09.07.2015 Views

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

homogeneity presupposition (3) by her. The core idea of <strong>the</strong> homogeneity presuppositionis to distribute <strong>the</strong> pluralized property P to all atoms <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> denotation of A; <strong>in</strong> case ofnegated sentences (3-b) this leads to apparent scope of A over negation. The homogeneitypresupposition is used by Beck to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> strong <strong>in</strong>terpretation of sentences like Thechildren are not asleep where negation and <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite NP appear and where <strong>the</strong> weakread<strong>in</strong>g (¬ > δ(CHILDREN)) isn’t grammatical. We follow Beck (2001) <strong>in</strong> this respectand argue that <strong>the</strong> apparent wide scope of universal quantifier over negation <strong>in</strong> exampleslike (2) is <strong>the</strong> result of <strong>the</strong> distribution of negative property to all atoms constitut<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> maximal plurality denoted by <strong>the</strong> universal NP, not a result of QR or any semantictransformation which would scope ∀ over ¬.(3) *P(A)a. =1 iff ∀x[x ∈ A → P (x)]b. =0 iff ∀x[x ∈ A → ¬P (x)]; undef<strong>in</strong>ed o<strong>the</strong>rwisePredictions: our proposal makes three follow<strong>in</strong>g predictions. First, we predict thatwhenever <strong>the</strong> illusion of ∀ > ¬ arises, <strong>the</strong> universal NP should be def<strong>in</strong>ite (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> senseof restriction of <strong>the</strong> quantificational doma<strong>in</strong> by such means as relative clauses, presuppositionalcollective modifiers, demonstratives, . . . ). Our corpus study shows that thisprediction is born out. Second prediction, because universal quantifer and conjunctionare logically equivalent (<strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ite doma<strong>in</strong>s), we expect that <strong>the</strong> conjunction of two def<strong>in</strong>iteNPs <strong>in</strong> negated Czech sentences should produce apparent ’wide scope of conjunction’ overnegation read<strong>in</strong>g. The second observation is demonstrated <strong>in</strong> (4) which (unlike its Englishtranslation) is <strong>in</strong>terpreted only as conjunction of two negated statements (¬p ∧ ¬q).This is not <strong>the</strong> case for <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite NPs where both scopes are possible. Third prediction:we predict that change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> word order typically associated with a change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formationstructure should have no effect on <strong>the</strong> scope of all and negation. Notice that <strong>in</strong>Czech negation is realized as a bound morpheme on <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ite verb. We predict that bothSV (i.e., all neg-V) and VS (i.e., neg-V all) orders should yield <strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong>tepretation,namely, ¬ > ∀. This is exactly what we found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> corpus. The decisive factor is <strong>the</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite <strong>in</strong>terpretation of universal NP as discussed above. The last prediction supports<strong>the</strong> traditional view of <strong>the</strong> architecture of language faculty (Chomsky, 1995) where <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>formation structure doesn’t <strong>in</strong>tervene with <strong>the</strong> semantic part of <strong>the</strong> derivation.(4) Petr nepřečetl Meditace a Babičku.Petr NEG-read.3sg Meditations and Grandmo<strong>the</strong>r’Petr didn’t read Meditations and The Grandmo<strong>the</strong>r.’¬p ∨ ¬q <strong>in</strong> EnglishSelected referencesBeck, S. 2001. Reciprocals are def<strong>in</strong>ites. Natural language semantics 9:69–138. Bür<strong>in</strong>g, D. 1997.The great scope <strong>in</strong>version conspiracy. L & P 20:175–194. Chomsky, N. 1995. The M<strong>in</strong>imalist Program.Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hajičová, E. 1975. Negace a presupozice ve významové stavběvěty. Praha: Academia. Horn, L. 1989. A natural history of negation. Chicago: Unversity of ChicagoPress. Jackendoff, R. 1972. Semantic <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> generative grammar. Cambridge, Ma: MITPress. Kadmon, N. 2001. Formal pragmatics. Blackwell. Kučerová, I. 2012. Grammatical mark<strong>in</strong>gof givenness. NLS 1:1–30. Percus, O. 2006.Anti-presuppositions. In Theoretical and empirical studiesof reference and anaphora, ed. A. Ueyamada, 52–73. Japan Soc. for <strong>the</strong> Promotion of Science. Re<strong>in</strong>hart,T. 2006. Interface strategies. Optimal and costly computations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Szabolcsi, A & B. Haddican. 2004. Conjunction meets negation. JoS 21:219–249.2

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!