G. A. Cohen on Self-Ownership, Property, and ... - Tom G. Palmer

G. A. Cohen on Self-Ownership, Property, and ... - Tom G. Palmer G. A. Cohen on Self-Ownership, Property, and ... - Tom G. Palmer

tomgpalmer.com
from tomgpalmer.com More from this publisher
10.07.2015 Views

230 Critical Review Vol. J2, No. 3division or appropriation of jointly owned assets on the grounds that“B might have good reason to exercise his right to forbid an appropriationby A fiom which B himself would benefit. For, if he forbidsA to appropriate, he can then bargain with A about the share of outputhe will get if he relents and allows A to appropriate. B is then.likely to improve his take by an amaunt greater than what A wouldotherwise have offered him” (ong>Cohenong> 1995, 84). According to ong>Cohenong>,B does not seek a more equal distribution of assets, but the improvementof his “share of output” of the jointly owned asset.It is not at all clear fkom the text how B’s veto threat would “improvehis take” unless B might later relent and allow A to appropriate,in which case the output would no longer be jointly owned and subjectto distribution. The argument that B might forbid A’s appropriationin order to hold out for a larger share of output is thus incoherent,for if A were to be allowed to appropriate, there would be nojoint product to share.Setting aside the above confusion, it bears noting that ong>Cohenong> iscareful to indicate that an agent “might” have good reason to refhean appropriation, for the agent ako might very well have good reasonsto agree to such an appropriation. There are many observable cases,afiter all, in which jointly owned resources (e.g., in business partnershipsand in marriage partnerships) are divided on the basis offieeagreement. These occasions happen when some one or more of thefollowing situations obtain:(A) The parties no longer wish to cooperate, because of differencesunrelated to the physical productivity of cooperation. (They may, forexample, mutually prefer not to be subject to the veto powers of jointowners over the disposition of jointly owned assets.)(B) The size or composition of the group of joint owners entailstransaction costs, in corning to agreement over the disposition of thejointly owned asset, that are greater than the sum of the losses thatwould be suffered by even the worst off under a loss of the right toan aliquot portion of the income stream generated by a jointlyowned asset. This would entail that those who would fare worstunder division could still be compensated for their losses from the resourcesfieed up by the elimination of the high transaction costs attributableto joint ownership. Under such conditions, and assumingthat the transaction costs of a one-time negotiation and arrangementof a division were not prohibitively high, then it would be rationalfor the joint owners to agree to division of their jointly owned assets.

Palmer ong>Cohenong> on Property and EquaZity23 I(C) One or more of the parties believe that she or they couldmanage a subdivided portion of the currently jointly owned resourcebetter than the collectivity could, thereby generating a surplus. Fromthis surplus she or they could offer the other joint owners compensationfor the lost aliquot portion of the income stream they wouldhave received h m the asset were it to remain jointly owned.@) The joint owners differ in their discounting of future incomestreams, and have correspondingly different preferences for savingsversus consumption, such that a division into several property wouldallow them to allocate income between investment and consumptiondifferently For example, if A prefers a policy of “Eat, drink, and bemerry, for tomorrow we may die,” whereas B prefers a policy of “Apenny saved is a penny earned” (or if A simply has a shorter timehorizon than B, due to advanced age or impending death, for example),then they may find it impossible to agree on whether to sacrificecurrent consumption for future satisfaction, and if so, what would bethe best tradeofE whereas with division, each would be able to satisfj.her own preference, even if it were to come at the cost of a lower aggregatephysical product.ong>Cohenong>’s arguments attempt to show that, under conditions of jointownership, division (appropriation) resulting in some inequality of assetswould be irrational, but his arguments fail to justif+ that conclusion.ong>Cohenong> is not clear on whether it is appropriation per se or appropriationthat would result in unequal distribution of “output” thatmatters to him. Whichever it is, though, the argument fails.7ong>Cohenong> does allow for the possibility, at least under conditions ofunanimity, of a precisely equal division of initial assets, in the mannerfavored by Hillel SreinerS8 Joint ownership, unlike equal division,“forbids a Nozickian formation of unequal private property by placingalI resources under collective control” (ong>Cohenong> Iggs,~oz). ong>Cohenong>(ibid., 10s) admits that, under conditions of unanimity, joint ownershipand equal division “may readily be converted into the other.“But arrangements other than strict equality, and not including the entiretyof the human race, or of all rationd agents, seem to be ruledout tout court?Of course, if property resources were to be divided and severalproperty established, joint ownership could be voluntarily reestablishedby the several owners agreeing jointly to recombine their assetsinto jointly owned assets.1° But ong>Cohenong>’s insistence that joint owners

230 Critical Review Vol. J2, No. 3divisi<strong>on</strong> or appropriati<strong>on</strong> of jointly owned assets <strong>on</strong> the grounds that“B might have good reas<strong>on</strong> to exercise his right to forbid an appropriati<strong>on</strong>by A fiom which B himself would benefit. For, if he forbidsA to appropriate, he can then bargain with A about the share of outputhe will get if he relents <strong>and</strong> allows A to appropriate. B is then.likely to improve his take by an amaunt greater than what A wouldotherwise have offered him” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> 1995, 84). According to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>,B does not seek a more equal distributi<strong>on</strong> of assets, but the improvementof his “share of output” of the jointly owned asset.It is not at all clear fkom the text how B’s veto threat would “improvehis take” unless B might later relent <strong>and</strong> allow A to appropriate,in which case the output would no l<strong>on</strong>ger be jointly owned <strong>and</strong> subjectto distributi<strong>on</strong>. The argument that B might forbid A’s appropriati<strong>on</strong>in order to hold out for a larger share of output is thus incoherent,for if A were to be allowed to appropriate, there would be nojoint product to share.Setting aside the above c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong>, it bears noting that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> iscareful to indicate that an agent “might” have good reas<strong>on</strong> to refhean appropriati<strong>on</strong>, for the agent ako might very well have good reas<strong>on</strong>sto agree to such an appropriati<strong>on</strong>. There are many observable cases,afiter all, in which jointly owned resources (e.g., in business partnerships<strong>and</strong> in marriage partnerships) are divided <strong>on</strong> the basis offieeagreement. These occasi<strong>on</strong>s happen when some <strong>on</strong>e or more of thefollowing situati<strong>on</strong>s obtain:(A) The parties no l<strong>on</strong>ger wish to cooperate, because of differencesunrelated to the physical productivity of cooperati<strong>on</strong>. (They may, forexample, mutually prefer not to be subject to the veto powers of jointowners over the dispositi<strong>on</strong> of jointly owned assets.)(B) The size or compositi<strong>on</strong> of the group of joint owners entailstransacti<strong>on</strong> costs, in corning to agreement over the dispositi<strong>on</strong> of thejointly owned asset, that are greater than the sum of the losses thatwould be suffered by even the worst off under a loss of the right toan aliquot porti<strong>on</strong> of the income stream generated by a jointlyowned asset. This would entail that those who would fare worstunder divisi<strong>on</strong> could still be compensated for their losses from the resourcesfieed up by the eliminati<strong>on</strong> of the high transacti<strong>on</strong> costs attributableto joint ownership. Under such c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> assumingthat the transacti<strong>on</strong> costs of a <strong>on</strong>e-time negotiati<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> arrangementof a divisi<strong>on</strong> were not prohibitively high, then it would be rati<strong>on</strong>alfor the joint owners to agree to divisi<strong>on</strong> of their jointly owned assets.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!