Dummett's Backward Road to Frege and to Intuitionism - Tripod

Dummett's Backward Road to Frege and to Intuitionism - Tripod Dummett's Backward Road to Frege and to Intuitionism - Tripod

memberstripod
from memberstripod More from this publisher
09.11.2012 Views

that are indirect references. He might say that in all the works in which it looks for all the world that Frege is introducing senses as a unique category to do a job objects cannot do, Frege is really distinguishing objects which are not senses from other objects which are, but without ever telling us his secret meaning. He might even say that while a truth-value is not a sense but an object, a sense is both a sense and an object. But all this is curiouser and curiouser. Frege’s plain meaning is that senses and objects are different categories. A sense is not an object but a sense. An object is not a sense but an object. And Frege is most naturally read in all these texts as arguing for the even more general thesis that no customary references are senses. Frege rarely argues that concrete objects in particular cannot be senses. He says “one can see Etna, but one cannot see the thought that Etna is higher than Vesuvius” (1979f: 225). He says “the sense of the word ‘sun’ is not somewhere in space, nor does it have mass” (1980e: 128). We can see why he has little interest in giving such arguments: they are shallow and overkill. “On Sense and Reference” and “[Comments on Sense and Meaning]” read so much more easily when we think of senses as a unique category that we can see how badly Dummett is bewitched by his belief that Frege says every entity is a function or an object. For example, Frege explains objects as the customary references of proper names. Frege says, discussing only the customary reference of a proper name, “I call such a meaning [i.e. customary reference] an object” (1979c: 119). Is that the role of any senses? Quite the opposite. Senses are introduced precisely because the category of objects is inadequate to explain the possibility of informative identity statements. Frege says “it is via a sense, and only via a sense that a proper name is related to an object” (1979c: 124); the word “object” is used without qualification. This implies that if senses are objects, they are named only via senses. If then senses are objects, is there not a vicious regress of objects? Or is the category of objects then adequate to explain the possibility of informative identity statements after all? This is not to mention the diagram in Frege’s letter to Husserl with all the senses on one line 52

and all the references on another. Frege says: The following schema should make my view clear: Proposition proper name concept word ↓ ↓ ↓ sense of the sense of thesense of the proposition proper name concept word (thought) ↓ ↓ ↓ meaning of the meaning of the meaning of the → object falling proposition proper name concept word under the concept (truth value) (object) (concept) (Frege 1980d: 63, brackets omitted) Frege places objects on only one line, the line of references. 29 Dummett is placing objects on both lines. If senses are objects, why does Frege not write “object” for the three senses on the line of senses? Or if only complete senses are objects, why does Frege not write “object” for the two complete senses? The answer is in “On Sense and Reference”: for they are not objects but senses. 30 This pulls the realm of senses out of the realm of customary references, pace Dummett (1981: 680). In fact, as we saw, Frege’s distinction between senses in general and references in general already does that. This answers the question, Just how tightly does Frege tie linguistic function to ontological category (Dummett, 1981a: 384)? Namely, tightly enough to pull the whole category of senses out of the category of customary references. And by parity of reason, tightly enough to pull tones and forces out of that realm. For if anything, they function even less like customary references than senses do. I 53

<strong>and</strong> all the references on another. <strong>Frege</strong> says:<br />

The following schema should make my view clear:<br />

Proposition proper name concept word<br />

↓ ↓ ↓<br />

sense of the sense of thesense of the<br />

proposition proper name concept word<br />

(thought)<br />

↓ ↓ ↓<br />

meaning of the meaning of the meaning of the → object falling<br />

proposition proper name concept word under the concept<br />

(truth value) (object) (concept)<br />

(<strong>Frege</strong> 1980d: 63, brackets omitted)<br />

<strong>Frege</strong> places objects on only one line, the line of references. 29 Dummett is placing objects on both lines.<br />

If senses are objects, why does <strong>Frege</strong> not write “object” for the three senses on the line of senses? Or if<br />

only complete senses are objects, why does <strong>Frege</strong> not write “object” for the two complete senses? The<br />

answer is in “On Sense <strong>and</strong> Reference”: for they are not objects but senses. 30<br />

This pulls the realm of senses out of the realm of cus<strong>to</strong>mary references, pace Dummett (1981:<br />

680). In fact, as we saw, <strong>Frege</strong>’s distinction between senses in general <strong>and</strong> references in general already<br />

does that. This answers the question, Just how tightly does <strong>Frege</strong> tie linguistic function <strong>to</strong> on<strong>to</strong>logical<br />

category (Dummett, 1981a: 384)? Namely, tightly enough <strong>to</strong> pull the whole category of senses out of<br />

the category of cus<strong>to</strong>mary references. And by parity of reason, tightly enough <strong>to</strong> pull <strong>to</strong>nes <strong>and</strong> forces<br />

out of that realm. For if anything, they function even less like cus<strong>to</strong>mary references than senses do. I<br />

53

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!