10.07.2015 Views

Commentary on the Beginning of Damascius' De Primis Principiis

Commentary on the Beginning of Damascius' De Primis Principiis

Commentary on the Beginning of Damascius' De Primis Principiis

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

2GENERAL REMARKThe first secti<strong>on</strong> is devoted to a searching investigati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> what <strong>the</strong> AbsoluteFirst Principle is. So D. adopts <strong>the</strong> descending order in <strong>the</strong> explanati<strong>on</strong> (i.e.derivati<strong>on</strong>) <strong>of</strong> reality; for in <strong>the</strong> sequel, <strong>the</strong> first principles will be exa mined whichimmediately follow <strong>the</strong> Absolutely first. Not that he disregards <strong>the</strong> ascending process;in fact, as we shall see, he gives two ἀναβάσεις in this secti<strong>on</strong> from what isimmediately given to us to what is <strong>the</strong> ultimate “given” [1] in rerum natura. Bu twhereas <strong>the</strong> ascent is easier inasmuch as we can more readily comprehend <strong>the</strong> order<strong>of</strong> presuppositi<strong>on</strong>, <strong>the</strong> descent is extremely difficult as it relates to <strong>the</strong> order <strong>of</strong>derivati<strong>on</strong>. Even though <strong>the</strong> two orders must be <strong>the</strong> observe and reverse sides <strong>of</strong><strong>on</strong>e and <strong>the</strong> same coin, namely <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>tological dependence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> lower <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>higher, and so <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e obtaining structure and order <strong>of</strong> reality, still tounderstand B ’s presupposing A is immensely easier than c<strong>on</strong>ceiving B ’s derivati<strong>on</strong>from A or A ’s producti<strong>on</strong> o r generati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> B. Accordingly D. makes <strong>the</strong> ascent <strong>the</strong>topic <strong>of</strong> a part <strong>of</strong> his first secti<strong>on</strong> (subservient as this ascent is here, let it be als<strong>on</strong>oticed, to <strong>the</strong> proper quasi-apprehensi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolutely first principle), butdevotes his whole (incomplete now) work to that all-puzzling descent, choosing topenetrate deeper in each succeeding reality when it is met in <strong>the</strong> downwards processra<strong>the</strong>r than in <strong>the</strong> ascent to <strong>the</strong> ultimate, where he treats <strong>the</strong> realities encounteredsummarily and <strong>on</strong>ly to <strong>the</strong> extent th at some indicati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir nature is required for<strong>the</strong> proper understanding <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ascent itself.The general structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first secti<strong>on</strong> is this:A) Abstract inquiry <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolutely Primal Principle1.4 – 18.25B) The Ascent18.26 – 41.20Aa) Is <strong>the</strong> Absolutely First Principle bey<strong>on</strong>d everything and every realitywhatsoever (τὰ πάντα), or is it part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sum-total <strong>of</strong> reality (τὶ τῶν πάντων)?1.4 – 5.2Ab) Why is it not <strong>the</strong> Ἓν <strong>the</strong> Absolutely First Principle?


35.2 – 9.10Ac) In what sense is <strong>the</strong> Absolutely First Principle absolutely unknowable (ἄγνωστον παντελῶς)?9.11 – 15.25Ad) Difficulties in D. ’s doctrine about <strong>the</strong> Absolutely First Principle, and <strong>the</strong>irsoluti<strong>on</strong>s15.26 – 18.23Ba) First Ascent18.23 – 27.4Bb) Sec<strong>on</strong>d Ascent27.5 – 38.25Bc) Supplement to <strong>the</strong> Ascents: Ascent through Wholenesses (Integrals)38.25 – 41.20Aa)1.4-6. Positi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem1.4 Πάντα is <strong>the</strong> sum-total <strong>of</strong> reality; it includes everything <strong>of</strong> whatever kindsubsisting in reality in whatever way. In effect πάντα = <strong>the</strong> real, but so understoodas to transcend <strong>the</strong> ordinary distincti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> true or primary reality and sec<strong>on</strong>dary,apparent reality [2]. Πάντα = <strong>the</strong> sum-total <strong>of</strong> what subsists in whichever way ,<strong>the</strong> totality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subsistent realities [3].It is <strong>the</strong> principle ( ἀρχή) <strong>of</strong> πάντα in this sense, that it is <strong>the</strong> absolutely firstprinciple. And <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong> is whe<strong>the</strong>r this ἀρχὴ τῶν πάντων is bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> πάνταwhose principle it is, or is a part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> πάντα, in which case it would be like <strong>the</strong> apex<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> πάντα, i.e. <strong>of</strong> everything that came to be as a reality out <strong>of</strong> it and after it.1.5. The προϊόν is that which comes to be present in reality , comes to subsistin it, as <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subsistence <strong>of</strong> that from, or out <strong>of</strong>, which it proceeds. Wemust keep toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se two elements in our c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> προϊέναι, προϊόν etc.: a)presence, manifestati<strong>on</strong>, subsistence in reality, b) resulting fro m <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>πρόοδος which produces as a result <strong>the</strong> προϊόν.1.6-2.7. Examinati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first <strong>the</strong>oretically available alternative:that <strong>the</strong> ἀρχὴ τῶν πάντων is bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> πάντα [4].


4Four reas<strong>on</strong>s are, in aporematic fashi<strong>on</strong>, brought against <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis. Allfollow from <strong>the</strong> essential nature <strong>of</strong> παντότης, given an assumpti<strong>on</strong> as to <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> Absolute first principle which D. in fact denies. I have underlined this assumpti<strong>on</strong>in <strong>the</strong> following formulati<strong>on</strong>s.1) Πάντα include everything; for, that from wh ich nothing is out <strong>of</strong> it, is <strong>the</strong>totality <strong>of</strong> everything subsisting in whichever way , <strong>the</strong> totality <strong>of</strong> all subsistence ἁπλῶς. But if <strong>the</strong> principle was bey<strong>on</strong>d πάντων, since it is something subsisting insome way, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> πάντα would miss it, and <strong>the</strong>refore th ey would no l<strong>on</strong>ger beπάντα, c<strong>on</strong>trary to <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Hence <strong>the</strong> Abs olutely F irst Principle cannot bebey<strong>on</strong>d τῶν πάντων.2) Two moments are included in <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> πάντα; two realities arepresupposed by <strong>the</strong> reality <strong>of</strong> πάντα; in still o<strong>the</strong>r words to th e same effect, in orderfor πάντα to be at all, to subsist at all, <strong>the</strong>re must previously be present as asubsistent reality and <strong>the</strong>refore metaphysically available two o<strong>the</strong>r characters: <strong>the</strong>seare <strong>the</strong> πολλότης and <strong>the</strong> πέρας. For πάντα is nothing but πολλὰ πεπερασμένα [5],πολλὰ who have been limited so that to give, as it were, a well-rounded(subParmenidean) whole. The many, indefinite in <strong>the</strong>mselves, are limited by a πέρας,and thus become all that subsists as reality, <strong>the</strong> sum total <strong>of</strong> reality. And so it isessentially involved in παντότης that it is a kind <strong>of</strong> ὅρος, <strong>of</strong> limit, and a certainπερίληψις (a certain “c<strong>on</strong>taining”); hence that which it applies to must be inclusive <strong>of</strong>its limits, both lower (i.e. that which is far<strong>the</strong>st removed from <strong>the</strong> principle), andhigher. But <strong>the</strong> higher limit <strong>of</strong> a totality is <strong>the</strong> principle from which it stems. But thisprinciple is <strong>the</strong> absolutely primal principle; <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>the</strong> Absolutely FirstPrinciple cannot but be included in <strong>the</strong> totality whose first item, <strong>the</strong> beginning [6], i tis.3) There is a certain co-ordinati<strong>on</strong> not <strong>on</strong>ly in <strong>the</strong> orderly system produced bya principle or cause [7] (and every field in which <strong>the</strong> operati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>on</strong>e principle takesplace must eo ipso exhibit a certain order), but also between <strong>the</strong> very principle an d<strong>the</strong> causatum. For something <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> πρός τι pertains to a principle, a causeor a first ( τὸ πρῶτον), in so far as for something to be a cause it must causesomething else and must bear <strong>the</strong> essential reference to that which it causes; andsimilarly for <strong>the</strong> principle and <strong>the</strong> first. Now wherever <strong>the</strong>re is co-ordinati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>the</strong>reπάντα are to be found, as including all <strong>the</strong> co-ordinated items. But <strong>the</strong> Primal


5Principle is subject to that co-ordinati<strong>on</strong> , and <strong>the</strong>refore it must be c<strong>on</strong>tained in<strong>the</strong> all-inclusive totality.4) Whatever is c<strong>on</strong>ceived in whichever way bel<strong>on</strong>gs to <strong>the</strong> πάντα [8]; but <strong>the</strong>Primal Principle can be c<strong>on</strong>ceived in some way; <strong>the</strong>refore it is included inπάντα.2.7-3.5. Examinati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d alternative: that <strong>the</strong> First Principle isc<strong>on</strong>tained in πάντα.Arguments against:1) 2.7-16. Everything is ei<strong>the</strong>r a principle or something which subsists invirtue <strong>of</strong> a principle; for <strong>the</strong> divisi<strong>on</strong> ἀρχή - ἀπ᾿ ἀρχῆς is exhaustive. Now if <strong>the</strong> πάνταinclude <strong>the</strong> primal principle <strong>the</strong>y cannot be ἀπ᾿ ἀρχῆς, from a b eginning, from aprinciple in <strong>the</strong>ir totality, qua πάντα. But nor can <strong>the</strong>y be a principle; for what wouldcome out <strong>of</strong> πάντα to set itself beside <strong>the</strong> absolute totality <strong>of</strong> everything? So <strong>the</strong>πάντα can nei<strong>the</strong>r be ἀπ᾿ ἀρχῆς, nor an ἀρχή – which is impossible. Everything elsebeing cogent, we can <strong>on</strong>ly raise <strong>the</strong> impossibility by aband<strong>on</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that<strong>the</strong> Primal Principle is included in πάντα.2.8. The τι must be adverbial, c<strong>on</strong>struing: οὐκ ἂν ἡ ἀρχὴ εἴη τῶν πάντων =<strong>the</strong> ἀρχή in this case would not be a principle <strong>of</strong> πάντα (since it is included in πάντα).But it is tempting to adopt S a ’s reading (testified by R): οὐκ ἂν εἴη τις ἀρχὴ τῶνπάντων.2.15. τοῦτο sc. τὸ τῶν πάντων ἀποτέλεσμα. Meaning: even this would havebeen c<strong>on</strong>tained in πάντα (καὶ τοῦτο γὰρ ἦν ἂν ἐν τοῖς πᾶσιν).2) 2.17-3.5. This part is divided into three unequal subparts. First (a) <strong>the</strong>re is<strong>the</strong> argument against <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d alternative briefly expounded (2.17-18). Then (b)comes a possible rejoinder to <strong>the</strong> argument (2.18-21). And (c) <strong>the</strong> rest is o ccupiedwith an elaborate refutati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rejoinder, which necessarily employs some noti<strong>on</strong>sthat will be fully clarified <strong>on</strong>ly later <strong>on</strong>, in <strong>the</strong> appropriate secti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> work.a) Some multiplicity and distincti<strong>on</strong> is <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> πάντα. For παντότηςimplies inclusi<strong>on</strong> into <strong>on</strong>e totality <strong>of</strong> many items distinct am<strong>on</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mselves in someway or o<strong>the</strong>r. Now if <strong>the</strong>re was no principle outside <strong>the</strong> πάντα and prior to <strong>the</strong>m,πάντα would be <strong>the</strong> first given reality, <strong>the</strong> ultimate datum in <strong>the</strong> explanati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Universe. But this is impossible [9] (2.18: πῶς οὖν … ἐξεφάνη; with emphasis <strong>on</strong> ε


6ὐθύς, i.e. without any prior reality being required for <strong>the</strong> reality <strong>of</strong> πάντα to subsist);hence, <strong>the</strong>re must be a principle before πάντα.b) The rejoinder c<strong>on</strong>sists in <strong>the</strong> view that o ne need not c<strong>on</strong>nect always and inevery way ( πανταχῇ) <strong>the</strong> πολλά with distincti<strong>on</strong> and multiplicity. For in an orderlysystem in which <strong>the</strong>re exists a single beginning as <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> everything thatfollows and <strong>of</strong> its order, this beginning, like an apex or summit <strong>of</strong> what follows, neednot be infected with <strong>the</strong> multiplicity which it produces in some way or o<strong>the</strong>r afteritself; that is, in short, <strong>the</strong> beginning and principle <strong>of</strong> multiplicity [10] may well be anabsolute One, even if this <strong>on</strong>e is part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> multiplicity; and similarly, <strong>the</strong> principle <strong>of</strong>distincti<strong>on</strong> may well be absolutely unified in itself though partaking in distincti<strong>on</strong>inasmuch as it is distinguished from that which follows from it.2.20. As <strong>the</strong> text stands we have: “but τὸ ἓν is <strong>the</strong> summit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> πολλά, andunit (μονάς) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> distinguished is <strong>the</strong> unified, while τὸ ἓν is even simpler than <strong>the</strong>unit”. There is <strong>of</strong> course perfect sense in this. We shall see that with D. <strong>the</strong> ἡνωμένονlies after τὸ ἓν in <strong>the</strong> “natural history” o f reality; so τὸ ἡνωμένον is not ἓν but ra<strong>the</strong>rμονάς, drawing <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong> between <strong>on</strong>e and unit which can be traced back toNeopythagoreanism and even to Aristotle, if not to ancient, early Pythagoreanism.But meaningful as <strong>the</strong> statements are, <strong>the</strong>y present some subtle occasi<strong>on</strong> forworry. Firstly, we might expect to hear that as <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e is summit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> many, so <strong>the</strong>unified is <strong>the</strong> summit (not <strong>the</strong> unit) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> distinguished. And this we can get byputting a comma after ἡνωμένον. But what <strong>the</strong>n <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fo llowing μονάς? In whatimmediately follows « μονάς» is used clearly to denote quasi-arithmetical unit, or atany rate, <strong>the</strong> unit <strong>of</strong> number [11]. So could it not be that it is applied here in <strong>the</strong>same sense? Hence my suggesti<strong>on</strong> for <strong>the</strong> inserti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> ἡνωμένον μονάς. And that this is probable seems to be c<strong>on</strong>firmed by what follows: mark <strong>the</strong>Ἀλλὰ πρῶτον μὲν etc. …ἔπειτα δὲ… The former disposes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> example (for as suchwe may c<strong>on</strong>strue, if <strong>the</strong> suggesti<strong>on</strong> is correct, <strong>the</strong> clause: “just as summi t <strong>of</strong> everynumber [12] is <strong>the</strong> unit”), whereas <strong>the</strong> latter combats <strong>the</strong> doctrine itself about <strong>the</strong>One.That <strong>the</strong>re is a marginal note in this place running so:τὸ ἓν κορυφὴ τῶν πολλῶν, τὸ δ᾿ ἡνωμένον ἤτοι μονὰς τῶν διακεκριμένων,


