10.07.2015 Views

A Survey of Generalized Basic Logic Al- gebras

A Survey of Generalized Basic Logic Al- gebras

A Survey of Generalized Basic Logic Al- gebras

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

2 Nikolaos Galatos and Peter Jipsenin the study <strong>of</strong> hoops, as introduced by Büchi and Owens [BO]. This showsthat it is a natural condition, appearing not only in logic, but also in algebra.While residuation corresponds to the left-continuity <strong>of</strong> a t-norm on the unitinterval, basic logic captures exactly the semantics <strong>of</strong> continuous t-norms onthe unit interval, as was shown later.On a personal note, we would like to mention that Petr Hájek’s bookhas been influential in developing some <strong>of</strong> the theory <strong>of</strong> residuated latticesand also connecting it with the study <strong>of</strong> logical systems. The book hadjust appeared shortly before a seminar on residuated lattices started at VanderbiltUniversity, organized by Constantine Tsinakis and attended by bothauthors <strong>of</strong> this article. The naturality <strong>of</strong> the definition <strong>of</strong> divisibility and itsencompassing nature became immediately clear and generalized BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>(or GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>) were born. These are residuated lattices (not necessarilycommutative, integral, contractive or bounded) that satisfy divisibility: ifx ≤ y, there exist z,w with x = zy = yw. It turns out that the representablecommutative bounded GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> are exactly the BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>. In otherwords, GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> are a generalization <strong>of</strong> BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> that focuses on andretains the divisibility property. Examples include lattice-ordered groups,their negative cones, (generalized) MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> and Heyting al<strong>gebras</strong>.Despite their generality, GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> decompose into direct products <strong>of</strong>lattice-ordered groups and integral GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, so it is these two subvarietiesthat are <strong>of</strong> main interest. From [Mu86] it follows that MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> arecertain intervals in abelian l-groups and in [GT05] it is shown that GMVal<strong>gebras</strong>are certain convex sublattices in l-groups. <strong>Al</strong>so, BL-chains (thebuilding blocks <strong>of</strong> BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>) are essentially ordinal sums <strong>of</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> l-groups (MV-chains and product chains). It is interesting that recent workhas shown that al<strong>gebras</strong> in many natural classes <strong>of</strong> GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> (includingcommutative, as well as k-potent) are made from parts <strong>of</strong> l-groups put (inthe form <strong>of</strong> a poset product) into a Heyting algebra grid. The poset productdecomposition does not work for all GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, but it is an open problemto find BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> that are not locally parts <strong>of</strong> l-groups, if such al<strong>gebras</strong>exist.2 BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> as residuated lattices2.1 Residuated latticesA residuated lattice is a structure (L, ∧, ∨, ·, \,/,1), where (L, ∧, ∨) is alattice, (L, ·,1) is a monoid and the law <strong>of</strong> residuation holds; i.e., for alla,b,c ∈ L,a · b ≤ c ⇔ b ≤ a\c ⇔ a ≤ c/b.Sometimes the expression x → y is used for x\y, while y ← x (or x y)is used for y/x. The corresponding operations are called the residuals <strong>of</strong>


A <strong>Survey</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Generalized</strong> <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> 3multiplication. FL-al<strong>gebras</strong> are expansions (L, ∧, ∨, ·, \,/,1,0) <strong>of</strong> residuatedlattices with an additional constant operation 0.Residuated lattices and FL-al<strong>gebras</strong> are called commutative if multiplicationis commutative, integral if 1 is the greatest element, representable (orsemilinear) if they are subdirect products <strong>of</strong> chains, and divisible if theysatisfy:If x ≤ y, there exist z,w such that x = zy = yw.In commutative residuated lattices we have x\y = y/x, and we denote thecommon value by x → y.An FL o -algebra, also known as a bounded residuated lattice, is an FLalgebrain which 0 ≤ x for all x. In this case 0 is also denoted by ⊥. Moreover,it turns out that ⊤ = 0/0 = 0\0 is the top element. Integral FL o -al<strong>gebras</strong>are also known as FL w -al<strong>gebras</strong>, and in the presence <strong>of</strong> commutativity asFL ew -al<strong>gebras</strong>. 1 For more on residuated lattices see [GJKO].2.2 BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>It turns out that BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, as defined by P. Hájek, are exactly the representableand divisible al<strong>gebras</strong> within the class <strong>of</strong> integral commutativebounded residuated lattices (i.e., within FL ew -al<strong>gebras</strong>).THEOREM 1 [BT03] [JT02] A residuated lattice is representable iff it satisfies[z\((x ∨ y)/x)z ∧ 1] ∨ [w((x ∨ y)/y)/w ∧ 1] = 1.The next result then follows easily.COROLLARY 2 An integal, commutative residuated lattice is representableiff it satisfies (x → y) ∨ (y → x) = 1 (prelinearity).P. Hájek defined BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> using the prelinearity condition, which capturesrepresentability in the integral, commutative case. He also used thesimplified form <strong>of</strong> divisibility x∧y = x(x→y), which we will see is equivalentto the general form in the integral commutative case; actually integrality followsfrom this particular form <strong>of</strong> divisibility, by setting x = 1. The variety(i.e. equational class) <strong>of</strong> BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> is denoted by BL.Representable Heyting al<strong>gebras</strong>, known as Gödel al<strong>gebras</strong>, are exactly theidempotent (x 2 = x) BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>. Moreover, Chang’s MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> are exactlythe involutive ((x→0)→0 = x) BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>. For additional subvarieties<strong>of</strong> FL w see Table 1 and 3, as well as Figure 1.1 The subscripts e, w are from the names <strong>of</strong> the rules exchange and weakening in pro<strong>of</strong>theory that correspond to commutativity and integrality.


