09.07.2015 Views

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

availability of <strong>the</strong> SR read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> (1) is to be accounted for <strong>in</strong> terms of language-specificproperties, I propose to adopt <strong>the</strong> analysis whereby Japanese zibun can undergo LF movementto a higher clause and be locally bound <strong>the</strong>re (Pica 1991, Hestvik 1992, Ish<strong>in</strong>o & Ura 2012).2 IDENTITY CONDITION. If null arguments result from DPE, we expect this operation to besubject to <strong>the</strong> same conditions on <strong>the</strong> identity with a discourse antecedent as for <strong>in</strong>stance VPEor sluic<strong>in</strong>g. I show that <strong>the</strong> conditions under which DPE is licensed are <strong>the</strong> same as thoseunder which a DP can be part of a larger elided constituent.2.1 A coherent behavior. Fox (2000) proposes <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple which summarizes <strong>the</strong>conditions under which a DP can be elided if it is part of a constituent targeted by ellipsis:(4) DP Parallelism condition on ellipsis (adapted from Fox 2000: 117)DPs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> elided constituent and its antecedent must ei<strong>the</strong>ra. have <strong>the</strong> same referential value (Referential Parallelism), orb. be bound <strong>in</strong> identical dependencies (Structural Parallelism).This accounts for <strong>the</strong> availability of both strict and sloppy read<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> examples like (5): <strong>the</strong>pronoun <strong>in</strong> (5b) satisfies (4a) and <strong>the</strong> one <strong>in</strong> (5c) satisfies (4b).(5) a. John th<strong>in</strong>ks he will w<strong>in</strong>, and Bill does, too.b. John i th<strong>in</strong>ks he i will w<strong>in</strong>, and Bill j does , too. Ref. Par.c. John th<strong>in</strong>ks he will w<strong>in</strong>, and Bill does , too. Str. Par.Crucially, <strong>the</strong> same is observed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> realm of pro-drop: under <strong>the</strong> strict read<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> nullsubject <strong>in</strong> (3B) has a coreferential antecedent ('her proposal'), and under <strong>the</strong> SR, it is bound <strong>in</strong>a dependency which is identical to <strong>the</strong> dependency <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>in</strong> (3A) is <strong>in</strong>volved.O<strong>the</strong>r (non-ambiguous) cases are also accounted for: <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>in</strong> (6) satisfies (4a) and <strong>the</strong>anaphoric null object <strong>in</strong> (7) (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> null object language Japanese) satisfies (4b):(6) Juan i está aquí. [e] i quiere hablar contigo. SpanishJuan is here wants talk with.you'Juan is here. He wants to talk to you.'(7) Taroo i -wa zibun i -o semeta-ga, Ken j -wa [e] j kabatta. JapaneseTaroo-TOP self-ACC blamed-while Ken-TOP defended (Takahashi 2010)'While Taroo blamed himself, Ken defended himself.'2.2 Test<strong>in</strong>g predictions. Anaphors are not referential, and are necessarily BVs, as <strong>in</strong> (7)(Re<strong>in</strong>hart 1983, Bür<strong>in</strong>g 2005). If pro-drop is to be accounted for under (4), we predict thatnull anaphors will not be licensed when <strong>the</strong> discourse context does not provide ano<strong>the</strong>ranaphor bound <strong>in</strong> an identical dependency. This is borne out: <strong>in</strong> (8), although <strong>the</strong> anaphor hasa coreferential antecedent, it cannot be elided, s<strong>in</strong>ce ellipsis of anaphors can only be licensedvia (4b). I show that <strong>the</strong> results are <strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong> languages with object-agreement like Basque.(8) John i -ga zibun i -o /#[e] i nagusameta (koto). JapaneseJohn-NOM self-ACC consoled (Hoji 1998: 130)'John consoled himself.'I also test predictions relative to MaxElide effects (Takahashi & Fox 2005, Merchant 2008).3 IN SUM, after defend<strong>in</strong>g that pro-drop boils down to DPE across all pro-drop languages, Ipush this result to its limits, by explor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> consequences for <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of <strong>the</strong> licens<strong>in</strong>g ofellipsis. I show that DPs are subject to <strong>the</strong> same identity condition on ellipsis both when <strong>the</strong>yare part of a larger elided constituent and when <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> bare target of ellipsis.Selected references ▪ Barbosa, M.P., 2009, “Two k<strong>in</strong>ds of subject pro”, Studia L<strong>in</strong>guistica63:2-58 ▪ Gallego, Á., 2010, “B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g through Agree” L<strong>in</strong>guistic Analysis 34:163-192 ▪Holmberg, A., 2010, “Null subject Parameters”, Parametric variation, Biberauer et al. (eds),Cambridge: CUP, 88-124 ▪ Ish<strong>in</strong>o, N. & H. Ura, 2012, “Towards a <strong>the</strong>ory of split b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g”,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!