7apparently identifying <strong>the</strong> ἡνωμένον with <strong>the</strong> μονάς (not certainly since ἤτοι which R.reads c<strong>on</strong>fidently, is not really clearly seen <strong>the</strong>re), does not tell much against mysuggesti<strong>on</strong> since it is by a very later hand.On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand it should be noted that <strong>the</strong> positi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> μέν prohibits <strong>the</strong>above suggested train <strong>of</strong> thought; for we should have κορυφὴ τῶν μέν etc. And also<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> suggesti<strong>on</strong>, <strong>the</strong> last clause καὶ τὸ ἓν ἔτι etc. has not <strong>the</strong> perfect point that ithas in <strong>the</strong> text as it stands. So, <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>the</strong> suggesti<strong>on</strong> is to be rejected.c) Taking <strong>the</strong> example <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> number, D. remarks that <strong>the</strong> unit c<strong>on</strong>tainsimplicitly and συνεπτυγμένως (not ἐν διεξόδῳ) all numbers, being <strong>the</strong>ir principle. Inthis way, <strong>the</strong> unit is everything whose unit it is, and this analogy, by implicati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>the</strong>nwould tel l that even in <strong>the</strong> One which is <strong>the</strong> summit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> πολλά, <strong>the</strong> πολλά arealready included, and so, eventually we have to h old <strong>on</strong> to <strong>the</strong> impossible view thatπολλά and πάντα appear right from <strong>the</strong> beginning in <strong>the</strong> great chain <strong>of</strong> being, as part<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ultimate datum.Then D. turns from <strong>the</strong> illustrati<strong>on</strong> to <strong>the</strong> illustrated itself (ἔπειτα δὲ etc.).The basis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rejoinder is formed by <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> One can bel<strong>on</strong>g to<strong>the</strong> multiplicity whose principle it is, just as <strong>the</strong> beginning bel<strong>on</strong>gs to that whosebeginning it is and <strong>the</strong> summit to that whose summit it is. Now in combating th isbasis D. does not wish to have recourse to <strong>the</strong> first argument (1) against <strong>the</strong> positi<strong>on</strong>that <strong>the</strong> Primal Principle bel<strong>on</strong>gs to <strong>the</strong> totality <strong>of</strong> reality, but wants to stay within <strong>the</strong>boundary <strong>of</strong> his sec<strong>on</strong>d argument (2) , especially because he differentiates between<strong>the</strong> absolutely Primal Principle and <strong>the</strong> One, and he intends to keep <strong>the</strong> matter openin order to explain fur<strong>the</strong>r his <strong>the</strong>sis by utilizing a plausible objecti<strong>on</strong> to <strong>the</strong> verydifferentiati<strong>on</strong> which he maintains, as we shall see in <strong>the</strong> sequel. In denying <strong>the</strong>menti<strong>on</strong>ed basis, D. leads to a pr<strong>of</strong>ound intuiti<strong>on</strong> as to <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One, which,again, is preliminarily treated here, since it will become <strong>the</strong> expressed object <strong>of</strong>inquiry in <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d (and, less directly, <strong>the</strong> third) secti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> work.The denial c<strong>on</strong>sists in this: if x bel<strong>on</strong>gs essentially to Y, <strong>the</strong>n it is required inorder to complete, or completely make up <strong>the</strong> Y, in <strong>the</strong> sense that, should it belacking, <strong>the</strong> Y would not be enti re. But this is not <strong>the</strong> relati<strong>on</strong>ship existing between<strong>the</strong> One and <strong>the</strong> πολλά; for <strong>the</strong> latter do not “miss” <strong>the</strong> One [13]; in fact anythingthat is c<strong>on</strong>tained in <strong>the</strong> πολλά under <strong>the</strong> aspect <strong>of</strong> divisi<strong>on</strong> ( μερισμός) is alsoc<strong>on</strong>tained in <strong>the</strong> One under <strong>the</strong> aspect <strong>of</strong> absolute indivisibility ( κατὰ τὸ πάντῃ


8ἀμερές). Thus nothing is missing, nei<strong>the</strong>r from <strong>the</strong> πολλά, nor from <strong>the</strong> One; whichmanifests <strong>the</strong> fundamental difference in <strong>the</strong> relati<strong>on</strong>ship between <strong>the</strong> One and <strong>the</strong>Many <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e hand, and <strong>the</strong> beginning and that <strong>of</strong> w hich it is <strong>the</strong> beginning, or<strong>the</strong> summit and that <strong>of</strong> which it is <strong>the</strong> summit <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. In effect D. protestsagainst being misled in <strong>the</strong> correct understanding <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> abstract metaphysicalrelati<strong>on</strong>ships involved here by undue c<strong>on</strong>cern with certain less abstract models.But why, it may be asked, is it as it is said to be in 2.22-25? The answer isgiven without development in 2.25-3.5, and is <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> outmost philosophicalimportance, being also uniquely, in a certain sense, characteristic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Damasciansystem.A fuller analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> answer must await a more appropriate place, when weare at <strong>the</strong> interior <strong>of</strong> D.’s <strong>the</strong>ory for good. But we can introduce here <strong>the</strong> future fullerdiscussi<strong>on</strong> as follows.It was noted above that it is extremely difficult to derive reality, as opposedto show its presuppositi<strong>on</strong>s; we can now perhaps get an indicati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> where exactly<strong>the</strong> difficulty lies. Suppose a reality B which metaphysically presupposes A; andsuppose that every o<strong>the</strong>r reality presupposed by B (if <strong>the</strong>re is such an <strong>on</strong>e) is alsopresupposed by A [14]. How can now B be derived from A (as it should, dependenceand presuppositi<strong>on</strong> being according to our explanati<strong>on</strong> but <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side <strong>of</strong>derivati<strong>on</strong>)? B presupposes A, and this means that B (and B-things) could not bepresent in <strong>the</strong> Universe <strong>of</strong> Reality, if A was absent from it; but obviously <strong>the</strong>character <strong>of</strong> B is not identically <strong>the</strong> same with that <strong>of</strong> A; and so how did it happenthat B came to be present, given that A was? We agreed, <strong>the</strong>re is no possibility <strong>of</strong>foreign, extraneous influence, no possibility <strong>of</strong> analyzing B as A modified in a certainway M and <strong>the</strong>n explaining that modificati<strong>on</strong> as proceeding from a source distinctfrom A. The modificati<strong>on</strong> must, if at all, proceed from A; but <strong>the</strong>n it must be in A in<strong>on</strong>e way or ano<strong>the</strong>r; it could not be created ex nihilo; and so, B itself, whose peculiarcharacter (ἰδιότης) c<strong>on</strong>sists in that modificati<strong>on</strong> (since it is this modificati<strong>on</strong> which, exhypo<strong>the</strong>si, differentiates B from A), - B itself must be somehow included in A.We c<strong>on</strong>clude from <strong>the</strong> above schematic development that nothing appearssuddenly at any place in <strong>the</strong> Chain <strong>of</strong> Reality. In order to present itself at any place,it must be already in its superior.


9But <strong>the</strong>n what is <strong>the</strong> distinctive character ( ἰδιότης) <strong>of</strong> B vis- à-vis A? It is <strong>the</strong>mode in which B “has” (or ra<strong>the</strong>r “is”) what is already in A under a different mode.But granted this, <strong>the</strong> mode under which everything present in A is in B isdifferent from <strong>the</strong> mode under which <strong>the</strong> same is in A, since <strong>the</strong> ἰδιότης <strong>of</strong> B is not,ex hypo<strong>the</strong>si that <strong>of</strong> A. And <strong>the</strong> exasperatingly difficult questi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> derivati<strong>on</strong> presentsitself in a new, and c<strong>on</strong>nected, form: for how did <strong>the</strong> mode characterizing B comeabout to be present in reality as a reality given <strong>the</strong> mode characterizing A?If to this questi<strong>on</strong> we reply by positing not <strong>on</strong>ly (<strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tent <strong>of</strong>) B, but <strong>the</strong>specific mode B itself in A, we <strong>on</strong>ly begin an infinite regress. Ano<strong>the</strong>r answer should,<strong>the</strong>refore, be sought.It is premature, as we said, to pursue fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se questi<strong>on</strong>s which lie right in<strong>the</strong> metaphysical heart <strong>of</strong> Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ism. But enough has been said, in order toappreciate D.’s point in <strong>the</strong> passage in questi<strong>on</strong>. The One can be <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> πάντα(πάντα ἀπ᾿ αὐτοῦ 3.3), just because it itself is πάντα before πάντα.Thus, for D., <strong>the</strong> One is not just and <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e; it is πάντα; it must be πάντα inorder to be able to “generate” πάντα. And so we meet here with a major modificati<strong>on</strong><strong>of</strong> Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic doctrine, <strong>the</strong> full significance <strong>of</strong> which will become apparent later [15].2.19. ἐξεφάνη: ἐκφαίνεσθαι is regularly used by Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ists to signify firstappearance or presence in reality <strong>of</strong> a certain character, in most cases in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>with <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong>: where did X first appeared in <strong>the</strong> Chain <strong>of</strong> Reality = which is <strong>the</strong>precise locati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> X-reality in <strong>the</strong> ordered derivati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> all reality from <strong>the</strong>Ultimate Principle down to <strong>the</strong> thre shold to unreality. Cf. <strong>the</strong> orphic use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> termand <strong>the</strong> orphic Phanes.3.1. Σπεύσιππος. Here we have a good opportunity <strong>of</strong> showing, in a specificcase, how near <strong>the</strong> Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic speculati<strong>on</strong>s were (in respect to <strong>the</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> problemsfaced, and in <strong>the</strong> spirit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> answers given, as well as in many details <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>soluti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>of</strong>fered) to <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>troversies in <strong>the</strong> Old Academy.Speusippus distinguished <strong>the</strong> One, <strong>the</strong> Νοῦς (which was <strong>the</strong> God for himproperly speaking) and <strong>the</strong> Good [ 16]. In fact he was pr<strong>on</strong>e to multiply hypostases(= levels <strong>of</strong> being) and <strong>the</strong>ir principles; which makes Aristotle complain that in thisway no coherent view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> World can be made [17]. C<strong>on</strong>trary to Plato [18] ando<strong>the</strong>r Plat<strong>on</strong>ist s who found in <strong>the</strong> One <strong>the</strong> very nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Good, Speusippusseparated <strong>the</strong>m [19]. In fact we are fortunately able to know <strong>the</strong> reas<strong>on</strong> why h e did


10separate <strong>the</strong>m. Basically, as Aristotle says [20], it was this: if <strong>the</strong> very nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Good c<strong>on</strong>sists in <strong>the</strong> One, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> principle opposite to <strong>the</strong> One, namely <strong>the</strong>Multiplicity, must be <strong>the</strong> Evil; but Speusippus denied that <strong>the</strong>re can be evil, indeed<strong>the</strong> Evil, in <strong>the</strong> absolutely first principles. So he made <strong>the</strong> Good and <strong>the</strong> Evil to lie at<strong>the</strong> completi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> derivati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> reality ra<strong>the</strong>r than at <strong>the</strong> beginning (like in <strong>the</strong>fully developed animal ra<strong>the</strong>r than at <strong>the</strong> seed and sperm) – to use <strong>the</strong> metaphorSpeusippus himself may have employed [21].We know, <strong>of</strong> course, from Aristotle (and Theophrastus ’ little metaphysicaltract), even if we could not see it already right in Plato’s dialogues, that ascending t<strong>of</strong>irst principles from <strong>the</strong> given via <strong>the</strong> presuppos iti<strong>on</strong>-ladder, and descending from<strong>the</strong>m in a derivati<strong>on</strong> attempt which aims at covering all reality and locatingeverything real at its appropriate place in <strong>the</strong> total Order <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Universe <strong>of</strong>Subsistence in general – that <strong>the</strong>se procedures were <strong>the</strong> preoccupat i<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> olderAcademy and <strong>of</strong> c<strong>on</strong>temporaneous Pythagorean circles. But how is this specificallyc<strong>on</strong>nected with our particular passage in D.?In fact <strong>the</strong>re were those, who denied any direct c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>, and accused D. <strong>of</strong>misunderstanding. Admirably enough <strong>the</strong>y even pointed at a passage in Aristotle,which, <strong>the</strong>y claimed, was misunderstood by D. [22]. The passage is in Met. N.1087b.25-33 (esp. b32, see also N. 1087b4-9), where admittedly <strong>the</strong> clause ἔσται γὰρ τὸ ἓν ὀλίγον matches well, in all externals, D.’s clause: οὐ γὰρ ἓν ὣς ἐλάχιστον.But in fact we have here just that kind <strong>of</strong> superficial interpretati<strong>on</strong> which marsso much in modern attempts at understanding ancient philosophy in general, andGreek Metaphysics in particular, and most especially Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ism. To see this clearlyin <strong>the</strong> present instance <strong>on</strong>e should firstly notice <strong>the</strong> extreme frivolity <strong>of</strong> Aristotle ’spoint here [23]. The argument is this: Some philosophers claim that a pair <strong>of</strong>c<strong>on</strong>traries ( ἐνάντια) are <strong>the</strong> ultimate principles <strong>of</strong> all reality. Som e (notablySpeusippus) maintain that this fundamental pair is <strong>the</strong> One and <strong>the</strong> πλῆθος. But <strong>the</strong>c<strong>on</strong>trary to Many is <strong>the</strong> Few (drawing <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> ordinary-language oppositi<strong>on</strong> between<strong>the</strong> few and <strong>the</strong> many). Hence <strong>the</strong>ir One must be <strong>the</strong> Few. As if <strong>on</strong>e who wouldpropound <strong>the</strong> view c<strong>on</strong>cerning <strong>the</strong> ultimate nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>trariety between Oneand Πλῆθος, could possibly mean by Πλῆθος <strong>the</strong> Many, instead <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> obviouslyintended Multiplicity, whe<strong>the</strong>r large or small.


11No philosopher could seriously be taken in by such an argument, nor be misledby it. Least <strong>of</strong> all a Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ist [24], and less than least D. himself.It might seem presumptuous to reject an explanati<strong>on</strong> (however futile) <strong>of</strong> whatD. is here referring to, without <strong>of</strong>fering ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>on</strong>e in its place. But I do not thi nkthat we should at all cost strive to pinpoint <strong>the</strong> sources <strong>of</strong> a testim<strong>on</strong>y like <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e wemeet here in D. To insist immoderately <strong>on</strong> this is <strong>the</strong> proximate cause <strong>of</strong> muchsuperficiality which has found its way into many a historical and interpretativeattempt. We may just be unable to reach a definite soluti<strong>on</strong> in some cases; crucialevidence may be lacking to us. In view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> hideous lacunae in <strong>the</strong> transmittedpicture <strong>of</strong> ancient philosophy under which we operate, it needs no extreme modestyto discard supe rficialities while at <strong>the</strong> same time c<strong>on</strong>fessing inability to reachdefinitive c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s.Happily though, in our case we need not have recourse to such generalremarks. For it can be shown that D. had in mind something immeasurably moreimportant than a misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> a frivolous argument ad hominem.Speusippus, we saw, distinguished and separated <strong>the</strong> One and <strong>the</strong> Good,c<strong>on</strong>sidering <strong>the</strong> former as first principle, <strong>the</strong> latter as final outcome in <strong>the</strong> derivati<strong>on</strong>or c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> totality <strong>of</strong> reality. No w Good implies perfecti<strong>on</strong>; and ifperfecti<strong>on</strong> appears or presents itself at <strong>the</strong> very last stage <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> said c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong>reality (as <strong>the</strong> crowning achievement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> producti<strong>on</strong>, much as <strong>the</strong>perfected animal stands at <strong>the</strong> very end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> line <strong>of</strong> development whose firstinchoate beginning is given with <strong>the</strong> seed), <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r we are removed fromthat final stage <strong>the</strong> less perfect is <strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong> affairs in which we are. In this way firstprinciples must be imperfect par excellence [25].But how are we to c<strong>on</strong>ceive that imperfecti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first principles accordingto Speusippus? We have a valuable hint from Aristotle. In Met. N.1092a11-15 [26],he says in so many words that for some people (namely Speusippus and (some <strong>of</strong>?)<strong>the</strong> Pythagoreans) <strong>the</strong> first principles are so incomplete and imperfect ( ἀτελεῖς) that<strong>the</strong> One (<strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ultimate Principles) is not even ὄν τι – it is not a being, <strong>on</strong>eam<strong>on</strong>g <strong>the</strong> beings [27].Perhaps <strong>the</strong>n we can amplify <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian hint [28]. Perhaps for Speusippus(or, at least, for a certain current interpretati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> Speusippus ’ system) <strong>the</strong> prior hasnothing <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> posterior which follows up<strong>on</strong> it, indeed which is derived from, or


