09.07.2015 Views

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Non-counterfactual past subjunctive conditionals <strong>in</strong> FrenchFabienne Mart<strong>in</strong>, University of Stuttgart1. Introduction. This paper focuses on past subjunctive conditionals (PSCs) <strong>in</strong> French. French PSCshave a conditionnel 2 <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequent. It is often assumed that French (like Greek) requires imperfectiveaspect as a counterfactual (CF) marker <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent (Iatridou 2000, Bjorkman & Halpert 2012).This should expla<strong>in</strong> why we f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent of PSCs <strong>the</strong> plus que parfait, a double past comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gan imperfective morphology to a first layer of past, cf. (1a). Non-imperfective past tenses, a.o. <strong>the</strong> presentperfect, are supposed to be banned, as confirmed by (1b).(1) SiIfonwe(a.)(a.)OK avait réfléchith<strong>in</strong>k-PQP(b.)(b.)*a réfléchi,th<strong>in</strong>k-PRST-PERF,onwen’NEGaurait pas signé.sign-COND.2-NEG‘If we had thought/ have thought about it, we wouldn’t have signed.’We start from <strong>the</strong> observation that this empirical picture should be ref<strong>in</strong>ed. We found many occurrencesof conditionals with a conditionnel 2 <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequent and a present perfect <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent <strong>in</strong> corpora,cf. e.g. (2)-(3). Their context of use makes clear that <strong>the</strong>y are not conf<strong>in</strong>ed to a substandard variant ofFrench, even if <strong>the</strong>y are banished by some prescriptive grammars. S<strong>in</strong>ce conditionals like (2)-(3) mix <strong>the</strong>morphologies typical of PSCs and past <strong>in</strong>dicative conditionals (PICs), we call <strong>the</strong>m ‘sw<strong>in</strong>g’ PSCs.(2) SiIfunamissilemissilesol-airground-aira effectivement été utilisé,<strong>in</strong>deed be-PRES.PFCT used,ilitaurait étébe-COND.2tirélaunchedà partir d’fromunabateauboatlarge de Long Island.coast of Long Island.‘If a missile has <strong>in</strong>deed been used, it would have been launched from a boat off <strong>the</strong> Long Island coast’(3) SiIfle<strong>the</strong>chefChiefa réellement tenusheld-PRES.PFCT really[c]es<strong>the</strong>sepropos,comments,ilheaurait commiscommit-COND.2unaacteactgraveseriousauat <strong>the</strong>‘If <strong>the</strong> Chief really has made <strong>the</strong>se comments, he would have committed a serious act’2. Sw<strong>in</strong>g PSCs vs standard PSCs. A first def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g property of sw<strong>in</strong>g PSCs si p, q if that <strong>the</strong>y aresystematically odd if p or ¬p follows from <strong>the</strong> context C (<strong>the</strong> set of worlds currently taken to beepistemically accessible by all participants): <strong>the</strong>y require p to be undecided relative to C. This sufficesto expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem of (1b), s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>re, C most probably entails ei<strong>the</strong>r p or ¬p. Sw<strong>in</strong>g PSCs thus differfrom standard PSCs, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> latter can be used if p is counterfactual <strong>in</strong> C. A second related property ofsw<strong>in</strong>g PSCs is that <strong>the</strong>y are typically used when p is contextually salient but not yet accepted or rejected— p is on <strong>the</strong> Table (Farkas & Bruce 2010). A sign of this is <strong>the</strong> frequent presence of anaphoricaladverbials like effectivement/ vraiment ‘<strong>in</strong>deed/really’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir antecedent, cf. (2)-(3). Assert<strong>in</strong>g a sw<strong>in</strong>gPSC is <strong>the</strong>n a way to address <strong>the</strong> question on <strong>the</strong> Table p. Interest<strong>in</strong>gly, do<strong>in</strong>g so through <strong>the</strong> assertion of asw<strong>in</strong>g PSC projects a different set of future common grounds (projected set, ps; Farkas & Bruce 2010)than through <strong>the</strong> assertion of a standard PSC. The way we <strong>in</strong>terpret A’s confirmation (6) of B’s reaction(5) illustrates <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t. Through (5), B reacts to A’s proposal (4) to add p to <strong>the</strong> common ground.(4) A. Le Boe<strong>in</strong>g 747 a été détruit par un missile, je crois/ ‘The Boe<strong>in</strong>g 747 was destroyed by a missile, I th<strong>in</strong>k’(5) a. B. S’il avait été détruit par un missile, il aurait été lancé par l’US Navy! (standard PSC)‘If it had been destroyed through a missile, it would have been launched by <strong>the</strong> US Navy!’b. B. S’il a été détruit par un missile, il aurait été lancé par l’US Navy! (sw<strong>in</strong>g PSC)‘If it has been destroyed through a missile, it would have been launched by <strong>the</strong> US Navy!’(6) A. Tu as raison/‘You’re right.’(5a) and (5b) have <strong>the</strong> same literal content p→ q. They also both presuppose that q is false or at leastimplausible <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> current context C 1 . But <strong>the</strong>y differ through <strong>the</strong>ir implicated content. As an answer to(5a), (6) is easily understood as a confirmation to p→ q but also to ¬p, because <strong>the</strong> rule of modus tollensis applied (ps = {C 1 ∪{p → q}∪{¬p}}). By contrast, as an answer to (5b), (6) cannot be <strong>in</strong>terpreted thatway. To beg<strong>in</strong> with, <strong>the</strong> reaction (5b) to <strong>the</strong> proposal (4) nei<strong>the</strong>r amounts to reject<strong>in</strong>g p, nor to accept<strong>in</strong>git. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it <strong>in</strong>vites to choose between (i) reject<strong>in</strong>g p and (ii) challeng<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> presupposition ¬q andaccept<strong>in</strong>g both p and q. The context state after a sw<strong>in</strong>g PSC is thus <strong>in</strong>quisitive wrt to p: its ps conta<strong>in</strong>stwo future common grounds, namely ps = {C 1 ∪ {p → q} ∪ {¬p},C 1 ∪ {p → q} ∪ {p} ∪ {q}}. However,A can still react to (5b) through (6) <strong>in</strong> order to signal she accepts <strong>the</strong> imposed choice. She can <strong>the</strong>ncont<strong>in</strong>ue by signal<strong>in</strong>g which future common ground she goes for, ei<strong>the</strong>r through (i) You are right. The

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!