10.05.2015 Views

Human Dignity and Bioethics

Human Dignity and Bioethics

Human Dignity and Bioethics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Commentary on Churchl<strong>and</strong> | 123<br />

are to survive. (In passing, lest we confuse causes with reasons, we<br />

should note that this is less an account of the origins of morality than<br />

an explanation of its point.) And surely this is part of the point of<br />

morality. Yet, one of the oldest puzzles about morality is that what<br />

my group needs to survive <strong>and</strong> flourish may be my own willingness<br />

to suffer or die. “Men need virtues as bees need stings,” Peter Geach<br />

once wrote. “An individual bee may perish by stinging, all the same<br />

bees need stings: an individual man may perish by being brave or<br />

just, all the same men need courage <strong>and</strong> justice.” 1 The best Churchl<strong>and</strong><br />

can do to make place for this truth is to note that altruistic<br />

behavior in the past might (via a complicated scenario that is purely<br />

speculative) have spread throughout the population.<br />

However we account for such sacrificial behavior, Churchl<strong>and</strong>’s<br />

depiction of a neurobiological foundation for morality cannot explain<br />

our experience of intentional action. A person is not simply<br />

a place where certain psychological states occur. A person is present<br />

in his actions without disappearing entirely into them—present in<br />

but also distanced from them. Activities of the brain do surely provide,<br />

as Churchl<strong>and</strong> puts it, “a biological substratum” for the mind’s<br />

thoughts <strong>and</strong> intentions, but those mental activities in turn interact<br />

with <strong>and</strong> shape the brain. Our thoughts are both located in the brain<br />

<strong>and</strong> distanced from it—which is why we are capable of what Thomas<br />

Nagel has called “the view from nowhere.”<br />

If we think of morality in Churchl<strong>and</strong>’s way, moral education—<br />

“stories about the glory of courage <strong>and</strong> the humiliation of cowardice…;<br />

songs about kindness rewarded <strong>and</strong> sharing blessed”—is not<br />

initiating the young into a set of obligations that unfold the meaning<br />

of human flourishing. It is, instead, simply training them in behaviors<br />

that “solidify social values.” There is all the difference in the<br />

world between indoctrinating the young in a set of norms we find<br />

useful <strong>and</strong> initiating the young into a set of norms that bind us also,<br />

even when we wish they did not. “We castrate <strong>and</strong> bid the geldings<br />

be fruitful,” was C. S. Lewis’s description of what moral education<br />

becomes on a view such as she espouses. 2<br />

Churchl<strong>and</strong>’s discussion of embryonic stem cell research is so<br />

lacking in nuance as to be embarrassing. She takes the distinction<br />

between therapeutic <strong>and</strong> reproductive embryo research to be obvious<br />

<strong>and</strong> in no need of clarification or argument. She evidently thinks

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!