12produced by, it; <strong>the</strong> principle in no way is what it generates, <strong>the</strong> cause what it causesto s ubsist. So we can better understand <strong>the</strong> sense in which a principle is moreimperfect than that <strong>of</strong> which it is a principle; it lacks that which its productpossess. And if this is so in general, <strong>the</strong>n with an ultimate principle, like <strong>the</strong> One, wereach <strong>the</strong> li mits <strong>of</strong> dispossessi<strong>on</strong>, <strong>of</strong> metaphysical poverty; if everything comes tosubsist as a result, ultimately, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> One must lack everything; farfrom being πάντα (after its own peculiar fashi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> course), it has no character, moreor less perfect, whatsoever, since every character comes after it, as a result <strong>of</strong> it. It isbereft <strong>of</strong> all full-blown reality, it is a “least”. We have here a doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> derivati<strong>on</strong>and c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> Reality diametrically opposed to D’s own.Were our <strong>on</strong>ly evidence Aristotle’s hint, still <strong>the</strong> above interpretati<strong>on</strong> would bea fair inference, given <strong>the</strong> peculiar Speusippean view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> derivati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> Reality as aprocessi<strong>on</strong> towards perfecti<strong>on</strong>. But we possess a striking c<strong>on</strong>firmati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> its validity ,as it will be shown elsewhere in <strong>the</strong> sequel.3.3. The syntax is ὅτι (causal) καὶ αὐτό (ἐστι) πάντα πρὸ τῶν πάντων.3.4-5. We have here, as in 2.20, four Principles: ἕν – πολλά – ἡνωμένον –διακεκριμένον. Their c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> and hierarchy will be <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> followingsecti<strong>on</strong>s. Here we see that any<strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m is πάντα, all-inclusive <strong>of</strong> any and everydeterminate reality; what differentiates <strong>the</strong>m <strong>on</strong>e from ano<strong>the</strong>r is <strong>the</strong> different modeunder which each <strong>on</strong>e is πάντα.3.5-13. Τὰ πάντα, <strong>the</strong> sum-total <strong>of</strong> definite reality, subsist, an d <strong>the</strong>refore canbe c<strong>on</strong>ceived, in at least three modes or ways: <strong>on</strong>e-ly ( ἑνιαίως) and unitedly (ἡνωμένως) and multipliedly ( πεπληθυσμένως). The nature, differentiati<strong>on</strong> andc<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se three modes will be explained later, in following secti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>work. In <strong>the</strong> lower margin <strong>of</strong> 2R we have <strong>the</strong> following note by <strong>the</strong> first hand:a) πάντα κατὰ μίαν ἰδέαν ἀδιάκριτον ἑνιαίωςb) πάντα κατὰ σχέσιν καὶ σύνταξιν τὴν ἡνωμένωςπρὸς ἄλληλαc) πάντα κατὰ διάκρισιν ἕκαστα πεπληθυσμένως.3.5. In order to gain a n adequate noti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> τὰ πάντα we must “unfold” ourc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> ( ἔννοια) to cover everything. It is always our c<strong>on</strong>ceptual powers whichstrive to be adequate to <strong>the</strong> intricate complexity <strong>of</strong> reality [29].


133.7-8. ἀφ᾿ ἑνὸς καὶ πρὸς ἕν: <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian technical terms. Like <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong>Aristotelian philosophy, <strong>the</strong>y were in, so to speak, comm<strong>on</strong> stock and <strong>of</strong> everyday useby <strong>the</strong> Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ists (ὡς εἰώθαμεν λέγειν).3.8. The ordinary (συνηθέστερον) use <strong>of</strong> « πάντα» is, <strong>of</strong> course, <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>edenoting a divided, distinguished multiplicity.3.10-11. D. closely c<strong>on</strong>nects c<strong>on</strong>struing <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e hand <strong>the</strong> One and <strong>the</strong>United (τὸ ἓν καὶ τὸ ἡνωμένον – which are principles, <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e proximate <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rmediated, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Multiple or multiplied, τὸ πεπληθυσμένον) as πάντα, with <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r hand co-c<strong>on</strong>ceiving ( συλλάβοιμεν) <strong>the</strong>m toge<strong>the</strong>r with everything else inaccordance with <strong>the</strong>ir relati<strong>on</strong>ship and co-ordinati<strong>on</strong> ( σχέσιν τε καὶ σύνταξιν) wi<strong>the</strong>verything else. And this we explained above: making <strong>of</strong> X <strong>the</strong> cause <strong>of</strong> πάντα, is tobring X into some sort <strong>of</strong> c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with its products, and this can <strong>on</strong>ly be if Xalready is, in some fashi<strong>on</strong> or o<strong>the</strong>r, its products.3.13-4.5. Here we have <strong>the</strong> first occurrence <strong>of</strong> a very important ἀπορία whichwill be treated more explicitly by D. in <strong>the</strong> sequel, within <strong>the</strong> present secti<strong>on</strong>. In short<strong>the</strong> ἀπορία is: Is not <strong>the</strong> One sufficient for <strong>the</strong> positi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolutelyPrimal Principle? Here this crucial questi<strong>on</strong> is introduced as follows:D. argued above that since <strong>the</strong> One is πάντα ἑνιαίως, and since <strong>the</strong> reality <strong>of</strong>παντότης cannot appear right at <strong>the</strong> absolute beginning presupposing as it doessomething prior to it (indeed two at least prior realities: πολλότης and πέρας, v.1.10), <strong>the</strong>re must be something above <strong>the</strong> One. He already met a first rejoinder (2.19-21) to <strong>the</strong> effect that <strong>the</strong> One has nothing to do with πάντα, being prior to <strong>the</strong>m. Hesupposes now <strong>the</strong> objector to argue that, granted that even <strong>the</strong> One must somehowcomprise πάντα, yet it is primarily just <strong>on</strong>e and <strong>on</strong>ly sec<strong>on</strong>darily πάντα, and hence<strong>on</strong>e need not posit a nything above it (3.13-17). To which D. replies that in this way,a certain distincti<strong>on</strong> is surrepti tiously introduced into <strong>the</strong> One ( διπλόην [30] ἐν αὐτῷθήσεται); for we would <strong>the</strong>n be able to distinguish two moments in it, <strong>on</strong>e being <strong>the</strong>primary according to which <strong>the</strong> One is just and <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r being sec<strong>on</strong>dary,and c<strong>on</strong>sisting in <strong>the</strong> One ’s comprising somehow τὰ πάντα. But <strong>the</strong> One in itself isexempt from <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> any such distincti<strong>on</strong> within itself; it is <strong>on</strong>ly we (i.e. ourc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> it) who are distinguished and divided in our desperate attempt to forman adequate noti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> it; in itself, <strong>the</strong> One is πάντα just by being One , and after


14<strong>the</strong> fashi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> its <strong>on</strong>e-ness, i.e. in an absolutely simple way; hence no moments canbe distinguished in it.But if we now correct <strong>the</strong> formulati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> said objecti<strong>on</strong>, in accordance with<strong>the</strong> true state <strong>of</strong> affairs, and say that <strong>the</strong> One, if it is πάντα at all, it is so by its very,absolutely simple, nature ( qua c<strong>on</strong>sidered as <strong>the</strong> cause <strong>of</strong> πάντα), implying <strong>the</strong>re bythat it is fit for <strong>the</strong> positi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolutely first principle – if we say this, again weerr, because <strong>the</strong> absolutely first principle must be superior (bey<strong>on</strong>d) even <strong>of</strong> that allpregnantabsolute simplicity which is <strong>the</strong> One [31].4.1. I indicated, with uncertainty, a lacuna, for two reas<strong>on</strong>s:a) The flow <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> passage seems to me being impaired. Without a lacuna wemust understand “if some<strong>on</strong>e says this, firstly he posits in <strong>the</strong> One a distincti<strong>on</strong>,whereas it is we who divide and are doubled and multiplied c<strong>on</strong>cerning its simplicity”.But if so, <strong>the</strong> natural phrasing would be πρῶτον μὲν διπλ. ἐν αὐτῷ θήσεται, ἡμῶνὄντων των μεριζόντων etc., or something similar.b) The μὲν in 3.17 is not co-ordinated to <strong>the</strong> δὲ <strong>of</strong> 4.1 – ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> phrase towhich δὲ bel<strong>on</strong>gs answers what is said in <strong>the</strong> sentence including μὲν. Fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> πρῶτον in 3.17 cannot be matched with ἡμεῖς δὲ etc., as if this latter sentence was asec<strong>on</strong>d reas<strong>on</strong> against <strong>the</strong> objector’s formulati<strong>on</strong>.(b) is ra<strong>the</strong>r weak. For πρῶτον μὲν can be taken as c<strong>on</strong>ti nued in εἰ δὲ καὶ τοῦτο etc. 4.3, which really, according to my interpretati<strong>on</strong> above, represents <strong>the</strong>reformulati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> objecti<strong>on</strong> in order to meet what was urged against it in its firstand original formulati<strong>on</strong>. (a) is str<strong>on</strong>ger but not c<strong>on</strong>clusive ei<strong>the</strong>r , given <strong>the</strong>idiosyncratic, hypomnematic manner <strong>of</strong> D.’s writing.If <strong>the</strong>re is a lacuna, <strong>the</strong>n ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> suggesti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sidering εἰ δὲ καὶ τοῦτοetc. (4.3) as answering to πρῶτον μὲν is correct, in which case <strong>the</strong> lacuna would beshort (something like ἡμεῖς δὲ etc.); or we must expect asec<strong>on</strong>d reas<strong>on</strong> (which <strong>on</strong>e?) against <strong>the</strong> first formulati<strong>on</strong>, in which case <strong>the</strong> lacunawould be l<strong>on</strong>ger.4.4-5. I think « αὐτῶν τῶν πάντων» refers to πάντα as a divided totality(which is <strong>the</strong> comm<strong>on</strong> noti<strong>on</strong> v . 3.8); « ἁπλουστάτης παντότητος» may refer to <strong>the</strong>ἡνωμένον, <strong>the</strong> United; « τῆς πάντα καταπιούσης ἁπλότητος» would <strong>the</strong>n signify <strong>the</strong>One. I suggest this, in order to capture <strong>the</strong> subtle difference (really trivial for a


15Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ist worth his name ) between ἁπλουστάτη παντότης <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e hand,and πάντα καταπιοῦσα ἁπλότης <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.4.6-10. This represents t he formal statement <strong>of</strong> D. ’s main <strong>the</strong>sis in <strong>the</strong> firstsecti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> his work. Such a doctrine can, <strong>of</strong> course, <strong>on</strong>ly be divined (μαντεύεται) byour soul, and this again <strong>on</strong>ly if she exerted herself to <strong>the</strong> uttermost <strong>of</strong> her powers.The absolutely ultimate ground <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Universe must have no co-ordinati<strong>on</strong>whatever, however slight, however indirect with <strong>the</strong> Universe <strong>of</strong> Realityitself [32].But if so, <strong>the</strong>n it cannot be even principle or cause; for every principle andcause qua principle and cause [33] is a principle and cause <strong>of</strong> something, and in thisway c<strong>on</strong>nected and co-ordinated with that <strong>of</strong> which it is a principle and cause. Andsimilarly, <strong>the</strong> Absolute Ground cannot be “first” reality, or before everything orbey<strong>on</strong>d everything – let al<strong>on</strong>e be everything in whatever way . All <strong>the</strong>se appellati<strong>on</strong>spresuppose some c<strong>on</strong>taminati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ultimate Principle effected through its beingbrought into a certain kind <strong>of</strong> relati<strong>on</strong>ship with what follows it [ 34]. In short <strong>the</strong>genuinely Absolute Ultimate Principle and Ground cannot be absolute orUltimate or Principle or Ground. C<strong>on</strong>sequently, it can by no means be praised, orc<strong>on</strong>ceived or surmised.4.10-5.2. There follows an analysis <strong>of</strong> th e last point, which leads, via aprotestati<strong>on</strong> against positing something above <strong>the</strong> One (5.2-5.14), to <strong>the</strong> directargumentati<strong>on</strong> (5.14-9.10) in favour <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main <strong>the</strong>sis.4.10. ἐννοεῖν = c<strong>on</strong>ceive.ὑπονοεῖν = sub-c<strong>on</strong>ceive, c<strong>on</strong>ceive indirectly and after a fashi<strong>on</strong>.ἐπινοεῖν may have something <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> flavor <strong>of</strong> “inve nt”, i.e. c<strong>on</strong>structmentally, in which sense it may form a fitting c<strong>on</strong>trast to νοεῖν, meant here broadly,= think <strong>of</strong> directly [35]. But mainly, I think, it c<strong>on</strong>veys <strong>the</strong> sense “c<strong>on</strong>ceiveadditi<strong>on</strong>ally to something (already c<strong>on</strong>ceived)”, as if applying to a sec<strong>on</strong>d orderc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>, or <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> a feature <strong>of</strong> something already c<strong>on</strong>ceived in aprimary c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>. Cf. similar c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s , like ἐπιγιγνόμενον τέλος (Aristotle),ἐπιφαινόμενον etc.Anything that we can c<strong>on</strong>ceive is, strictly speaking ( καὶ τοῦτό γεἀληθέστερον), something determinate; to a definite c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> corresp<strong>on</strong>ds adeterminate c<strong>on</strong>tent – however abstrac this c<strong>on</strong>tent and <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>cept “intending”


16[36] it may be. Now <strong>the</strong> def inite determinateness (however abstract) <strong>of</strong> a c<strong>on</strong>tentimplies its being “set against” o<strong>the</strong>r c<strong>on</strong>tents equally determinate (though, maybe,more or less abstract), just as its self-identity as that determinate c<strong>on</strong>tent which it is,is <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side <strong>of</strong> its oth erness from o<strong>the</strong>r c<strong>on</strong>tents. Thus, evidently,determinateness (alike in c<strong>on</strong>tents and in c<strong>on</strong>cepts“intending” c<strong>on</strong>tents)presupposes a multiplicity <strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> whose members <strong>the</strong> particular determinateness inquesti<strong>on</strong> is. C<strong>on</strong>sequently, every proper c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>ce ives τὶ τῶν πάντων, as D.says, since it c<strong>on</strong>ceives a determinate c<strong>on</strong>tent, which, just in virtue <strong>of</strong> its bearing(and c<strong>on</strong>sisting in) a definite determinateness, c<strong>on</strong>trasts itself to, ultimately, everyo<strong>the</strong>r <strong>on</strong>tologically available (= subsisting) c<strong>on</strong>tent.But if this is our mind ’s proper way <strong>of</strong> c<strong>on</strong>ceiving, we can attain to somethinghigher, something <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> a principle, by striving towards a διακάθαρσις <strong>of</strong>our c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s. This “thorough purificati<strong>on</strong>” c<strong>on</strong>sists in trying to lay aside preciselythat afo rementi<strong>on</strong>ed definite determinateness which goes toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong>c<strong>on</strong>ceived c<strong>on</strong>tent’s being <strong>on</strong>e out <strong>of</strong> many (co-ordinated in some way or o<strong>the</strong>r)c<strong>on</strong>tents. This “purging” from our c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> μερισμός, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> divisi<strong>on</strong> intoparts, which is implicit in our normal understanding <strong>of</strong> determinateness (and <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>realm <strong>of</strong> reality towards and to which this understanding attaches) leads toc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s [37] whose intended c<strong>on</strong>tent (if we may speak <strong>of</strong> “c<strong>on</strong>tents” here)covers <strong>the</strong> entire field <strong>of</strong> what was apprehended before <strong>the</strong> κάθαρσις aspartiti<strong>on</strong>ed and divided up into <strong>the</strong> various determinate c<strong>on</strong>tents. Not, <strong>of</strong> course,that <strong>the</strong> new, purified c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s (and <strong>the</strong> realities corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to <strong>the</strong>m) areabsolutely indeterminate; in fact <strong>the</strong> very plural used in indicating <strong>the</strong>m implies that<strong>the</strong>y are distinguished <strong>on</strong>e from ano<strong>the</strong>r and <strong>the</strong>re cannot be distincti<strong>on</strong> in <strong>the</strong> totallyindeterminate; it is ra<strong>the</strong>r that <strong>the</strong>y are not distinguished, and not determinate, in <strong>the</strong>fashi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> former <strong>on</strong>es, not, that is, as a part <strong>of</strong> a whole is c<strong>on</strong>trast ed to, anddistinguished from, ano<strong>the</strong>r part <strong>of</strong> it, but as <strong>on</strong>e and <strong>the</strong> same whole (i.e. <strong>the</strong> totality<strong>of</strong> everything) is distinguished in accordance with various modes and characters <strong>of</strong> itssubsistence. But it is premature at this stage to insist fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>on</strong> this point.The validity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> above interpretati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> purificati<strong>on</strong> (διακαθαίρειν) as appliedto reas<strong>on</strong>ed philosophy is born out, for example by D. ’s remarks <strong>on</strong> 275.8, 276.9-12.[37a]