4 Nikolaos Galatos and Peter Jipsendivisible x(x\(x ∧ y)) = x ∧ y = ((x ∧ y)/x)xprelinear x\y ∨ y\x = 1 = x/y ∨ y/xlinear or chain x ≤ y or y ≤ xintegral x ≤ 1bottom 0 ≤ xcommutative xy = yxidempotent xx = xTable 1. Some residuated lattice axioms2.3 <strong>Al</strong>gebraizationP. Hájek defined basic logic BL via a Hilbert-style system, whose sole inferencerule is modus ponens; see Table 2.(sf) (ϕ → ψ) → ((ψ → χ) → (ϕ → χ)) (suffixing)(int) (ϕ · ψ) → ϕ (integrality)(com) (ϕ · ψ) → (ψ · ϕ) (commutativity)(conj) (ϕ · (ϕ → ψ)) → (ψ · (ψ → ϕ)) (conjunction)(·→) ((ϕ · ψ) → χ) → (ϕ → (ψ → χ))(→·) (ϕ → (ψ → χ)) → ((ϕ · ψ) → χ)(→pl) ((ϕ → ψ) → χ) → (((ψ → ϕ) → χ) → χ) (arrow prelinearity)(bot) 0 → ϕϕ ∧ ψ := ϕ · (ϕ → ψ)(conjunction definition)ϕ ∨ ψ := [(ϕ → ψ) → ψ] ∧ [(ψ → ϕ) → ϕ] (disjunction definition)¬ϕ := ϕ → 0 (negation definition)1 := 0 → 0 (unit definition)ϕϕ → ψψ(mp)Table 2. Hajek’s basic logic.Using this system, one defines as usual the notion <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> from assumptions.If ψ is a propositional formula in the language <strong>of</strong> BL, and Φ is aset <strong>of</strong> such formulas, then Φ ⊢ BL ψ denotes that ψ is provable in BL from(non-logical, i.e., no substitution instances are allowed) assumptions Φ.The following results states that ⊢ BL is algebraizable (in the sense <strong>of</strong> Blokand Piggozzi [BP89]) with respect to the variety BL <strong>of</strong> BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>. It followsdirectly from the more general algebraization <strong>of</strong> substructural logics by


A <strong>Survey</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Generalized</strong> <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> 5FL wpsMTLGBL wFL ewpsBLMTLGBL ewpsMVBLHAMVGA.GA 4GA 3ΠGA 2BAOFigure 1. Some subvarieties <strong>of</strong> FL w ordered by inclusion


6 Nikolaos Galatos and Peter JipsenFL wFL ewGBL wGBL ewpsMTLMTLpsBLBLHApsMVMVMV nGAGA nΠBAFL-al<strong>gebras</strong> with weakening= integral residuated lattices with bottomFL w -al<strong>gebras</strong> with exchange= commutative integral residuated lattices with bottomGBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> with weakening= divisible integral residuated lattices with bottomGBL w -al<strong>gebras</strong> with exchange= commutative GBL w -al<strong>gebras</strong>pseudo monoidal t-norm al<strong>gebras</strong>= integral residuated lattices with bottom and prelinearitymonoidal t-norm al<strong>gebras</strong>= psMTL with commutativitypseudo BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>= psMTL with divisibilitybasic logic al<strong>gebras</strong>= MTL with divisibilityHeyting al<strong>gebras</strong>= residuated lattices with bottom and x ∧ y = xypseudo MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>= psBL with x ∨ y = x/(y\x) = (x/y)\xMV-al<strong>gebras</strong> or ̷Lukasiewicz al<strong>gebras</strong>= BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> that satisfy ¬¬x = x= commutative pseudo MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> generated by n + 1-chains= subdirect products <strong>of</strong> the n + 1-element MV-chainGödel al<strong>gebras</strong> or linear Heyting al<strong>gebras</strong>= BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> that are idempotent= Heyting al<strong>gebras</strong> with prelinearityGödel al<strong>gebras</strong> generated by n + 1-chains= subdirect products <strong>of</strong> the n + 1-element Heyting chainproduct al<strong>gebras</strong>= BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> that satisfy ¬¬x ≤ (x → xy) → y(¬¬y)Boolean al<strong>gebras</strong>= Heyting al<strong>gebras</strong> that satisfy ¬¬x = x= MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> that are idempotentTable 3. Some subvarieties <strong>of</strong> FL w


A <strong>Survey</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Generalized</strong> <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> 7residuated lattices given in [GO06].As usual, propositional formulas in BL are identified with terms <strong>of</strong> BL.Recall that for a set E ∪ {s = t} <strong>of</strong> equations, E |= BL s = t (s = t is asemantial consequence <strong>of</strong> E with respect to BL) denotes that for every BLalgebraB and for every assignment f into B (i.e., for every homomorphismfrom the formula/term algebra into B), if f(u) = f(v) for all (u = v) ∈ E,then f(s) = f(t).THEOREM 3 For every set Φ ∪ {ψ} <strong>of</strong> propositional formulas and every setE ∪ {s = t} <strong>of</strong> equations,• Φ ⊢ BL ψ iff {ϕ = 1 : ϕ ∈ Φ} |= BL ψ = 1• E |= BL s = t iff {(u → v) ∧ (v → u) : (u = v) ∈ E} ⊢ BL (s → t) ∧ (t → s)• ϕ ⊣⊢ (ϕ → 1) ∧ (1 → ϕ)• s = t =||= BL (s → t) ∧ (t → s) = 1As a corollary we obtain that the lattice <strong>of</strong> axiomatic extensions <strong>of</strong> BL isdually isomorphic to the subvariety lattice <strong>of</strong> BL.3 Fuzzy logics and triangular norms: retainingrepresentabilityTruth in a fuzzy logic comes in degrees. In a so-called standard model, truthvalues are taken to be real numbers from the interval [0,1], while logicalconnectives <strong>of</strong> arity n are interpreted as functions from [0,1] n to [0,1]. Inparticular, multiplication in a standard model is assumed to be continuousand a triangular norm (t-norm), namely a binary operation on the interval[0,1] that is associative, commutative, monotone and has 1 as its unit element.It is easy to see that any such continuous t-norm defines a BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>tructure on [0,1]. In fact, BL is complete with respect to continuous t-norms, as proved in [CEGT], where it is shown algebraically that the variety<strong>of</strong> BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> is generated by all continuous t-norms.̷Lukasiewicz t-norm (L(x,y) = max{x+y−1,0}), product t-norm (Π(x,y) =xy), and Gödel t-norm (G(x,y) = min{x,y}), define three special standardmodels <strong>of</strong> BL. The corresponding logics that extend BL are denoted by ̷L,GL and Π.Chang [Ch59] proved that the standard model given by L(x,y) generatesthe variety <strong>of</strong> MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>. Thus, ̷L is precisely the infinite-valued̷Lukasiewicz logic and it is axiomatized relatively to BL by ¬¬ϕ → ϕ. <strong>Al</strong>so,GL is Gödel logic, namely the superintuitionistic logic defined by adding toBL the axiom ϕ → ϕ 2 , and it is the smallest superintuitionistic logic that is


