Dummett's Backward Road to Frege and to Intuitionism - Tripod

Dummett's Backward Road to Frege and to Intuitionism - Tripod Dummett's Backward Road to Frege and to Intuitionism - Tripod

memberstripod
from memberstripod More from this publisher
09.11.2012 Views

himself. He will always be the world’s best Frege scholar to me. I want to thank him for over fifty years of wonderful service not only to the community of Frege scholars, but to the world of philosophy at large. Thanks to his devotion and integrity, and his ability to bring out the huge volumes of thought implicit in Frege, he has done more than anyone to bring Frege to his rightful place in philosophy. Notes 1. Dummett prefers the term “referents” (1981: 94; 1981a: 2). 2. My (1979: 59–85), summarized in my (1982: 2–5), and updated in my (1996: 104–9; 2003: 104–9). All three provide a specific analysis explaining why Frege’s formally explicit definition of Number is implicitly and functionally a contextual definition, in contrast to Dummett’s general and conclusory paragraph (1995: 4–5). The heart of the analysis is that once we see that parallel completions of (A) identity statements about numbers, (B) statements of the equinumerosity of certain concepts, and (C) identity statements about the extensions of those concepts, are logically equivalent, the mediation of (B) can drop out and the identification of numbers with the extensions can take on a life of its own (and this takes us to the later Frege). The end result is an explicit definition, just as Dummett says, but this is just a husk covering up the contextual work of (B)’s mediation. I mailed a copy of my (1979) to Dummett in 1979. He never replied. I wonder if he ever received it. Imagine if he had recanted in 1979! 3. Strictly, about the object that represents identity, namely, a double course-of-values. 4. The geometry permutation is also a private language argument (compare Dummett 1981: 638–42). In Grundlagen, Frege uses private language arguments to show that numbers are mind-independently objective long before he uses the context principle to define numbers. 5. This is not Quine’s sense, which involves a fact of the matter (Gibson 1987: 147; Quine 1987: 155). 6. Grundgesetze vol. 1, §§ 0, 30; Frege (1980c: 36–37; 1970d: 42–43; 1970f: 59–61). 66

7. Frege (1979j: 271; see 1980c: 37; 1979f: 209; 1971: 53, 59); Kluge (1971: xxvii). 8. Thus the Heijenoort-Hintikka critique of Frege’s distinction between metalanguage and object- language is misplaced. For Frege, the distinction has nothing to do with whether his quantifiers range over names as well as objects. For him, the key issue is that science must begin with explications, on pain of vicious regress of definitions. Frege demands that explications occur in a propaedeutic because they are too uncertain to belong to rigorous science. This is what requires and justifies his use of metalanguage. Even if Frege’s quantifiers range over names as well as objects, he can still make the distinction by using predicates such as “x is a name of y” and “z explicates name x.” The quantifiers would then be the vehicles for general statements about explication (my 2003: 82; compare Dummett 1981: 226). Indeed, what better way is there to talk about general relationships among names and objects, in object-languages or metalanguages? In Neurath’s metaphor, formal object-languages and formal metalanguages are rebuilt ships at sea, built from the timbers of a natural language. Thus to call an object-language level 0 and its metalanguages levels 1...n is to go in the wrong direction. It is the natural language which is the level 0 starting point, and the object-language is the level n result. Any formalization of a natural language ought to preserve its capacity for referring both to objects and to its own words, as well as to their relationships. And “Carnap...has...shown that a language can without self-contradiction be used in the analysis of itself” (Ayer 1952: 71; see Carnap 1959: xiv, 53). That is, a language can function as, and so be, both an object-language and a metalanguage. Within a universal logic, it is not only possible but necessary to discuss itself as an object-language metalinguistically. Of course, we can also discuss a universal logic from without, i.e. from within another logic. What reason is there to suppose that Frege’s quantifiers do range over both names and objects? Frege seems to use German as a metalanguage to explicate the semantics of his eight primitive terms informally as object-language, then to formalize their use through regimentation; and all his defined terms are mere abbreviations. He knows the use-mention distinction, and his formal notation seems 67

7. <strong>Frege</strong> (1979j: 271; see 1980c: 37; 1979f: 209; 1971: 53, 59); Kluge (1971: xxvii).<br />

8. Thus the Heijenoort-Hintikka critique of <strong>Frege</strong>’s distinction between metalanguage <strong>and</strong> object-<br />

language is misplaced. For <strong>Frege</strong>, the distinction has nothing <strong>to</strong> do with whether his quantifiers range<br />

over names as well as objects. For him, the key issue is that science must begin with explications, on<br />

pain of vicious regress of definitions. <strong>Frege</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s that explications occur in a propaedeutic because<br />

they are <strong>to</strong>o uncertain <strong>to</strong> belong <strong>to</strong> rigorous science. This is what requires <strong>and</strong> justifies his use of<br />

metalanguage. Even if <strong>Frege</strong>’s quantifiers range over names as well as objects, he can still make the<br />

distinction by using predicates such as “x is a name of y” <strong>and</strong> “z explicates name x.” The quantifiers<br />

would then be the vehicles for general statements about explication (my 2003: 82; compare Dummett<br />

1981: 226). Indeed, what better way is there <strong>to</strong> talk about general relationships among names <strong>and</strong><br />

objects, in object-languages or metalanguages? In Neurath’s metaphor, formal object-languages <strong>and</strong><br />

formal metalanguages are rebuilt ships at sea, built from the timbers of a natural language. Thus <strong>to</strong> call<br />

an object-language level 0 <strong>and</strong> its metalanguages levels 1...n is <strong>to</strong> go in the wrong direction. It is the<br />

natural language which is the level 0 starting point, <strong>and</strong> the object-language is the level n result. Any<br />

formalization of a natural language ought <strong>to</strong> preserve its capacity for referring both <strong>to</strong> objects <strong>and</strong> <strong>to</strong> its<br />

own words, as well as <strong>to</strong> their relationships. And “Carnap...has...shown that a language can without<br />

self-contradiction be used in the analysis of itself” (Ayer 1952: 71; see Carnap 1959: xiv, 53). That is, a<br />

language can function as, <strong>and</strong> so be, both an object-language <strong>and</strong> a metalanguage. Within a universal<br />

logic, it is not only possible but necessary <strong>to</strong> discuss itself as an object-language metalinguistically. Of<br />

course, we can also discuss a universal logic from without, i.e. from within another logic.<br />

What reason is there <strong>to</strong> suppose that <strong>Frege</strong>’s quantifiers do range over both names <strong>and</strong> objects?<br />

<strong>Frege</strong> seems <strong>to</strong> use German as a metalanguage <strong>to</strong> explicate the semantics of his eight primitive terms<br />

informally as object-language, then <strong>to</strong> formalize their use through regimentation; <strong>and</strong> all his defined<br />

terms are mere abbreviations. He knows the use-mention distinction, <strong>and</strong> his formal notation seems<br />

67

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!