17The highest point which this process <strong>of</strong> purificati<strong>on</strong> can reach is <strong>the</strong> On e – <strong>the</strong>simplest subsisting reality, which still (and that was essential in <strong>the</strong> process) coverseverything (and hence is, after a fashi<strong>on</strong>, everything), exhausts <strong>the</strong> field <strong>of</strong> bothbeing and n<strong>on</strong>-being [38]. For i t is, as we shall see, not <strong>the</strong> One itself but moreappropriately specifically and immediately <strong>the</strong> ἡνωμένον (that is <strong>the</strong> third FirstPrinciple, counting from <strong>the</strong> One as <strong>the</strong> first, since <strong>the</strong> absolutely ineffable UltimateGround must be properly left out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> counting) which is <strong>the</strong> proper principle <strong>of</strong>being; but in <strong>the</strong> abstract noti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> πολλά, n<strong>on</strong>-bein g is also included al<strong>on</strong>g withbeing, since a n<strong>on</strong>-being is equally “some-<strong>on</strong>e-thing”.D. c<strong>on</strong>nects <strong>the</strong> all-inclusiveness (<strong>of</strong> n<strong>on</strong>-being as well as <strong>of</strong> being) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Onewith its absolute simplicity (τῶν δὲ πολλῶν ἁπλῶς, τὸ ἕν (sc. ἔσχατον)· τοῦ γὰρ ἑνὸςἁπλούστερον οὐδὲν ἔχομεν ἐννοεῖν, τοῦ πάντη ἑνὸς καὶ μόνον ἑνὸς etc.). See 60.5: διὰ τοῦτο γὰρ ἁπλούστατον (sc. τὸ ἕν), ὅτι περιεκτικώτατον. And <strong>the</strong>re is a deep lyingmetaphysical reas<strong>on</strong> for this c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>. Suppose X is <strong>the</strong> [39] absolutely simplereality; <strong>the</strong>n i t must be all-inclusive. For suppose that it is not; <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re is“something” which is not X; let it be y. Ei<strong>the</strong>r X and y have something in comm<strong>on</strong>, z,or not; if <strong>the</strong> f οrmer, <strong>the</strong>n X is complex, being a certain modificati<strong>on</strong> or qualificati<strong>on</strong><strong>of</strong> z, ano<strong>the</strong>r be ing <strong>the</strong> y; if <strong>the</strong> latter, reality cannot be derived in its totality from asingle ultimate principle, which is <strong>the</strong> negati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> metaphysical m<strong>on</strong>ism, and, in <strong>the</strong>last analysis, <strong>the</strong> negati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> interc<strong>on</strong>nectedness <strong>of</strong> all reality [40]. Andc<strong>on</strong>versely, suppo se that X is all-inclusive; <strong>the</strong>n it must be absolutely simple. Forsuppose that it is not; <strong>the</strong>n we can distinguish in it at least two, say, “notes” orcharacters Y, Z; obviously, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong>re can be Z-things which are not Y (and viceversa), and <strong>the</strong>se would not properly fall under X; if it is objected that Y and Z maybe necessarily c<strong>on</strong>nected so that nothing can be <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e which is not <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r aswell (and that, in fact, at <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> abstracti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> which we move, we shouldexpect that this is so), <strong>the</strong>n we reply that in such a case we should ask for <strong>the</strong>ground <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> that c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> (since philosophy is nothing if not <strong>the</strong>earnest and devoted search for Ultimate explanati<strong>on</strong>s); and <strong>the</strong>n that Ground wouldbe <strong>the</strong> really ultimate principle, not <strong>the</strong> X as it was supposed.4.17-18. A textual difficulty is presented by <strong>the</strong> occurrence <strong>of</strong> καὶ in 4.18before κατὰ. The reading and punctuati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> A (comma after μόνον) give <strong>the</strong>following sense (retaining <strong>the</strong> καὶ): “it is <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>the</strong>re (in <strong>the</strong> One) that <strong>the</strong>se ar e to be


18found, and (<strong>the</strong>re found) in accordance with <strong>the</strong> One – as it befits <strong>the</strong> One”. Now thismight be possible; for instance <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>trast could be meant <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One which is firstprinciple etc., and, <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> o ne hand, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ineffable which is bey<strong>on</strong>d even <strong>the</strong>seh<strong>on</strong>ours, and <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand <strong>of</strong> anything that follows <strong>the</strong> One which maybe has<strong>the</strong>se or similar features, but in an inferior way and degree. But <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> καὶπάντα τὰ ἄλλα makes this interpretati<strong>on</strong> unacceptably strained.I have adopted in <strong>the</strong> text <strong>the</strong> simple expedient <strong>of</strong> a<strong>the</strong>tizing καὶ (perhaps <strong>the</strong>same word or compendium was transcribed twice, as καὶ and as κατὰ?). One couldpropose ἐκεῖ μὲν


19is in this secti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>ly subservient to <strong>the</strong> elucidati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> that, and not carried <strong>on</strong> foritself.4.23. It is because <strong>the</strong> One is πάντα, that everything comes out from <strong>the</strong>One, devolves from it, winds <strong>of</strong>f from it.4.25-5.1. There is a nature <strong>of</strong> πολλὰ inherent in <strong>the</strong>m, internally c<strong>on</strong>stituting<strong>the</strong>m in <strong>the</strong>ir diverse multiplicity; and <strong>the</strong>re is a nature <strong>of</strong> πολλά transcendent to<strong>the</strong>m, externally c<strong>on</strong>stituting (i.e. producing) <strong>the</strong>m in <strong>the</strong>ir diverse multiplicity. Even τὰ πολλά, qua πολλά, have <strong>on</strong>e certain nature ( and <strong>the</strong>y “ are” or, better, is indeed<strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first principles, as we shall see); o<strong>the</strong>rwise <strong>the</strong>y could not subsist at all:<strong>the</strong> primal prerequisite for subsistence (i.e. presence in tot al reality) is<strong>on</strong>eness. (This should be c<strong>on</strong>nected with what we already said about <strong>the</strong>presuppositi<strong>on</strong> and derivati<strong>on</strong> order <strong>of</strong> reality).5.1-2. πᾶν and ὅλον are distinct from each o<strong>the</strong>r. But <strong>of</strong> this later, in itsappropriate place, where, descending in <strong>the</strong> s tructure <strong>of</strong> reality (i.e. following <strong>the</strong>derivati<strong>on</strong>–order <strong>of</strong> reality) we shall meet <strong>the</strong>m.*5.2-5.14. Here is <strong>the</strong> important protestati<strong>on</strong>: if <strong>the</strong> One is such as (roughlyand preliminarily) was described above by D., why is it not <strong>the</strong> absolutely primalprinciple? What sense can we give to <strong>the</strong> claim and <strong>the</strong>re is still “something” [42] elsebey<strong>on</strong>d (ἐπέκεινα) <strong>the</strong> One? Are we not proceeding in <strong>the</strong> void, having passed <strong>the</strong>bounds <strong>of</strong> reality (and sense) and merely indulging in c<strong>on</strong>ceptual hallucinati<strong>on</strong>s?The metaphysical ground <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> protestati<strong>on</strong> is this. What is nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> One,nor <strong>on</strong>e, it is μηδέν, i.e. nothing. So are we posing <strong>the</strong> Nothing as <strong>the</strong> absolutely andultimately Primal Principle? [43] Besides, what is <strong>the</strong> necessity forcing <strong>the</strong> Reas<strong>on</strong> toaccept such a principle bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> One? We have as certain datum <strong>the</strong> Many . Weask for <strong>the</strong>ir cause or principle. Such a cause cannot be <strong>the</strong> Nothing – for Nothing canbeget nothing. Nor can it be that <strong>the</strong> πολλὰ are self- caused; for <strong>the</strong>y cannotc<strong>on</strong>stitute ei<strong>the</strong>r a cause <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves as such, or many causes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves assuch; from which it follows that <strong>the</strong>y are no cause <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves.Pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first point: qua πολλὰ, qua indeterminate multiplicity, <strong>the</strong>y aredisordered, un-ordered (it is <strong>the</strong>ir proceeding from <strong>the</strong> One, that imposes <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>msome form <strong>of</strong> co-ordinati<strong>on</strong> necessary for <strong>the</strong>m in order to subsist even asπολλὰ); so in nowise can <strong>the</strong>y be a cause <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves; for multiplicity as such and


20in its elf (apart from <strong>the</strong> ordering influence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One functi<strong>on</strong>ing as regulatingprinciple) is not some-<strong>on</strong>e-thing ex hypo<strong>the</strong>si.Pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d point: <strong>the</strong>y can not be many causes (<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves). Forsince in <strong>the</strong>ir pristine, unc<strong>on</strong>taminated c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>y a re totally un-coordinated (achaotic mess – if <strong>on</strong>e can speak even <strong>of</strong> a chaotic mess), it is not possible that“any<strong>on</strong>e” [44] <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m can be a cause <strong>of</strong> any o<strong>the</strong>r; and <strong>the</strong> same is proven by <strong>the</strong>c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> that were it so, we would end by making “<strong>on</strong>e and th e same” itemsimultaneously cause and effect in <strong>the</strong> same respect [45]. So, if at all, each <strong>on</strong>ewould be cause <strong>of</strong> itself. But <strong>the</strong>ir multiplicity as such would still remain uncaused;and we were investigating about <strong>the</strong> cause <strong>of</strong> πολλὰ, qua πολλά.So that cause is nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> Μηδέν, nor <strong>the</strong> Πολλά. It has, <strong>the</strong>refore, to be <strong>the</strong>One.This exactly was <strong>the</strong> procedure – urges <strong>the</strong> objector. From which it is clearlyseen that <strong>the</strong>re is no need <strong>of</strong> anything else than <strong>the</strong> One, as cause <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> πολλά (Ἅλφου γὰρ οὐδενός… ἢ τοῦ ἑνὸς 5.6); <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>the</strong> One is cause above <strong>the</strong>πολλά – and nothing else ( διὸ μόνον τὸ ἓν αἴτιον τῶν πολλῶν 5.6-7); in fact thiswas <strong>the</strong> reas<strong>on</strong> for which we at all posited <strong>the</strong> One as αἴτιον to begin with, <strong>the</strong>se are<strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>ly and sole credentials for <strong>the</strong> sovereignty <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One ( διὸ καὶ τὸ ἕν πάντων αἴτιον, ὅτι τῶν πολλῶν αἴτιον δεῖ μόνον εἶναι τὸ ἕν 5.7-8). So what are <strong>the</strong> credentialsfor a principle bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> One? What necessity necessitates us to posit such afur<strong>the</strong>r principle [46].5.9. There is an anwkard textual situati<strong>on</strong> here (see my textual note ad loc.).Perhaps we might read: ᾗ γὰρ ἀσύντακτα, [ καὶ] πῶς ἓν αἴτιον ἔσται τὰ πολλά; Orindeed: ἦ γὰρ ἀσύντακτα (for verily <strong>the</strong>y (<strong>the</strong> πολλά) are un-coordinated), καὶ πῶςetc. Perhaps also, but I do not think it is likely, <strong>the</strong>re is a lacuna here, to be suppliedso as to give <strong>the</strong> following sense, “The πολλά cannot be an ultimate cause; for ei<strong>the</strong>r<strong>the</strong>y are coordinated or not; if <strong>the</strong> former, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re must be something which coordinates<strong>the</strong>m, for in <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>the</strong>y cannot generate order; if <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d, how can<strong>the</strong>y be <strong>on</strong>e αἴτιον, since <strong>the</strong>y are totally and absolutely unc<strong>on</strong>nected, so that <strong>the</strong>reis no sense in which <strong>the</strong>y possess a unity <strong>of</strong> whatever kind or degree”.5.14-9.10. Here is D.’s reply to <strong>the</strong> objectio n urged above that <strong>the</strong> Onesuffices as an ultimate principle.


21He begins by acknowledging <strong>the</strong> force <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> objecti<strong>on</strong> (5.17-18). He himselfputs in <strong>the</strong> mouth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> objector, what he evidently thinks is a str<strong>on</strong>g point, namelythat if <strong>the</strong> One is <strong>the</strong> very limi t at which our c<strong>on</strong>ceiving powers (and <strong>the</strong>se whenutterly strained for that matter) can reach, how can we entertain at all <strong>the</strong> noti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong>something bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> One. Obviously D. is far from Mysticism, in <strong>the</strong> modernEuropean sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term, he is a thorough Greek Rati<strong>on</strong>alist. [47]The formulati<strong>on</strong> in 5.17-20, leaves no doubt that <strong>the</strong> issue was deeply felt byD.: “We must begin with what is nearer to us and more graspable by our mind ( ἐκ τῶν ἡμῖν γνωριμωτέρων) [48], and building <strong>on</strong> this secure for our understa ndingfoundati<strong>on</strong>, we must accustom ( ἀνεθιστέον) our mental unformulable travails, <strong>the</strong>anguish and pangs <strong>of</strong> a birth which cannot come to pass, to <strong>the</strong> ineffable awarenessor apprehensi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> that proud, sublime Truth” [49].5.19-20. οὐκ οἶδα ὅπως εἴπω qualifies <strong>the</strong> συναίσθησις: that sublime truth isnot <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> sensati<strong>on</strong>, percepti<strong>on</strong>, imaginati<strong>on</strong>, reas<strong>on</strong>ing, c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>,intellecti<strong>on</strong>.There follow three arguments for <strong>the</strong> principle bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> One: A. 5.20-6.7; B.6.8-17; C. 6.17-7.8.A. 5.20-6.7. For Neopla t<strong>on</strong>ism, it takes power to possess unc<strong>on</strong>taminatedpurity; to be able to secure separate existence, to preserve <strong>on</strong>e ’s own precious selfidentityapart and distinct from what is similar or dissimilar to itself, to keep clearfrom what o<strong>the</strong>r claims <strong>on</strong>eself as its own or from what else aspires to <strong>on</strong>e and<strong>the</strong>refore attempts to draw it down to fructify, as it were, <strong>the</strong> aspiring receptor, to becapable <strong>of</strong> “affirming” <strong>on</strong>e ’s own nature so as to guard it unmolested fromextraneous mingling; untouched by foreign influences – <strong>the</strong>se are marks <strong>of</strong> power, <strong>of</strong>eminence, <strong>of</strong> value, <strong>of</strong> priority [50]. This is so everywhere, in this World and in thingstranscending this World, in men and in nature. Thus, in general, in each and everycase, before <strong>the</strong> related and co-ordinated lies t he relati<strong>on</strong>less and un-coordinated,before that which in its own nature involves an <strong>on</strong>tological reference (be it str<strong>on</strong>g orweak) to something else, <strong>the</strong>re always lies that which, being disseve red fromanything else in <strong>the</strong> field examined, enjoys an unmolested, referenceless purity.But now this general metaphysical principle can be applied in two stages:firstly we recognize and posit by reas<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> it <strong>the</strong> principle or cause <strong>of</strong> any givenordered field as something over and above <strong>the</strong> field itself and its immanen t order, as