8 Nikolaos Galatos and Peter Jipsenalso a fuzzy logic. Finally, Π is product logic and is defined relatively to BLby ¬¬ϕ → (((ϕ → (ϕ · ψ)) → (ψ · ¬¬ψ)); see [Ci01].It is easy to see that, due to the completeness <strong>of</strong> [0,1], a t-norm is residuatediff it is left-continuous; divisibility provides right-continuity, in thiscontext. It turns out that the variety <strong>of</strong> representable FL ew -al<strong>gebras</strong> is generatedby left-continuous t-norms; see [JM02]. The corresponding logic iscalled monoidal t-norm logic or MTL. Uninorm logic, on the other hand,corresponds to representable FL eo -al<strong>gebras</strong>, i.e., integrality is not assumed.The introduction <strong>of</strong> BL lead to the study <strong>of</strong> such general fuzzy logics, whererepresentability is the main defining property, while divisibility is droppedalltogether. In the rest <strong>of</strong> the survey, we focus on generalizations that retainthe divisibility property.4 <strong>Generalized</strong> BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>: retaining divisibility4.1 GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>A generalized BL-algebra (or GBL-algebra for short) is defined to be a divisibleresiduated lattice. We begin with presenting some equivalent reformulations<strong>of</strong> divisibility:If x ≤ y, there exist z,w such that x = zy = yw.LEMMA 4 [GT05] The following are equivalent for a residuate lattice L.1. L is a GBL-algebra.2. L satisfies ((x ∧ y)/y)y = x ∧ y = y(y\(x ∧ y)).3. L satisfies the identities (x/y ∧ 1)y = x ∧ y = y(y\x ∧ 1).Pro<strong>of</strong>. (1) ⇔ (2): Assume that L is a GBL-algebra and x,y ∈ L. Sincex ∧ y ≤ y, there exist z,w such that x ∧ y = zy = yw. Since zy ≤ x ∧ y, wehave z ≤ (x ∧ y)/y, so x ∧ y = zy ≤ ((x ∧ y)/y)y ≤ x ∧ y, by residuation, i.e.((x ∧ y)/y)y = x ∧ y. Likewise, wo obtain the second equation. The otherdirection is obvious.(2) ⇔ (3): By basic properties <strong>of</strong> residuation, we gety ∧ x = y(y\(y ∧ x)) = y(y\y ∧ y\x) = y(1 ∧ y\x).Likewise, we get the opposite identity.Conversely assume (3). Note that for every element a ≥ 1, we have 1 =a(a\1 ∧ 1) ≤ a(a\1) ≤ 1; so, a(a\1) = 1. For a = x\x, we have a 2 = a,by properties <strong>of</strong> residuation and 1 ≤ a. Thus, a = (1/a)a 2 = (1/a)a = 1.


10 Nikolaos Galatos and Peter JipsenConsequently, negative cones <strong>of</strong> l-groups are equationally defined. Aswe mentioned, cancellative GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> in general (witout the asumption<strong>of</strong> integrality) include l-groups as well. However, we will see that everycancellative GBL-algebra is the direct product <strong>of</strong> an l-group and a negativecone <strong>of</strong> an l-group. More generally, we will see that a similar decompositionexists for arbitrary GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>.4.3 GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong>Recall that an MV-algebra is a commutative bounded residuated lattice thatsatisfies the identity x ∨ y = (x → y) → y. This identity implies that theresiduated lattice is also integral, divisible and representable, hence MVal<strong>gebras</strong>are examples <strong>of</strong> BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>.It turns out that MV-algrebras are intervals in abelian l-groups. If G =(G, ∧, ∨, ·, \,/,1) is an abelian l-group and a ≤ 1, then Γ(G,a) = ([a,1], ∧, ∨, ◦, →,1,a)is an MV-algebra, where x ◦ y = xy ∨ a, and x → y = x\y ∧ 1. (A versionwhere a ≥ 1 also yields an MV-algebra.) If M is an MV-algebra then thereis an abelian l-group G and an element a ≤ 1 such that M ∼ = Γ(G,a); see[Ch59], [Mu86].<strong>Generalized</strong> MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>, or GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong>, are generalizations <strong>of</strong> MVal<strong>gebras</strong>in a similar way as GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> generalize BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, and aredefined as residuated lattices that satisfy x/((x∨y)\x) = x∨y = (x/(x∨y))\x.As with GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong> have alternative characterizations.LEMMA 8 [BCGJT] A residuated lattice is a GMV algebra iff it satisfiesx ≤ y ⇒ y = x/(y\x) = (x/y)\x.THEOREM 9 [BCGJT] Every GMV-algebra is a GBL-algebra.Pro<strong>of</strong>. We make use <strong>of</strong> the quasi-equational formulation from the precedinglemma. Assume x ≤ y and let z = y(y\x). Note that z ≤ x and y\z ≤ x\z,hencex\z = ((y\z)/(x\z))\(y\z)= (y\(z/(x\z)))\(y\z) since (u\v)/w = u\(v/w)= (y\x)\(y\z) since z ≤ x ⇒ x = z/(x\z)= (y(y\x)\z since u\(v\w) = vu\w= z\z.Therefore x = z/(x\z) = z/(z\z) = z, as required. The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> x = (x/y)yis similar.LEMMA 10 [BCGJT]


