19.11.2012 Views

J. S. BACH Jonathan Berkahn - Victoria University - Victoria ...

J. S. BACH Jonathan Berkahn - Victoria University - Victoria ...

J. S. BACH Jonathan Berkahn - Victoria University - Victoria ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

At times, so eccentric are his textural solutions, the thought of Beethoven’s<br />

deafness crosses one’s mind. William Newman raises the ‘gnawing, ever-present<br />

question of how well Beethoven could actually hear the sonority of what he was<br />

writing’, arguing that ‘no one who has practised the last five sonatas extensively can<br />

fail to be almost painfully aware of continuing problems of balance, projection, and<br />

clear sonority [musical examples showing the end of the Sonata op.101 and bb.118-19<br />

of the Diabelli variations].’ 80<br />

Of course, the pieces are what they are, and short of desperate expedients like<br />

Weingartner’s arrangement of the ‘Hammerklavier’ sonata for orchestra, these<br />

‘problems’ are not easy to fix. With this music there is no real alternative to taking the<br />

rough with the smooth. But what happens, listening carefully over time, is that one<br />

comes to realise that the noise is an essential part of the music: at times the sheer<br />

difficulty of following the musical argument compels attention as nothing else can.<br />

A classical aesthetic might be defined as one in which means (orchestration,<br />

say, or instrumental technique or textural complication) submit themselves humbly to<br />

artistic ends; and would-be classical works are vulnerable to criticism insofar as this<br />

perfect submission is lacking. As we move further away from this aesthetic, however,<br />

means—even apparently unsatisfactory ones—force themselves on our attention as<br />

ends in their own right. Thus John Daverio can speak of the ‘incomprehensibility’ of<br />

Schumann’s music as a ‘constitutive aesthetic quality’ in its own right, 81 and Charles<br />

Ives defends Brahms’s orchestration thus:<br />

To think hard and deeply and to say what is thought, regardless of consequences, may produce a first<br />

impression either of great translucence or of great muddiness, but in the latter there may be hidden<br />

80 Performance practices in Beethoven’s piano sonatas (London: Dent, 1971), p.46.<br />

81 ‘Schumann’s systems of musical fragments and Witz’, Nineteenth-century music and the German<br />

Romantic ideology (New York: Schirmer, 1993), pp.50, 53; see also D. Ferris, ‘“Was will dieses<br />

Grau’n bedeuten?” Schumann's “Zwielicht” and Daverio’s “incomprehensibility topos”’, Journal of<br />

Musicology 22/1 (Winter 2005), 131-153.<br />

352

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!