22something whose immediate product, and, so to speak, reflecti<strong>on</strong>, <strong>the</strong> immanentorder (and hence <strong>the</strong> field as a certain determinate field) is. In this way, we raiseabove <strong>the</strong> ὁμοταγῆ (things which co-bel<strong>on</strong>g to a certain order) <strong>the</strong> principle <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m;this does not have <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>nectedness displayed by <strong>the</strong> ὁμοταγῆ, this lacks <strong>the</strong>ir way<strong>of</strong> <strong>on</strong>tologically referring to each o<strong>the</strong>r, and is so, in virtue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> said <strong>the</strong>orem,“higher” from <strong>the</strong>m , lying “above” <strong>the</strong>m . But though this principle (and here weprepare for <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d stage <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> applicati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orem) is immune from <strong>the</strong>inter-referring <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> items bel<strong>on</strong>ging to <strong>the</strong> field whose principle it is, yet is notcompletely absolved from any referring whatsoever; for if a principle, it is a principle<strong>of</strong> something , if higher, it is higher than something; if first, it is first withreference to what follows it , if a cause, it is a cause <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> caused thing .Thus reference-being still inf ests such principles as are seen through <strong>the</strong> firstapplicati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> our <strong>the</strong>orem. We thus, again in c<strong>on</strong>formity to it, must pose that whichis totally immune from any reference, relati<strong>on</strong> or c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> and co-ordinati<strong>on</strong>whatsoever; and as <strong>the</strong> One, which is high er [51] than everything else, has thatrelati<strong>on</strong>ship to be higher than, and a principle <strong>of</strong>, everything else and thus thisminimal co-ordinati<strong>on</strong> with everything else; so that reality which our sec<strong>on</strong>dapplicati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> aforementi<strong>on</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>orem requires, must b e above and bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong>One with an above-ness and bey<strong>on</strong>d-ness which transcends any c<strong>on</strong>ceivable andformulable above-being or bey<strong>on</strong>d-being [52].We shall compare in detail this doctrine with that <strong>of</strong> Proclus later, whenenough material has been ga<strong>the</strong>red from D.’s development. But we may point here,preliminarily, its metaphysical significance.Suppose, for brevity ’s sake, that two reality-c<strong>on</strong>tents X and Y are mutuallyexclusive and jointly exhaustive in a certain field, in <strong>the</strong> sense that any itembel<strong>on</strong>ging to <strong>the</strong> field must be ei<strong>the</strong>r X or Y, but cannot be both; suppose also that<strong>the</strong>y essentially divide <strong>the</strong> given field between <strong>the</strong>m, i.e. <strong>the</strong>y are not merelyaccidental properties <strong>of</strong> what bel<strong>on</strong>gs to <strong>the</strong> field. By field we mean a system <strong>of</strong> itemsobeying a certain order, this obeying being c<strong>on</strong>stitutive <strong>of</strong> it as that specific field, i.e.an essentially co-ordinated system <strong>of</strong> items. Since X and Y pertain essentially to <strong>on</strong>eand <strong>the</strong> same field, <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>mselves are ὁμοταγῆ, coordinated, <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> samelevel, namely that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> field in questi<strong>on</strong> (which may be picturesquely portrayed as ahoriz<strong>on</strong>tal cut <strong>of</strong> reality). Hence, <strong>the</strong>y cannot be c<strong>on</strong>nected as <strong>the</strong> primary to <strong>the</strong>


23sec<strong>on</strong>dary, as <strong>the</strong> eminent to <strong>the</strong> inferior (in degree or kind), as <strong>the</strong> possessi<strong>on</strong> to <strong>the</strong>privati<strong>on</strong>: <strong>the</strong>y are ra<strong>the</strong>r both positive natures, perfected to <strong>the</strong> same degree each inits own kind and manner, pitched, as it were, <strong>on</strong>e against <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> samet<strong>on</strong>e; <strong>the</strong>y corresp<strong>on</strong>d to each o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y are not subordinated <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.The field, qua <strong>the</strong> field which it is, must have a transcendent principle, <strong>the</strong>cause <strong>of</strong> its immanent principle <strong>of</strong> ordering. And since X and Y essentially divide <strong>the</strong>field, being thus a cardinal comp<strong>on</strong>ent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prevai ling order, <strong>the</strong>ir so doing, and<strong>the</strong>refore <strong>the</strong>ir natures enabling <strong>the</strong>m to so do, must equally well proceed from <strong>the</strong>said principle. This principle being bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> initial field, and thus exempt from <strong>the</strong>order which it creates, cannot be ei<strong>the</strong>r X or Y. X an d Y, as disjoint but c<strong>on</strong>nectedreality-c<strong>on</strong>tents, appear for <strong>the</strong> first “time” in <strong>the</strong> chain <strong>of</strong> reality o n <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> thatinitial field . But still <strong>the</strong>y must come from somewhere; and, fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y mustalready be in that from which <strong>the</strong>y come in order to be able to come at all andmanifest <strong>the</strong>mselves primarily and for <strong>the</strong> first “time” in <strong>the</strong> said field [53].C<strong>on</strong>sequently, since <strong>the</strong> principle <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> field must be X and Y, but cannot be so in<strong>the</strong> divided way in which <strong>the</strong> field itself is X and Y, it must be X a nd Y in anundivided fashi<strong>on</strong>, it must possess X and Y in <strong>the</strong>ir unity which is seen thus to bepresupposed by <strong>the</strong>ir separated subsistence. X and Y, we said, are present in <strong>the</strong>initial field as divided by intrinsically c<strong>on</strong>nected reality-c<strong>on</strong>tents; here, in th e principle<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> field, <strong>the</strong> divisi<strong>on</strong> disappears, and <strong>the</strong> intrinsic c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> is transformed intoundivided unitedness, which is really but <strong>the</strong> cause <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>nected separatedness.So we have <strong>the</strong> field, whose formal expressi<strong>on</strong> (in so far as its structur e isc<strong>on</strong>cerned, and with reference to what was assumed as an essential feature <strong>of</strong> thatstructure, namely <strong>the</strong> specific interc<strong>on</strong>nectedness <strong>of</strong> X and Y), may be given as“ei<strong>the</strong>r X or Y ”. And we have <strong>the</strong> field ’s principle, whose corresp<strong>on</strong>ding formalexpressi<strong>on</strong> we saw must be “both X and Y ” [54]. Is <strong>the</strong>re anything else in <strong>the</strong>present c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> to which we must proceed in however dark a way?D.’s c<strong>on</strong>tenti<strong>on</strong> is that <strong>the</strong>re is; that bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> principle which is both X and Yat <strong>on</strong>ce, <strong>the</strong>re must be ano<strong>the</strong>r which can be said to be nei<strong>the</strong>r X , nor Y, nor even Xand Y, which <strong>the</strong>refore, in a certain sense must be nei<strong>the</strong>r X nor Y , exhaustivethough X and Y are, as we assumed at <strong>the</strong> beginning. Three reas<strong>on</strong>s are given herefor this necessity – but <strong>the</strong> significance will gradua lly become more and fuller and


24clearer, as <strong>the</strong> system is fur<strong>the</strong>r developed and articulated and <strong>the</strong> insight deepensaccordingly.This much however can be indicated here: if to be a principle <strong>of</strong> a fieldessentially divided by X and Y, is to be undividedly X and Y at <strong>on</strong>ce, clearly to be afur<strong>the</strong>r “principle” (i.e a fur<strong>the</strong>r necessary link in <strong>the</strong> chain <strong>of</strong> reality) but nei<strong>the</strong>r Xnor Y, is to be no proper principle at all, but bey<strong>on</strong>d a principle. We thus reachabsolute transcendence.6.5-7. The two different fundamental ways <strong>of</strong> co-ordinati<strong>on</strong> (that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> interc<strong>on</strong>necteditems <strong>of</strong> an ordered system, and that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cause to its effect) are clearlyindicated here.B. 6.8-17. The sec<strong>on</strong>d argument hinges <strong>on</strong> what we have already said aboveabout <strong>the</strong> relati<strong>on</strong>ship <strong>of</strong> πάντα to <strong>the</strong>ir principle. If <strong>the</strong> One is still πάντα ἑνιαίως, itcannot be <strong>the</strong> absolutely primal ground <strong>of</strong> all reality; for whence did <strong>the</strong> πάντα comewhich <strong>the</strong> One is ἑνιαίως? Τὰ πάντα, we saw, cannot be something absolutelyultimate. Thus, <strong>the</strong> One (which is, aft er <strong>the</strong> proper fashi<strong>on</strong>, πάντα) is not yetsomething absolutely free from, and bey<strong>on</strong>d, <strong>the</strong> πάντα – which, as we saw, <strong>the</strong>absolutely primal ground <strong>of</strong> all reality must be. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, if <strong>the</strong> One is <strong>the</strong> simplestreality in whose absolute simplicity everything is “ resolved” or reduced and thusencompassed, <strong>the</strong>n it is <strong>the</strong> summit , <strong>the</strong> top point <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> πολλά, and we again haveseen (in <strong>the</strong> discussi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem posed at <strong>the</strong> very beginning <strong>of</strong> this work) thatthis cannot be <strong>the</strong> case with <strong>the</strong> ultimate ground which mus t be absolutely bey<strong>on</strong>d<strong>the</strong> πάντα.6.9. διακρινόμενα: about <strong>the</strong> triad ἡνωμένον – διακρινόμενον – διακεκριμένονand its significance, cf. <strong>the</strong> fourth secti<strong>on</strong>. This triad is in an important sense <strong>the</strong>fundamental form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> universal structure <strong>of</strong> reality according to D.6.9.-10. We have here an in timati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> derivati<strong>on</strong>: ἕν – πολλά –ἡνωμένον – διακρινόμενον, which will occupy us very much at later stages <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>development.6.10. subject <strong>of</strong> διακρίνεται, τὰ διακρινόμενα; subject <strong>of</strong> ἐξελίττεται, τὰπολλά.6.11-12. Τὰ πολλὰ are said to be after <strong>the</strong> One and not in <strong>the</strong> One; <strong>the</strong> Oneis said to be, in a certain way, τὰ πάντα. No tensi<strong>on</strong> really exists: τὰ πολλὰ are to bedistinguished from <strong>the</strong> πάντα. In fact, as we shall see, πολλότης (multiplicity as such)


25is <strong>on</strong>e mode <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subsistence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> πάντα characterizing <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d reality after<strong>the</strong> One, just as ἑνιαίως (<strong>on</strong>e-ly), is ano<strong>the</strong>r such mode c<strong>on</strong>stituting <strong>the</strong> characteristicpeculiarity (ἰδιότης) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One, and ἡνωμένως (united-ly) is still ano<strong>the</strong>r defining <strong>the</strong>third principle, <strong>the</strong> ἡνωμένον or ὄν.6.13. Both <strong>the</strong> One and <strong>the</strong> United (ἡνωμένον) are πάντα, <strong>the</strong> formerpossessing in an absolutely unitary and simple way <strong>the</strong> very nature <strong>of</strong> πάντα in <strong>the</strong>irtotality (since it is <strong>the</strong> first principle – <strong>the</strong> absolutely primal gro und bey<strong>on</strong>d it notbeing counted – <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> πάντα simpliciter), <strong>the</strong> latter involving in absolute unitedness<strong>the</strong> whole structure ( σύνταξιν) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> πάντα in <strong>the</strong>ir totality (since it is <strong>the</strong>proximate principle <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir devoluti<strong>on</strong>, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir making explicit <strong>the</strong>ir orderly system <strong>of</strong>derivati<strong>on</strong>) [55].6.13-17. The argument thus follows: But <strong>the</strong> πάντα, in nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> twomenti<strong>on</strong>ed aspects can be a real ly primal and ultimate principle: Not in <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d,because as a structured totality, τὰ πάντα include <strong>the</strong> last <strong>of</strong>f -spring <strong>of</strong> reality(whatever this is) and <strong>the</strong>refore can be a principle <strong>of</strong> nothing, hence <strong>the</strong>y are not aprinciple at all. Nor in <strong>the</strong>ir first aspect can <strong>the</strong> πάντα be an ultimate principle; forunder that aspect τὰ πάντα is <strong>the</strong> One – and from here follows wh at we said ingeneral above about this sec<strong>on</strong>d argument.6.14. εἰ μὲν κατὰ σύνταξιν sc. λαμβάνονται or νοοῦνται or θεωροῦνται ( τὰπάντα) = if <strong>the</strong>y are taken in <strong>the</strong>ir structured totality.6.14. and 15. ὅτι: causal c<strong>on</strong>juncti<strong>on</strong>.6.14. σὺν αὐτοῖς sc. ἐστι.6.15. αὐτῶν sc. τῶν πάντων.6.15-16. And if <strong>the</strong>y are taken in <strong>the</strong> aspect which is proper to <strong>the</strong> One (thatis, in a certain sense , to <strong>on</strong>e am<strong>on</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m), <strong>the</strong>n (<strong>the</strong>y are not ultimate principleeven in that acceptati<strong>on</strong>) because <strong>the</strong> One (to which <strong>the</strong>y are identical in thatacceptati<strong>on</strong>) is both <strong>on</strong>e and πάντα-in-<strong>the</strong>-fashi<strong>on</strong>-<strong>of</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-<strong>on</strong>e, etc.In <strong>the</strong> higher margin <strong>of</strong> A (f. 3v) <strong>the</strong> first hand has written:πάντα ἓν κατὰ φύσιν πολλὰπάντα ἡνωμένον κατὰ σύνταξιν διακεκριμένα.which means: <strong>the</strong> πάντα taken in <strong>the</strong>ir very nature (in <strong>on</strong>e comprehensi<strong>on</strong>) as <strong>the</strong> allinclusivetotality pertain to <strong>the</strong> One, which gives as proximate product <strong>the</strong> πολλά(multiplicity as such); <strong>the</strong> πάντα taken in <strong>the</strong>ir united structuredness pertain to <strong>the</strong>


26ἡνωμένον, which generates <strong>the</strong> divided, disting uished realities ( διακεκριμένα) whichfollow fur<strong>the</strong>r below in <strong>the</strong>ir orderly devolvement from <strong>the</strong> unitedness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ἡνωμένον [56].C. 6.17-7.8. The One is reached by a last strained effort <strong>of</strong> our c<strong>on</strong>ceptualpowers, by <strong>the</strong> utmost thorough purificati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> our “suspecting” or divining, ra<strong>the</strong>rthan properly intellectually c<strong>on</strong>ceiving, powers. But <strong>the</strong> absolutely ultimate Groundmust be absolutely unreachable, incomprehensible by any <strong>of</strong> our divining orc<strong>on</strong>ceiving faculties. From such absolutely ineffable principle everything must beineffably produced.We may ask “Why?” is that. More than that, we are entitled to ask “why?” inaccordance with Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic Principles. For if I am right in c<strong>on</strong>str uing Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ism(and especially A<strong>the</strong>nian Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ism) as a methodologic ally Absolute Rati<strong>on</strong>alism(indeed as <strong>the</strong> unique system in <strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> World determinedly pushing to <strong>the</strong>very last c<strong>on</strong>sequences what is implied by such Rati<strong>on</strong>alism), <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re must be,according to Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ism, an adequate and sufficient reas<strong>on</strong> for everythingincluding that which transcends in absolutely all ways Reas<strong>on</strong>.The answer to our legitimate questi<strong>on</strong>, is <strong>the</strong>n this. We ascend from <strong>the</strong>already given or reached to its presuppositi<strong>on</strong>, from <strong>the</strong> derivative to its principle,from <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>dary to <strong>the</strong> primary, from <strong>the</strong> effect to its metaphysical cause. And werepeat <strong>the</strong> process again and again, to <strong>the</strong> extent that Reas<strong>on</strong> necessitates us to doso. And Reas<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>strains us to do so in all cases where <strong>the</strong> presupposed cannot betaken as <strong>the</strong> ultimate Datum, as not itself requiring a presuppositi<strong>on</strong>, as not standingin need <strong>of</strong> a fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>on</strong>tological explanati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> its presence in <strong>the</strong> Universal Reality.We can <strong>on</strong>ly stop , we are rati<strong>on</strong>alistically entitled to suspend fur<strong>the</strong>r movement,when we have ascended to so mething, in which Reas<strong>on</strong> acknowledges <strong>the</strong> Plat<strong>on</strong>icἀνυπόθετον.Retracing <strong>the</strong>n thus <strong>the</strong> derivati<strong>on</strong>-chain upwards we reach at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>the</strong>One. This is presupposed (in a structured and orderly way) by everything else whichwe can in whatever direct or devious way c<strong>on</strong>ceive. But does it presuppose in its turnsomething else? Or have we come to <strong>the</strong> rock bottom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Universe, <strong>the</strong> ultimatefoundati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> all reality, <strong>the</strong> absolutely unpresupposing reality?To answer this crucial questi<strong>on</strong> let it be asked: Is <strong>the</strong> One “given” in reality insuch a way as to require no explanati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> its presence <strong>the</strong>re? Is <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong> “Why


