianism, Grisez, Germa<strong>in</strong>, determ<strong>in</strong>ism:self-referential problem <strong>of</strong>,HHalmos, Paul, writ<strong>in</strong>g style, Hansen, Gary D., bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle:econometrics, Hard<strong>in</strong>, Garrett, <strong>in</strong>formation glut,Hayek, F.A.bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle, calculation, , , cooperation <strong>and</strong> reciprocation,dependence effect: Galbraith,free-market values, money, social justice, on socialism <strong>and</strong> freedom,–subjectivism, utilitarianism, Hazlitt, Henrydeterm<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> free will,–


Index 521ethics <strong>in</strong> Human Action, free will <strong>and</strong> responsibility,–natural rights, Health <strong>and</strong> safety, governmentregulations, High, Jack, on general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, History. See NarrativesHobart, R.E., extreme positions <strong>and</strong>partial determ<strong>in</strong>ism, Hobbes, omas, government <strong>and</strong>public policy, Hobbyists, government regulation<strong>and</strong>, Hoppe, Hans-Hermann, libertarianism<strong>and</strong> utilitarian ethics,Hotel reservations, Kle<strong>in</strong>: how toensure hotel reservations arehonored, Hotell<strong>in</strong>g-Lerner pric<strong>in</strong>g, socialism,Huerta de Soto, Jésus, on generalequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, Human Action (Mises), –Human capital, subjectivism, Hume, David, government <strong>and</strong>public policy, Hungary, gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, , ,–Hutt, William H., –disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ories, –endur<strong>in</strong>g value <strong>of</strong> message, Keynes: dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory, Keynes: sell<strong>in</strong>g ideas, market processes, micro orientation, money, –style <strong>of</strong> argument, –Hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, compet<strong>in</strong>g, –IIdentification problem, generalequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, Imports, versus exports, Incentives, for protest<strong>in</strong>g poor<strong>in</strong>justices <strong>and</strong> poor customerservice, Income distribution, marg<strong>in</strong>alproductivity<strong>the</strong>ory: George,Incomes, general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory,Individualism, government regulation<strong>and</strong> methodological<strong>in</strong>dividualism, Inflation, Allais: allocation effects,Insider <strong>in</strong>formation, Kirner, InstitutionsAustrian Economics <strong>and</strong>, macroeconomics, monetary system, prices, social cooperation, –Interdependence, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Interestcapital <strong>the</strong>ory: subjectivism,–will<strong>in</strong>gness to wait, Interventionism. See also Regulationpsychological roots <strong>of</strong>, IntuitionismKirzner <strong>and</strong> Hayek on, Mises, Investment, macroeconomics,–Irel<strong>and</strong>, Peter N., models, JJobs, ration<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> subjectivism, Judicial process<strong>and</strong> government regulation,–


522 IndexMises: ethics, rights <strong>and</strong> law,–Rothbard: axioms, rights <strong>and</strong>natural law, –<strong>and</strong> voluntary economic behavior,Justificationism, Bartley, KKant, Immanuel, free will <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>laws <strong>of</strong> nature, Keynes, John Maynard, –appraisal, crowd<strong>in</strong>g out o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>tellectualdevelopments, Hutt on, –<strong>in</strong>vestment, a Keynesian?, –last<strong>in</strong>g appeal, l<strong>in</strong>ger<strong>in</strong>g Keynesianism, a monetarist?, overreaction <strong>and</strong> label-shift<strong>in</strong>g,–re<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong>, <strong>the</strong> salesman, Keynesianism. See also FundamentalistKeynesianism; NewKeynesian schoolabout, K<strong>in</strong>g, Robert G., attitudes <strong>and</strong>pressures <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics,K<strong>in</strong>gs. See Constitutional monarchyKirzner, <strong>Is</strong>rael, on morality <strong>of</strong> capitalism<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it, –,Kle<strong>in</strong>, David, how to ensure goodcustomer service, Knight, Frank H., redistribution,Knowledgecalculation, –George, –<strong>and</strong> subjectivism, –Krugman, Paul, methodology, LLab<strong>and</strong>, David, market test <strong>of</strong> ideas,–Lachmann, Ludwig, dynamicsubjectivism, L<strong>and</strong>, –changes <strong>in</strong> tastes or policies,–diversion <strong>and</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness to wait,–George: rent, <strong>in</strong>ternational capital movements,ownership <strong>of</strong>, –, L<strong>and</strong>esberger, Julius, gold st<strong>and</strong>ard,Lange-Taylor solution, socialism, Laws. See Judicial processLeadership, U.S. political system,–Leijonhufvud, Axel, Keynes, ,, Lerner, Abba P.money <strong>and</strong> price stick<strong>in</strong>ess, socialism, Liberalismattitudes to gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, <strong>and</strong> egalitarianism, –Libertariansconstitutional monarchy versusdemocracy, –Hoppe <strong>and</strong> utilitarian ethics, utilitarian conception <strong>of</strong>, Liberty. See also Freedomcoexistence with democracy, <strong>and</strong> democracy, –Liquidity preferenceHutt, Keynes, Loan guarantees, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Lucas Project,


