05.11.2014 Views

Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

180 JOSEPH TORCHIA<br />

that is, in terms of the soul and the body alike. While he would<br />

always uphold the primacy of the spiritual over the corporeal<br />

life, one of his abiding concerns was the explanation of the unity<br />

of the body and the soul in human beings. 35 In De Civitate Dei<br />

xix.4, however, his chief interest lies in coming to terms with the<br />

reality of misfortune in human life, and not with a focus upon<br />

its goods. In opposition to the Stoics, he vehemently denies that<br />

virtue provides any guarantee against the encroachment of such<br />

negativity.<br />

If they are genuine virtues (and genuine virtues can exist<br />

only in those in whom true godliness is present) they do not profess<br />

to have the power to ensure that the people in whom they<br />

exist will not suffer any miseries; genuine virtues are not such<br />

liars as to advance such claims. 36<br />

So too, Augustine strongly opposes the Stoic dismissal of<br />

physical distresses as neither goods nor evils. For him, such ills<br />

are genuinely evil, at least in existential terms. 37 Unlike the Stoic<br />

materialists (who ground their happiness completely in the present<br />

life), however, the Christian Augustine can face these trials<br />

with a patient endurance that finds support in the hope of eternal<br />

life.<br />

35<br />

One of Augustine’s most explicit statements on this particular issue is<br />

found in the De moribus Ecclesiae catholicae et de moribus Manichaeorum<br />

I,4(6). See De moribus Ecclesiae catholicae et de moribus Manichaeorum<br />

I,27(52), for Augustine’s classic definition of the human being as “a rational<br />

soul, making use of a mortal and earthly body.” In this definition, we see a<br />

blending of Augustine’s emphasis on the primacy of the soul with a recognition<br />

of the importance of the body in human existence.<br />

36<br />

De Civitate Dei xix,4, 180-184: CC xlviii, 668.<br />

37<br />

This statement must be qualified, since it might be construed as contradicting<br />

Augustine’s interpretation of evil as a lack or deficiency of being<br />

and goodness. While Augustine defined evil in negative terms in a metaphysical<br />

sense, he still recognized the real impact of such negativity in human<br />

life. Accordingly, his denial that evil has an ontological status of its own does<br />

not imply that it has no effect (e.g., in the way that starvation, as the absence<br />

of nourishment, has an effect on the one who is starving).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!