29.12.2014 Views

Download PDF - Robson Hall Faculty of Law

Download PDF - Robson Hall Faculty of Law

Download PDF - Robson Hall Faculty of Law

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

A Tough Pill to Swallow 155<br />

remedial effects by either preventing future crime or by making society a “safer<br />

place”, for instance, by incarcerating <strong>of</strong>fenders and keeping them <strong>of</strong>f the streets in<br />

the short term while they are rehabilitated for (hopefully) the long term<br />

betterment <strong>of</strong> society. The problem with this theory is that it produces<br />

counterintuitive results in two possible scenarios. First, in cases where no social<br />

good would be served by punishment, the theory would disallow any punishment<br />

as it would, on balance, be more harmful than helpful. Imprisoning someone,<br />

thus lessening the amount <strong>of</strong> “good” (freedom, happiness, etc.) in the world,<br />

when it produces no “good” in return, would be wrong on this view.<br />

Problematically, this means that where there is no deterrent, remedial, or public<br />

safety effect, punishment cannot be justified and <strong>of</strong>fenders get <strong>of</strong>f “scot free”.<br />

Some might argue that prison time is never a “good” because it hardens criminals<br />

at the worst and makes them difficult to reintegrate into society at best. If indeed<br />

this is true, then prison might very well be abolished altogether, on the utilitarian<br />

account, except perhaps in the second and even more counterintuitive set <strong>of</strong><br />

circumstances, namely that the theory would condone punishing random<br />

innocent people if doing so would enhance the overall social good. That is, if it<br />

would be better to make an example out <strong>of</strong> an innocent person than to let the law<br />

appear to have been flouted or avoided by the true culprit who got away, then we<br />

should punish the innocent person.<br />

Beyond the philosophical absurdities, there are practical reasons why a purely<br />

utilitarian justification for punishing NCR persons would not be tenable. There<br />

are many provisions in the Code relating to treating and rehabilitating NCR<br />

persons as a condition for their release back into society. 37 Therefore, since there<br />

are already safeguards in place to ensure public safety by denying the mentally ill’s<br />

re-entry into society until they are better, there is arguably no social good to be<br />

obtained by further punishing the mentally ill person for their reckless actions<br />

which precipitated their mental instability. It is possible that there may be some<br />

deterrent effects to be had, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as non-adherence to medication would be<br />

recognized as potentially inculpatory, and this deterrence would function as a<br />

social good justifying punishment on the utilitarian account; however, I think it is<br />

clear that the primary motivation in punishing reckless omissions <strong>of</strong> medication<br />

adherence is in reality largely based on the desire to punish a perceived moral<br />

wrong – that is, retributive justice and social denunciation.<br />

Retributivist theories <strong>of</strong> punishment presuppose a unified moral theory<br />

(which may vary by society) and condones punishment where the moral theory is<br />

violated. 38 Such theories may be as fundamental and simple as the imperative <strong>of</strong><br />

adhering to the state-made laws <strong>of</strong> the land or may involve higher-order ethical<br />

37<br />

38<br />

Criminal Code, supra note 2 at s 672.54.<br />

Thom Brooks, “Kantian Punishment and Retributivism: A Reply to Clark” (2005) 18:2 Ratio<br />

237 at 241.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!