Index 523Lucas, Robert E., Jr., models, Lucas supply function, MMachan, Tibor, utilitarianism, Macroeconomics, –about, –appraisal <strong>and</strong> opportunities,–attitudes <strong>and</strong> pressures, bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle, –, capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest, coord<strong>in</strong>ation, –credit <strong>and</strong> money, imperfections <strong>of</strong> reality, –<strong>in</strong>stitutions, macroeconomic disorder: Hutt,methodology, –monetary disorder, –money <strong>and</strong> price stick<strong>in</strong>ess,–sav<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>and</strong> money,–time element, Marg<strong>in</strong>al-cost-pric<strong>in</strong>ggeneral equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, socialism, , Marg<strong>in</strong>al-productivity <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong>functional <strong>in</strong>come distribution,George, <strong>Market</strong> value, for property seizedunder em<strong>in</strong>ent doma<strong>in</strong>:subjectivism, <strong>Market</strong>place <strong>of</strong> ideas, –about, Austrian School <strong>of</strong> Economics,–<strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> Lab<strong>and</strong>-<strong>and</strong>-Tollison-type th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g,methodology, st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>and</strong> ersatz st<strong>and</strong>ards,–style <strong>of</strong> argument, truth <strong>and</strong> games, worries about, Marshall, Alfred, socialism, Materialism, versus subjectivism <strong>in</strong>policy, –Ma<strong>the</strong>matical physics, conventions<strong>in</strong> science, Ma<strong>the</strong>maticsmethodology <strong>and</strong> rigor, tautologies, McCloskey, Donaldclarity versus obscurantism, fallacy-monger<strong>in</strong>g, methodology, models, utilitarianism, Meltzer, Allan, Keynes, Menger, Anton, gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, ,, Menger, Carl, gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, ,Merit, Hayek, Methodology, –academic <strong>in</strong>centives <strong>and</strong> games,–attitudes <strong>and</strong> pressures, Austrian Economics, clarity versus obscurantism,–compet<strong>in</strong>g hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, –econometrics, –fallacy-monger<strong>in</strong>g, –George, , –macroeconomics, –market analogy, models, –o<strong>the</strong>r evidence, preach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> countermethodology,–rigor, –Micro orientation, Hutt, Military draft, subjectivism,


524 IndexMises, Ludwig vonbus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle, , calculation <strong>and</strong> socialism, calculation debates, economic <strong>the</strong>ory as an “a priori”science, , ethics, rights <strong>and</strong> law, –,–general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, prices, , , propositions, socialism, –ModelsLucas, methodology, –Modigliani, Franco, socialism, Monarchy, constitutional monarchyversus democracy, –Monetary system, United States <strong>of</strong>America, Monetary <strong>the</strong>orybalance-<strong>of</strong>-payments, capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment, disorder, –general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, monetary disequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory,, , narrative <strong>and</strong> statistical history,Moneybus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle: econometrics, capital formation <strong>and</strong>, –costs: subjectivism, <strong>and</strong> credit, econometrics, endogeneity, Hayek, Hutt, –macroeconomics, –price stick<strong>in</strong>ess, –Money prices, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Morality. See EthicsNNarratives<strong>and</strong> statistical history: monetarists,urchronia <strong>and</strong> alternative history,–Natural law, , , –Natural rights, Rothbard, Natural sciences, tautologies,–Neoclassical school <strong>of</strong> economics,Rosen on, New Classical schoolabout, coord<strong>in</strong>ation, New Keynesian schoolabout, attitudes <strong>and</strong> pressures, coord<strong>in</strong>ation, Nihilism, subjectivism, Nonempiricism, Austrian Economics,Normative <strong>and</strong> positive propositions,Nozick, Robertentitlements, utilitarianism, –OObjective ethics, Rothbard <strong>and</strong>Mises on, Obscurantism versus clarity, –Opportunity cost, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Optimum conditions, socialism, Overregulation. See RegulationPPartial determ<strong>in</strong>ism, extreme positions<strong>and</strong>, –Partial-equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, generalequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, Pigou effect,


