24.11.2012 Views

Complete Issue in PDF - Abstracta

Complete Issue in PDF - Abstracta

Complete Issue in PDF - Abstracta

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Comments on Possibility of Knowledge<br />

Consider<strong>in</strong>g that most epistemologists claim that their theories of knowledge<br />

capture our everyday concept of knowledge and best concord with our everyday use of<br />

the word “knowledge” and with our pretheoretical <strong>in</strong>tuitions about knowledge claims,<br />

the claim that most of these theories are revisionist may easily be misunderstood as the<br />

claim that these theories are all wrong. For this reason I want to emphasize two po<strong>in</strong>ts.<br />

First, as I have just noted, theories are only revisionist if the obstacles they dissipate are<br />

not just products of mistaken theoriz<strong>in</strong>g. So unless these pr<strong>in</strong>ciples really are as<br />

<strong>in</strong>tuitively plausible as some epistemologists believe, theories which offer dissipat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>stead of overcom<strong>in</strong>g strategies are not revisionist at all.<br />

The second po<strong>in</strong>t I want to emphasize is that a theory of knowledge can be<br />

revisionist or conservative <strong>in</strong> more than one way. So far I discussed only the acceptance<br />

or denial of certa<strong>in</strong> epistemic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. Let’s call a theory which denies an <strong>in</strong>tuitively<br />

plausible epistemic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple pr<strong>in</strong>ciple-revisionist and a theory which accepts it<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple-conservative. In these terms scepticism may be the only completely pr<strong>in</strong>cipleconservative<br />

epistemology. But of course an epistemologist cannot simply rely on what<br />

epistemic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples people <strong>in</strong>tuitively assent to; we also have to consider our everyday<br />

use of the word “knowledge” and our pretheoretical <strong>in</strong>tuitions concern<strong>in</strong>g knowledge<br />

claims. Call a theory which respects our everyday use of “knowledge” as well as our<br />

<strong>in</strong>tuitive judgments about knowledge claims use-conservative and a theory which for<br />

some reason discards them use-revisionist. As we all know, when asked, people<br />

subscribe to many pr<strong>in</strong>ciples which they fail to live up to. Thus, there is no reason to<br />

expect that pr<strong>in</strong>ciple-conservatism will always go hand <strong>in</strong> hand with use-conservatism.<br />

It is therefore perfectly possible that some theory of knowledge best captures our<br />

everyday use of “knowledge” and our <strong>in</strong>tuitions about knowledge-claims while at the<br />

same time be<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple-revisionist. In fact, one possible explanation of the sceptical<br />

paradox is that no theory of knowledge can be pr<strong>in</strong>ciple-conservative and useconservative<br />

at the same time. Thus deny<strong>in</strong>g (1) is certa<strong>in</strong>ly use-revisionist, while<br />

deny<strong>in</strong>g (2) or (3) is probably pr<strong>in</strong>ciple-revisionist. 110<br />

110 Thanks to Andreas Erz for comments on an earlier draft of this paper.<br />

98<br />

Simon Sauter<br />

Heidelberg University<br />

Simon.Sauter@stud.uni-heidelberg.de

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!