19.11.2012 Views

J. S. BACH Jonathan Berkahn - Victoria University - Victoria ...

J. S. BACH Jonathan Berkahn - Victoria University - Victoria ...

J. S. BACH Jonathan Berkahn - Victoria University - Victoria ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

thought and practice until very recently. 13 The situation is more complicated for music<br />

than it is for poetry. Not only are questions of authorial intention relevant to<br />

hermeneutic interpretation of what a given work ‘means’ (an inquiry roughly<br />

equivalent to that of Wimsatt and Beardsley), but they are equally relevant to issues of<br />

performance, editions, realisations, and arrangement. In no case is this knowledge of<br />

intention both more desirable and more definitively irrecoverable than in the case of<br />

unfinished works. This being so, there is always a sense in which any given<br />

completion is going to be ‘unsatisfactory’, the best of a bad job—as expressed, for<br />

example, by Toscanini’s bad temper toward Alfano’s completion of Turandot (‘I saw<br />

Puccini coming in and slapping my face!’) and Richard Swift’s argument that the<br />

sketches of Mahler’s 10 th symphony are too incomplete to permit completion of the<br />

piece by anyone other than the composer himself—by anyone at all, that is. 14 The<br />

advocacy of this last position testifies to the extent that, in our culture today, a musical<br />

work can exist purely as text without even the possibility of performance. 15<br />

13 ‘The intentional fallacy’, Sewanee Review (1946), 466-88; reprinted in On literary intention, de. D.<br />

Newton-de-Molina (Edinburgh, 1976), pp.1-13. This assumption has been problematised in relation<br />

to music by R. Taruskin, Text and act: essays on music and performance (Oxford: Oxford<br />

<strong>University</strong> Press; 1995) and many other articles: I. Anhalt, ‘Text, context, music’, Canadian<br />

<strong>University</strong> Music Review/Revue de musique des universités canadiennes 9/2 (1989), 1-21; V.<br />

Rantala, ‘The work of art: Identity and interpretation’, Semiotica 87/3-4 (1991), 271-292; C.<br />

Dahlhaus, ‘Textgeschichte und Rezeptionsgeschichte’, in Rezeptionsästhetik und<br />

Rezeptionsgeschichte in der Musikwissenschaft ed. F. Krummacher and H. Danuser (Laaber: Laaber-<br />

Verlag, 1991), pp. 105-114.<br />

14 ‘Mahler’s Ninth and Cooke’s Tenth’, 19th-century Music 2/2 (November 1978) 165-72.<br />

15 Nicholas Cook is hostile to this way of thinking about music: ‘Between process and product: Music<br />

and/as performance’, Music Theory Online 7/2 (April 2001),<br />

http://www.societymusictheory.org/mto/issues/mto.01.7.2/mto.01.7.2.cook.html (accessed 30<br />

September 2006), and Nelson Goodman attempted to do without reference to the work as an abstract<br />

concept, defining it simply as the set of its accurate performances (Languages of art; an approach to<br />

a theory of symbols (London: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1969), pp.112-22, 177-92; while Jerrold<br />

Levinson was less reluctant to accept the existence of the musical work as a quasi-Platonic entity, he<br />

saw the means of performance as an essential part of the work (‘What a musical work is?’ and ‘What<br />

a musical work is, again’, Music, art, and metaphysics: Essays in philosophical aesthetics (Ithaca,<br />

N.Y.: Cornell <strong>University</strong> Press, 1990). In The imaginary museum of musical works: an essay in the<br />

philosophy of music (Oxford: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1994), Lydia Goehr sought to supplant the<br />

essentialist definitions of Goodman and Levinson with the emergent, socially negotiated idea of the<br />

‘work concept’, which she identified as having arisen around 1800. Swift’s argument in relation to<br />

the completion of Mahler’s 10 th can be seen as an extreme consequence of this Werktreue ethic, in<br />

which the performance most in accord with the composer’s intentions is—none at all. See also J.<br />

Anderson, ‘Musical identity’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 40/3 (Spring 1982), 285-91;<br />

K. Stierle, ‘Der Text als Werk und als Vollzug’, Der Hörer als Interpret, ed. H. de La Motte-Haber<br />

and R. Kopiez (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang; 1995), 11-28; and B. Edlund, ‘On scores and works<br />

of music: interpretation and identity’, British Journal of Aesthetics 36/4 (October 1996), 367-380.<br />

252

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!