A <strong>Survey</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Generalized</strong> <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> 11(i) Every integral GBL-algebra satisfies the identity (y/x)\(x/y) = x/yand its opposite.(ii) Every integral GMV-algebra satisfies the identity x/y ∨y/x = e and itsopposite.(iii) Every integral GMV-algebra satisfies the identities x/(y∧z) = x/y∨x/z,(x ∨ y)/z = x/z ∨ y/z and the opposite ones.(iv) Every commutative integral GMV-algebra is representable.It will be shown in Section 5 that the assumption <strong>of</strong> integrality in condition(iv) is not needed. They do not have to be intervals, but they are convexsublattices in l-groups. More details can be found in [GT05], while thestandard reference for MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> is [CDM00].Ordinal sum constructions and decompositions have been used extensivelyfor ordered algebraic structures, and we recall here the definition for integralresiduated lattices. Usually the ordinal sum <strong>of</strong> two posets A 0 ,A 1 is definedas the disjoint union with all elements <strong>of</strong> A 0 less than all elements <strong>of</strong> A 1(and if A 0 has a top and A 1 has a bottom, these two elements are <strong>of</strong>tenidentified). However, for most decomposition results on integral residuatedlattices a slightly different point <strong>of</strong> view is to replace the element 1 <strong>of</strong> A 0 bythe algebra A 1 . The precise definition for an arbitrary number <strong>of</strong> summandsis as follows.Let I be a linearly ordered set, and for i ∈ I let {A i : i ∈ I} be a family<strong>of</strong> integral residuated lattices such that for all i ≠ j, A i ∩ A j = {1} and 1 isjoin irreducible in A i . Then the ordinal sum ⊕ ⋃i∈I A i is defined on the seti∈I A i by⎧⎪⎨ x ·i y if x,y ∈ A i for some i ∈ Ix · y = x if x ∈ A i \ {1} and y ∈ A j where i < j⎪⎩y if y ∈ A i \ {1} and x ∈ A j where i < j.The partial order on ⊕ i∈I A i is the unique partial order ≤ such that 1 is thetop element, the partial order ≤ i on A i is the restriction <strong>of</strong> ≤ to A i , and ifi < j then every element <strong>of</strong> A i \ {1} precedes every element <strong>of</strong> A j . Finally,the lattice operations and the residuals are uniquely determined by ≤ andthe monoid operation.It not difficult to check that this construction again yields an integralresiduated lattice, and that it preserves divisibility and prelinearity. If I ={0,1} with 0 < 1 then the ordinal sum is simply denoted by A 0 ⊕ A 1 . Theassumption that 1 is join-irreducible can be omitted if A 1 has a least elementm, since if x ∧ 0 y = 1 in A 0 then x ∧ y still exists in A 0 ⊕ A 1 and has value


12 Nikolaos Galatos and Peter Jipsenm. If 1 is join-reducible in A 0 and if A 1 has no minimum then the ordinalsum cannot be defined as above. However an “extended” ordinal sum maybe obtained by taking the ordinal sum <strong>of</strong> (A 0 ⊕ 2) ⊕ A 1 , where 2 is the2-element MV-algebra.The following representation theorem was proved by Agliano and Montagna[AM03].THEOREM 11 Every linearly ordered commutative integral GBL-algebra Acan be represented as an ordinal sum ⊕ i∈I A i <strong>of</strong> linearly ordered commutativeintegral GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong>. Moreover A is a BL-algebra iff I has a minimum i 0and A i0 is bounded.Thus ordinal sums are a fundamental construction for BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, and commutativeintegral GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong> are the building blocks.4.4 Pseudo BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> and pseudo MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>Pseudo BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> [DGI02] [DGI02b] are divisible prelinear integral boundedresiduated lattices, i.e., prelinear integral bounded GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>. Similarly,pseudo MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> are integral bounded GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong> (in this case prelinearityholds automatically). Hence BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> and MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> are exactlythe commutative pseudo BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> and pseudo MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> respectively,but the latter do not have to be commutative. They do not have to be representableeither, as prelinearity is equivalent to representability only under theassumption <strong>of</strong> commutativity. By a fundamental result <strong>of</strong> [Dv02], all pseudoMV-al<strong>gebras</strong> are obtained from intervals <strong>of</strong> l-groups, as with MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> inthe commutative case. Hence any nonrepresentable l-group provides examples<strong>of</strong> nonrepresentable pseudo MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>. The tight categorical connectionsbetween GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong> and l-groups (with a strong order unit) haveproduced new results and interesting research directions in both areas [Ho05],[DH07], [DH09].The relationship between noncommutative t-norms and pseudo BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>is investigated in [FGI01]. In particular it is noted that any continuous t-normmust be commutative. Hájek [Ha03a] shows that noncommutative pseudoBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> can be constructed on “non-standard” unit intervals, and in[Ha03b] it is shown that all BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> embed in such pseudo BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>.As for Boolean al<strong>gebras</strong>, Heyting al<strong>gebras</strong> and MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>, the constant0 can be used to define unary negation operations −x = 0/x and ∼x = x\0.For pseudo BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, these operations need not coincide. Pseudo MVal<strong>gebras</strong>are involutive residuated lattices which means the negations satisfy∼−x = x = −∼x. However, for pseudo BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> this identity need nothold, and for quite some time it was an open problem whether the weakeridentity ∼−x = −∼x might also fail. Recently it was noted in [DGK09] that


A <strong>Survey</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Generalized</strong> <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> 15RLRRLGBLIRLGMVRGBLIRRLIGBLCGBLRGMVIGMVIRGBLCRGBLCIGBLBH BrWHIRGMVLG LG − RBrRLG RLG − RBr 4RBr 3RBr 2CLG CLG − GBAOFigure 2. Some subvarieties <strong>of</strong> RL ordered by inclusion


