10.05.2015 Views

Human Dignity and Bioethics

Human Dignity and Bioethics

Human Dignity and Bioethics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Commentary on Meilaender <strong>and</strong> Lawler| 287<br />

mean to suggest that Lincoln would have denied sustenance to the<br />

young or the elderly or the sick. Lincoln was attacking the injustice<br />

of slave labor, <strong>and</strong> his arguments were marshaled accordingly. I have<br />

no doubt that Lincoln would defend the right to life as vigorously as<br />

he defended the right to liberty. We have evidence of his capacious<br />

humanity in the closing lines of the Second Inaugural when he calls<br />

on Americans “to care for him who shall have borne the battle, <strong>and</strong><br />

for his widow, <strong>and</strong> his orphan.”<br />

The example of Lincoln leads me to think that we have a model<br />

for how to combine <strong>and</strong> celebrate both the respects in which human<br />

beings are equal <strong>and</strong> the respects in which they are unequal. One<br />

need not imperil the other. Indeed, the life of Lincoln—a superior<br />

man who devoted <strong>and</strong> sacrificed his life to the teaching of equality—<br />

reminds us that we can’t have one without the other. We shouldn’t<br />

lose sight of the success of the American Founders, among whom I<br />

include Lincoln, in combining the egalitarian <strong>and</strong> the inegalitarian.<br />

They didn’t seem to struggle with it as we do. They were a happy<br />

amalgam: Greco-Roman, Judeo-Christian Lockeans. Whether this<br />

synthesis coheres in theory or not, perhaps we need to take it more<br />

seriously as a basis for sound policy guidance<br />

Meilaender asserts that there are two places where judgments of<br />

individual worth should not be given any scope: at the threshold<br />

of death <strong>and</strong> participation in human society. Meilaender seems to<br />

say these are absolutes. He quotes Kierkegaard approvingly: “If you<br />

save a person’s life in the dark, thinking that it is a friend—but it<br />

was the neighbor—this is no mistake.” I can imagine scenarios in<br />

which it might have been a very big mistake: what if your neighbor<br />

also happened to be your enemy <strong>and</strong> you happened to have been<br />

on a nighttime reconnaissance mission? Kierkegaard’s statement is<br />

radically apolitical; it abstracts entirely from the distinction between<br />

friend <strong>and</strong> foe. Does the political fact that some neighbors are friends<br />

<strong>and</strong> allies while others are deadly <strong>and</strong> inveterate foes require that individuals<br />

in authority be entrusted with the power of life <strong>and</strong> death<br />

over other individuals? Or are the claims of “the neighbor” indeed<br />

absolute? If human judgments have no place at the threshold of<br />

death does that require not only opposition to the death penalty but<br />

thoroughgoing pacifism as well?<br />

This question points back to the striking contrast between St.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!