27.04.2015 Views

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

19.2. SKOLEM NORMAL FORM 251<br />

19.9 Theorem (Strong Löwenheim–Skolem theorem). Let A be a nonenumerable<br />

model of an enumerable set of sentences Ɣ. Then A has an enumerable subinterpretation<br />

that is also a model of Ɣ.<br />

Proof: It will suffice to prove the theorem for the special case of sets of ∀-sentences.<br />

For suppose we have proved the theorem in this special case, <strong>and</strong> consider the general<br />

case where A is a model of some arbitrary set of sentences Ɣ. Then as in our earlier<br />

discussion, A has an expansion A # to a model of Ɣ # , the set of Skolem forms of<br />

the sentences in Ɣ. Since Skolem forms are ∀-sentences, by the special case of the<br />

theorem there will an enumerable subinterpretation B # that is also a model of Ɣ # .<br />

Then since the Skolem form of a sentence implies the original sentence, B # will also<br />

be a model of Ɣ, <strong>and</strong> so will be its reduct B to the original language. But this B will<br />

be an enumerable subinterpretation of A.<br />

To prove the theorem in the special case where all sentences in Ɣ are ∀-sentences,<br />

consider the set B of all denotations in A of closed terms of the language of Ɣ.<br />

(We may assume there are some closed terms, since if not, we may add a constant<br />

c to the language <strong>and</strong> the logically valid sentence c = c to Ɣ.) Since that language<br />

is enumerable, so is the set of closed terms, <strong>and</strong> so is B. Since B is closed under<br />

the functions that are denotations of the function symbols of the language, it is the<br />

domain of an enumerable subinterpretation B of A. And by Proposition 19.7, every<br />

∀-sentence true in A is true in B,soB is a model of Ɣ.<br />

Two interpretations A <strong>and</strong> B for the same language are called elementarily equivalent<br />

if every sentence true in the one is true in the other. Taking for Ɣ in the above<br />

version of the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem the set of all sentences true in A, the<br />

theorem tells us that any interpretation has an enumerable subinterpretation that is<br />

elementarily equivalent to it. A subinterpretation B of an interpretation A is called<br />

an elementary subinterpretation if for any formula F(x 1 , ..., x n ) <strong>and</strong> any elements<br />

b 1 , ..., b n of |B|, the elements satisfy the formula in A if <strong>and</strong> only if they satisfy<br />

it in B. This implies elementary equivalence, but is in general a stronger condition.<br />

By extending the notion of Skolem normal form to formulas with free variables,<br />

the above strong version of the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem can be sharpened to<br />

a still stronger one telling us that any interpretation has an enumerable elementary<br />

subinterpretation.<br />

Applications of Skolem normal form will be given in the next section. Since<br />

we are not going to be needing the sharper result stated in the preceding paragraph<br />

for these applications, we do not go into the (tedious but routine) details<br />

of its proof. Instead, before turning to applications we wish to discuss another,<br />

more philosophical issue. At one time the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem (especially<br />

in the strong form in which we have proved it in this section) was considered<br />

philosophically perplexing because some of its consequences were perceived<br />

as anomalous. The apparent anomaly, sometime called ‘Skolem’s paradox’, is that<br />

there exist certain interpretations in which a certain sentence, which seems to say<br />

that nonenumerably many sets of natural numbers exist, is true, even though the<br />

domains of these interpretations contain only enumerably many sets of natural numbers,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the predicate in the sentence that we would be inclined to translate

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!