16 Nikolaos Galatos and Peter Jipsen5 Decomposition <strong>of</strong> GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>The structure <strong>of</strong> l-groups has been studied extensively in the past decades.The structure <strong>of</strong> GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong> has essentially been reduced to that <strong>of</strong> l-groups (with a nucleus operation), and GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong> are parts <strong>of</strong> l-groups.The study <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> has proven to be much moredifficult. Nevertheless, the existing results indicate that ties to l-groups exist.We first show that the study <strong>of</strong> GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> can be reduced to the integralcase, by showing that every GBL-algebra is the direct product <strong>of</strong> an l-groupand an integral GBL-algebra. This result was proved in the dual setting <strong>of</strong>DRl-monoids in [Ko96] and independently in the setting <strong>of</strong> residuated latticesin [GT05]. With hindsight, the later result can, <strong>of</strong> course, be deduced byduality from the former. The presentation below follows [GT05].An element a in a residuated lattice L is called invertible if a(a\1) = 1 =(1/a)a, and it is called integral if 1/a = a\1 = 1. We denote the set <strong>of</strong>invertible elements <strong>of</strong> L by G(L) and the set <strong>of</strong> integral elements by I(L).Recall that a positive element a is an element that satisfies a ≥ 1.Note that a is invertible if and only if there exists an element a −1 suchthat aa −1 = 1 = a −1 a. In this case a −1 = 1/a = a\1. It is easy to see thatmultiplication by an invertible element is an order automorphism.LEMMA 13 [GT05] Let L be a GBL-algebra.(i) Every positive element <strong>of</strong> L is invertible.(ii) L satisfies the identities x/x = x\x = 1.(iii) L satisfies the identity 1/x = x\1.(iv) For all x,y ∈ L, if x ∨ y = 1 then xy = x ∧ y.(v) L satisfies the identity x = (x ∨ 1)(x ∧ 1).Pro<strong>of</strong>. For (i), note that if a is a positive element in L, a(a\1) = 1 = (1/a)a,by definition; that is, a is invertible. For (ii), we argue as is the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>Lemma 4.By (ii) and residuation, we have x(1/x) ≤ x/x = 1, hence 1/x ≤ x\1.Likewise, x\1 ≤ 1/x.For (iv), we have x = x/1 = x/(x∨y) = x/x∧x/y = 1∧x/y = y/y∧x/y =(y ∧ x)/y. So, xy = ((x ∧ y)/y)y = x ∧ y.Finally, by Lemma 4, (1/x ∧ 1)x = x ∧ 1. Moreover, by (i) x ∨ 1 isinvertible and (x ∨ 1) −1 = 1/(x ∨ 1) = 1/x ∧ 1. Thus, (x ∨ 1) −1 x = x ∧ 1, orx = (x ∨ 1)(x ∧ 1).


A <strong>Survey</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Generalized</strong> <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> 17The following theorem shows that if L is a GBL-algebra then the sets G(L)and I(L) are subuniverses <strong>of</strong> L. We denote the corresponding subal<strong>gebras</strong>by G(L) and I(L).THEOREM 14 [GT05] Every GBL-algebra L is isomorphic to G(L) ×I(L).Pro<strong>of</strong>. We begin with a series <strong>of</strong> claims.Claim 1: G(L) is a subuniverse <strong>of</strong> L.Let x,y be invertible elements. It is clear that xy is invertible. Additionally,for all x,y ∈ G(L) and z ∈ L, z ≤ x −1 y ⇔ xz ≤ y ⇔ z ≤ x\y. It followsthat x\y = x −1 y, hence x\y is invertible. Likewise, y/x = yx −1 is invertible.Moreover, x ∨ y = (xy −1 ∨ 1)y. So, x ∨ y is invertible, since every positiveelement is invertible, by Lemma 13(i), and the product <strong>of</strong> two invertibleelements is invertible. By properties <strong>of</strong> residuation, x ∧ y = 1/(x −1 ∨ y −1 ),which is invertible, since we have already shown that G(L) is closed underjoins and the division operations.Claim 2: I(L) is a subuniverse <strong>of</strong> L.Note that every integral element a is negative, since 1 = 1/a implies 1 ≤1/a and a ≤ 1. For x,y ∈ I(L), we get:1/xy = (1/y)/x = 1/x = 1, so xy ∈ I(L).1/(x ∨ y) = 1/x ∧ 1/y = 1, so x ∨ y ∈ I(L).1 ≤ 1/x ≤ 1/(x ∧ y) ≤ 1/xy = 1, so x ∧ y ∈ I(L).1 = 1/(1/y) ≤ 1/(x/y) ≤ 1/(x/1) = 1/x = 1, so x/y ∈ I(L).Claim 3: For every g ∈ (G(L)) − and every h ∈ I(L), g ∨ h = 1.Let g ∈ (G(L)) − and h ∈ I(L). We have 1/(g ∨h) = 1/g ∧1/h = 1/g ∧1 =1, since 1 ≤ 1/g. Moreover, g ≤ g ∨ h, so 1 ≤ g −1 (g ∨ h). Thus, by theGBL-algebra identities and properties <strong>of</strong> residuation1 = (1/[g −1 (g ∨ h)])[g −1 (g ∨ h)]= ([1/(g ∨ h)]/g −1 )g −1 (g ∨ h)= (1/g −1 )g −1 (g ∨ h)= gg −1 (g ∨ h)= g ∨ h.Claim 4: For every g ∈ (G(L)) − and every h ∈ I(L), gh = g ∧ h.In light <strong>of</strong> Lemma 13(iv), g −1 h = (g −1 h∨1)(g −1 h∧1). Multiplication by gyields h = (h∨g)(g −1 h∧1). Using Claim 3, we have gh = g(g −1 h∧1) = h∧g,since multiplication by an invertible element is an order automorphism.Claim 5: For every g ∈ G(L) and every h ∈ I(L), gh = hg.