Index 525Platt, John R., compet<strong>in</strong>g hypo<strong>the</strong>ses,Po<strong>in</strong>caré, Henriconventions <strong>in</strong> science, science compared to a library,Policygovernment <strong>and</strong> public policy,, l<strong>and</strong>ownership, –policy drift <strong>and</strong> governmentregulation, subjectivism, –utilitarianism: rights, contract<strong>and</strong> utility <strong>in</strong> policy espousal,–<strong>Political</strong> economy, –. See alsoRegulationbureaucracy, cooperation <strong>and</strong> reciprocation,–democratic process, ethics, government <strong>and</strong> public policy,, liberty <strong>and</strong> democracy, –political process, positive <strong>and</strong> normative propositions,vot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> special <strong>in</strong>terests, <strong>Political</strong> obligation, utilitarianism,–<strong>Political</strong> philosophy. See also SocialphilosophyBlanchard: political rights <strong>and</strong>duties, socialism, <strong>Political</strong> system. See also UnitedStates <strong>of</strong> Americapoliticians <strong>and</strong> governmentregulation, –Wittman: democratic markets,–Popper, Karlchance <strong>and</strong> ethics, on essentialism, ethics <strong>and</strong> complexity, Population control, Positive <strong>and</strong> normative propositions,Preach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> methodology,–Predictions, Austrian Economics on,Prescott, Edward C., bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle:econometrics, Prescriptive <strong>and</strong> descriptive laws, Prices. See also Money pricescalculation, Hayek on free-market values, Hutt, <strong>in</strong>stitutions, Kirzner <strong>and</strong> Nozick on, Mises, prices system <strong>and</strong> subjectivism, socialism, , –stick<strong>in</strong>ess, –subjectivism, Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> complementarity, Bohr,Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> Generic Consistency,Gerwirth, Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, economics <strong>and</strong>, –Priorities, subjectivism, Process, Austrian School <strong>of</strong> Economicsattention to, Productivity, George, –Pr<strong>of</strong>it, Kirzner: morality <strong>of</strong> capitalism<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it, –Property, subjectivism <strong>and</strong> marketvalue when seized underem<strong>in</strong>ent doma<strong>in</strong>, Property rightscrowd<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>and</strong> governmentregulation, George,


526 IndexRothbard: axiomatic approach,–subjectivism, PropositionsMises, positive <strong>and</strong> normative propositions,Protection, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Prowse, Michael, constitutionalmonarchy, Publication <strong>of</strong> articlesAustrian School <strong>of</strong> Economics,market test <strong>of</strong> ideas, Purchas<strong>in</strong>g-power argument, generalequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, RR<strong>and</strong>, Ayn, market test <strong>of</strong> ideas, R<strong>and</strong>omness, ethics, –Rational expectationsHutt, methodology, Rational ignorance, Rawls, John, utilitarianism, , ,–Real-balance effect, Real-bills doctr<strong>in</strong>e, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Real-bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle school, Real disturbances, Recoord<strong>in</strong>ation, Redistributiondiscrim<strong>in</strong>ation argument, egalitarianism <strong>and</strong> liberalism, Regulation, –bureaucracy <strong>and</strong>, costs, courts’ role <strong>in</strong>, –crowd<strong>in</strong>g out, –flaw <strong>in</strong> political system, –fragmented decisions <strong>and</strong>agglomerated activities, hobbyists <strong>and</strong>, methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism,policy drift, policy implications, politicians, –special <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>and</strong> syn<strong>the</strong>ticmajorities, voters, –Relative poverty, Relativism, fallibilism, authoritarianism,–RightsMises: ethics, rights <strong>and</strong> law,–Rothbard: axioms, –Rothbard: natural law <strong>and</strong>natural rights, utilitarianism: rights, contract<strong>and</strong> utility <strong>in</strong> policy espousal,–value judgments, e Road to Serfdom (Hayek), ,–Robb<strong>in</strong>s, Lionel, socialism, Rock<strong>of</strong>f, Hugh, gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, Rosen, Sherw<strong>in</strong>, Austrian Economics,–Rothbard, Murrayaxioms about rights, –Hoppe <strong>and</strong> anarcho-Lockeanrights, l<strong>and</strong>ownership, Mises <strong>and</strong> objective ethics, Mises <strong>and</strong> utilitarianism,–, morality <strong>and</strong> law, –natural law <strong>and</strong> natural rights,–, on subjectivism, Russia, gold st<strong>and</strong>ard, , ,