27is <strong>the</strong>re at all an One to begin with?” totally devoid <strong>of</strong> meaning? To be sure, if whatis immediately given to us (say, this sensible World) subsists in <strong>on</strong>e way or o<strong>the</strong>r,and if its subsistence and nature ultimately presuppose <strong>the</strong> subsistence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One,<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> One must subsist; fur<strong>the</strong>r, if everything presupposes <strong>the</strong> One, while <strong>the</strong>One presupposes nothing else (nothing which we can form some sort <strong>of</strong> c <strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong><strong>of</strong>), <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> One must be given as <strong>the</strong> fountainhead <strong>of</strong> all reality, as <strong>the</strong> beginningand <strong>the</strong> first link in <strong>the</strong> chain <strong>of</strong> reality. But why should <strong>the</strong>re be a sensible World atall? Why <strong>the</strong>re should be anything at all to begin with? True, if anything exists, <strong>the</strong>One must subsist as <strong>the</strong> firstly given reality. But this does not answer <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong>“Why and whence and How does <strong>the</strong> One subsist?” We, as Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ists, do notdoubt <strong>of</strong> its subsistence. But Reas<strong>on</strong> demands an explanati<strong>on</strong> for it.When we have thus clearly seen that to ask for an <strong>on</strong>tological explanati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> subsistence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One is not to doubt its subsistence; and when we have alsoproperly understood <strong>the</strong> associated point that such a demand for <strong>the</strong> One ’spresuppositi<strong>on</strong> and derivati<strong>on</strong> cannot possibly be answered by an appeal in <strong>the</strong>certain existence <strong>of</strong> its products and effects (since this settles <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong> about <strong>the</strong>real subsistence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One, and not that about <strong>the</strong> “Reas<strong>on</strong>” or ground for itssubsistence); <strong>the</strong>n we also see that <strong>the</strong> One is not <strong>the</strong> painfully sought after ultimatedatum. Reas<strong>on</strong> compels us to proceed fur<strong>the</strong>r.But to proceed fur<strong>the</strong>r whereto? We assumed that every c<strong>on</strong>ceivable realitydepends <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> One, without <strong>the</strong> One depending in any <strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. Therefore noc<strong>on</strong>ceivable realit y can in any way whatsoever provide <strong>the</strong> explanati<strong>on</strong> for <strong>the</strong>subsistence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One. But “something”, as we have argued, must account for thatsubsistence. From which two propositi<strong>on</strong>s <strong>the</strong>re necessarily and rati<strong>on</strong>alisticallyfollow, that <strong>the</strong> ultimate ground and <strong>on</strong>tological explanati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One and <strong>of</strong>everything c<strong>on</strong>ceivable is “Something” absolutely inc<strong>on</strong>ceivable; and since everyc<strong>on</strong>ceivable derivati<strong>on</strong> leads back to <strong>the</strong> One, <strong>the</strong> producti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> everything from thatinc<strong>on</strong>ceivable reality must also be inc<strong>on</strong>ceiva ble. Hence <strong>the</strong> most significantstatement, 6.26-7.2: “And if we inquire about a “use” for that ultimate groundinc<strong>on</strong>ceivable, <strong>the</strong>n this is <strong>the</strong> all-necessary “use”: that everything must proceed from<strong>the</strong>nce as if from a sanctuary, from <strong>the</strong> Ineffable in an ineffable way” etc. εἰ δὲ χρεἰαναὐτοῦ τινα ἐπιζητοῦμεν, αὔτη ἐστὶν ἡ πάντων ἀναγκαιοτάτη χρεία, τὸ ἐκεῖθεν, ὥσπερἐξ ἀδύτου, πάντα προιέναι, ἔκ τε ἀπορρήτου καὶ τὸν ἀπόρρητον τρόπον.


28We find in this here a good instance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> importance and reas<strong>on</strong>edoriginality <strong>of</strong> D. in <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>text <strong>of</strong> Greek Metaphysics.6.18-19. We argued above for <strong>the</strong> intrinsic c<strong>on</strong>nectedness betweenἁπλούστατον and περιεκτικώτατον, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most-simple, and <strong>the</strong> most-comprehensive.6.20-21. Well rendered by Chaignet (p. 11): “…puisque, m ême dans leschoses d’ ici-bas, ce qui, en s ’ élevant en haut, échappe toujours à nos pens ées estplus digne de notre vénérati<strong>on</strong>…”.6.22-23. The absolutely ultimate ground, so c<strong>on</strong>strued, dangerouslyapproaches <strong>the</strong> absolute Nothing. And <strong>the</strong>re is an important c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> between <strong>the</strong>two, as we shall so<strong>on</strong> see.6.26. ὥς φησι καὶ Πλάτων: Sophist, 238C.7.2. ὁμοίως: i.e. not in <strong>the</strong>ir orderly structure according to <strong>the</strong> prior andposterior. The ineffable principle does not produce <strong>the</strong> various realities as occupying<strong>the</strong>ir definite positi<strong>on</strong>s in <strong>the</strong> structured system <strong>of</strong> reality; for if it were so, thatprinciple would have to produce first [57] this and <strong>the</strong>n that, in which case it wouldinvolve and pre-c<strong>on</strong>tain <strong>the</strong> universal order <strong>of</strong> reality, and also in that case <strong>the</strong>previously produced would be nearer to it than <strong>the</strong> subsequently produced. But <strong>the</strong>ineffable principle is absolutely bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> real and its order, and a fortiori has nodefinite locati<strong>on</strong> in <strong>the</strong> chain <strong>of</strong> Reality, not even at its beginning (where <strong>the</strong> Onereigns s upreme); it ra<strong>the</strong>r engulfs <strong>the</strong> chain indiscriminately. More <strong>of</strong> this in <strong>the</strong>sequel.7.3. περιτρέπεσθαι [58] has a special force in D. as we shall <strong>of</strong>ten haveoccasi<strong>on</strong> to notice. It means that in ascribing an attribute to something weviolate that very noti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> it which <strong>the</strong> attributi<strong>on</strong> was meant to c<strong>on</strong>vey . Itis precisely this predicament which occasi<strong>on</strong>s <strong>the</strong> l<strong>on</strong>g development beginning at9.11. For instance if we call <strong>the</strong> Ultimate Ground ineffable or unknowable in order toexpress its inc<strong>on</strong>ceivability, <strong>the</strong>n we eo ipso assert its c<strong>on</strong>ceivability as inco nceivable.There is much more to this trouble than <strong>the</strong> dialectical quibble which prima facieappears to be, as we shall se in commenting <strong>on</strong> 9.11 sqq.7.6. ἀδύτου. The idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ineffable principle as <strong>the</strong> sacred sanctuary <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>universal Temple <strong>of</strong> Reality is crucial to our correct understanding <strong>of</strong> it.7.7-8. Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic metaphysics and <strong>the</strong>ology is not for <strong>the</strong> πολλοί.


29*7.9-9.10. The Ultimate Ground was found to be ineffable and inc<strong>on</strong>ceivable.But our anguish in trying to grasp, in however enfeebled a way, <strong>the</strong> One lead s in <strong>the</strong>same result; our attempts are like birth-pangs without birth; <strong>the</strong>y suffer περιτροπή(as it was explained above): <strong>the</strong> One must also be ineffabl e – and th is is supportedby highest authority.But if so, in positing a reality higher than that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One are we positingsomething bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> ineffable which <strong>the</strong> One is? Are we not mistakenly striving fora squared so to speak ineffability?D. counters this objecti<strong>on</strong> by 1) interpreting <strong>the</strong> Parmenides passage(brought forward as evidence for <strong>the</strong> objecti<strong>on</strong>) in a way c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant with his view(7.15-8.17); and 2) explaining that <strong>the</strong> inc<strong>on</strong>ceivability and ineffability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ultimateground is absolute, whereas that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One is in a certain (very important, <strong>of</strong>course) sense. This sec<strong>on</strong>d c<strong>on</strong>tenti<strong>on</strong> naturally leads to <strong>the</strong> l<strong>on</strong>g developmentbeginning <strong>on</strong> 9.11 about <strong>the</strong> precise sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolute unknowability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>Ultimate.7.11. Parmenides 141e- 142a. Rightly Chaignet (p. 12, n. 4) corrects R. ’sabsurd reference to Parm. 160b.7.15-18. D. ’s interpretati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> Parm., differs in many respects from <strong>the</strong>Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic Orthodoxy finally formulated and established by Proclus [59]. One suchdifference, affecting <strong>the</strong> overa ll scheme and setting D. quite apart from all hispredecessors [60], is D. ’s c<strong>on</strong>tenti<strong>on</strong> that <strong>the</strong> first Parmenidean Hypo<strong>the</strong>sis does notrelate to <strong>the</strong> absolutely primal principle, but <strong>on</strong>ly to <strong>the</strong> One. In a sense D. agreeswith all his predecessors; but this agreement, seen in <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>text <strong>of</strong> his positing aPrinciple superior to <strong>the</strong> One, turns to be substantial disagreement.We shall come back again to this point in commenting <strong>on</strong> 37.26 sqq. below.But we reserve <strong>the</strong> detailed comparative treatment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main Ne oplat<strong>on</strong>ic answersto <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong> about <strong>the</strong> highest Principles (those above Being) for <strong>the</strong> third secti<strong>on</strong><strong>of</strong> this work.According to D., Plato wishes us (without explicitly stating it) to apply hisprocedure for arriving at <strong>the</strong> One, in order to transcend th e One itself. By <strong>the</strong>negati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> every definite determinate reality he led us to <strong>the</strong> One; he expcects us to


30fully see his point, and to take, through <strong>the</strong> negati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One itself, <strong>the</strong> ultimatestep towards <strong>the</strong> Ultimate.7.18-19. Only <strong>the</strong> posited, can be raised. Only <strong>the</strong> affirmed at a stage, can benegated at ano<strong>the</strong>r. Thus D. after saying that Plato expects us to arrive at someintimati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolute Ultimate by <strong>the</strong> negati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>the</strong> raising <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> last realitywhich our strained efforts can after proper c <strong>on</strong>ceptual purificati<strong>on</strong> attain to in anobscure way, i.e. by <strong>the</strong> cancellati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One, he subtly remarks that even <strong>the</strong> Onerepresents an <strong>on</strong>tological affirmati<strong>on</strong>, a certain “positi<strong>on</strong>” or “positedness” whichreflects its presence in reality, however this a ll-comprehending presence is to bedistinguished from <strong>the</strong> “rude” positedness or presence <strong>of</strong> every determinate in itslimitati<strong>on</strong> as subordinate reality (something or o<strong>the</strong>r am<strong>on</strong>g <strong>the</strong> πάντα).Θέσις in D., when technically used, bears this sense <strong>of</strong> positi<strong>on</strong> or presence inreality.The reference is to Sophistes, 245b: πεπονθός τε γὰρ τὸ ὂν ἓν εἶναί πως οὐταὐτὸν ὂν τῷ ἑνὶ φαίνεται. But c<strong>on</strong>sult <strong>the</strong> entire development 242c-245e, <strong>the</strong><strong>of</strong>fshoot <strong>of</strong> which is precisely to show that we must distinguish τὸ ἓν from τὸ ὄν, andthat <strong>the</strong> ὄν is <strong>on</strong>e not by being <strong>the</strong> One, but by “suffering” (πάσχον) <strong>the</strong> acti<strong>on</strong>, as itwere, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> One – in this sense being dependent, and thus “inferior”, to <strong>the</strong> One,which in its turn need not such supporting influence from <strong>the</strong> ὄν in order to subsi st(= be present in reality).D. correctly understands <strong>the</strong> real meaning <strong>of</strong> Plato ’s argument <strong>the</strong>re [61].Otiose as such a claim may sound amidst <strong>the</strong> prejudices <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> modern age, it can besupported, but without going into <strong>the</strong> details <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>habitually stra ngelymisunderstood Plat<strong>on</strong>ic Theory <strong>of</strong> Participati<strong>on</strong>. Countless cases like this, relate <strong>the</strong>same story: modern scholarship as a result <strong>of</strong> a complete alienati<strong>on</strong> from <strong>the</strong> truespirit <strong>of</strong> late (at least) Hellenism, more <strong>of</strong>ten than not blinkers even in itsunderstanding <strong>of</strong> Classical Greece.7.19-8.5. According to D. ’s interpretati<strong>on</strong>, Plato is not speaking in <strong>the</strong>Parmenides at all about <strong>the</strong> Ultimate Ground; he reverently stopped at <strong>the</strong> πρόθυρα<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ἄδυτον, i.e. by <strong>the</strong> One.8.3. παρακινδυνευτικώτατος ὁ λόγος: cf. Sophistes, 245 b: φέρε δή, τίναἀρχήν τις ἄν ἄρξαιτο παρακινδυνευτικοῦ λόγου; This was said just at <strong>the</strong> beginning<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> development, whose c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> was referred to by D. above.


318.3. ἐκπίπτων εἰς ἰδιώτιδας ἀκοάς: sublime truths are <strong>on</strong>ly for <strong>the</strong> initiated, notfor <strong>the</strong> laity, as it were, for <strong>the</strong> πολλοί. Any doctrine passing <strong>the</strong> ordinary capability <strong>of</strong>ordinary men ’s understanding is certain to be laughed at by <strong>the</strong> multitude. Thispr<strong>of</strong>ound triviality is explicitly stated by Plato in his Sec<strong>on</strong>d Epistle: 314a1 -c6. Cf.also: op.cit. 312d7: φραστέον δή σοι δι᾿ αἰνιγμῶν, ἵν᾿ ἄν τι ἡ δέλτος ἢ πόντου ἢ γῆςἐν πτυχαῖς πάθῃ, ὁ ἀναγνοὺς μὴ γνῷ [62].This characteristically Plat<strong>on</strong>ic view, which is echoed and reflected with greateror lesser explicitness in numerous pass ages in <strong>the</strong> Plat<strong>on</strong>ic corpus, and which isfur<strong>the</strong>r borne by <strong>the</strong> momentous fact <strong>of</strong> Plato ’s pr<strong>of</strong>essing views (according to <strong>the</strong>explicit testim<strong>on</strong>y <strong>of</strong>, <strong>of</strong> all philosophers, Aristotle) which are never explicitlyformulated and articulated by him in his edited wo rks, is <strong>of</strong> course very near <strong>the</strong>heart and mind <strong>of</strong> every Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ist, such as D.8.4. καὶ τὸν περὶ τοῦ μηδαμῇ μηδαμῶς ὄντος (sc. λόγον) ἀνακινήσας: (sc. ὁΠλάτων): D. refers again to a passage in <strong>the</strong> Sophist [63], namely to <strong>the</strong>development 237a sqq., that is to <strong>the</strong> ἀπορία and argument about <strong>the</strong> μὴ ὄν which ismade by Plato to precede that about <strong>the</strong> ὄν (both ἁπορίαι being c<strong>on</strong>nected by him, v.243b-c).8.4. περιετράπη (sc. ὁ Πλάτων): Plato himself emphasizes <strong>the</strong> περιτροπήsuffered by his argument. V. 238d-239c: in saying that <strong>the</strong> μὴ ὄν is ἀδιανόητόν τε καὶἄρρητον καὶ ἄφθεγκτον καὶ ἄλογον, not a being ( ὄν) and not a something ( τι) – insaying <strong>the</strong>se <strong>on</strong>e affirms that <strong>the</strong> μὴ ὄν is something and is said after all, and issomehow c<strong>on</strong>ceived (i.e. as inc<strong>on</strong>ceivable) etc.D. faces a similar περιτροπή, but with reference to <strong>the</strong> μηδέν which transcendseven <strong>the</strong> maximum, <strong>the</strong> One – not in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with that which fails to be even <strong>the</strong>minimum, i.e. an <strong>on</strong>e, some-<strong>on</strong>e-thing (cf. 6.22-26).8.5. εἰς τὸν τῆς ἀνομοιότητος πόντον, cf. Plato Politicus, 273d sqq.: διὸ δὴκαὶ τότ᾿ ἤδη θεὸς ὁ κοσμήσας αὐτὸν (sc. τὸν Κόσμον), καθορῶν ἐν ἀπορίαις ὄντα,κηδόμενος ἵνα μὴ χειμασθεὶς ὑπὸ ταραχῆς διαλυθεὶς εἰς τὸν τῆς ἀνομοιότητος ἄπειρονὄντα πόντον δύῃ, … etc. The ἄπειρος πόντος τῆς ἀνομοιότητος is, <strong>of</strong> course, <strong>the</strong>receptacle, ὑποδοχή – matter as space in its intrinsic disordered state, with order andform being imposed by <strong>the</strong> <strong>De</strong>miurg, in <strong>the</strong> shaping <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Κόσμος.


