10.11.2014 Views

Bondarenko Dmitri M. Homoarchy

Bondarenko Dmitri M. Homoarchy

Bondarenko Dmitri M. Homoarchy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

114<br />

political integration” is also taken into account (Murdock and Wilson 1972: 256). On universality<br />

and the fundamental role of the community from the earliest phases of human social history see,<br />

e.g., Murdock and Wilson 1972; Artemova 1983; Kabo 1986; Butinov 2000: 75–93. On the<br />

discussion on the point, particularly in the British functionalist and structuralist anthropology and in<br />

the Soviet ethnography see, e.g., Bromley 1981: 181–185; Nikishenkov 1986: 133–139; Girenko<br />

2000; Reshetov 2000. In my view, the emphasis on the fact that “autonomous communities” have<br />

never been truly autonomous but initially formed parts of wider systems of intercommunity<br />

interaction recently made by Stephen Kowalewski (2003), does not disregard the concept of<br />

community in general though may profitably shift researchers’ attention from studying it “as such”<br />

to doing it in a much more historical context, in light of its place in a broader cultural milieu. In<br />

fact, this discussion is an “echo” of the furious debate which is in full swing in present-day<br />

archaeology: between the adherents of the approaches which can be labeled as world-system<br />

(“regional-interaction-based”) and particularistic (“local-community-oriented”) ones (vide stricto<br />

Kristiansen 1998 vs. Harding 2000; see also, e.g., Blanton and Feinman 1984; Peregrine 1992;<br />

Peregrine and Feinman 1996; Algaze 1993; Kradin 2002b). My belief is that these approaches do<br />

not contradict but rather compliment each other (compare with the debate between the worldsystem<br />

and civilization approaches adherents and its estimation by the present author: <strong>Bondarenko</strong><br />

and Korotayev 2000d; <strong>Bondarenko</strong> 2003b; 2005e: 51–57; 2005f; <strong>Bondarenko</strong> et al. 2003) and<br />

hence, as has just been argued, the concept of community still remains valid.<br />

4 However, Crumley does see power relations (heterarchic and otherwise) not as “a thing<br />

in itself” but in their interaction with, and dependence on the social, mental (value system), and<br />

ecological milieu, and legitimately builds her concept on these foundations.<br />

5 In the meantime, I leave apart the problems I feel with Carneiro’s specific interpretation<br />

concentrated in such “minor linguistic peculiarities” as that I would prefer to speak in the nonunilinear<br />

vein about “processes”, not “the process” and about “types” as not synonymous with<br />

“stages.”<br />

6 As Elizabeth Brumfiel wrote only a dozen years ago (1995: 130), “The coupling of<br />

differentiation and hierarchy is so firm in our minds that it takes tremendous intellectual effort to<br />

even imagine what differentiation without hierarchy could be”. Usually if the very fact of complex<br />

heterarchical societies’ existence is recognized (as for example, within the wholoculturalist<br />

framework), it is considered as an historical accident, anomaly; such cultures are declared incapable<br />

to achieve high levels of complexity and internal stability (Tuden and Marshall 1972: 454–456).<br />

7 Remarkably, in the theory of biological evolution the transition from a more to less<br />

hierarchical structure without diminishing of organisms’ adaptivity to the environment is not<br />

regarded as a sign of degradation or regress (see, e.g., Severtsov 1949; 1967; Futuyma 1997).<br />

8 The Tasmanians “… separated from the Aborigines of Australia in an early period of<br />

their history and then were developing in isolation for a long time” (Kabo 1986: 34), actually, for<br />

8,000 or 9,000 years (Clark, G. and Piggott 1970: 99), so they may legally be regarded as an<br />

independent case, at least in general outline. In the respect we are interested in, this is clearly<br />

testified by the fact that the Australians’ and Tasmanians’ overall social non-egalitarianism was<br />

based on different backgrounds: religious-ideological (Artemova 1993: 46–54; 2000a: 56–62;

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!