27.12.2014 Views

Presenting evidence in court

Presenting evidence in court

Presenting evidence in court

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Present<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>evidence</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>court</strong>–some fundamental problems to<br />

be considered<br />

Anders Eriksson<br />

Department of Philosophy, L<strong>in</strong>guistics and Theory of Science, University of Gothenburg, Sweden<br />

anders.eriksson@l<strong>in</strong>g.gu.se<br />

The question of how to present <strong>evidence</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>court</strong> has been a hotly debated question for some<br />

years now. One may identify the Daubert rul<strong>in</strong>g 1 as a possible start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t, but it is likely that<br />

even without Daubert, these questions would still have emerged. We have had some<br />

presentations at our own meet<strong>in</strong>gs too on this topic, most notably a couple of presentations by<br />

Geoffrey Morrison advocat<strong>in</strong>g the Likelihood Ratio approach. But it is now time to take a<br />

broader grip on these questions. There are many more aspects that just the pros and cons of the<br />

Likelihood Ratio approach to be considered.<br />

The ongo<strong>in</strong>g discussions have resulted <strong>in</strong> two important surveys, one <strong>in</strong> the US and one <strong>in</strong> the<br />

U.K.. The results of these surveys have been published <strong>in</strong> two recent reports – Strengthen<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Forensic Science <strong>in</strong> the United States (2009) published by the National Research Council and<br />

Expert Evidence <strong>in</strong> Crim<strong>in</strong>al Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> England and Wales (2011) published by The Law<br />

Commission. Both reports have a strong focus on the question of admissibility as may be<br />

expected, but most of what is said is nevertheless highly relevant also <strong>in</strong> those countries where<br />

the concept of admissibility does not exist with<strong>in</strong> the legal system. It is rather obvious <strong>in</strong> these<br />

reports and many other publications that the authors see DNA analysis as the role model for all<br />

types of <strong>evidence</strong>.<br />

With the exception of nuclear DNA analysis, however, no forensic method has been<br />

rigorously shown to have the capacity to consistently, and with a high degree of certa<strong>in</strong>ty,<br />

demonstrate a connection between <strong>evidence</strong> and a specific <strong>in</strong>dividual or source (National<br />

Research Council report, p. 7)<br />

Whether it is possible or even desirable to squeeze all types of <strong>evidence</strong> <strong>in</strong>to this model is<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g you might want to consider. But even if that should <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple be possible we are<br />

very far from that today and then the question arises how the strength of different types of<br />

<strong>evidence</strong> can be evaluated and compared. This is by no means obvious even if we limit the scope<br />

to the field of forensic phonetics. And perhaps even more problematic is the case when different<br />

types of <strong>evidence</strong> are contradictory. I will describe a case (Donnelly, 2005) where eyewitness<br />

testimony contradicted DNA and how this caused almost total confusion.<br />

The Daubert rul<strong>in</strong>g by the US Supreme Court meant a substantial change away from previously<br />

accepted admissibility rules def<strong>in</strong>ed by the Frye rul<strong>in</strong>g 2 . The Frye rul<strong>in</strong>g meant that admissible<br />

<strong>evidence</strong> should be based on pr<strong>in</strong>ciples generally accepted with<strong>in</strong> the relevant scientific<br />

community, <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple mean<strong>in</strong>g consensus. The Daubert rul<strong>in</strong>g replaced the idea of scientific<br />

consensus by a set of more general criteria meant as a guide but not as “a def<strong>in</strong>itive checklist or<br />

test”.<br />

1 Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc, 509 US 579 (1993)<br />

2 Frye v. United States, 293 F. 1013 (D.C. Cir. 1923)


1) Is the <strong>evidence</strong> based on a testable theory or technique;<br />

2) has the theory or technique been peer reviewed;<br />

3) <strong>in</strong> the case of a particular technique, does it have a known error rate and standards controll<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the techniques operation;<br />

4) is the underly<strong>in</strong>g science generally accepted<br />

As a general guide these rules make a lot of sense, stress<strong>in</strong>g scientific validity and the<br />

competence of the expert witness, but without requir<strong>in</strong>g consensus <strong>in</strong> the scientific community.<br />

The problematic part is, however, who is to be the judge if the <strong>evidence</strong> complies with these<br />

rules. In the US where Daubert has now been applied for some years the f<strong>in</strong>al word concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

admissibility seems to have shifted from the scientific community to the trial judge who <strong>in</strong> most<br />

cases is likely to possess little or no competence to evaluate scientific validity and reliability. As<br />

may be expected this has not been without problems as I will expla<strong>in</strong>.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, I will say a few words about <strong>in</strong>dividualization. The problem of <strong>in</strong>dividualization has a<br />

long history. One formulation of what it means for entities to be identical goes by the name of<br />

The Identity of Indiscernibles often referred to as Leibniz's law. Leibniz first formulated the<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> his Discourse on Metaphysics (1686): "it is not true that two substances may be<br />

exactly alike and differ only numerically". In logical terms the law is often re-formulated as: if,<br />

for every property F, object x has F if and only if object y has F, then x is identical to y. This is<br />

also by and large the way we th<strong>in</strong>k about identity <strong>in</strong> forensic speaker identification although we<br />

never come even close to the "for every property" requirement <strong>in</strong> any analysis. Two questions<br />

arise when we th<strong>in</strong>g about this law: 1) Is it true even <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple and 2) If it were can we even<br />

approach fulfilment of the requirements by any practically applicable methods <strong>in</strong> forensic<br />

science. Some scientist have argued that the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is simply false, at least for some areas of<br />

Quantum Physics (Cortes, 1976). Others (e.g. Saks & Koehler, 2008) have attacked the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

on more practical grounds. Based on these and other studies, I will argue that we should abandon<br />

the concept of identity altogether <strong>in</strong> the forensic context.<br />

References<br />

Cortes, A. (1976). Leibniz's pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of the identity of <strong>in</strong>discernibles: A false pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Philosophy of<br />

Science, 43(4): 491–505.<br />

Donnelly, P. (2005). Appeal<strong>in</strong>g statistics. Significance, 2(1), 46–48.<br />

National Research Council. (2009). Strengthen<strong>in</strong>g Forensic Science <strong>in</strong> the United States: A Path Forward.<br />

Wash<strong>in</strong>gton D.C.: The National Academies Press.<br />

Law Commission. (2011). Expert Evidence <strong>in</strong> Crim<strong>in</strong>al Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> England and Wales. (LAW COM No<br />

325)<br />

Leibniz, G. W. (1686). Discourse on Metaphysics. (on-l<strong>in</strong>e translation by G. R. Montgomery.<br />

http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/Leibniz-Discourse.htm)<br />

Saks, M. J. and J. J. Koehler (2008). The <strong>in</strong>dividualization fallacy <strong>in</strong> forensic science <strong>evidence</strong>. Vanderbilt<br />

Law Review, 61(1): 199–219.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!