32NOTES[1] Not quite “given” though! But <strong>of</strong> this, more in its proper place below.[2] Apparent reality is, <strong>of</strong> course, to be sharply distinguished from appearancein <strong>the</strong> modern sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> expressi<strong>on</strong>, in which it means <strong>the</strong> way something appearsto a percipient being. We can use <strong>the</strong> word “appearance” in such c<strong>on</strong>texts providedwe und erstand it objectively, as signifying a, usually inferior ordegraded,manifestati<strong>on</strong> (partial from <strong>the</strong> very reas<strong>on</strong> that it is a manifestati<strong>on</strong>) <strong>of</strong> a reality asdistinct from <strong>the</strong> full indivisible reality as such and in itself. It is, as it were, <strong>the</strong>outward projecti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> interiority <strong>of</strong> a reality. (In modern philosophy compare withHegel. And cf. Heidegger’s analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>cept <strong>of</strong> phaenomen<strong>on</strong>).[3] We provide here <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>the</strong> rudiments for <strong>the</strong> correct understanding <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>basic noti<strong>on</strong>s (like that <strong>of</strong> total ity) which we shall encounter in <strong>the</strong> present c<strong>on</strong>text .These are <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ound disquisiti<strong>on</strong>s later in this work, as <strong>the</strong>y are metwith, in following <strong>the</strong> great project <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> derivati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> all reality.[4] Τοῦτο in 1.6 refers <strong>of</strong> course to <strong>the</strong> proxim ately menti<strong>on</strong>ed alternative in<strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d formulati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong>: καὶ τὰ πάντα σὺν αὑτῇ λέγομεν εἶναι, ἤ μετ’αὐτὴν καὶ ἀπ᾿ αὐτῆς;[5] The syntax in 1.10 is <strong>of</strong> course: τὰ πάντα (subject) βούλεται εἶναι πολλὰπεπερασμένα (predicate).[6] ἀρχὴ as beginning and principle.[7] We shall have ample occasi<strong>on</strong> to revert to an explanati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> αἴτιον, <strong>of</strong>something, that is, whose both abstract and real nature in ancient philosophy ingeneral usually eludes modern commentators.[8] It would require a m<strong>on</strong>ograph to correct <strong>the</strong> faulty impressi<strong>on</strong>s that acertain type <strong>of</strong> modern mind is likely to ga<strong>the</strong>r from such a propositi<strong>on</strong>. Let it sufficehere to say, that for <strong>the</strong> objective thinking <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ancients, <strong>on</strong>e cannot really c<strong>on</strong>ceivewhat is totally n<strong>on</strong>-subsistent. Therefore <strong>the</strong> above propositi<strong>on</strong> does not blur <strong>the</strong>boundaries between <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>ceptual and <strong>the</strong> real. Indeed it presupposes that <strong>the</strong>truly c<strong>on</strong>ceptual is but a replica <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> real . The c<strong>on</strong>ceptual is objectively and<strong>on</strong>tologically, not subjectively and epistemologically understood.[9] The why will be explained in detail in <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d and third secti<strong>on</strong>s. Inbrief it is that every multiplicity presupposes <strong>on</strong>eness, and every distincti<strong>on</strong>unificati<strong>on</strong>.


33[10] I say “<strong>of</strong> multiplicity” and “<strong>of</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong>”, not “<strong>of</strong> a multiplicity” o r “<strong>of</strong> adistincti<strong>on</strong>”, because at <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> abstracti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> which we move we have to dowith multiplicity or distincti<strong>on</strong> or whatever in general ( ἁπλῶς), in <strong>the</strong>ir abstractnature, and not with a particular multiplicity or distincti<strong>on</strong> etc. Evidently in orde r for<strong>the</strong>re to exist a specific multiplicity, <strong>the</strong> subsistence <strong>of</strong> multiplicity in general musthave been <strong>on</strong>tologically secured, as it were, in advance.[11] “At any rate” since <strong>the</strong> ἀριθμός may be any specific multiplicity inaccordance with standard Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic usage.[12] Of every number = (in Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic parlance) <strong>of</strong> every multiplicity which issubjoined to a principle from which it flows as <strong>the</strong> numbers flow from <strong>the</strong> unit. Not =<strong>of</strong> every number, like 3 or 4.[13] Of course <strong>the</strong>y include <strong>on</strong>es, but not <strong>the</strong> One; <strong>the</strong>y even include <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e(not <strong>the</strong> One) as opposed to <strong>the</strong> two or three, say; but not <strong>the</strong> One which is evenabove this oppositi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e to any determinate or indeterminate multiplicity.This again will be treated fully later.[14] This in effect means that <strong>the</strong>re is no o<strong>the</strong>r dependence <strong>of</strong> B apart from<strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e passing through A. And this is, ultimately, always <strong>the</strong> case with strictlyM<strong>on</strong>istic Systems. (By M<strong>on</strong>ism I understand <strong>the</strong> view according to which <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>on</strong>ly<strong>on</strong>e ultimate principle – not <strong>the</strong> vie w that <strong>the</strong>re is ultimately <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e sort <strong>of</strong>subsistents or realities or entities or things ). We shall have more to say <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>philosophical meaning <strong>of</strong> M<strong>on</strong>ism later <strong>on</strong>.[15] I emphasize <strong>the</strong> singularity <strong>of</strong> D.’s positi<strong>on</strong>. But <strong>of</strong> course we are aware <strong>of</strong>its sy stematic c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with cognate attempts to solve <strong>the</strong> same problems. Forinstance, to refer <strong>on</strong>ly to <strong>the</strong> obvious, it is normal Proclean doctrine that what is in<strong>the</strong> result καθ᾿ ὕπαρξιν is in <strong>the</strong> cause κατ᾿ αἰτίαν; and <strong>the</strong>re seems to be just adifference in formulati<strong>on</strong> between this and D. ’s view. Certainly I am <strong>the</strong> last to wishto argue from possibly accidental differences in formulati<strong>on</strong> to real disagreement indoctrine. If I insist <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> matter, it is because I believe to be able to back <strong>the</strong>apparent difference by assigning a different “mechanism” for <strong>on</strong>tological derivati<strong>on</strong> toD. and, to remain within <strong>the</strong> example chosen, Proclus. But <strong>of</strong> this later.On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, it should be noted that D does not seem to propound thisview in oppositi<strong>on</strong> to o<strong>the</strong>r Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ists. He c<strong>on</strong>trasts it to Speusippus’ c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> –and even this in a qualified way ( ἔδοξε λέγειν 3.1). But again we must equally not


34forget that, for <strong>the</strong> time being, we are moving at <strong>the</strong> preliminary tackling <strong>of</strong> thosequesti<strong>on</strong>s which will be exhaustively investigated in <strong>the</strong> sequel, at <strong>the</strong> points where<strong>the</strong>ir respective natural positi<strong>on</strong> calls for, under <strong>the</strong> appropriate secti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> work.[16] V. “Aetius” apud Stobaeum, Fr. 38 (ed. Lang).[17] V. Metaphysica Λ, 1075b37- 1076 a4 (cf. also N , 1090b13-19). No ticeesp. his rebu ke: οὐδὲν γὰρ ἡ ἑτέρα (sc. οὐσία = hypostasis here) τῇ ἑτέρᾳσυμβάλλεται οὖσα ἢ μὴ οὖσα. Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ism precisely tries to avoid this rebu ke:everything distinguishable must be distinguished but <strong>the</strong> absolute c<strong>on</strong>nectedness in<strong>the</strong> total derivati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> reality must be, <strong>of</strong> course, preserved. Of course this was alsoSpeusippus’ point (as well as <strong>of</strong> Plato and <strong>the</strong> Old Academy). B<strong>on</strong>itz judiciouslyremarks with reference to Aristotle ’s accusati<strong>on</strong> in Met. Λ, 1072b30 sqq. and Z1028b21 sqq.: Haec enim diversa rerum genera Speusippus putandus est n<strong>on</strong> prorsusseiuncta inter se posuisse, sed pr<strong>of</strong>ecto perfectiora ex simplicio ribus et imperfectisrepetiit, veluti geometricas magnitudines ex arithmeticis sim., unde prope necessarioeo est deductus, ut postremo demum ideoque perfectissimo in genere rerum b<strong>on</strong>itatisuum assignaret locum. (In his <str<strong>on</strong>g>Commentary</str<strong>on</strong>g> to Aristotelis Metaphysica, p. 503).[18] Specifically for Plato, see A , 988a14 (in <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>text), and AristoxenusElementa Harm<strong>on</strong>ica, B30, ὅτι ἀγαθόν (fort. leg. τἀγαθόν) ἐστιν ἕν.[19] See, e.g., Metaphysica Z , 1028b21 toge<strong>the</strong>r with Λ, 1072b30. Cf. ingeneral Frs. 33a-33c and 34a sqq. (Lang).[20] See <strong>the</strong> very illuminating chapter 4 <strong>of</strong> Book N (1091a30-1092a17). Andalso note what <strong>the</strong> ancient commentators say ad loc., brief notices <strong>of</strong> which arec<strong>on</strong>veniently given by Lang pp. 67-70.[21] See, e.g., Frs. 34a-34b Lang.[22] V. Zeller p. 1001, 2.[23] I do not mean to shock any serious student <strong>of</strong> Aristotle with thisexpressi<strong>on</strong>, for it is as far from my mind as anythi ng can be to imply that Aristotlewas trying here to refute “scientifically” his opp<strong>on</strong>ent, and that he failed, comingforth with a frivolity meant by him as serious argument. In fact I believe that in this,and in very many o<strong>the</strong>r similar cases, Aristotle i s refuting dialectically (in his sense<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word), not scientifically. We must take seriously his careful statementsdistinguishing sharply between arguments drawn ἐξ ἐνδόξων (= comm<strong>on</strong>sensicallyplausible views <strong>on</strong> various matters, which are unparadoxical for <strong>the</strong> ordinary people)


35and scientific arguments proceeding from what is in itself prior ( πρότερον τῇ φύσει).In his writings both types <strong>of</strong> argumentati<strong>on</strong> are intertwined c<strong>on</strong>tinuously , althoughagain, <strong>the</strong>y for <strong>the</strong> most part fall under his aporematic and s cientific treatment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>issues involved corresp<strong>on</strong>dingly . And arguments like <strong>the</strong> present <strong>on</strong>e are intendedby him as nothing more than pieces <strong>of</strong> “dialectics” – always in his sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term.[24] Compare for instance <strong>the</strong> disparaging and just criticism that Syrianuslevels <strong>on</strong> such “dialectical” tricks (which dupe nobody, and least <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> all toosubtle thinking <strong>of</strong> a Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ist) in his <str<strong>on</strong>g>Commentary</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> B, M, and N <strong>of</strong> Metaphysics.(Γ is more positive and hence less affected by such “dialectical” fervor – at least in s<strong>of</strong>ar as oppositi<strong>on</strong> to positi<strong>on</strong>s dear to a Plat<strong>on</strong>ist is c<strong>on</strong>cerned).[25] See esp. Fr. 34e Lang. Also Fr. 34a – and all <strong>the</strong> 34 ’s and 35’s Lang. It is<strong>of</strong> great importance that, according to <strong>the</strong> express testim<strong>on</strong>y <strong>of</strong> Aristotle, at leastsome Pythagoreans were thinking al<strong>on</strong>g <strong>the</strong> same lines, which <strong>of</strong> course comes as nosurprise given <strong>the</strong> intimate relati<strong>on</strong>ship <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> old Academy to PythagoreanPhilosophy. “Plato, <strong>the</strong> best Pythagorean” was c<strong>on</strong>sidered as a comm<strong>on</strong>place inPlat<strong>on</strong>ic traditi<strong>on</strong>.[26] The already menti<strong>on</strong>ed Fr. 34e Lang.[27] Perhaps, we may interpret « τι» adverbially. But this does not affect <strong>the</strong>philosophical meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sentence.Ross (<str<strong>on</strong>g>Commentary</str<strong>on</strong>g> to Aristotle’s Metaphysics, p. 489) unaccountably suggeststhat in moving from <strong>the</strong> proposi ti<strong>on</strong> that <strong>the</strong> One is imperfect to <strong>the</strong> propositi<strong>on</strong> thatit is not a being, “Aristotle draws a c<strong>on</strong>sequence <strong>of</strong> his own probably not drawn bySpeusippus”. This is a most extraordinary statement: at least he should, in c<strong>on</strong>formitywith his suggesti<strong>on</strong>, a<strong>the</strong>tize t he « φησίν» in 1092a14! Aristotle begins his answerwith: εἰσὶ γὰρ καὶ ἐνταῦθα etc. in 1092a15.But perhaps Ross’ strange noti<strong>on</strong> is <strong>the</strong> desperate child <strong>of</strong> discomfort at wha<strong>the</strong> thinks is entailed by μηδὲ ὄν τι. Because he (loc. cit.) takes this as “(<strong>the</strong> One ) isnot”. If so, we have here but <strong>on</strong>e more <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> innumerable instances wheremisunderstanding <strong>of</strong> « ὄν» leads modern thinkers to awkward soluti<strong>on</strong>s. This is not<strong>the</strong> place to explicate <strong>the</strong> ancient metaphysical noti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> being; but let it be said thatwhen Plato, even in his published works, made <strong>the</strong> Good bey<strong>on</strong>d οὐσία and εἶναι, hedid not presumably wished to maintain that <strong>the</strong> absolutely First Principle is n<strong>on</strong>existent,in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> unreal, totally absent from Reality, Nothing.


