10.05.2015 Views

Human Dignity and Bioethics

Human Dignity and Bioethics

Human Dignity and Bioethics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

344 | Susan M. Shell<br />

Kantian principles will thus retain a sense of the ultimate mysteriousness<br />

of life—not on dogmatically religious grounds but as an extension<br />

of the speculative modesty that flows from a critical awareness<br />

of the necessary structure <strong>and</strong> limits of human cognition. We cannot<br />

help but underst<strong>and</strong> our own organs <strong>and</strong> aptitudes as naturally<br />

purposive in a way we are not free to disregard. To be sure, such underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

does not meet the dem<strong>and</strong>s of objective scientific knowledge.<br />

That the eye is “for seeing” cannot be established on the basis of<br />

a mechanical science (or its contemporary equivalent). And yet this<br />

assumption is, in Kant’s view, the indispensable subjective foundation<br />

of any objective scientific inquiry into the processes of vision. 20<br />

Man is not a brain in a vat; but he is also not a disembodied spirit<br />

free to use the matter in which it happens to be housed any way it<br />

chooses. Kant interprets this to mean that one must respect oneself<br />

“as an animal being,” e.g., by not killing oneself or defiling oneself by<br />

lust. It also means that one ought not employ one’s body in ways that<br />

strike us as counter-purposive: e.g., committing suicide for the sake<br />

of pleasure. Some of Kant’s arguments in this regard are no doubt<br />

idiosyncratic, especially where sexual matters are concerned. Still,<br />

the general point seems both valid <strong>and</strong> of potential bioethical significance.<br />

Recognition of the impossibility, in principle, of reducing<br />

life to a mere mechanism argues for humility when confronted with<br />

new opportunities for genetic or other radical “enhancements” of the<br />

human organism. Wherever we strive to exceed the st<strong>and</strong>ard set by<br />

normal life functions (a st<strong>and</strong>ard roughly equivalent to “health”), we<br />

risk grave harms that we cannot in principle foresee. *Ethical compunction<br />

here conspires with ordinary prudence to urge the greatest<br />

caution in engaging in experiments that exceed what natural functions<br />

by themselves support.<br />

A pragmatic orientation in Kant’s sense no doubt suggests other<br />

ethical limits on uses of one’s body—proscribing, for example, sale<br />

of organs or of services that drastically impinge on basic bodily processes.<br />

21 Here fine distinctions may have to be drawn: selling one’s<br />

hair or small quantities of blood differs from selling a kidney or contracting<br />

to become a maternal surrogate. Still the implicit ethical<br />

* One example: according to one very recent study, disabling the cell’s “aging”<br />

gene—a procedure undertaken in the hopes of extending its life expectancy—<br />

proves instead vastly to increase its susceptibility to cancer.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!