27.04.2015 Views

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

234 THE UNPROVABILITY OF CONSISTENCY<br />

18.3 Theorem (Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem, abstract form). Let T be a<br />

consistent, axiomatizable extension of P, <strong>and</strong> let B(x) be a formula having properties<br />

(P1)–(P3) above. Then not ⊢ T ∼B( 0 = 1 ).<br />

The proof will occupy the remainder of this chapter. Throughout, let T be an<br />

extension (not necessarily consistent) of Q. A formula B(x) with properties (P1)–<br />

(P3) of Lemma 18.2 we call a provability predicate for T .Webeginwithafew<br />

words about this notion. The formula Prv T (x) considered so far we call the traditional<br />

provability predicate for T , though, as we have indicated, we are not going to give the<br />

proof of Lemma 18.2, <strong>and</strong> so are not going to be giving the proof that the ‘traditional<br />

provability predicate’ is a ‘provability predicate’ in the sense of our official definition<br />

of the latter term.<br />

If T is ω-consistent, taking the traditional Prv T (x) for B(x), we have also the<br />

following property, the converse of (P1):<br />

(P4)<br />

If ⊢ T B( A ) then ⊢ T A.<br />

[For if we had ⊢ T Prv T ( A ), or in other words ⊢ T ∃y Prf T ( A , y), but did not have<br />

⊢ T A, then for each b, ∼Prf T ( A , b) would be correct <strong>and</strong> hence provable in Q <strong>and</strong><br />

hence in T , <strong>and</strong> we would have an ω-inconsistency in T .] We do not, however, include<br />

ω-consistency in our assumptions on T , or (P4) in our definition of the technical<br />

term ‘provability predicate’. Without the assumption of (P4), which is not part of our<br />

official definition, a ‘provability predicate’ need not have much to do with provability.<br />

In fact, the formula x = x is easily seen to be a ‘provability predicate’ in the sense<br />

of our definition.<br />

On the other h<strong>and</strong>, a formula may arithmetically define the set of Gödel numbers<br />

of theorems of T without being a provability predicate for T .IfT is consistent <strong>and</strong><br />

Prv T (x) is the traditional provability predicate for T , then not only does Prv T (x)<br />

arithmetically define the set of Gödel numbers of theorems of T , but so does the<br />

formula Prv* T (x), which is the conjunction of Prv T (x) with ∼Prv T ( 0 = 1 ), since the<br />

second conjunct is true. But notice that, in contrast to Theorem 18.1, ∼Prv* T ( 0 = 1 )<br />

is provable in T . For it is simply<br />

∼(Prv T ( 0 = 1 )&∼Prv T ( 0 = 1 ))<br />

which is a valid sentence <strong>and</strong> hence a theorem of any theory. The formula Prv* T (x),<br />

however, lacks property (P1) in the definition of provability predicate. That is, it<br />

is not the case that if ⊢ T A then ⊢ T Prv* T ( A ). Indeed, it is never the case that<br />

⊢ T Prv* T ( A ), since it is not the case that ⊢ T ∼Prv T ( 0 = 1 ), by Theorem 18.1.<br />

The traditional provability predicate Prv T (x) has the further important, if nonmathematical,<br />

property beyond (P0)–(P4), that intuitively speaking Prv(x) can plausibly<br />

be regarded as meaning or saying (on the st<strong>and</strong>ard interpretation) that x is the Gödel<br />

number of a sentence that is provable in T . This is conspicuously not the case for<br />

Prv* T (x), which means or says that x the Gödel number of a sentence that is provable<br />

in T <strong>and</strong> T is consistent.<br />

The thought that whatever is provable had better be true might make it surprising<br />

that a further condition was not included in the definition of provability predicate,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!