A <strong>Survey</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Generalized</strong> <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> 196 Further results on the structure <strong>of</strong> GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>In this section we briefly summarize results from a series <strong>of</strong> papers [JM06][JM09] [JM10]. The collaboration that lead to these results started when thesecond author and Franco Montagna met at a wonderful ERCIM workshopon S<strong>of</strong>t Computing, organized by Petr Hájek in Brno, Czech Republic, in2003. This is yet another example how Petr Hájek’s dedication to the field<strong>of</strong> fuzzy logic has had impact far beyond his long list <strong>of</strong> influential researchpublications.6.1 Finite GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> are commutativeLEMMA 17 If a is an idempotent in an integral GBL-algebra A, then ax =a ∧ x for all x ∈ A. Hence every idempotent is central, i.e. commutes withevery element.Pro<strong>of</strong>. Suppose aa = a. Then ax ≤ a ∧ x = a(a\x) = aa(a\x) = a(a ∧ x) ≤ax.In an l-group only the identity is an idempotent, hence it follows fromthe decomposition result mentioned above that idempotents are central in allGBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>.In fact, using this lemma, it is easy to see that the set <strong>of</strong> idempotents in aGBL-algebra is a sublattice that is closed under multiplication. In [JM06] itis proved that this set is also closed under the residuals.THEOREM 18 The idempotents in a GBL-algebra A form a subalgebra,which is the largest Brouwerian subalgebra <strong>of</strong> A.By the results <strong>of</strong> the preceding section, the structure <strong>of</strong> any GBL-algebrais determined by the structure <strong>of</strong> its l-group factor and its integral GBLalgebrafactor. Since only the trivial l-group is finite, it follows that any finiteGBL-algebra is integral. A careful analysis <strong>of</strong> one-generated subal<strong>gebras</strong> ina GBL-algebra gives the following result.THEOREM 19 [JM06] Every finite GBL-algebra and every finite pseudo-BLalgebrais commutative.Since there exist noncommutative GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, such as any noncommutativel-group, the next result is immediate.COROLLARY 20 The varieties GBL and psBL are not generated by theirfinite members, and hence do not have the finite model property.


20 Nikolaos Galatos and Peter Jipsen〈⊤, ⊤〉BBB ∂⊥ † = ⊤Figure 3.As mentioned earlier, BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> are subdirect products <strong>of</strong> ordinal sums<strong>of</strong> commutative integral GMV-chains, and a similar result holds without commutativityfor representable GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>. So it is natural to ask to whatextent GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> are determined by ordinal sums <strong>of</strong> GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong> andHeyting al<strong>gebras</strong>. We briefly recall a construction <strong>of</strong> a GBL-algebra thatdoes not arise from these building blocks.For a residuated lattice B with top element ⊤, let B ∂ denote the dualposet <strong>of</strong> the lattice reduct <strong>of</strong> B. Now we define B † to be the ordinal sum <strong>of</strong>B ∂ and B ×B, i.e., every element <strong>of</strong> B ∂ is below every element <strong>of</strong> B ×B (seeFigure 3). Note that B † has ⊤ as bottom element, so to avoid confusion, wedenote this element by ⊥ † . A binary operation · on B † is defined as follows:〈a,b〉 · 〈c,d〉= 〈ac,bd〉〈a,b〉 · u = u/au · 〈a,b〉 = b\uu · v = ⊤ = ⊥ †Note that even if B is a commutative residuated lattice, · is in general noncommutative.LEMMA 21 • For any residuated lattice B with top element, the algebraB † defined above is a bounded residuated lattice.


A <strong>Survey</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Generalized</strong> <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> 21• If B is nontrivial, then B † is not a GMV-algebra, and if B is subdirectlyirreducible, so is B † .• B † is a GBL-algebra if and only if B is a cancellative GBL-algebra.6.2 The Blok-Ferreirim decomposition result for normalGBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>Building on work <strong>of</strong> Büchi and Owens [BO], Blok and Ferreirim [BF00] provedthe following result.PROPOSITION 22 Every subdirectly irreducible hoop is the ordinal sum <strong>of</strong> aproper subhoop H and a subdirectly irreducible nontrivial Wajsberg hoop W.This result was adapted to BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> in [AM03]. To discuss furtherextensions to GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> we first recall some definitions about filters andcongruences in residuated lattices.A filter <strong>of</strong> a residuated lattice A is an upward closed subset F <strong>of</strong> A whichcontains 1 and is closed under the meet and the monoid operation. A filter Fis said to be normal if aF = Fa for all a ∈ A, or equivalently if a\(xa) ∈ Fand (ax)/a ∈ F whenever x ∈ F and a ∈ A. A residuated lattice is said tobe normal if every filter <strong>of</strong> it is a normal filter. A residuated lattice is saidto be n-potent if it satisfies x n+1 = x n , where x n = x · ...·x (n times). Notethat n-potent GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> are normal ([JM09]).In every residuated lattice, the lattice <strong>of</strong> normal filters is isomorphic tothe congruence lattice: to any congruence θ one associates the normal filterF θ = ↑{x : (x,1) ∈ θ}. Conversely, given a normal filter F, the set θ F <strong>of</strong> allpairs (x,y) such that x\y ∈ F and y\x ∈ F is a congruence such that theupward closure <strong>of</strong> the congruence class <strong>of</strong> 1 is F. Hence a residuated latticeis subdirectly irreducible if and only if it has a smallest nontrivial normalfilter.In [JM09] the following result is proved.THEOREM 23 (i) Every subdirectly irreducible normal integral GBL-algebrais the ordinal sum <strong>of</strong> a proper subalgebra and a non-trivial integral subdirectlyirreducible GMV-algebra.(ii) Every n-potent GBL-algebra is commutative and integral.A variety V has the finite embeddability property (FEP) iff every finitepartial subalgebra <strong>of</strong> an algebra in V partially embeds into a finite algebra<strong>of</strong> V. The FEP is stronger than the finite model property: for a finitelyaxiomatized variety V, the finite model property implies the decidability <strong>of</strong>the equational theory <strong>of</strong> V, while the FEP implies the decidability <strong>of</strong> the


