the mystical theology of valentin weigel - DataSpace at Princeton ...

the mystical theology of valentin weigel - DataSpace at Princeton ... the mystical theology of valentin weigel - DataSpace at Princeton ...

dataspace.princeton.edu
from dataspace.princeton.edu More from this publisher
12.11.2014 Views

erum”), but rather brings the particular goods together in a higher kind of unity because they are actually identical (“unum simplicitate substantiae”). 606 That is, if the summum bonum is perfectly powerful, then it needs no other thing to assist it, and if it is thus perfectly sufficient then it is lacking nothing and so needs no money or possessions to satisfy those needs; if it is therefore perfectly sufficient and powerful, then it is necessarily perfectly dignified and noble and therefore most worthy of respect and so on. Boethius links all of the particular goods in this way, and, as Weigel notes, the difference between them is a trick of language: “sunt unum simplicitate substantiae, licet nomina sint inter se diversa, ut sufficientiae et potentiae una eademque natura est.” 607 However imperfect the happiness the particular goods can bring is, Lady Philosophy assures Boethius that the very existence of imperfect happiness implies the existence of perfect happiness: “in quocunque enim genere est reperire imperfectum, in eodem etiam est reperire perfectum.” 608 Imperfect happiness implies perfect happiness, and anything perfect must be identical with God himself, since there can be no perfection that is not God, who would then be incomplete and thus imperfect: therefore all of the imperfect goods must be identical with God’s very substance. 609 While Boethius is keen to demonstrate that all good things participate in God’s substance (and that God, because he is perfectly self-sufficient therefore must rule the entire universe sovereignly and providentially), he is not particularly focused on demonstrating that all things participate in God’s substance. That is, while Boethius 606 Weigel, De vita beata, 45. 607 Ibid, 45-46. 608 Ibid, 51. 609 The universe, of course, could not have an imperfect source, because something can be judged imperfect only with respect to perfection (“imperfectum non est principium rerum, quia perfectum est prius ipso imperfecto”), and so perfection must come prior to anything imperfect. Ibid, 51. 224

argues that there cannot be more than one highest good in which the other goods participate, he does not say anything about how creation as a whole participates in God. This is the point at which Boethius’ ideas intersect with Dionysius’ in Weigel’s paraphrase, where the unity of the summum bonum in Boethius leads Weigel to investigate God’s unity in Dionysius. Whereas for Boethius, God was happiness itself, power itself and beauty itself and so on, for Dionysius, God is not lacking anything: “nec beatitudo, nec bonitas, nec pulchritudo, nec lux, nec vita, nec perfectio, nec justitia est distincta a DEO etc.” 610 This first list of names for God is followed by several sets of even longer lists that are nowhere to be found in Weigel’s source: “DEUS est sufficientia, potentia, dignitas, gloria, laetiti, bonitas, beatitudo, lux, intellectus, voluntas, amor, mens, verbum, Spiritus omnis veritatis, fons, essentia, Unum etc. et hae omnia sunt unum in DEO, unitate simplicissima, sine omnia mutua penetration.” 611 These flourishes of cataphasic excess, which would have been at home in Dionysius’ Divine Names, give God scores of names from every register of language, from the more humble names taken from the material world (fons and lux) to the lofty and immaterial names (essentia and Unum). Having made all these assertions about God, Weigel demonstrates that he has learned from Dionysius the via negativa, pairing assertions with negations and negating the negations: “DEUS est omnia ablata omni imperfectione, nec tamen est hoc aut illud, non enim sic esset omnia, et super omnia, nec est hic et ibi, non enim esset ubique, nec est hodie aut cras, non enim esset aeternus.” 612 As Dionysius himself might have written, 610 Weigel, De vita beata, 52-53. This list is not in the Boethius passage, where Boethius is only discussing whether happiness is identical with God. 611 Ibid, 55-56. 612 Ibid, 56. 225

argues th<strong>at</strong> <strong>the</strong>re cannot be more than one highest good in which <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r goods<br />

particip<strong>at</strong>e, he does not say anything about how cre<strong>at</strong>ion as a whole particip<strong>at</strong>es in God.<br />

This is <strong>the</strong> point <strong>at</strong> which Boethius’ ideas intersect with Dionysius’ in Weigel’s<br />

paraphrase, where <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> summum bonum in Boethius leads Weigel to<br />

investig<strong>at</strong>e God’s unity in Dionysius. Whereas for Boethius, God was happiness itself,<br />

power itself and beauty itself and so on, for Dionysius, God is not lacking anything: “nec<br />

be<strong>at</strong>itudo, nec bonitas, nec pulchritudo, nec lux, nec vita, nec perfectio, nec justitia est<br />

distincta a DEO etc.” 610 This first list <strong>of</strong> names for God is followed by several sets <strong>of</strong><br />

even longer lists th<strong>at</strong> are nowhere to be found in Weigel’s source: “DEUS est sufficientia,<br />

potentia, dignitas, gloria, laetiti, bonitas, be<strong>at</strong>itudo, lux, intellectus, voluntas, amor, mens,<br />

verbum, Spiritus omnis verit<strong>at</strong>is, fons, essentia, Unum etc. et hae omnia sunt unum in<br />

DEO, unit<strong>at</strong>e simplicissima, sine omnia mutua penetr<strong>at</strong>ion.” 611 These flourishes <strong>of</strong><br />

c<strong>at</strong>aphasic excess, which would have been <strong>at</strong> home in Dionysius’ Divine Names, give<br />

God scores <strong>of</strong> names from every register <strong>of</strong> language, from <strong>the</strong> more humble names taken<br />

from <strong>the</strong> m<strong>at</strong>erial world (fons and lux) to <strong>the</strong> l<strong>of</strong>ty and imm<strong>at</strong>erial names (essentia and<br />

Unum).<br />

Having made all <strong>the</strong>se assertions about God, Weigel demonstr<strong>at</strong>es th<strong>at</strong> he has<br />

learned from Dionysius <strong>the</strong> via neg<strong>at</strong>iva, pairing assertions with neg<strong>at</strong>ions and neg<strong>at</strong>ing<br />

<strong>the</strong> neg<strong>at</strong>ions: “DEUS est omnia abl<strong>at</strong>a omni imperfectione, nec tamen est hoc aut illud,<br />

non enim sic esset omnia, et super omnia, nec est hic et ibi, non enim esset ubique, nec<br />

est hodie aut cras, non enim esset aeternus.” 612 As Dionysius himself might have written,<br />

610 Weigel, De vita be<strong>at</strong>a, 52-53. This list is not in <strong>the</strong> Boethius passage, where Boethius is only discussing<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r happiness is identical with God.<br />

611 Ibid, 55-56.<br />

612 Ibid, 56.<br />

225

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!