the mystical theology of valentin weigel - DataSpace at Princeton ...

the mystical theology of valentin weigel - DataSpace at Princeton ... the mystical theology of valentin weigel - DataSpace at Princeton ...

dataspace.princeton.edu
from dataspace.princeton.edu More from this publisher
12.11.2014 Views

pledged to uphold and promote—but one from which his divergent beliefs left him alienated, fearful of what might happen to him if he were to voice questions about its theology and how it functioned as an institution. This is why indifference are key concepts for understanding Weigel’s writings: Gelassenheit and apophasis are both forms of indifference and both constitute Weigel’s response to confessionalization. That Weigel signed the Formula Concordiae was part of a larger pattern of attempting to keep a low profile to avoid being censured by the Lutheran ecclesiastical authorities. He did not publish his works during his lifetime (with the exception of one sermon), which is sensible considering the disputatious culture of Streitschriften of his time. Also, in his works he gives positive examples of people not taking action, which he values as a way of fulfilling a truer form of Christianity than defend-to-the-death martyrs. Luther, on the other hand, felt the need to take action, and more importantly, to defend his beliefs no matter what the cost, famously remarking that he would rather see the world reduced to chaos and nothingness than go back on what he believed to be the truth. What sets Weigel apart from Luther is not his strength of character (or lack thereof), but rather that he has a different attitude altogether towards the value of the earthly church. For Luther, the church ought to exist in some form and so ought to be the best that it could be, whereas Weigel did not believe that the church ought to exist at all, and that therefore all churches, even a thoroughly reformed one, would be equally undesirable. He thought that churches were by definition un-Christian, and as such, saw no point in taking personal risk to defend this church—or indeed, even taking personal risk to attack the church and militate in favour of secularism and abolishment of the church. For Weigel, reforming the church would be like tying a ribbon over a gangrenous wound—it may 258

improve appearances but, because it fundamentally misdiagnoses the problem, it would do nothing to cure the patient. As it happens, the decision not to publish his writings was a good instinct for somebody trying to keep a low profile and avoid causing controversy. When his writings were published after his death, they caused a great uproar, a panic about Weigelianer plotting against the Church, and a raft of anti-Weigelian Streitschriften by more establishment-minded Lutheran theologians. What so exercised Weigel’s critics was the fact that Weigel did not believe in the very idea of ecclesiastical institutions, which goes beyond simple anticlericalism or a dissatisfaction with a particular institution. Those who attacked Weigel saw clearly that his writings deprived the church of all of its functions, such that it had nothing to offer the laypeople it claimed to serve. Sermons, sacraments, theology, doctrine, interpreting the Bible: all of these Weigel said laypeople could perform, write or interpret themselves because these things were simply the created correlates of the uncreated original, which every person possesses as God’s most precious legacy to humankind, the gift of God himself. Each person, regardless of which church she belongs to, or even if she belongs to no church at all, carries within her a priest to perform sacraments, as well as a heavenly Book that is the source of all wisdom and saving knowledge. Moreover, although this precious treasure might be buried under deep layers of ignorance after the Fall, people’s faculties have not been so corroded by sin that the relationship to God is functionally severed. The uproar about Weigelianism, to put the matter another way, stems from the fact that Weigel represents a peculiar limit-case of heresy. The idea he embraces— namely that no earthly Church can possibly be truly Christian—is not accidentally 259

pledged to uphold and promote—but one from which his divergent beliefs left him<br />

alien<strong>at</strong>ed, fearful <strong>of</strong> wh<strong>at</strong> might happen to him if he were to voice questions about its<br />

<strong>the</strong>ology and how it functioned as an institution. This is why indifference are key<br />

concepts for understanding Weigel’s writings: Gelassenheit and apophasis are both forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> indifference and both constitute Weigel’s response to confessionaliz<strong>at</strong>ion.<br />

Th<strong>at</strong> Weigel signed <strong>the</strong> Formula Concordiae was part <strong>of</strong> a larger p<strong>at</strong>tern <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>at</strong>tempting to keep a low pr<strong>of</strong>ile to avoid being censured by <strong>the</strong> Lu<strong>the</strong>ran ecclesiastical<br />

authorities. He did not publish his works during his lifetime (with <strong>the</strong> exception <strong>of</strong> one<br />

sermon), which is sensible considering <strong>the</strong> disput<strong>at</strong>ious culture <strong>of</strong> Streitschriften <strong>of</strong> his<br />

time. Also, in his works he gives positive examples <strong>of</strong> people not taking action, which he<br />

values as a way <strong>of</strong> fulfilling a truer form <strong>of</strong> Christianity than defend-to-<strong>the</strong>-de<strong>at</strong>h martyrs.<br />

Lu<strong>the</strong>r, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, felt <strong>the</strong> need to take action, and more importantly, to defend<br />

his beliefs no m<strong>at</strong>ter wh<strong>at</strong> <strong>the</strong> cost, famously remarking th<strong>at</strong> he would ra<strong>the</strong>r see <strong>the</strong><br />

world reduced to chaos and nothingness than go back on wh<strong>at</strong> he believed to be <strong>the</strong> truth.<br />

Wh<strong>at</strong> sets Weigel apart from Lu<strong>the</strong>r is not his strength <strong>of</strong> character (or lack <strong>the</strong>re<strong>of</strong>), but<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>at</strong> he has a different <strong>at</strong>titude altoge<strong>the</strong>r towards <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> earthly church.<br />

For Lu<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> church ought to exist in some form and so ought to be <strong>the</strong> best th<strong>at</strong> it<br />

could be, whereas Weigel did not believe th<strong>at</strong> <strong>the</strong> church ought to exist <strong>at</strong> all, and th<strong>at</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>refore all churches, even a thoroughly reformed one, would be equally undesirable. He<br />

thought th<strong>at</strong> churches were by definition un-Christian, and as such, saw no point in taking<br />

personal risk to defend this church—or indeed, even taking personal risk to <strong>at</strong>tack <strong>the</strong><br />

church and milit<strong>at</strong>e in favour <strong>of</strong> secularism and abolishment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> church. For Weigel,<br />

reforming <strong>the</strong> church would be like tying a ribbon over a gangrenous wound—it may<br />

258

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!