A <strong>Survey</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Generalized</strong> <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> 23THEOREM 26 Every n-potent GBL-algebra embeds into the poset product <strong>of</strong>a family <strong>of</strong> finite and n-potent MV-chains.Every normal GBL-algebra embeds into a poset product <strong>of</strong> linearly orderedintegral bounded GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong> and linearly ordered l-groups.For Heyting al<strong>gebras</strong> the above theorem reduces to the well-known embeddingtheorem into the complete Heyting algebra <strong>of</strong> all upward closed subsets <strong>of</strong>some poset.Various properties can be imposed on poset products to obtain embeddingtheorems for other subclasses <strong>of</strong> GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>. The follow result from [JM10]collects several <strong>of</strong> them.THEOREM 27 A GBL-algebra is• a BL-algebra iff it is isomorphic to a subalgebra A <strong>of</strong> a poset product⊗i∈I A i such that(a) each A i is a linearly ordered MV-algebra,(b) I = (I, ≤) is a root system, i.e. every principal filter <strong>of</strong> I is linearlyordered, and(c) the function on I which is constantly equal to 0 is in A;• an MV-algebra iff it is isomorphic to a subalgebra A <strong>of</strong> a poset product⊗i∈I A i such that conditions (a) and (c) above hold and(d) I = (I, ≤) is a poset such that ≤ is the identity on I;• representable iff it is embeddable into a poset product ⊗ i∈I A i such thateach A i is a linearly ordered GMV-algebra and (b) holds;• an abelian l-group iff it is embeddable into a poset product ⊗ i∈I A isuch that each A i is a linearly ordered abelian l-group and condition(d) above holds;• n-potent iff it is embeddable into a poset product <strong>of</strong> linearly orderedn-potent MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>;• a Heyting algebra iff it is isomorphic to a subalgebra A <strong>of</strong> a poset product⊗ i∈I A i where condition (c) holds and in addition(e) every A i is the two-element MV-algebra;• a Gödel algebra iff it is isomorphic to a subalgebra A <strong>of</strong> a poset product⊗i∈I A i where (b), (c) and (e) hold;• a Boolean algebra iff it is isomorphic to a subalgebra A <strong>of</strong> a poset product⊗ i∈I A i where (c), (d) and (e) hold.


24 Nikolaos Galatos and Peter JipsenOf course this survey covers only some <strong>of</strong> the highlights <strong>of</strong> a few researchpapers concerned with GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong> and related classes. Volumes have beenwritten about BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>, l-groups and Heyting al<strong>gebras</strong>, aswell as about many other al<strong>gebras</strong> that satisfy divisibility, and the readeris encouraged to explore the literature further, starting with the referencesbelow.BIBLIOGRAPHY[AFM07] P. Aglianò, I. M. A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna, <strong>Basic</strong> hoops: an algebraic study<strong>of</strong> continuous t-norms, Studia <strong>Logic</strong>a 87 no. 1, (2007), 73–98.[AM03] P. Aglianò and F. Montagna, Varieties <strong>of</strong> BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> I: general properties, Journal<strong>of</strong> Pure and Applied <strong>Al</strong>gebra 181, (2003), 105–129.[AF88] M. Anderson and T. Feil, “Lattice Ordered Groups, An Introduction”, D. ReidelPublishing Company, Dordrecht, Boston, Lancaster, Tokyo 1988.[BCGJT] P. Bahls, J. Cole, N. Galatos, P. Jipsen and C. Tsinakis, Cancellative ResiduatedLattices, <strong>Al</strong>gebra Universalis 50 (1), (2003), 83–106.[BF00] W. J. Blok and I. M. A. Ferreirim, On the structure <strong>of</strong> hoops, <strong>Al</strong>gebra Universalis43 (2000), 233–257.[BP89] W. J. Blok and D. Pigozzi, <strong>Al</strong>gebraizable <strong>Logic</strong>s, Mem. Amer. Math. Soc. 396(1989).[BP94] W. J. Blok and D. Pigozzi, On the structure <strong>of</strong> Varieties with Equationally DefinablePrincipal Congruences III, <strong>Al</strong>gebra Universalis 32 (1994), 545-608.[BT03] K. Blount and C. Tsinakis, The structure <strong>of</strong> residuated lattices, InternationalJournal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Al</strong>gebra and Computation 13(4), (2003), 437–461.[Bo82] B. Bosbach, Residuation groupoids, Result. Math. 5 (1982) 107-122.[BO] J. R. Büchi and T. M. Owens, Complemented monoids and hoops, unpublished[Ch59]manuscript.C. C. Chang, A new pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the completeness <strong>of</strong> the ̷Lukasiewicz axioms, Trans.Amer. Math. Soc. 93 (1959) 74–80.[CDM00] R. Cignoli, I. D’Ottaviano and D. Mundici, “<strong>Al</strong>gebraic foundations <strong>of</strong> manyvaluedreasoning”, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Boston, London2000.[CEGT] R. Cignoli, F. Esteva, L. Godo and A. Torrens, <strong>Basic</strong> Fuzzy <strong>Logic</strong> is the logic <strong>of</strong>continuous t-norms and their residua, S<strong>of</strong>t Computing 4, (2000), 106–112.[Ci01] P. Cintula, The ̷LΠ and ̷LΠ 1 propositional and predicate logics, Fuzzy logic2(Palma, 1999/Liptovský Ján, 2000), Fuzzy Sets and Systems 124 no. 3, (2001),289–302.[DGI02] A. Di Nola, G. Georgescu and A. Iorgulescu, Pseudo BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> I, Multiple-Valued <strong>Logic</strong> 8 (2002), 673–714.[DGI02b] A. Di Nola, G. Georgescu and A. Iorgulescu, Pseudo BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> II, Multiple-Valued <strong>Logic</strong> 8 (2002), 715–750.[DL03] A. Di Nola and A. Lettieri, Finite BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, Discrete Mathematics 269 (2003),93–112.[Dv02] A. Dvurečenskij, Pseudo MV-al<strong>gebras</strong> are intervals in l-groups, Journal <strong>of</strong> AustralianMathematical Society 70 (2002), 427–445.[Dv07] A. Dvurečenskij, Aglianò-Montagna Type Decomposition <strong>of</strong> Pseudo Hoops andits Applications, Journal <strong>of</strong> Pure and Applied <strong>Al</strong>gebra 211 (2007), 851–861.[DGK09] A. Dvurečenskij, R. Giuntini and T. Kowalski, On the structure <strong>of</strong> pseudo BLal<strong>gebras</strong>and pseudo hoops in quantum logics, Foundations <strong>of</strong> Physics (2009), DOI10.1007/s10701-009-9342-5[DH07] A. Dvurečenskij and W. C. Holland, Top varieties <strong>of</strong> generalized MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>and unital lattice-ordered groups, Comm. <strong>Al</strong>gebra 35 (2007), no. 11, 3370–3390.


