27.04.2015 Views

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

184 PROOFS AND COMPLETENESS<br />

In addition to such substantive variations as we have been discussing, considerable<br />

variations in style are possible, <strong>and</strong> in particular in typographical layout. For instance,<br />

if one opens an introductory textbook, one may well encounter something like what<br />

appears in Figure 14-1.<br />

(i) ~A → ~B<br />

(ii)<br />

(iii) ~A<br />

B<br />

(1) ~A → ~B (Q0), (i)<br />

(2) ~A (Q0), (iii)<br />

(3) ~B (Q1), (1), (2)<br />

(4) B (Q0), (ii)<br />

(5) ~~A (Q4), (3), (4)<br />

(6) A (Q3), (5)<br />

(7) B → A (Q2), (6)<br />

Figure 14-1. A ‘natural deduction’.<br />

What appears in Figure 14-1 is really the same as what appears in Example 14.21,<br />

differently displayed. The form of display adopted in this book, as illustrated in<br />

Example 14.21, is designed for convenience when engaged in theoretical writing<br />

about deductions. But when engaged in the practical writing of deductions, as in<br />

introductory texts, the form of display in Figure 14-1 is more convenient, because it<br />

involves less rewriting of the same formula over <strong>and</strong> over again. In lines (1)–(7) in<br />

Figure 14-1, one only writes the sentence D on the right of the sequent Ɣ ⇒ D that<br />

occurs at the corresponding line in Example 14.21. Which of the sentences (i), (ii),<br />

(iii) occur in the set Ɣ on the left of that sequent is indicated by the spatial position<br />

where D is written: if it is written in the third column, all of (i)–(iii) appear; if in the<br />

second, only (i) <strong>and</strong> (ii) appear; if in the first, only (i). Colloquially one sometimes<br />

speaks of deducing a conclusion D ‘under’ certain hypotheses Ɣ, but in the form of<br />

display illustrated in Figure 14-1, the spatial metaphor is taken quite literally.<br />

It would take us too far afield to enter into a detailed description of the conventions<br />

of this form of display, which in any case can be found expounded in many introductory<br />

texts. The pair of examples given should suffice to make our only real point here:<br />

that what is substantively the same kind of procedure can be set forth in very different<br />

styles, <strong>and</strong> indeed appropriately so, given the different purposes of introductory texts<br />

<strong>and</strong> of more theoretical books like this one. Despite the diversity of approaches possible,<br />

the aim of any approach is to set up a system of rules with the properties that if<br />

D is deducible from Ɣ, then D is a consequence of Ɣ (soundness), <strong>and</strong> that if D is a<br />

consequence of Ɣ, then D is formally deducible from Ɣ (completeness). Clearly, all<br />

systems of rules that achieve these aims will be equivalent to each other in the sense<br />

that D will be deducible from Ɣ in the one system if <strong>and</strong> only if D is deducible from<br />

Ɣ in the other system. Except for one optional section at the end of the next chapter,<br />

there will be no further mention of the details of our particular proof procedure in the<br />

rest of this book.<br />

A word may now be said about the relationship between any formal notion, whether<br />

ours or a variant, of deduction of a sentence from a set of sentences, <strong>and</strong> the notion in

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!