Dummett's Backward Road to Frege and to Intuitionism - Tripod

Dummett's Backward Road to Frege and to Intuitionism - Tripod Dummett's Backward Road to Frege and to Intuitionism - Tripod

memberstripod
from memberstripod More from this publisher
09.11.2012 Views

(compare Dummett 1981: 626). And for Frege, everything is regimented at once. This resolves the problem of double oratio obliqua. In ordinary language, the obliqua chips fall where they may. But in the formal notation, since all opaque contexts and all senses, however indirect, are regimented at once, it is always determinate which sense is expressed in which context. Definitions stipulate references only via senses, but Dummett’s program rightly does not concern them. For Frege, definitions are never needed to say what we want to say. They merely abbreviate. 3. Does the program work? Dummett never attempts an example of how his program works. I have already argued that it does not work even if we pump it up with advance knowledge of which portions of sentences to count as subsentential names, and of the senses and references of all primitive logical names, in the object- language. But an example may help. Suppose the vocabulary of object-language L is already given as four blank object-names, “a,” “b,” “c,” and “d,” one blank concept-name, “F( ),” “blank” meaning without their senses or references, plus Frege’s eight primitive logical names with their senses and references. We are then told the truth- conditions of all atomic sentences of L. That can be done only via thoughts, but we can then disregard the thoughts in a sleight of hand in place of the magical start the program demands. Now, if we knew which objects in the world were a, b, c, and d, and that they were the only four objects in the world, and (3) that only a, b, and c fall under the concept F, then there would be no permutation problems for the object-names (e.g. cards or decks), and we could enumeratively define “F( )” as referring to the function that maps arguments a, b, and c, but not d, onto the True. But we are not entitled to know these things on Dummett’s program. Knowing them would amount to knowing the truth-values of the 16

sentences, and we were only supposed to know their truth-conditions. But let us pretend that we magically succeeded in defining the reference of “F( )” in the enumerative manner suggested. Can we thereby derive the sense expressed by “F( )” as the same as that expressed by “( ) falls under the purely extensional in sense (2) mapping-function which maps the arguments a, b, and c, but not d, onto the value the True”? I cannot think of what else Dummett might have in mind. But the reference of “F( )” can be presented in indefinitely many ways, for example, as the reference now under discussion. Thus there can be indefinitely many object-languages L1...Ln that agree on the reference but differ on the sense of “F( ).” Suppose that all and only a, b, and c are red and round. How can we tell whether speakers of L are using “F( )” to express the sense ‘( ) is red’, ‘( ) is round’, ‘( ) is red and round’, or ‘( ) is red or round’? Or in a world in which all and only red objects are round, and in which infinitely many objects are red, so that F( ) must be intensional in sense (3), how can we identify the sense expressed by “F( )”? By hypothesis, the only senses “F( )” could possibly express for us are: ‘( ) is red’, ‘( ) is round’, ‘( ) is red and round’, or ‘( ) is red or round’. Which sense is it? How can we identify which sense it is without already grasping the senses expressed by “red” or “round”? Since a is an object and concept F is merely a mapping-function, the truth-condition, Fa, is purely extensional in sense (2), and leaves us clueless as to which sense is expressed by “Fa.” What kind of ideal language is it in which we cannot even distinguish colors from shapes? 9 Is L perhaps too small? It seems large enough to refute Dummett’s program. And we can always add more names. Appealing to “All red things have color” or “All round things have shape” will not do. Where all and only red things are round, these two statements have the same extensional in sense (2) truth- condition. We cannot even say “Red is a color” in Frege’s notation. The closest we can come is “If anything is red, then it has a color.” And L has only one nonlogical predicate! But it would not help 17

sentences, <strong>and</strong> we were only supposed <strong>to</strong> know their truth-conditions.<br />

But let us pretend that we magically succeeded in defining the reference of “F( )” in the<br />

enumerative manner suggested. Can we thereby derive the sense expressed by “F( )” as the same as<br />

that expressed by “( ) falls under the purely extensional in sense (2) mapping-function which maps the<br />

arguments a, b, <strong>and</strong> c, but not d, on<strong>to</strong> the value the True”? I cannot think of what else Dummett might<br />

have in mind. But the reference of “F( )” can be presented in indefinitely many ways, for example, as<br />

the reference now under discussion. Thus there can be indefinitely many object-languages L1...Ln that<br />

agree on the reference but differ on the sense of “F( ).”<br />

Suppose that all <strong>and</strong> only a, b, <strong>and</strong> c are red <strong>and</strong> round. How can we tell whether speakers of L<br />

are using “F( )” <strong>to</strong> express the sense ‘( ) is red’, ‘( ) is round’, ‘( ) is red <strong>and</strong> round’, or ‘( ) is red or<br />

round’? Or in a world in which all <strong>and</strong> only red objects are round, <strong>and</strong> in which infinitely many objects<br />

are red, so that F( ) must be intensional in sense (3), how can we identify the sense expressed by<br />

“F( )”? By hypothesis, the only senses “F( )” could possibly express for us are: ‘( ) is red’, ‘( ) is<br />

round’, ‘( ) is red <strong>and</strong> round’, or ‘( ) is red or round’. Which sense is it? How can we identify which<br />

sense it is without already grasping the senses expressed by “red” or “round”? Since a is an object <strong>and</strong><br />

concept F is merely a mapping-function, the truth-condition, Fa, is purely extensional in sense (2), <strong>and</strong><br />

leaves us clueless as <strong>to</strong> which sense is expressed by “Fa.” What kind of ideal language is it in which<br />

we cannot even distinguish colors from shapes? 9<br />

Is L perhaps <strong>to</strong>o small? It seems large enough <strong>to</strong> refute Dummett’s program. And we can<br />

always add more names.<br />

Appealing <strong>to</strong> “All red things have color” or “All round things have shape” will not do. Where<br />

all <strong>and</strong> only red things are round, these two statements have the same extensional in sense (2) truth-<br />

condition. We cannot even say “Red is a color” in <strong>Frege</strong>’s notation. The closest we can come is “If<br />

anything is red, then it has a color.” And L has only one nonlogical predicate! But it would not help<br />

17

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!