A <strong>Survey</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Generalized</strong> <strong>Basic</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> 25[DH09] A. Dvurečenskij and W. C. Holland, Komori’s characterization and top varieties<strong>of</strong> GMV-al<strong>gebras</strong>, <strong>Al</strong>gebra Universalis 60 (2009), no. 1, 37–62.[FGI01] P. Flondor, G. Georgescu and A. Iorgulescu, Pseudo t-norms and pseudo BLal<strong>gebras</strong>,S<strong>of</strong>t Computing 5 no. 5 (2001), 355–371.[GJKO] N. Galatos, P. Jipsen, T. Kowalski and H. Ono, “Residuated lattices: an algebraicglimpse at substructural logics”, Studies in <strong>Logic</strong> and the Foundations <strong>of</strong>Mathematics, Vol. 151, Elsevier, 2007.[GO06] N. Galatos and H. Ono, <strong>Al</strong>gebraization, parametrized local deduction theorem andinterpolation for substructural logics over FL, Studia <strong>Logic</strong>a, 83 (2006), 1–32.[GT05] N. Galatos and C. Tsinakis, <strong>Generalized</strong> MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>, Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Al</strong>gebra 283(2005), 254–291.[GLP05] G. Georgescu, L. Leuştean and V. Preoteasa, Pseudo hoops, Journal <strong>of</strong> MultipleValued <strong>Logic</strong> and S<strong>of</strong>t Computing 11 (2005), 153–184.[Gl99]A. Glass, “Partially ordered groups”, in: Series in <strong>Al</strong>gebra, vol. 7, World Scientific,1999.[Ha98] P. Hàjek, <strong>Basic</strong> Fuzzy <strong>Logic</strong> and BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, S<strong>of</strong>t Computing 2 (1998), 124–128.[Haj98] P. Hàjek, “Metamathematics <strong>of</strong> Fuzzy <strong>Logic</strong>”, Trends in <strong>Logic</strong>, Studia <strong>Logic</strong>aLibrary no. 4, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Boston, London 1998.[Ha03]P. Hàjek, Fuzzy logic with non-commutative conjunctions, Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> andComputation 13 (2003) No. 4, 469–479.[Ha03a] P. Hàjek, Observations on non-commutative fuzzy logic, S<strong>of</strong>t Computing 8 (2003),71–89.[Ha03b] P. Hàjek, Embedding standard BL-al<strong>gebras</strong> into non-commutative pseudo BLal<strong>gebras</strong>,Tatra Mountains Mathematical Publications, 27 (2003), 125–130.[Ho05] W. C. Holland, Small varieties <strong>of</strong> lattice-ordered groups and MV-al<strong>gebras</strong>, Contributionsto general algebra. 16, (2005) 107–114.[Io08] A. Iorgulescu, “<strong>Al</strong><strong>gebras</strong> <strong>of</strong> logic as BCK al<strong>gebras</strong>”, Editura ASE, 2008.[JM02][Ji03][Ji09][JM06][JM09][JM10][JT02][Ko96][Mu86]S. Jenei and F. Montagna, A pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> standard completeness for Esteva andGodo’s logic MTL, Studia <strong>Logic</strong>a 70 (2002), no. 2, 183–192.P. Jipsen, An overview <strong>of</strong> generalized basic logic al<strong>gebras</strong>, Neural Network World,13 (2003), 491–500.P. Jipsen, Generalizations <strong>of</strong> Boolean products for lattice-ordered al<strong>gebras</strong>, Annals<strong>of</strong> Pure and Applied <strong>Logic</strong>, 161 (2009), 228–234.P. Jipsen and F. Montagna, On the structure <strong>of</strong> generalized BL-al<strong>gebras</strong>, <strong>Al</strong>gebraUniversalis 55 (2006), 226–237.P. Jipsen and F. Montagna, The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBLal<strong>gebras</strong>and its applications, <strong>Al</strong>gebra Universalis 60 (2009), 381–404.P. Jipsen and F. Montagna, Embedding theorems for classes <strong>of</strong> GBL-al<strong>gebras</strong>,Journal <strong>of</strong> Pure and Applied <strong>Al</strong>gebra, (2010), in press.P. Jipsen and C. Tsinakis, A survey on residuated lattices, in: J. Martinez (Ed.),Ordered <strong>Al</strong>gebraic Structures, Kluwer 2002, 19–56.T. Kovar, A genral theory <strong>of</strong> dually residuated lattice ordered monoids, doctoralthesis, Palacky University <strong>of</strong> Olomouc, 1996.D. Mundici, Interpretations <strong>of</strong> AFC*-al<strong>gebras</strong> in ̷Lukasiewicz sentential calculus,Journal <strong>of</strong> Functional Analysis 65 (1986), 15–63.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!