27.04.2015 Views

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

25.3. NONSTANDARD MODELS OF ANALYSIS 313<br />

nonlogical symbol of L* the same denotation as does the given interpretation. Thus<br />

the lower part of N ** is N *. A sentence of L* will be true in an interpretation of L**<br />

if <strong>and</strong> only if it is true in the lower part of that interpretation. Thus a sentence of L*is<br />

a theorem of (that is, is in) true arithmetic if <strong>and</strong> only if it is a theorem of true analysis.<br />

Our first aim in this section will be to establish the existence of nonst<strong>and</strong>ard models<br />

of analysis of two distinct kinds. An interpretation of L** is called an ∈-model if (as<br />

in the st<strong>and</strong>ard interpretation) the elements of the upper domain are sets of elements<br />

of the lower domain, <strong>and</strong> the interpretation of ∈ is the membership or elementhood<br />

relation ∈ (between elements of the lower <strong>and</strong> the upper domain). The sentence<br />

∀X∀Y (∀x(x∈X ↔ x∈Y ) → X = Y )<br />

is called the axiom of extensionality. Clearly it is true in any ∈-model <strong>and</strong> hence in<br />

any model isomorphic to an ∈-model. Conversely, any model M of extensionality<br />

is isomorphic to an ∈-model M # . [To obtain M # from M, keep the same lower<br />

domain <strong>and</strong> the same interpretations for symbols of L*, replace each element α of<br />

the upper domain of M by the set α # of all elements a of the lower domain such that<br />

a ∈ M α, <strong>and</strong> interpret ∈ not as the relation ∈ M but as ∈. The identity function on the<br />

lower domain together with the function sending α to α # is an isomorphism. The only<br />

point that may not be immediately obvious is that the latter function is one-to-one. To<br />

see this, note that if α # = β # , then α <strong>and</strong> β satisfy ∀x(x ∈ X ↔ x ∈ Y )inM, <strong>and</strong><br />

since (2) is true in M, α <strong>and</strong> β must satisfy X = Y , that is, we must have α = β.]<br />

Since we are going to be interested only in models of extensionality, we may restrict<br />

our attention to ∈-models.<br />

If the lower part of an ∈-model M is the st<strong>and</strong>ard model of arithmetic, we call<br />

M an ω-model. The st<strong>and</strong>ard model of analysis is, of course, an ω-model. If an<br />

ω-model of analysis is nonst<strong>and</strong>ard, its upper domain must consist of some class<br />

of sets properly contained in the class of all sets of numbers. If the lower part of an<br />

∈-model M is isomorphic to the st<strong>and</strong>ard interpretation N *ofL*, then M as a whole<br />

is isomorphic to an ω-model M # . [If j is the isomorphism from N * to the lower part<br />

of M, replace each element α of the upper domain of M by the set of n such that<br />

j(n) ∈ α, to obtain M # .] So we may restrict our attention to models that are of one of<br />

two kinds, namely, those that either are ω-models, or have a nonst<strong>and</strong>ard lower part.<br />

Our first result is that nonst<strong>and</strong>ard models of analysis of both kinds exist.<br />

25.9 Proposition. Both nonst<strong>and</strong>ard models of analysis whose lower part is a nonst<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

model of arithmetic <strong>and</strong> nonst<strong>and</strong>ard ω-models of analysis exist.<br />

Proof: The existence of nonst<strong>and</strong>ard models of arithmetic was established in the<br />

problems at the end of Chapter 12 by applying the compactness theorem to the theory<br />

that results upon adding to arithmetic a constant ∞ <strong>and</strong> the sentences ∞ ≠ n for all<br />

natural numbers n. The same proof, with analysis in place of arithmetic, establishes<br />

the existence of a nonst<strong>and</strong>ard model of analysis whose lower parts is a nonst<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

model of arithmetic. The strong Löwenheim–Skolem theorem implies the existence<br />

of an enumerable subinterpretation of the st<strong>and</strong>ard model of analysis that is itself<br />

a model of analysis. This must be an ω-model, but it cannot be isomorphic to the<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard model, whose upper domain is nonenumerable.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!