09.07.2015 Views

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

Practical Information - Generative Linguistics in the Old World

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

However when <strong>the</strong> VP (or IP) is elided sprout<strong>in</strong>g is available (11,12). Unlike <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> movementexamples <strong>in</strong> (9,10) swip<strong>in</strong>g is possible and sprout<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> object of <strong>the</strong> preposition alone is not.(11) Amy talked to someone. Jim did [talk to someone] too, but I don’t know who *(to)(12) Someone was wait<strong>in</strong>g for someth<strong>in</strong>g. I remember who, but I can’t remember what *(for).New Account: Descriptively, we see that sprout<strong>in</strong>g is conditioned on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner antecedent be<strong>in</strong>gboth <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite (someth<strong>in</strong>g or null) and implicit (elided or null). This rules <strong>in</strong> null <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite andelided <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite antecedents. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand this rules out traces of movement and un-elidedsometh<strong>in</strong>g which are respectively not <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite and not implicit. Why is it that sprout<strong>in</strong>g occursunder <strong>the</strong>se conditions? An important commonality is that <strong>in</strong> both environments <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>nerantecedent becomes Given <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense of Schwarzschild (1999). Merchant (2001) argues thatellipsis is licensed by Given-ness and elid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> overt <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite <strong>in</strong>ner antecedent someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>(11,12) ensures that it is Given. The null <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite complement qua <strong>in</strong>ner antecedent <strong>in</strong> (2) alsobecomes Given when <strong>the</strong> optionally transitive verb is uttered without an <strong>in</strong>ternal argument.A Repercussion: The set of th<strong>in</strong>gs ‘Given’ <strong>in</strong> a discourse is necessarily updated with each newutterance. In <strong>the</strong> dialogue <strong>in</strong> (6), <strong>the</strong> fragment answer utterance updates that which is Given so asto <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>the</strong> elided <strong>in</strong>ner antecedent. The fact that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner antecedent is <strong>the</strong>reby made Givenexpla<strong>in</strong>s why it is irrelevant that <strong>the</strong>re is an overt counterpart (someth<strong>in</strong>g) previously <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>discourse: In light of <strong>the</strong> new utterance, <strong>the</strong> overt version is now Given. The irrelevance ofprevious overt <strong>in</strong>stances of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner antecedent is unexpla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> Larson’s formulation.Constra<strong>in</strong>ts on Sprout<strong>in</strong>g: In <strong>the</strong> null <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite and ellipsis <strong>in</strong>stances above, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>nerantecedent is Given because it is not pronounced. Ask<strong>in</strong>g a content question of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>nerantecedent trivially requires that <strong>the</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>g wh-word be pronounced and thus contrastwith <strong>the</strong> implicit <strong>in</strong>ner antecedent. I posit that this wh-word must <strong>the</strong>n be contrastively focusedand <strong>in</strong> turn have moved to a local focus position before mov<strong>in</strong>g to spec,CP. This local focusmovement will differ cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistically. In English sprout<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> option for local focusmovement is extraposition and only elements that can extrapose can sprout. This makes <strong>the</strong>correct predictions <strong>in</strong> rul<strong>in</strong>g out objects of prepositions (13) among o<strong>the</strong>rs. In languages likeDutch without extraposition, scrambl<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>the</strong> option and constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>the</strong>reon limit sprout<strong>in</strong>g. InDutch <strong>in</strong>direct objects can nei<strong>the</strong>r scramble (Neeleman 1994) nor sprout (14).(13) *J. talked to yesterday a tall man *J. talked, but I don’t know who Amy talked to(14) *J. heeft M. niet boeken uitgedeeld *J. heeft boeken uitgedeeld, maar ik weet niet wieJ. has M. not books out-handed J. has books out-handed but I know not who‘Jan has not handed out books to Marie’ ‘Jan handed out books, but I don’t know who to’In Sum: Determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> conditions on sprout<strong>in</strong>g allows for a unified account of its constra<strong>in</strong>ts.Sprout<strong>in</strong>g relies on <strong>the</strong> relevant sluiced element be<strong>in</strong>g contextually Given. It falls out from thiscondition that <strong>the</strong> Given element is unpronounced and its correspond<strong>in</strong>g wh-word contrastive.Licens<strong>in</strong>g this contrast is not always possible and thus effects constra<strong>in</strong>ts on sprout<strong>in</strong>g.Barker. 2012. How to Sprout. SALT 22. ⋅ Chung, Ladusaw, & McCloskey. 1995. Sluic<strong>in</strong>g andlogical form. Natural Lang. Sem. ⋅ Chung, Ladusaw, & McCloskey. 2010. Sluic<strong>in</strong>g(:) BetweenStructure & Inference. In Represent<strong>in</strong>g Language. ⋅ Larson. 2012. Sprout<strong>in</strong>g Anew. CLS 48. ⋅Merchant. 2001. The syntax of silence: Sluic<strong>in</strong>g, islands, & identity <strong>in</strong> ellipsis. ⋅ Merchant. 2002.Swip<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Germanic. In Studies <strong>in</strong> Comparative Germanic Syntax. ⋅ Merchant. 2004. Fragments& Ellipsis. L<strong>in</strong>g. & Phil. ⋅ Neeleman. 1994. Complex Predicates. Diss. Utrecht U. ⋅ Rosen. 1976.Guess what about? NELS 6. ⋅ Ross. 1969. Guess who? CLS 5. ⋅ Schwarzschild. 1999.Givenness, Avoid F, & o<strong>the</strong>r constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> placement of accent. Natural Lang. Sem.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!