10.07.2015 Views

Untitled - socium.ge

Untitled - socium.ge

Untitled - socium.ge

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

436 Rosalind Williamsindustrial societies, so that human history is then the record of “the long marchof progress under the guidance of reason” (p. 42). Similarly, the “networksociety” is hailed as the climax of inevitable technological progress towardmore ubiquitous, more rapid, more portable, more miniaturized, more powerfulcommunication.Another version of presentism, already alluded to, involves taking the categoriesand concerns of the present, shaking (or stirring) them with history, andadding the dimension of time to inquire into their origins. This is an obvioustemptation in dealing with the concept of “network society.” As Castells hascautioned, this concept, as he uses it, cannot be freely floated through thewaves of history to far and distant shores. It relates to a specific technologicalparadigm, based on microelectronics; a specific type of technological system,that of linked computers; a specific form of globalization, acting in real time;and other very specific types of information, employment, and other socialbehaviors. So it is quite possible and helpful to look back, as Castells does, onthe emer<strong>ge</strong>nce of contemporary network society in the unanticipated confluenceof three originally independent processes: “the crisis of industrialism, therise of freedom-oriented social movements, and the revolution in informationand communication technologies” (p. 22). But once one moves further back intime, very quickly the gap between the concept of a network society and thespecifics of networks in that historical situation grows ever wider.One can readily see this gap, for example, in the standard work on electricalnetworks in the early twentieth century – Thomas P. Hughes’s classicNetworks of Power (1983) – where both the specific content of the networksystem and the context in which it operated are markedly different from thatof contemporary computer systems. If one looks back even further – at theRoman Empire, for example – to ask how it might be analyzed as a “networksociety,” the mismatch becomes even more striking. If the network iscomposed of roads and aqueducts, and the labor force is based on slavery, andthe social goals are focused on the maintenance and extension of imperialpower, this is an entirely different “network society” from the one based on thedevelopment of computer networks in a job-holding, market-oriented economy.Concepts, too, have a history, and when one from the present is anachronisticallyimposed on the particularities of the past, the effort to <strong>ge</strong>neralize canquickly become absurd.That is why historians of technology have to be particularly careful. Wehave been outspoken in rejecting the types of presentism that would deny thevery reality of the past or read the historical record as the grand narrative oftechnological progress. However, in our very self-definition, we are indulgingin presentism of the last sort, by applying the concept of “technology” to thepast, especially the distant past. In this respect, the history of technology is onegrand exercise in anachronism.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!