36[28] The interpretati<strong>on</strong> given to this crucial clause (1092a14) by Ps. Alexanderseems to me very weak – though, no doubt, <strong>the</strong>re is truth in it, if properly c<strong>on</strong>strued.[29] The danger lies not (according to <strong>the</strong> Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic viewpoint) in our subtlec<strong>on</strong>ceptual operati<strong>on</strong>s overstepping, as it were, reality and operating in vacuum (touse Kant ’s formulati<strong>on</strong>), but ra<strong>the</strong>r in our faculties and apparatus, oversubtle andhairsplitting as <strong>the</strong>y can be, not being really sufficiently sensitive and varied to copewith <strong>the</strong> w<strong>on</strong>derful richness <strong>of</strong> articulati<strong>on</strong> in reality. Reas<strong>on</strong>, when correctly followed,cannot possibly overpass reality substantiating and projecting his figments unto her;so marvelously and inexhaustibly delicate reality is. Mind cannot outwit reality .The real problem is that it all too <strong>of</strong>ten cannot cope with it.This very important view, implicit as it is in <strong>the</strong> Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic methodology, isexplicitly stated by Simplicius in his <str<strong>on</strong>g>Commentary</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> Epictetus (p. 99 Didot) withreference to <strong>the</strong> crucial for Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ism ascent towards <strong>the</strong> first Principles: οὐδὲ γὰρεὐλαβητέον μὴ κενεμβατῶμεν (a word much employed by D.) μείζονά τινα καὶὑπερβαίνοντα τὰς πρώτας ἀρχὰς περὶ αὐτῶν ἐννοοῦντες. Οὐ γὰρ δυνατὸν τηλικοῦτονπήδημα πηδῆσαι τὰς ἡμετέρας ἐννοίας ὡς παρισωθῆναι τῇ ἀξίᾳ τῶν πρώτων ἀρχῶν,οὐ λέγω καὶ ὑπερπτῆναι.We feel here <strong>the</strong> healthy breeze <strong>of</strong> pure Hellenic Rati<strong>on</strong>alism blowing. Themorbid and checkered thinking <strong>of</strong> those who are c<strong>on</strong>tinuously afraid lest thoughtoverpass reality in its innate drive towards <strong>the</strong> ultimate had not yet <strong>the</strong>n infestedmankind. The view is that <strong>of</strong> reality possessing riches bey<strong>on</strong>d measure, over <strong>the</strong>re forReas<strong>on</strong> to appropriately express <strong>the</strong>m by identifying itself to <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> existence– not that <strong>of</strong> a poverty-stricken reality shamefully overstepped by Reas<strong>on</strong> in almos tany <strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> his bolder enterprises.[30] διπλόη: The Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic technical term for any possible distincti<strong>on</strong> whichsomething is capable <strong>of</strong> suffering , a subdivisi<strong>on</strong> within itself . The first distincti<strong>on</strong> is abifurcati<strong>on</strong>.[31] The reas<strong>on</strong> why, will become clear in <strong>the</strong> immediate sequel.[32] This was <strong>the</strong> outcome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> initial questi<strong>on</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>Principle <strong>of</strong> Everything can be anything (i.e. something or o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> those which in<strong>the</strong>ir totality make up <strong>the</strong> extent <strong>of</strong> ‘everything ’). And this will also be more directlyargued for in <strong>the</strong> sequel (5.17 sqq.).


37[33] It is essential that this should be added, as <strong>the</strong> causal relati<strong>on</strong>ship isc<strong>on</strong>stitutive <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> a cause as such, not a more or less accidental orextrinsic feature <strong>of</strong> it.[34] We sha ll see that we cannot determinately even say that anythingfollows from it.[35] I do not think that Chaignet ’s rendering “car, tout ce que nousc<strong>on</strong>cev<strong>on</strong>s, soit par intuiti<strong>on</strong>, soit par réflexi<strong>on</strong>, etc. » is particularly happy.[36] In <strong>the</strong> medieval scholastic sense <strong>of</strong> “intentio”.[37] These c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s (esp. <strong>the</strong> higher <strong>on</strong>es) are not <strong>the</strong> proper c<strong>on</strong>tent <strong>of</strong>our mind; ra<strong>the</strong>r we, operating at <strong>the</strong> limits <strong>of</strong> our faculties, get some intimati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong> corresp<strong>on</strong>ding realities, and are thus able to form some sort <strong>of</strong> not i<strong>on</strong>sarticulating those intimati<strong>on</strong>s.[37a] 275.8 : οὐ μέντοι ἀλλὰ διακαθαίροντες αὐτὰς ( sc. τὰς ἐπιβολὰς ἤἐννοίας) καὶ συναιροῦντες εἰς τὸ δυνατόν etc. 276.9-12: τρίτην δὲ τούτοις ἐπάγομενδιακάθαρσιν ἐννοιῶν, οὐσίαν τε ἐκεῖ καὶ ζωὴν καὶ νοῦν θεωροῦντες οὐχ οὕτω μετὰδιακρίσεως ἐπὶ τῶν ὀνομάτων τούτων ἔχειν δοκεῖ. ἀλλὰ κατὰ τὴν μίαν τοῦ ἡνωμένουφύσιν, αὐτοῦ πρὸς ἑαυτὸ μόνον προβαλλομένου κατὰ τὴν δοκοῦσαν ὕφεσιν.[38] This is, <strong>of</strong> course, standard Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic doctrine. It bears some ra<strong>the</strong>rexternal (c<strong>on</strong>tra Chaignet, p. 8 n. 2) similarity to <strong>the</strong> Stoic doctrine <strong>of</strong> τί as coveringboth being and n<strong>on</strong>-being, with <strong>the</strong> crucial difference however that Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ism farfrom identifying being with being a body, c<strong>on</strong>siders true being as ἀσώματον. On <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r hand it is interesting to take notice <strong>of</strong> a certain Stoic development recorded byAlexander Aphrodisiensis , in Top icorum, 359, 12 Wallies (Fr. II 329 v. Arnim).There a divisi<strong>on</strong> seems to be entertained like thisἕν/ \(e.g. ἐννόημα) τι/ \ὄν (σῶμα) ἀσώματονIt would be perhaps interesting to pursue fur<strong>the</strong>r this subject, especially whenc<strong>on</strong>nected with certain testim<strong>on</strong>y usually left to pass unnoticed or unregarded, forinstance Fr. II 168 and Fr. I 65.


38[39] It can be shown that <strong>the</strong>re cannot be more than <strong>on</strong>e absolutely simplereality. For if <strong>the</strong>re were, <strong>the</strong>y would have to be totally and absolutely unc<strong>on</strong>nected .For if <strong>the</strong>y entertained any communi<strong>on</strong> at all, if <strong>the</strong>y had anything in comm<strong>on</strong>, <strong>the</strong>nthat would be isolabl e as a moment in <strong>the</strong>ir natures, since it could not exhaust <strong>the</strong>entirety <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir nature, o<strong>the</strong>rwise <strong>the</strong>y would coalesce into <strong>on</strong>e and <strong>the</strong> same entityand <strong>the</strong>y could not be more than <strong>on</strong>e. But <strong>the</strong>n, with an identifiable comp<strong>on</strong>ent in<strong>the</strong>ir nature, <strong>the</strong>y could be no more absolutely simple. And for <strong>the</strong> absurdity <strong>of</strong>c<strong>on</strong>ceiving <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m as entirely disc<strong>on</strong>nected, see following note. Far<strong>the</strong>r, arguing aposteriori, it can be shown that <strong>the</strong>re is just <strong>on</strong>e absolutely simple reality, <strong>the</strong> One.[40] If reality is going to have even <strong>the</strong> weakest and minimal coherence andc<strong>on</strong>nectedness, if realities are going to entertain some sort <strong>of</strong> communi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>e withano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> Ultimate Principle must be <strong>on</strong>e single reality; o<strong>the</strong>rwise we wouldbe able to c<strong>on</strong>ceive <strong>of</strong> two (or more) absolute ly desevered and totally unc<strong>on</strong>nectedUniverses – not merely spatially separated (like, say, Epicurean Worlds) or temporallydistinct (like, say, Stoic Worlds), but with absolutely no comm<strong>on</strong> feature, let it beabstract (like “being”, or “<strong>on</strong>e”, or “identical”) whatsoever.This view is indicated by Proclus, in Theologia Plat<strong>on</strong>ica II 2 p. 15.10-14and sqq. ed. Westerink and Saffrey. And see, <strong>on</strong> this subject in general <strong>the</strong> three firstchapters <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d book <strong>of</strong> that work.For Proclus <strong>the</strong>re is ano<strong>the</strong>r, less abstract, line <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> M<strong>on</strong>ism, c<strong>on</strong>sisting,mainly, in our actually seeing that anything whatsoever, being or n<strong>on</strong>-being inwhatever way and mode, does have in fact something in comm<strong>on</strong> with anythingelse – namely that i t is <strong>on</strong>e. This is what is presupposed in particular in <strong>the</strong>development in Ch. 3 <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> menti<strong>on</strong>ed sec<strong>on</strong>d book.[41] V. e.g. 4.14. But v. 71.23 where <strong>the</strong> παντελὴς ἀδιάκριτος αἰτία is <strong>the</strong> One.[42] Not really “something”, as we shall see![43] It is <strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> t he pr<strong>of</strong>oundest thoughts in Metaphysics, and it is D. ’s own,that in a certain sense, yes, <strong>the</strong>re must be an absolute Nothing at <strong>the</strong> absolutecommencement <strong>of</strong> Reality, as <strong>the</strong>re is at its end. See what is so<strong>on</strong> to follow.[44] In catachrestic use.[45] This is <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> διὰ τὸ κύκλῳ 5.10. The force <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> argument relies<strong>on</strong> our keeping in mind that we have to do with undifferentiated πολλά qua πολλά;so if <strong>the</strong>y can be cause <strong>of</strong> <strong>on</strong>e ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>re is no sufficient reas<strong>on</strong> that this would


39not apply universally to <strong>the</strong>m, i.e., that each <strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m should be a cause <strong>of</strong> anyo<strong>the</strong>r; and similarly <strong>the</strong>re is no sufficient reas<strong>on</strong> why any<strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m in particularshould be such as every<strong>on</strong>e else depend ed <strong>on</strong> it without its depending <strong>on</strong> anythingelse. We must c<strong>on</strong>centrate <strong>on</strong> t he fact that any<strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m is c<strong>on</strong>sidered merely aswhat goes in to make up <strong>the</strong> indiscriminate and indefinite plurality which <strong>the</strong> πολλὰ ᾗπολλὰ c<strong>on</strong>stitute.[46] Simplicius, who esteems D. highly (our Damascius, « ὁ ἡμέτεροςΔαμάσκιος» as he says , <strong>the</strong>y were colleagues during <strong>the</strong> last days <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Plat<strong>on</strong>icAcademy in A<strong>the</strong>ns, when Damascius was in fact <strong>the</strong> last head <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> venerableinstituti<strong>on</strong>), emphasizes that, in <strong>the</strong> investigati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> very difficult problem <strong>of</strong>τόπος, he wanted to find out <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> τόπος ἐκ τῆς χρείας αὐτοῦ (e.g. In Phys.,625.3 Diels; and v. 5.6 χρῂζει, esp. 6.26-7!) – that is, from its role or functi<strong>on</strong> in <strong>the</strong>structured system <strong>of</strong> reality. So, we may infer that D. was particularly sensitive topoint out everywhere <strong>the</strong> pragmatic reas<strong>on</strong>, in a functi<strong>on</strong>alist acceptati<strong>on</strong>, why weare impelled to posit this or that principle, this or that reality.[47] It is crucially important that this should be clearly seen, in view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> factthat D. (like his great predecessor, Iamblichus) accepted all k inds <strong>of</strong> mysteries. Atlast we must sharply distinguish between mystic and mystery.[48] This is <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>stant Aristotle’s injuncti<strong>on</strong>, not comm<strong>on</strong>ly taken sufficientlyinto account by his modern interpreters. Cf. Met aphysica Z , 2 ad fin. Cf. Physica184a16 sqq.; Ethica Nicomachea 1095b3.[49] It is interesting to see how “Herennius” put this passage: ἀλλ᾿ ὅμως ἐκ τῶν ἡμῖν γνωριμωτέρων, +ἀνερεθίον+ (sic; an ἀνερυτέον?) τὰς ἐν ἡμῖν ἀρρήτουςὠδίνας εἰς τὴν ἄρρητον συναίσθησιν τῆς φανοτάτης (!) ἀληθείας· Mai p. 5 70.Ἀνερυτέον might perhaps be a variant <strong>on</strong> ἀνεθιστέον, with its moment <strong>of</strong> purifying(warding <strong>of</strong>f, and thus keeping <strong>the</strong> purity <strong>of</strong> something).[50] One may object that, <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>trary, it is ra<strong>the</strong>r a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> real power tohave <strong>on</strong>e’s own when strugglingly immersed in a commoti<strong>on</strong>, esp. when <strong>on</strong>e is ableto subject it to his sway. But, firstly, in such a case, and to <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>on</strong>esucceeds in subduing a field and rendering it subject to <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> <strong>on</strong>e ’s nature, tosuch an extent does <strong>on</strong>e raise <strong>on</strong>eself above <strong>the</strong> “c<strong>on</strong>quered” field . And, sec<strong>on</strong>dly,keeping alo<strong>of</strong> does not entail being inert, uncausative and unproductive – <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>c<strong>on</strong>trary, it is a mark <strong>of</strong> impotence to be able to “govern” a field <strong>on</strong>ly mechanically by


40being immersed in it, handling it with <strong>on</strong>e ’s own hands as it were; supreme power iswielded <strong>on</strong>ly when <strong>on</strong>e “governs” and “causes” by doing nothing in particular in<strong>the</strong> relevant respect . This all important Neoplat<strong>on</strong>ic noti<strong>on</strong>, will be fully analysedlater <strong>on</strong>. It, <strong>of</strong> course, c<strong>on</strong>nects with <strong>the</strong> Neoplato nic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Causality. And itmarvelously coincides with a basic doctrine <strong>of</strong> Taoism, esp. in its primary applicati<strong>on</strong>to <strong>the</strong> ultimate ground <strong>of</strong> all reality.[51] “Higher”: in <strong>the</strong> sense delineated in <strong>the</strong> Preliminary Note.[52] Since we cannot really say that that principle is “higher” than <strong>the</strong> One, inany positively c<strong>on</strong>ceived sense.[53] For a systematic metaphysical analysis and pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> this last point, c<strong>on</strong>sult<strong>the</strong> two last chapters <strong>of</strong> my “Things and Predicati<strong>on</strong>”.[54] We commit a simplificati<strong>on</strong> here in that <strong>the</strong>re can be distinguished twodifferent ways <strong>of</strong> that “both X and Y” corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to what D. terms ἡνωμένον andδιακρινόμενον (<strong>the</strong> latter as distinct from <strong>the</strong> διακεκριμένον), or to what Proclus callsμονὴ and πρόοδος. But <strong>of</strong> this later, in secti<strong>on</strong>s three and four.[55] My paren<strong>the</strong>ses are intended to explain <strong>the</strong> difference in <strong>the</strong> aspect underwhich <strong>the</strong> One <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e hand, and <strong>the</strong> ἡνωμένον <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, are both πάντα.[56] Chaignet fails to understand <strong>the</strong> point completely – v. p. 11 n. 3.[57] Of co urse metaphysical dependence , priority and posteriority is heremeant. Temporal priority is not applicable even in <strong>the</strong> producti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>of</strong> principles f arbelow <strong>the</strong> Ineffable Ground.[58] Cf. Plato, Phaedo 95b.[59] Cf. in this c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> Simplicius, In Physica Commentaria, ed. Dielsp. 795.[60] With <strong>the</strong> excepti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> Iamblichus whose articulated expositi<strong>on</strong> has notunfortunately survived to us. It is possible to rec<strong>on</strong>struct his views from what Proclusand Damascius argue in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with , and in reference to, <strong>the</strong>m; such arec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> will be attempted in <strong>the</strong> third secti<strong>on</strong>.[61] Chaignet, expectedly, fails to see <strong>the</strong> point. V. p. 13, n. 2.[62] Cf. also <strong>the</strong> well known passages <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> VII th Epistle, esp. 341a-342a.[63] The Sophist was <strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Plat<strong>on</strong>ic dialogues in <strong>the</strong> Iamblichean Can<strong>on</strong>.V. Prolegomena to Plato ’s Philosophy c. XXVI. Westerink ’s rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>


corrupt passage (“An<strong>on</strong>ymous Prolegomena etc.” p. XXXIX-XL) is <strong>the</strong> correct <strong>on</strong>e41(excepting some doubts c<strong>on</strong>cerning Politicus).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!