Index 527SSalerno, Joseph T.calculation, prices <strong>and</strong> calculation, Samuelson, Paul, tautologies, Sargent, omas, on general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Sav<strong>in</strong>gsl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness to wait, macroeconomics, –real capital formation, sav<strong>in</strong>g preference: Hutt, Say’s Law, Hutt on, Scarcityapplied to methodology, Sowell: politics <strong>and</strong> economics <strong>of</strong>scarcity, Schlick, Moritzdeterm<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> free will,–extreme positions <strong>and</strong> partialdeterm<strong>in</strong>ism, Schmidtz, David, entitlements, Schoeck, Helmut, <strong>in</strong>centives forprotest<strong>in</strong>g poor <strong>in</strong>justices <strong>and</strong>poor customer service, Schumpeter, JosephGeorge, liberty <strong>and</strong> democracy, Science, conventions <strong>in</strong>, Scientism, subjectivism, Scott, Anthony, l<strong>and</strong>: changes <strong>in</strong>tastes, taxes or policies, Secondary effects, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Secondh<strong>and</strong>ism, Separation <strong>of</strong> powers, Shock effect, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, Simultaneous equations. See EquationsystemsSlote, Michael, ethical judgments<strong>and</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ism, Slumps. See Bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycleSocial contract, Buchanan, –Social cooperationabout, comparative <strong>in</strong>stitutions,–market test <strong>of</strong> ideas, Social justice, Hayek, Social philosophy. See also <strong>Political</strong>philosophyGeorge, –socialism, Socialismcalculation, efficiency, –George, Hayek, –subjectivism, Sowell, omas, politics <strong>and</strong> economics<strong>of</strong> scarcity, Special <strong>in</strong>terests, <strong>and</strong> governmentregulation, St<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>and</strong> ersatz st<strong>and</strong>ards,–Subjectivism, –about, capital <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>the</strong>ory, –conclud<strong>in</strong>g thoughts, degrees <strong>of</strong>, –economic <strong>the</strong>ory, –George, –knowledge <strong>and</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation,–materialism versus subjectivism<strong>in</strong> policy, –policy, –Subsidies, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, TTariffs, general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory,Tastes, l<strong>and</strong>ownership, –Tautologies, –about, –


528 Indexbalance-<strong>of</strong>-payments, –conventions <strong>in</strong> science, economics, –examples <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural sciences,–Walras’s Law, –Taxationl<strong>and</strong>, l<strong>in</strong>k to expenditures, tax cuts <strong>and</strong> budget limits, eory, Euken, rift, l<strong>and</strong>ownership, TimeAustrian Economics <strong>and</strong>, George, –macroeconomics, Tollefsen, Olaf, determ<strong>in</strong>ism: selfreferentialproblem <strong>of</strong>, Tollison, Robert, market test <strong>of</strong>ideas, –Trade, custom unions, Trade <strong>in</strong>terventions, general equilibrium<strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>Truth</strong>. See <strong>Market</strong>place <strong>of</strong> ideas<strong>Truth</strong> judgment, Buchanan, UUchronia, –Ultrasubjectivists, United States <strong>of</strong> Americaalternative histories, democratic process, , –monetary system, political process, Unplanned order, George, –UtilitarianismMises, , , –political obligation, –rights, contract <strong>and</strong> utility <strong>in</strong>policy espousal, –Rothbard <strong>and</strong> natural rights, VValue judgmentsrights, <strong>and</strong> value-free propositions:Austrian Economics, Value <strong>the</strong>oryGeorge, –Hayek, V<strong>and</strong>berg, Viktor, contractarianism,VAR technique, Vaughn, Karencontractarianism, Mises <strong>and</strong> utilitarianism, Vickrey, William, multi-part pric<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> socialism, Voluntary compliance, Vot<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> special <strong>in</strong>terests, vote-trad<strong>in</strong>g process, voters <strong>and</strong> government regulation,–W<strong>in</strong>ston Churchill on voters <strong>and</strong>democracy, WWait<strong>in</strong>g, l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness towait, –Walras’s Law, , –, Warburton, Clark, Keynes, Wealth effect, Welfare properties, subjectivism, Williamson, Steve, models, W<strong>in</strong>ks, Rob<strong>in</strong>, historical evidence,Wittmann, Donald, democraticmarkets, –Workers’ sovereignty, subjectivism,World War I <strong>and</strong> II, alternativehistories, Wright, R<strong>and</strong>all, models, Writ<strong>in</strong>g style, Halmos,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!