24.11.2012 Views

Complete Issue in PDF - Abstracta

Complete Issue in PDF - Abstracta

Complete Issue in PDF - Abstracta

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Comments on The Possibility of Knowledge<br />

What then does Cassam do? He first proposes perception as the means of choice<br />

on level 1 (cf. 158). Now, s<strong>in</strong>ce perceptual knowledge of other m<strong>in</strong>ds is perceptual<br />

knowledge, that would actually require him to deal, on level 2, with Stroud’s U once<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>. On the (counterfactual) assumption that Stroud’s U could be removed with the<br />

help of Dretske’s notion of epistemic perception, Cassam would then have to go on to<br />

remove, on level 2′, the second-order obstacles that are specific to epistemic perception<br />

as a means to knowledge of other m<strong>in</strong>ds.<br />

Cassam, however, skips this <strong>in</strong>itial step and just takes epistemic perception<br />

directly as the level 1 means to knowledge of other m<strong>in</strong>ds. Consequently, on level 2<br />

(rather than 2′), he removes a range of obstacles to epistemic perception as a means to<br />

such knowledge. That’s ok as far as it goes, but also here Cassam gives us reason to<br />

raise our eyebrows when he realises that his way of deal<strong>in</strong>g with these obstacles ‘blur[s]<br />

the divid<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>e between the obstacle-overcom<strong>in</strong>g and obstacle-dissipat<strong>in</strong>g responses’;<br />

which, to be sure, he th<strong>in</strong>ks is ‘not necessarily a bad th<strong>in</strong>g’ (164). Well, it may not be a<br />

bad th<strong>in</strong>g for the specific response at hand, but it certa<strong>in</strong>ly is for the general schema.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, Cassam discusses two enabl<strong>in</strong>g conditions for epistemic perception as a<br />

means to knowledge of other m<strong>in</strong>ds, the ‘Identity Condition’ and the ‘Spatiality<br />

Condition’ (171). On p. 172, Cassam realises that the Identity Condition, like the<br />

enabl<strong>in</strong>g conditions <strong>in</strong> the HPsap example, once aga<strong>in</strong> raises the question whether<br />

expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g how enabl<strong>in</strong>g conditions are fulfilled does not really amount to remov<strong>in</strong>g<br />

obstacles, i. e. whether the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between levels 2 and 3 can be upheld. Cassam this<br />

time devotes an entire section (5.4) to the issue, argu<strong>in</strong>g (just like <strong>in</strong> the case of HPsap)<br />

that there is a difference <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tuitiveness between regular obstacles and those aris<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from enabl<strong>in</strong>g conditions; however, here as there, I can discern no such difference. In<br />

any event, while Cassam goes out of his way to save the dist<strong>in</strong>ction, he ends up say<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that ‘there is no need to go to the stake for the sake of ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a sharp dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

between Levels 2 and 3’ (186). That is a bit of a blow to the charitable reader who up to<br />

here has tried hard to make sense of the dist<strong>in</strong>ction, and of Cassam’s general schema as<br />

a whole.<br />

We see then that Cassam’s general structural schema of EHPQs starts to wobble<br />

badly even when applied – with care – to his own example cases. Now, Cassam can be<br />

expected to meet such criticism simply by ton<strong>in</strong>g down the strength of his claims.<br />

54

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!