09.07.2015 Views

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Rita Manz<strong>in</strong>i, Firenze(1) is governed by a morphological markedness hierarchywhich governs <strong>the</strong> obliteration offeatures bundles at Vocabulary Insertion. The more highly marked <strong>the</strong> feature bundles are, <strong>the</strong> morelikely <strong>the</strong>y are to be obliterated. Such a model still undergenerates; for <strong>in</strong>stance Calabrese is awareof <strong>the</strong> order<strong>in</strong>g problems created by <strong>the</strong> third and fifth columns <strong>in</strong> (1) and by <strong>the</strong> proclitic Ø P vs.enclitic P Ø alternations. Undergeneration also characterizes <strong>the</strong> OT approach of Legendre (2010),cf. <strong>the</strong> discussion by Manz<strong>in</strong>i &Savoia (2011).Analysis. I advocate a different view of what happens <strong>in</strong> (1)-(2). The hierarchy between 1 st and 2 ndperson <strong>in</strong> (1) is best modelled as a conceptual, ra<strong>the</strong>r than a l<strong>in</strong>guistic one; <strong>the</strong> speaker is moresalient (pragmatically) than <strong>the</strong> hearer, as <strong>in</strong> (3). Thus it is possible to have subject clitic sets wherespeaker reference is lexicalized, while speaker reference lacks a lexicalization, be<strong>in</strong>g recoverable<strong>in</strong>dependently of context <strong>in</strong> virtue of its salience. The reverse is not possible. This split between 1 stand 2 nd person may not be def<strong>in</strong>ed for plural referents, as <strong>in</strong> (4). Aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>re is no evidence that (4)refers to a syntactictically structured content, as opposed to a purely conceptual one.(3) (pragmatic) salience of speaker reference(4) (3) not def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pluralIn languages which differentiate non-modal subject clitic series from modal (<strong>in</strong>terrogative) ones, <strong>the</strong>modal series can keep <strong>the</strong> conditions of <strong>the</strong> non-modal one (i.e. Ø P), or it can neutralize <strong>the</strong> split,or it can reverse it. The neutralization of <strong>the</strong> split corresponds to a simple mechanism of <strong>the</strong> type <strong>in</strong>(4) with (<strong>in</strong>terrogative) modality substituted for plural. Possibly <strong>the</strong> reverse of <strong>the</strong> prom<strong>in</strong>encehierarchy <strong>in</strong> (3) (i.e. hearer more salient) may hold <strong>in</strong> languages which reverse <strong>the</strong> lexicalizationsplit <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrogative contexts. Turn<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> have/ be alternation <strong>in</strong> (2), it is tempt<strong>in</strong>g to read <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>predom<strong>in</strong>ant alignment of hearer with be and speaker with have a reflex of <strong>the</strong> classical ergativitysplit, whereby most prom<strong>in</strong>ent arguments are aligned with nom<strong>in</strong>ative (transitive have), thougho<strong>the</strong>r arguments may be aligned with absolutive (ergative be). In this <strong>in</strong>stance, however, <strong>the</strong> reversealignment is also possible (cf. <strong>the</strong> last column <strong>in</strong> (2)). S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> two alignments subtly differ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>irconsequences for <strong>the</strong> plural, possibly a markedness effect is at play, allow<strong>in</strong>g for lesser variation <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> marked alignment. In any event, note <strong>the</strong> substantial identity of <strong>the</strong>se parameters with thosedef<strong>in</strong>ed by typological data despite <strong>the</strong> different gra<strong>in</strong> of <strong>the</strong> variation <strong>in</strong>volved (micro- vs. macrovariation).Discussion. The models discussed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature (cartography, DM, OT) have a similar outlookon variation. DM (e.g. Calabrese) is clearest on variation be<strong>in</strong>g a PF <strong>in</strong>terface matter, s<strong>in</strong>ce it pairsabstract, (potentially) universal bundles of features with a PF exponent only <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> postsyntacticMorphological Structuer component. The Kaynian silent categories approach, presuppos<strong>in</strong>gsometh<strong>in</strong>g like an underly<strong>in</strong>g universal cartographic tree, is also compatible with a PF <strong>in</strong>terfaceview of variation, whereby certa<strong>in</strong> pieces of structure are left unpronounced, though syntacticallypresent. The view I take is that variation is def<strong>in</strong>ed by lexical items carv<strong>in</strong>g directly <strong>the</strong> universalconceptual/ categorial space. This reflects <strong>the</strong> traditional lexicalist conception of <strong>the</strong> architecture ofgrammar, under which <strong>the</strong> mapp<strong>in</strong>g between LF content and PF content, with its potential forvariation, is carried out by <strong>the</strong> lexicon. S<strong>in</strong>ce lexical items cut <strong>the</strong> conceptual repertory <strong>in</strong> slightlydifferent ways, and <strong>the</strong> syntax is projected from <strong>the</strong> lexicon (Chomsky 1995), differ<strong>in</strong>g lexicons,though built on <strong>the</strong> basis of an identical conceptual repertory, will yield different syntaxes.My argument here is not that an account of, say, <strong>the</strong> gaps <strong>in</strong> subject clitic paradigm <strong>in</strong> (1)along <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>in</strong> (3)-(4) cannot be executed at <strong>the</strong> PF <strong>in</strong>terface it obviously can. The po<strong>in</strong>t is that<strong>the</strong> non syntactically structured <strong>in</strong>terface offered by <strong>the</strong> conceptual system is sufficient to yield <strong>the</strong>desired parametrization as well. Vice versa, <strong>the</strong> extra mechanisms (rigid hierarchies) made availableby a syntactically structured <strong>in</strong>terface are not exploited by lexicalization/ parametrization certa<strong>in</strong>ly<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> cases at hand and arguably <strong>in</strong> all (sufficiently documented) <strong>in</strong>stances. This is not expected iflexicalization/ parametrization is a PF <strong>in</strong>terface phenomenon, feed<strong>in</strong>g on syntactic(-like) structures.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!