Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

studiamoralia.org
from studiamoralia.org More from this publisher
05.11.2014 Views

176 JOSEPH TORCHIA But what does Augustine’s assessment of this seemingly esoteric theological issue tell us about his understanding of the adiaphora in an ethical context? In my estimation, it reveals some key metaphysical presuppositions that assume a highly prominent role in his overall understanding of moral living. First, Letter 82 demonstrates Augustine’s reluctance to view any aspect of created reality in exclusively negative terms. Just as the ceremonies of the Old Law cannot be evil (because they were ordained by God for His own salvific purposes), creation as a whole cannot be evil. But it is not enough to say that created realities are “not evil.” If they were created by God, they must be viewed as fundamentally good as well. This is borne out, in fact, by one of the earliest teachings in Genesis (1:31): God looked at everything He had made, and He found it very good. In this connection, Augustine reinforces his arguments in Letter 82 with a reference to St. Paul’s words in I Timothy (4:4): Everything God created is good; nothing is to be rejected when it is received with thanksgiving, for it is made by God’s word and prayer. 2. Ethical Dimension Augustine provides a more focused ethical critique of the adiaphora in De Civitate Dei xix.4. As his remarks reveal, valuations of things or actions as morally “good,” “bad,” or “indifferent” reflect a certain vision of the nature of reality. In support of this observation, we see that Augustine readily establishes the ultimate goal of human striving (and by implication, the basis of human happiness): eternal life constitutes the supreme Good, while eternal death is the supreme evil. 25 In Augustinian terms, correct or right living provides the ultimate determinant for the achievement of the former option rather than the latter one. But it is clear that such a position points to a belief in a supernatural destiny for human beings. Accordingly, Augustine places 25 De Civitate Dei xix,4, 1-6: CC xlviii, 664.

ST. AUGUSTINE’S CRITIQUE OF THE ADIAPHORA 177 himself at odds with those who would localize the ultimate good or evil of humanity in the present life, and ground our happiness in the body, the soul, pleasure, virtue, or the primary gifts of human nature. 26 While Augustine does not yet name his opponents explicitly, we can easily infer that the Stoics are the focus of his critique. “All these philosophers have wished,” he contends, “to be happy here on earth and to achieve bliss by their own efforts.” 27 From a practical standpoint, however, the folly of these efforts is readily apparent. The very vicissitudes of the present life militate against such a naive optimism in the capacity of human striving. Indeed, the mere possession of wisdom provides no defense against misfortune and disaster. For who is competent, however torrential the flow of his eloquence, to unfold all the miseries of this life? For is there any pain, the opposite of pleasure, any disturbance, the contrary of repose, that cannot befall a wise man’s body? Then what about the primary goods, so called, of the mind itself? Then again, what of virtue itself? Although it claims the top-most place among human goods, what is its activity in this world but unceasing warfare with vices, and those not external vices but internal... vices? 28 Augustine’s detailed catalogue of the varieties of human misery provides the supporting data for his contention that the basis of genuine happiness cannot be found in the present life. But the recognition of this fact by no means commits him to a pessimism regarding the prospects for achieving happiness. From a Christian standpoint, such a telos is indeed attainable, but only in the life to come. This supernatural end is wholly consistent with the spiritual dimension of human existence, and the immortality of the human soul. 26 De Civitate Dei xix,4, 11-18: CC xlviii, 664. 27 De Civitate Dei xix,4: 11-18. 28 De Civitate Dei xix,4, 22-23; 27-29; 39-40; 61; 65: CC xlviii, 664-65.

ST. AUGUSTINE’S CRITIQUE OF THE ADIAPHORA 177<br />

himself at odds with those who would localize the ultimate good<br />

or evil of humanity in the present life, and ground our happiness<br />

in the body, the soul, pleasure, virtue, or the primary gifts of<br />

human nature. 26<br />

While Augustine does not yet name his opponents explicitly,<br />

we can easily infer that the Stoics are the focus of his critique.<br />

“All these philosophers have wished,” he contends, “to be happy<br />

here on earth and to achieve bliss by their own efforts.” 27 From<br />

a practical standpoint, however, the folly of these efforts is readily<br />

apparent. The very vicissitudes of the present life militate<br />

against such a naive optimism in the capacity of human striving.<br />

Indeed, the mere possession of wisdom provides no defense<br />

against misfortune and disaster.<br />

For who is competent, however torrential the flow of his eloquence,<br />

to unfold all the miseries of this life? For is there any<br />

pain, the opposite of pleasure, any disturbance, the contrary of<br />

repose, that cannot befall a wise man’s body? Then what about<br />

the primary goods, so called, of the mind itself? Then again,<br />

what of virtue itself? Although it claims the top-most place<br />

among human goods, what is its activity in this world but unceasing<br />

warfare with vices, and those not external vices but internal...<br />

vices? 28<br />

Augustine’s detailed catalogue of the varieties of human<br />

misery provides the supporting data for his contention that the<br />

basis of genuine happiness cannot be found in the present life.<br />

But the recognition of this fact by no means commits him to a<br />

pessimism regarding the prospects for achieving happiness.<br />

From a Christian standpoint, such a telos is indeed attainable,<br />

but only in the life to come. This supernatural end is wholly consistent<br />

with the spiritual dimension of human existence, and the<br />

immortality of the human soul.<br />

26<br />

De Civitate Dei xix,4, 11-18: CC xlviii, 664.<br />

27<br />

De Civitate Dei xix,4: 11-18.<br />

28<br />

De Civitate Dei xix,4, 22-23; 27-29; 39-40; 61; 65: CC xlviii, 664-65.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!