10.05.2015 Views

Human Dignity and Bioethics

Human Dignity and Bioethics

Human Dignity and Bioethics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Two Arguments from <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Dignity</strong> | 457<br />

(1a)<br />

<strong>Human</strong> beings have worth.<br />

<strong>and</strong> that<br />

(2a)<br />

A life in which someone lacks the threshold capacities is<br />

not a life worthy of human beings.<br />

It assumes further that, if human beings have worth, then it is bad<br />

that they should have to live lives that are unworthy of them. Since<br />

(1a) says that people have worth, then (1a) together with this assumption<br />

implies that:<br />

(3a.1)<br />

That human beings should have to live lives that are not<br />

worthy of them is bad.<br />

The Aristotelian Argument also assumes that if someone’s having<br />

to live a life that is not worthy of her is bad, then—if government is<br />

to be appropriately respectful of human worth—that bad is one that<br />

government must avert. This assumption, when conjoined with (2a)<br />

<strong>and</strong> (3a.1), implies that<br />

(3a.2.1) The bad of a human being’s having to live a life in which<br />

she lacks the threshold capacities is one that government<br />

must avert if it is to be appropriately respectful of human<br />

worth.<br />

The proponent of the argument takes for granted that:<br />

(3a.2.2) Government must be appropriately respectful of human<br />

worth.<br />

So it follows from (3a.2.1) that<br />

(3a.2.3) The bad of a human being’s having to live a life in which<br />

she lacks the threshold capacities is one that government<br />

must avert.<br />

(3a.2.3) seems to imply the conclusion of the Aristotelian Argument,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!