10.07.2015 Views

Perversion the Social Relation

Perversion the Social Relation

Perversion the Social Relation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

82 Octave Mannonition is of no use at all. In a word, <strong>the</strong> belief must survive its refutation,even if it <strong>the</strong>reby becomes impossible to grasp and one can see nothingbut its utterly paradoxical effects.This example opens up paths of all sorts: <strong>the</strong> use of misinformation^ to propagandists ends, even if it must later be admitted that <strong>the</strong> informationgiven out was false; hollow promises; <strong>the</strong> psychology of <strong>the</strong>practical joke; and <strong>the</strong> psychology of impostors. There is no reason thatsomeone who does magic tricks, however reasonable and lucid she maybe, should not make a living from <strong>the</strong> transformed belief that she is amagician, or that that should not greatly enhance <strong>the</strong> pleasure that plyingher trade gives her. Like <strong>the</strong> Hopi who admits that <strong>the</strong>re are no realKatcinas left today, she holds a "but all <strong>the</strong> same" in reserve, one that ismuch harder to grasp than <strong>the</strong> Hopi's "but all <strong>the</strong> same," or even all butimpossible to pin down, except in little details that require interpretation.Yet sometimes it is obvious that <strong>the</strong> belief that one might supposehad been abandoned has in fact been maintained. I shall give some examplesof this; <strong>the</strong> first, which we owe to Claude Lévi-Strauss, is famous.It involves a shaman who, although he knows <strong>the</strong> tricks of his and hisfellow shamans' trade inside out, one day finds himself fascinated by ano<strong>the</strong>rshaman who uses <strong>the</strong> same tricks; he becomes capable of believingagain, with all his former naivete. I have summarized <strong>the</strong> story poorly,but everyone has read <strong>the</strong> essay in question and been more or less surprisedby this paradox; as he describes it, Lévi-Strauss interprets it asproof that an impostor can be his own dupe and invent an excuse forhimself in all good faith. As <strong>the</strong> preceding pages will have suggested, <strong>the</strong>real explanation is different, and, not surprisingly, at once more obviousand more puzzling. Voltaire's treatment of imposture, which comesdown to repeating that two shamans or two Katcinas ought not to beable to look each o<strong>the</strong>r in <strong>the</strong> face without laughing, does not reflect <strong>the</strong>reality of <strong>the</strong> matter.Pace Voltaire, we have already begun to glimpse that <strong>the</strong>re are severalways of believing and not believing. There is some slight resemblancebetween <strong>the</strong> shaman and <strong>the</strong> Hopi: <strong>the</strong> shaman too must have believednaively before repudiating his belief, although we do not know anythingabout <strong>the</strong> crisis he may have undergone when he was initiated into <strong>the</strong>tricks of his trade. However, <strong>the</strong> positions that <strong>the</strong> two end up in are notidentical: <strong>the</strong> shaman recovers his naivete, but his faith is not reinforced.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!