09.07.2015 Views

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Reflexivity without reflexivesEric Reuland, Anna Volkova 1Utrecht <strong>in</strong>stitute of <strong>L<strong>in</strong>guistics</strong> OTS, Universiteit UtrechtBackground: What prevents pronom<strong>in</strong>als from be<strong>in</strong>g locally bound? Does this a) reflect an<strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic property of pronom<strong>in</strong>als (Chomsky 1981), is it b) a relative (economy) effect, thatonly shows up where <strong>the</strong>re is a more dedicated competitor (see from different perspectives,Safir 2004, Boeckx, Hornste<strong>in</strong> and Nunes 2007, Lev<strong>in</strong>son 2000), does it c) have a semanticbasis as <strong>in</strong> Schlenker (2005), or does it d) follow from general conditions on agree basedcha<strong>in</strong>s, and reflexive predicates (Reuland 2011)? To resolve this issue, it is important to studylanguages that are reported to allow locally bound pronom<strong>in</strong>als, and assess whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong>fact do have <strong>the</strong>m, and, which factors come <strong>in</strong>to play when local b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g obta<strong>in</strong>s. Khanty(Uralic, spoken <strong>in</strong> Northwest Siberia) is such a language (Nikolaeva 1995). In this talk wereview data collected on a field trip <strong>in</strong> July 2012, and show that <strong>the</strong>se support option d).A first set of facts and <strong>the</strong>ir consequences: łuveł <strong>in</strong> object position can be bound by a coargumentsubject. It can also receive a value from discourse, show<strong>in</strong>g that łuveł is a truepronom<strong>in</strong>al (1a). (1b) with a quantificational antecedent shows that <strong>the</strong> local dependency isone of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g, not coreference.(1) a. UtltiteXo i łuveł i/k išəәk-s-əәłłe.teacher he.ACC praise-PST-SG.3SG The teacher praised him(self).b. NemXojat i łuveł i/k ănt išəәk-ł-əәłłe.no.one he.ACC NEG praise-NPST-SG.3SG No one praises himself / him.This fact rules out both <strong>the</strong> approaches <strong>in</strong> a) and c). But it is compatible with <strong>the</strong> approaches<strong>in</strong> b) – <strong>the</strong>re is no competitor – and prima facie problematic for <strong>the</strong> approach <strong>in</strong> d). IfnemXojat ‘no one’ b<strong>in</strong>ds łuveł ‘him’, this is potentially a violation of <strong>the</strong> cha<strong>in</strong> condition <strong>in</strong>Reuland (2011) s<strong>in</strong>ce łuveł is fully specified for phi-features. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, this approachfaces <strong>the</strong> fact that logical syntax representations as <strong>in</strong> (2) with two identical variables <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>coargument doma<strong>in</strong> are ruled out (Reuland 2011).(2) *DP (V x x)A second set of facts and <strong>the</strong>ir consequences: i) Khanty has two types of verbal agreement:obligatory subject agreement and optional object agreement (OAgr), as illustrated <strong>in</strong> (3).(3) UtltiteXo poXlen’ki išəәk-s-əәłłe / išəәk-s.teacher boy praise-PST-SG.3SG / praise-PST.3SG The teacher praised <strong>the</strong> boy.The follow<strong>in</strong>g condition applies: a personal pronoun can be locally bound – yield<strong>in</strong>g areflexive predicate – only if <strong>the</strong> verb carries object agreement, cf. <strong>the</strong> ill-formedness of (4).(4) *UtltiteXo i łuveł i išəәk-s.teacher he.ACC praise-PST.3SG The teacher praised him / *himself.ii) The presence of object agreement facilitates object drop, as <strong>in</strong> (5).(5) TămXătł ma c’ăta van-s-em.today I <strong>the</strong>re see-PST-SG.1SG{LC: Yesterday my son went to Beryozovo.} Today I saw (him /*myself) <strong>the</strong>re.But a zero object is <strong>in</strong>compatible with local b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g. The predicate <strong>in</strong> (5) cannot be<strong>in</strong>terpreted as reflexive.These facts are <strong>in</strong>compatible with any straightforward version of <strong>the</strong> no-competitorapproaches <strong>in</strong> b). That is, even with object agreement <strong>the</strong> pronoun “is” not a reflexive;noth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> competition <strong>the</strong>ories would lead us to expect that łuveł + OAgr would be aw<strong>in</strong>ner aga<strong>in</strong>st bare łuveł or bare OAgr (assum<strong>in</strong>g we can compare <strong>the</strong>m, although <strong>the</strong>y reflectdifferent numerations). How does option d) fare?1 The authors are listed alphabetically.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!